0% found this document useful (0 votes)
18 views5 pages

36 Utilitarianism

The document discusses the moral philosophies of utilitarianism and Kantianism and their application to the fictional scenario of whether Batman should kill the Joker. It provides an overview of utilitarianism, which focuses on producing the greatest happiness for the greatest number of people through our actions. In contrast, Kantian ethics focuses on absolute adherence to moral rules regardless of consequences. The document then analyzes whether Batman's refusal to kill the Joker aligns more with Kantian ethics or a utilitarian perspective given the ongoing harm the Joker causes.
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as DOCX, PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
18 views5 pages

36 Utilitarianism

The document discusses the moral philosophies of utilitarianism and Kantianism and their application to the fictional scenario of whether Batman should kill the Joker. It provides an overview of utilitarianism, which focuses on producing the greatest happiness for the greatest number of people through our actions. In contrast, Kantian ethics focuses on absolute adherence to moral rules regardless of consequences. The document then analyzes whether Batman's refusal to kill the Joker aligns more with Kantian ethics or a utilitarian perspective given the ongoing harm the Joker causes.
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as DOCX, PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 5

Ethics – Br. Angelo Roberto T.

Diana, OMI MBA

Utilitarianism: Crash Course Philosophy #36


Should Batman kill the Joker? If you were to ask the Dark Knight himself, with his hard-and-fast no-killing
rule, he’d say absolutely not. Actually, in fact, he would say: [Batman voice] “Absolutely not.”

When you think about it, dude is pretty Kantian in his ethics. Regardless of what Joker does, there are some
lines that good people do not cross, and for Batman, killing definitely falls on the wrong side of that line.

But, let’s be real here: Joker is never gonna stop killing. Sure, Batman will have him thrown back in Arkham,
but we all know that he’s gonna get out – he always gets out – and once he’s free, he will kill again. And maim
and terrorize. And when he does... won’t a little bit of that be Batman’s fault?

Batman has been in a position to kill Joker hundreds of times. He has had the power to save anyone from ever
being a victim of the Joker again. If you have the ability to stop a killer, and you don’t, are you morally pure
because you didn’t kill? Or are you morally dirty because you refused to do what needs to be done?

[Theme Music]

So, why do I describe Batman as Kantian? Well, the school of thought laid out by 18th century German
philosopher Immanuel Kant – now known as Kantianism – is pretty straightforward. More precisely: It’s
absolute. Kantianism is all about sticking to the moral rule book. There are never any exceptions, or any
excuses, for violating moral rules. And our man Batman tries his hardest to stick to his code, no matter what.

But there are other ways of looking at ethics. Like, instead of focusing on the intent behind our behavior, what
if we paid more attention to the consequences? One moral theory that does this is utilitarianism. It focuses on
the results, or consequences, of our actions, and treats intentions as irrelevant. Good consequences equal good
actions, in this view. So, what’s a good consequence?
Ethics – Br. Angelo Roberto T. Diana, OMI MBA

Modern utilitarianism was founded in the 18th century by British philosophers Jeremy Bentham and John
Stuart Mill, but the theory has philosophical ancestors in ancient Greek thinkers such as Epicurus. All of these
guys agreed that actions should be measured in terms of the happiness, or pleasure, that they produce. After all,
they argued, happiness is our final end – it’s what we do everything else for.

Think about it like this: many things that you do, you do for the sake of something else. You study to get a
good grade. You work to get money. But why do you want good grades, or money? There are different
answers we could give – like maybe we’re seeking affirmation for our intelligence, or the approval of our
parents, or a degree that will give us a career we want. But why do we want that particular career? Why do we
want approval?

We can keep asking questions, but ultimately our answer will bottom out in, “I want what I want because I
think it will make me happy.” That’s what we all want – it’s one of the few things everyone has in common.
And utilitarians believe that’s what should drive our morality. Like Kant, utilitarians agree that a moral theory
should apply equally to everyone. But they thought the way to do that was to ground it in something that’s
really intuitive. And there’s really nothing more basic than the primal desire to seek pleasure and avoid pain.

So, it’s often said that utilitarianism is a hedonistic moral theory – this means the good is equal to the pleasant,
and we ought, morally, to pursue pleasure and happiness, and work to avoid pain. But, utilitarianism is not
what you’d call an egoistic theory. Egoism says that everyone ought, morally, to pursue their own good. In
contrast to that, utilitarianism is other-regarding. It says we should pursue pleasure or happiness – not just for
ourselves, but for as many sentient beings as possible.

To put it formally: “we should act always so as to produce the greatest good for the greatest number.” This is
known as the principle of utility. OK, no one’s gonna argue with a philosophy that tells them to seek pleasure.
But, sometimes doing what provides the most pleasure to the most people can mean that you have to take one
for the team. It can mean sacrificing your pleasure, in order to produce more good overall. Like when it’s your
birthday and your family says you can choose any restaurant you want.
Ethics – Br. Angelo Roberto T. Diana, OMI MBA

The thing that would make you happiest is Thai food, but you know that that would make the rest of your
family miserable. So when you choose Chinese – which is nobody’s favorite, but everybody can make do –
then you’ve thought like a utilitarian. You’ve chosen the action that would produce the most overall happiness
for the group, even though it produced less happiness for you than other alternatives would have.

The problem is, for the most part, we’re all our own biggest fans. We each come pre-loaded with a bias in
favor of our own interests. This isn’t necessarily a bad thing – caring about yourself is a good way to promote
survival. But where morality is concerned, utilitarians argue, as special as you are, you’re no more special than
anybody else. So your interests count, but no more than anyone else’s.

