Inference in Fol

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 51

Inference in First-Order Logic

Philipp Koehn

5 March 2024

Philipp Koehn Artificial Intelligence: Inference in First-Order Logic 5 March 2024


A Brief History of Reasoning 1

450B . C. Stoics propositional logic, inference (maybe)


322B . C. Aristotle “syllogisms” (inference rules), quantifiers
1565 Cardano probability theory (propositional logic + uncertainty)
1847 Boole propositional logic (again)
1879 Frege first-order logic
1922 Wittgenstein proof by truth tables
1930 Gödel ∃ complete algorithm for FOL
1930 Herbrand complete algorithm for FOL (reduce to propositional)
1931 Gödel ¬∃ complete algorithm for arithmetic systems
1960 Davis/Putnam “practical” algorithm for propositional logic
1965 Robinson “practical” algorithm for FOL—resolution

Philipp Koehn Artificial Intelligence: Inference in First-Order Logic 5 March 2024


The Story So Far 2

● Propositional logic

● Subset of propositional logic: horn clauses

● Inference algorithms
– forward chaining
– backward chaining
– resolution (for full propositional logic)

● First order logic (FOL)


– variables
– functions
– quantifiers
– etc.

● Today: inference for first order logic

Philipp Koehn Artificial Intelligence: Inference in First-Order Logic 5 March 2024


Outline 3

● Reducing first-order inference to propositional inference

● Unification

● Generalized Modus Ponens

● Forward and backward chaining

● Logic programming

● Resolution

Philipp Koehn Artificial Intelligence: Inference in First-Order Logic 5 March 2024


4

reduction to

propositional inference

Philipp Koehn Artificial Intelligence: Inference in First-Order Logic 5 March 2024


Universal Instantiation 5

● Every instantiation of a universally quantified sentence is entailed by it:

∀v α
S UBST({v/g}, α)

for any variable v and ground term g

● E.g., ∀ x King(x) ∧ Greedy(x) Ô⇒ Evil(x) yields

King(John) ∧ Greedy(John) Ô⇒ Evil(John)


King(Richard) ∧ Greedy(Richard) Ô⇒ Evil(Richard)
King(F ather(John)) ∧ Greedy(F ather(John)) Ô⇒ Evil(F ather(John))

Philipp Koehn Artificial Intelligence: Inference in First-Order Logic 5 March 2024


Existential Instantiation 6

● For any sentence α, variable v, and constant symbol k


that does not appear elsewhere in the knowledge base:
∃v α
S UBST({v/k}, α)

● E.g., ∃ x Crown(x) ∧ OnHead(x, John) yields


Crown(C1) ∧ OnHead(C1, John)
provided C1 is a new constant symbol, called a Skolem constant

Philipp Koehn Artificial Intelligence: Inference in First-Order Logic 5 March 2024


Instantiation 7

● Universal Instantiation
– can be applied several times to add new sentences
– the new KB is logically equivalent to the old

● Existential Instantiation
– can be applied once to replace the existential sentence
– the new KB is not equivalent to the old
– but is satisfiable iff the old KB was satisfiable

Philipp Koehn Artificial Intelligence: Inference in First-Order Logic 5 March 2024


Reduction to Propositional Inference 8

● Suppose the KB contains just the following:


∀ x King(x) ∧ Greedy(x) Ô⇒ Evil(x)
King(John)
Greedy(John)
Brother(Richard, John)

● Instantiating the universal sentence in all possible ways, we have


King(John) ∧ Greedy(John) Ô⇒ Evil(John)
King(Richard) ∧ Greedy(Richard) Ô⇒ Evil(Richard)
King(John)
Greedy(John)
Brother(Richard, John)

● The new KB is propositionalized: proposition symbols are


King(John), Greedy(John), Evil(John), Brother(Richard, John), etc.

Philipp Koehn Artificial Intelligence: Inference in First-Order Logic 5 March 2024


Reduction to Propositional Inference 9

● Claim: a ground sentence is entailed by new KB iff entailed by original KB


● Claim: every FOL KB can be propositionalized so as to preserve entailment
● Idea: propositionalize KB and query, apply resolution, return result
● Problem: with function symbols, there are infinitely many ground terms,
e.g., F ather(F ather(F ather(John)))
● Theorem: Herbrand (1930). If a sentence α is entailed by an FOL KB,
it is entailed by a finite subset of the propositional KB
● Idea: For n = 0 to ∞ do
create a propositional KB by instantiating with depth-n terms
see if α is entailed by this KB
● Problem: works if α is entailed, loops if α is not entailed
● Theorem: Turing (1936), Church (1936), entailment in FOL is semidecidable

Philipp Koehn Artificial Intelligence: Inference in First-Order Logic 5 March 2024


Practical Problems with Propositionalization 10

● Propositionalization seems to generate lots of irrelevant sentences.

