Common Sense View of Reality
Common Sense View of Reality
Common Sense View of Reality
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
Duke University Press and are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend
access to The Philosophical Review
the real and the only real. Apart from this practical standard
there is no measure for reality, there is no meaning to the term.
The familiar saying, "the burnt child fears the fire," illustrates
the meaning of reality from the practical standpoint. The child
will, without hesitation, touch that which he may imagine in play
is hot; but the glowing stove has for him a reality determined
purely by practical experience. And what is true of the child is
to a great degree true of the race in its earliest stages of devel-
opment. The external world is a practical world. Not that
fancy and imagination do not play an important r6le, but they
are continually being eliminated and corrected through practical
experience. As the child and the race advance, the criterion of
practicability becomes more and more pronounced, unless turned
aside and subverted by the introduction of speculative thinking,
and even then, while such philosophizing may have a great effect
upon the thinking of a people, history has shown that it has a
relatively slight influence upon their conduct. To sum up in
brief, it is this determination of the external world from the prac-
tical standpoint, from the standpoint of interest, that may be de-
fined as the common-sense view of reality.
With whatever tenacity the common-sense view may have held
its place in ordinary thinking, the history of philosophy shows
that from the very beginning speculation broke away from the
naive conception of reality in an attempt to harmonize the con-
tradictions between logical thinking and perception. Even before
systematic philosophy had developed in Greece, the Eastern
sages had declared that the whole world of sense was illusion,
that phenomena were but the veil of maya, that life itself was a
dream, and its goal was Nirvana. The first attempt at systematic
thinking, that of the Milesian school, seems to have been prompted
by a desire to find in the dpx7 a resting place for thought be-
yond immediate externality, though there seems to be here no
direct break with the popular conception concerning the material
universe. This break was not, however, long delayed. Both
Heraclitus and Parmenides speak of the illusion of the senses;
while Zeno attempted with his refined logic to refute all assertion
of the multiplicity and changeability of being. For the Pythag-
boot straps. But now comes upon the scene the master who is
to bring back the lost cosmos, and to restore metaphysics to her
once proud position as a science. The professor at Koenigsberg
hears the note of scepticism, awakens from his dogmatic slum-
bers, the Critique of Pure Reason is given to the world, and a
new era of philosophy is inaugurated.
But have the claims of Kant been realized ? Is metaphysics to-
day on a more firm foundation than when the author of the Critique
wrote: "Time was when she was the queen of all the sciences.
Now it is the fashion of the time to heap contempt and scorn upon
her, and the matron mourns, forlorn and forsaken like Hecuba."
Compared with the many devotees of empirical science, how few
there are who to-day turn their attention to metaphysics, not
because the questions raised are not still of burning interest, but
because there is a general despair of reaching any result. Will
this condition ever be changed? Possibly, but not until meta-
physics has shaken off the incubus of a perverted epistemology,
the pursuit of which leaves thought in a hopeless tangle; not
until the common-sense view of the world in the form of a
critical realism is made the starting-point of a sincere investigation
of reality.
In examining more closely the warfare of epistemology upon
the common-sense view of reality, a warfare waged for the most
part by the aid of logical subtleties, no claim of unfairness can
certainly be made if the same logical reasons are used in the
defence as are employed in the attack. The history of philosophy
shows that this attack upon the reality of the external world has
proceeded along two main lines, one empirical, the other a priori.
While it is not here the purpose to present all the lines of this
attack in detail, an attempt will be made to select certain repre-
sentative positions of epistemology in this controversy, and ex-
amine their claims to acceptance. And first, the empirical argu-
ments may be for matters of convenience put under three main
categories: (i) Arguments based on the relativity of sense per-
ception; (2) Arguments based on certain phenomena derived
from physical science ; (3) Arguments based on the construction
of the human body, and particularly on the character and ar-