Now, you might say that you agree with that. I mean, we all like to think of ourselves as being generous and
selfless. But, even though I’m sure you are a totally nice person – you have to admit that things seem way
more important – weightier, higher-stakes – when they apply to you, rather than to some stranger. So,
utilitarians suggest that we make our moral decisions from the position of a benevolent, disinterested spectator.

Rather than thinking about what I should do, they suggest that I consider what I would think if I were advising
a group of strangers about what they should do. That way, I have a disposition of good will, but I’m not
emotionally invested. And I’m a spectator, rather than a participant.

This approach is far more likely to yield a fair and unbiased judgment about what’s really best for the group.
Now, to see utilitarianism put to the test, let’s pop over to the Thought Bubble for some Flash Philosophy.

20th century British philosopher Bernard Williams offered this thought experiment: Jim is on a botanical
expedition in South America when he happens upon a group of 20 indigenous people, and a group of soldiers.
The whole group of indigenous people is about to be executed for protesting their oppressive regime. For some
reason, the leader of the soldiers offers Jim the chance to shoot one of the prisoners, since he’s a guest in their
land. He says that if Jim shoots one of the prisoners, he’ll let the other 19 go. But if Jim refuses, then the
soldiers will shoot all 20 protesters. What should Jim do? More importantly, what would you do?

Williams actually presents this case as a critique of utilitarianism. The theory clearly demands that Jim shoot
one man so that 19 will be saved. But, Williams argues, no moral theory ought to demand the taking of an
innocent life. Thinking like a Kantian, Williams argues that it’s not Jim’s fault that the head soldier is a total
Ethics – Br. Angelo Roberto T. Diana, OMI MBA

dirt bag, and Jim shouldn’t have to get literal blood on his hands to try and rectify the situation.

So, although it sounds pretty simple, utilitarianism is a really demanding moral theory. It says, we live in a
world where sometimes people do terrible things. And, if we’re the ones who happen to be there, and we can
do something to make things better, we must. Even if that means getting our hands dirty. And if I sit by and
watch something bad happen when I could have prevented it, my hands are dirty anyway.

So, Jim shouldn’t think about it as killing one man. That man was dead already, because they were all about to
be killed. Instead, Jim should think of his decision as doing what it takes to save 19. And Batman needs to kill
the Joker already.

Thanks, Thought Bubble! Now, if you decide you want to follow utilitarian moral theory, you have options.
Specifically, two of them. When Bentham and Mill first posed their moral theory, it was in a form now known
as Act Utilitarianism, sometimes called classical utilitarianism.

And it says that, in any given situation, you should choose the action that produces the greatest good for the
greatest number. Period. But sometimes, the act that will produce the greatest good for the greatest number can
seem just wrong.

For instance, suppose a surgeon has five patients, all waiting for transplants. One needs a heart, another a lung.
Two are waiting for kidneys and the last needs a liver.

The doctor is pretty sure that these patients will all die before their names come up on the transplant list. And
he just so happens to have a neighbor who has no family. Total recluse. Not even a very nice guy. The doctor
knows that no one would miss this guy if he were to disappear. And by some miracle, the neighbor is a match
for all five of the transplant patients.

So, it seems like, even though this would be a bad day for the neighbor, an act-utilitarian should kill the
neighbor and give his organs to the five patients. It’s the greatest good for the greatest number. Yes, one
innocent person dies, but five innocent people are saved.

This might seem harsh, but remember that pain is pain, regardless of who’s experiencing it. So the death of the
Ethics – Br. Angelo Roberto T. Diana, OMI MBA

neighbor would be no worse than the death of any of those patients dying on the transplant list. In fact, it’s five
times less bad than all five of their deaths.

So thought experiments like this led some utilitarians to come up with another framework for their theory. This
one is called Rule Utilitarianism. This version of the theory says that we ought to live by rules that, in general,
are likely to lead to the greatest good for the greatest number.

So, yes, there are going to be situations where killing an innocent person will lead to the greatest good for the
greatest number. But, rule utilitarians want us to think long-term, and on a larger scale. And overall, a whole
society where innocent people are taken off the streets to be harvested for their organs is gonna have a lot less
utility than one where you don’t have to live in constant fear of that happening to you.

So, rule utilitarianism allows us to refrain from acts that might maximize utility in the short run, and instead
follow rules that will maximize utility for the majority of the time. As an owner of human organs, this
approach might make sense to you. But I still gotta say: If Batman were a utilitarian of either kind, it wouldn’t
look very good for the Joker.

Today we learned about utilitarianism. We studied the principle of utility, and learned about the difference
between act and rule utilitarianism. Next time, we’ll take a look at another moral theory – contractarianism.

Crash Course Philosophy is produced in association with PBS Digital Studios. You can head over to their
channel and check out a playlist of the latest episodes from shows like The Good Stuff, Gross Science, and
PBS Idea Channel. This episode of Crash Course was filmed in the Doctor Cheryl C. Kinney Crash Course
Studio with the help of all of these awesome people and our equally fantastic graphics team is Thought Cafe.

Source: CrashCourse. (November 22, 2016). Utilitarianism: Crash Course Philosophy #36 [Video File]
retrieved from https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=-
a739VjqdSI&list=PL8dPuuaLjXtNgK6MZucdYldNkMybYIHKR&index=37

You might also like