● E.g., from ∀ x King(x) ∧ Greedy(x) Ô⇒ Evil(x)


King(John)
∀ y Greedy(y)
Brother(Richard, John)

it seems obvious that Evil(John), but propositionalization produces lots of facts


such as Greedy(Richard) that are irrelevant

● With p k-ary predicates and n constants, there are p ⋅ nk instantiations

● With function symbols, it gets nuch much worse!

Philipp Koehn Artificial Intelligence: Inference in First-Order Logic 5 March 2024


11

unification

Philipp Koehn Artificial Intelligence: Inference in First-Order Logic 5 March 2024


Plan 12

● We have the inference rule


– ∀ x King(x) ∧ Greedy(x) Ô⇒ Evil(x)

● We have facts that (partially) match the precondition


– King(John)
– ∀ y Greedy(y)

● We need to match them up with substitutions: θ = {x/John, y/John} works


– unification
– generalized modus ponens

Philipp Koehn Artificial Intelligence: Inference in First-Order Logic 5 March 2024


Unification 13

● U NIFY(α, β) = θ if αθ = βθ

p q θ
Knows(John, x) Knows(John, Jane)
Knows(John, x) Knows(y, M ary)
Knows(John, x) Knows(y, M other(y))
Knows(John, x) Knows(x, M ary)

Philipp Koehn Artificial Intelligence: Inference in First-Order Logic 5 March 2024


Unification 14

● U NIFY(α, β) = θ if αθ = βθ

p q θ
Knows(John, x) Knows(John, Jane) {x/Jane}
Knows(John, x) Knows(y, M ary)
Knows(John, x) Knows(y, M other(y))
Knows(John, x) Knows(x, M ary)

Philipp Koehn Artificial Intelligence: Inference in First-Order Logic 5 March 2024


Unification 15

● U NIFY(α, β) = θ if αθ = βθ

p q θ
Knows(John, x) Knows(John, Jane) {x/Jane}
Knows(John, x) Knows(y, M ary) {x/M ary, y/John}
Knows(John, x) Knows(y, M other(y))
Knows(John, x) Knows(x, M ary)

Philipp Koehn Artificial Intelligence: Inference in First-Order Logic 5 March 2024


Unification 16

● U NIFY(α, β) = θ if αθ = βθ

p q θ
Knows(John, x) Knows(John, Jane) {x/Jane}
Knows(John, x) Knows(y, M ary) {x/M ary, y/John}
Knows(John, x) Knows(y, M other(y)) {y/John, x/M other(John)}
Knows(John, x) Knows(x, M ary)

Philipp Koehn Artificial Intelligence: Inference in First-Order Logic 5 March 2024


Unification 17

● U NIFY(α, β) = θ if αθ = βθ

p q θ
Knows(John, x) Knows(John, Jane) {x/Jane}
Knows(John, x) Knows(y, M ary) {x/M ary, y/John}
Knows(John, x) Knows(y, M other(y)) {y/John, x/M other(John)}
Knows(John, x) Knows(x, M ary) f ail

● Standardizing apart eliminates overlap of variables, e.g., Knows(z17, M ary)

Knows(John, x) Knows(z17, M ary) {z17/John, x/M ary}

Philipp Koehn Artificial Intelligence: Inference in First-Order Logic 5 March 2024


18

generalized modus ponens

Philipp Koehn Artificial Intelligence: Inference in First-Order Logic 5 March 2024


Generalized Modus Ponens 19

● Generalized modus ponens used with KB of definite clauses


(exactly one positive literal)

● All variables assumed universally quantified

p1′, p2′, . . . , pn′, (p1 ∧ p2 ∧ . . . ∧ pn ⇒ q)


where pi′θ = piθ for all i

● Rule: King(x) ∧ Greedy(x) Ô⇒ Evil(x)


● Precondition of rule: p1 is King(x) p2 is Greedy(x)
● Implication: q is Evil(x)
● Facts: p1′ is King(John) p2′ is Greedy(y)
● Substitution: θ is {x/John, y/John}
⇒ Result of modus ponens: qθ is Evil(John)

Philipp Koehn Artificial Intelligence: Inference in First-Order Logic 5 March 2024


20

forward chaining

Philipp Koehn Artificial Intelligence: Inference in First-Order Logic 5 March 2024


Example Knowledge 21

● The law says that it is a crime for an American to sell weapons to hostile nations.
The country Nono, an enemy of America, has some missiles, and all of its
missiles were sold to it by Colonel West, who is American.

● Prove that Col. West is a criminal

Philipp Koehn Artificial Intelligence: Inference in First-Order Logic 5 March 2024


Example Knowledge Base 22

● . . . it is a crime for an American to sell weapons to hostile nations:


American(x) ∧ W eapon(y) ∧ Sells(x, y, z) ∧ Hostile(z) Ô⇒ Criminal(x)
● Nono . . . has some missiles, i.e., ∃ x Owns(N ono, x) ∧ M issile(x):
Owns(N ono, M1) and M issile(M1)
● . . . all of its missiles were sold to it by Colonel West
M issile(x) ∧ Owns(N ono, x) Ô⇒ Sells(W est, x, N ono)
● Missiles are weapons:
M issile(x) ⇒ W eapon(x)
● An enemy of America counts as “hostile”:
Enemy(x, America) Ô⇒ Hostile(x)
● West, who is American . . .
American(W est)
● The country Nono, an enemy of America . . .
Enemy(N ono, America)

Philipp Koehn Artificial Intelligence: Inference in First-Order Logic 5 March 2024


Forward Chaining Proof 23

Philipp Koehn Artificial Intelligence: Inference in First-Order Logic 5 March 2024


Forward Chaining Proof 24

(Note: ∀ x M issile(x) ∧ Owns(N ono, x) Ô⇒ Sells(W est, x, N ono))

Philipp Koehn Artificial Intelligence: Inference in First-Order Logic 5 March 2024


Forward Chaining Proof 25

(Note: American(x) ∧ W eapon(y) ∧ Sells(x, y, z) ∧ Hostile(z) Ô⇒ Criminal(x))

Philipp Koehn Artificial Intelligence: Inference in First-Order Logic 5 March 2024


Properties of Forward Chaining 26

● Sound and complete for first-order definite clauses


(proof similar to propositional proof)

● Datalog (1977) = first-order definite clauses + no functions (e.g., crime example)


Forward chaining terminates for Datalog in poly iterations: at most p ⋅ nk literals

● May not terminate in general if α is not entailed

● This is unavoidable: entailment with definite clauses is semidecidable

Philipp Koehn Artificial Intelligence: Inference in First-Order Logic 5 March 2024


Efficiency of Forward Chaining 27

● Simple observation: no need to match a rule on iteration k


if a premise wasn’t added on iteration k − 1
Ô⇒ match each rule whose premise contains a newly added literal

● Matching itself can be expensive

● Database indexing allows O(1) retrieval of known facts


e.g., query M issile(x) retrieves M issile(M1)

● Matching conjunctive premises against known facts is NP-hard

● Forward chaining is widely used in deductive databases

Philipp Koehn Artificial Intelligence: Inference in First-Order Logic 5 March 2024


Hard Matching Example 28

Diff(wa, nt) ∧ Diff(wa, sa) ∧


Diff(nt, q)Diff(nt, sa) ∧
Diff(q, nsw) ∧ Diff(q, sa) ∧
Diff(nsw, v) ∧ Diff(nsw, sa) ∧
Diff(v, sa) Ô⇒ Colorable()
Diff(Red, Blue) Diff(Red, Green)
Diff(Green, Red) Diff(Green, Blue)
Diff(Blue, Red) Diff(Blue, Green)

● Colorable() is inferred iff the constraint satisfaction problem has a solution

● CSPs include 3SAT as a special case, hence matching is NP-hard

Philipp Koehn Artificial Intelligence: Inference in First-Order Logic 5 March 2024


Forward Chaining Algorithm 29

function FOL-FC-A SK(KB, α) returns a substitution or false


repeat until new is empty
new ← ∅
for each sentence r in KB do
( p 1 ∧ . . . ∧ p n Ô⇒ q) ← S TANDARDIZE -A PART(r)
for each θ such that (p 1 ∧ . . . ∧ p n)θ = (p ′1 ∧ . . . ∧ p ′n)θ
for some p ′1, . . . , p ′n in KB
q ′ ← S UBST(θ, q)
if q ′ is not a renaming of a sentence already in KB or new then do
add q ′ to new
φ ← U NIFY(q ′, α)
if φ is not fail then return φ
add new to KB
return false

Philipp Koehn Artificial Intelligence: Inference in First-Order Logic 5 March 2024


30

backward chaining

Philipp Koehn Artificial Intelligence: Inference in First-Order Logic 5 March 2024


Backward Chaining 31

● Start with query

● Check if it can be derived by given rules and facts


– apply rules that infer the query
– recurse over pre-conditions

Philipp Koehn Artificial Intelligence: Inference in First-Order Logic 5 March 2024


Backward Chaining Example 32

Philipp Koehn Artificial Intelligence: Inference in First-Order Logic 5 March 2024


Backward Chaining Example 33

Philipp Koehn Artificial Intelligence: Inference in First-Order Logic 5 March 2024


Backward Chaining Example 34

Philipp Koehn Artificial Intelligence: Inference in First-Order Logic 5 March 2024


Backward Chaining Example 35

Philipp Koehn Artificial Intelligence: Inference in First-Order Logic 5 March 2024


Backward Chaining Example 36

Philipp Koehn Artificial Intelligence: Inference in First-Order Logic 5 March 2024


Backward Chaining Example 37

Philipp Koehn Artificial Intelligence: Inference in First-Order Logic 5 March 2024


Backward Chaining Example 38

Philipp Koehn Artificial Intelligence: Inference in First-Order Logic 5 March 2024


Properties of Backward Chaining 39

● Depth-first recursive proof search: space is linear in size of proof

● Incomplete due to infinite loops


Ô⇒ fix by checking current goal against every goal on stack

● Inefficient due to repeated subgoals (both success and failure)


Ô⇒ fix using caching of previous results (extra space!)

● Widely used (without improvements!) for logic programming

Philipp Koehn Artificial Intelligence: Inference in First-Order Logic 5 March 2024


Backward Chaining Algorithm 40

function FOL-BC-A SK(KB, goals, θ) returns a set of substitutions


inputs: KB, a knowledge base
goals, a list of conjuncts forming a query (θ already applied)
θ, the current substitution, initially the empty substitution ∅
local variables: answers, a set of substitutions, initially empty
if goals is empty then return {θ}
q ′ ← S UBST(θ, F IRST(goals))
for each sentence r in KB
where S TANDARDIZE -A PART(r) = ( p 1 ∧ . . . ∧ p n ⇒ q)
and θ′ ← U NIFY(q, q ′) succeeds
new goals ← [ p 1, . . . , p n∣R EST(goals)]
answers ← FOL-BC-A SK(KB, new goals, C OMPOSE(θ′, θ)) ∪ answers
return answers

Philipp Koehn Artificial Intelligence: Inference in First-Order Logic 5 March 2024


41

logic programming

Philipp Koehn Artificial Intelligence: Inference in First-Order Logic 5 March 2024


Logic Programming 42

● Computation as inference on logical KBs


Logic programming Ordinary programming
1. Identify problem Identify problem
2. Assemble information Assemble information
3. Tea break Figure out solution
4. Encode information in KB Program solution
5. Encode problem instance as facts Encode problem instance as data
6. Ask queries Apply program to data
7. Find false facts Debug procedural errors

● Should be easier to debug Capital(N ewY ork, U S) than x ∶= x + 2 !

Philipp Koehn Artificial Intelligence: Inference in First-Order Logic 5 March 2024


Prolog 43

● Basis: backward chaining with Horn clauses + bells & whistles

● Widely used in Europe, Japan (basis of 5th Generation project)

● Compilation techniques ⇒ approaching a billion logical inferences per second

● Program = set of clauses = head :- literal1, . . . literaln.

criminal(X) :- american(X), weapon(Y), sells(X,Y,Z), hostile(Z).


missile(M1).
owns(Nono,M1).
sells(West,X,Nono) :- missile(X), owns(Nono,X).
weapon(X) :- missile(X).
hostile(X) :- enemy(X,America).
American(West).
Enemy(Nono,America).

Philipp Koehn Artificial Intelligence: Inference in First-Order Logic 5 March 2024


Prolog Systems 44

● Depth-first, left-to-right backward chaining

● Built-in predicates for arithmetic etc., e.g., X is Y*Z+3

● Closed-world assumption (“negation as failure”)


e.g., given alive(X) :- not dead(X).
alive(joe) succeeds if dead(joe) fails

Philipp Koehn Artificial Intelligence: Inference in First-Order Logic 5 March 2024


45

resolution

Philipp Koehn Artificial Intelligence: Inference in First-Order Logic 5 March 2024


Resolution: Brief Summary 46

● Full first-order version:

`1 ∨ ⋯ ∨ `k , m1 ∨ ⋯ ∨ m n
(`1 ∨ ⋯ ∨ `i−1 ∨ `i+1 ∨ ⋯ ∨ `k ∨ m1 ∨ ⋯ ∨ mj−1 ∨ mj+1 ∨ ⋯ ∨ mn)θ

where U NIFY(`i, ¬mj ) = θ.

● For example,
¬Rich(x) ∨ U nhappy(x) Rich(Ken)
U nhappy(Ken)
with θ = {x/Ken}

● Apply resolution steps to CN F (KB ∧ ¬α); complete for FOL

Philipp Koehn Artificial Intelligence: Inference in First-Order Logic 5 March 2024


Conversion to CNF 47

Everyone who loves all animals is loved by someone:


∀ x [∀ y Animal(y) Ô⇒ Loves(x, y)] Ô⇒ [∃ y Loves(y, x)]

1. Eliminate biconditionals and implications

∀ x [¬∀ y ¬Animal(y) ∨ Loves(x, y)] ∨ [∃ y Loves(y, x)]

2. Move ¬ inwards: ¬∀ x, p ≡ ∃ x ¬p, ¬∃ x, p ≡ ∀ x ¬p:

∀ x [∃ y ¬(¬Animal(y) ∨ Loves(x, y))] ∨ [∃ y Loves(y, x)]


∀ x [∃ y ¬¬Animal(y) ∧ ¬Loves(x, y)] ∨ [∃ y Loves(y, x)]
∀ x [∃ y Animal(y) ∧ ¬Loves(x, y)] ∨ [∃ y Loves(y, x)]

Philipp Koehn Artificial Intelligence: Inference in First-Order Logic 5 March 2024


Conversion to CNF 48

3. Standardize variables: each quantifier should use a different one


∀ x [∃ y Animal(y) ∧ ¬Loves(x, y)] ∨ [∃ z Loves(z, x)]

4. Skolemize: a more general form of existential instantiation.


Each existential variable is replaced by a Skolem function
of the enclosing universally quantified variables:
∀ x [Animal(F (x)) ∧ ¬Loves(x, F (x))] ∨ Loves(G(x), x)

5. Drop universal quantifiers:


[Animal(F (x)) ∧ ¬Loves(x, F (x))] ∨ Loves(G(x), x)

6. Distribute ∧ over ∨:
[Animal(F (x)) ∨ Loves(G(x), x)] ∧ [¬Loves(x, F (x)) ∨ Loves(G(x), x)]

Philipp Koehn Artificial Intelligence: Inference in First-Order Logic 5 March 2024


Our Previous Example 49

● Rules
– American(x) ∧ W eapon(y) ∧ Sells(x, y, z) ∧ Hostile(z) Ô⇒ Criminal(x)
– M issile(M1) and Owns(N ono, M1)
– M issile(x) ∧ Owns(N ono, x) Ô⇒ Sells(W est, x, N ono)
– M issile(x) ⇒ W eapon(x)
– Enemy(x, America) Ô⇒ Hostile(x)
– American(W est)
– Enemy(N ono, America)
● Converted to CNF
– ¬American(x) ∨ ¬W eapon(y) ∨ ¬Sells(x, y, z) ∨ ¬Hostile(z) ∨ Criminal(x)
– M issile(M1) and Owns(N ono, M1)
– ¬M issile(x) ∨ ¬Owns(N ono, x) ∨ Sells(W est, x, N ono)
– ¬M issile(x) ∨ W eapon(x)
– ¬Enemy(x, America) ∨ Hostile(x)
– American(W est)
– Enemy(N ono, America)
● Query: ¬Criminal(W est)

Philipp Koehn Artificial Intelligence: Inference in First-Order Logic 5 March 2024


Resolution Proof 50

Philipp Koehn Artificial Intelligence: Inference in First-Order Logic 5 March 2024

You might also like