Jurisprudence - Philosophy or Science
Jurisprudence - Philosophy or Science
Jurisprudence - Philosophy or Science
Scholarship Repository
1927
Jurisprudence--Philosophy or Science
Henry Rottschaefer
Recommended Citation
Rottschaefer, Henry, "Jurisprudence--Philosophy or Science" (1927). Minnesota Law Review. 1465.
https://scholarship.law.umn.edu/mlr/1465
This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the University of Minnesota Law School. It has been accepted for inclusion in Minnesota Law
Review collection by an authorized administrator of the Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected].
MINNESOTA
LAW REVIEW
Journal of the State Bar Association
VOLUI%1E 11 MARCH, 1927 No. 4
some of them can be, and have been, dealt with by both meth-
ods. A frandy empirical theory as to the nature of law is not
only conceivable but is actually found in the definitions of such
writers as Gray' and Salmond. 2 Such methods are the very an-
tithesis of attempts to develop the concept of lav by the processes
of abstract reason found in Del Vecchio's Formal Bases of Law
and Tourtoulon's Philosophy in the Development of Law in the
chapter on Scientific or Pure Law 3 It seems, then, that the
classification of the problems under either philosophy or science
will depend upon whether we classify the actual product of juris-
tic thinking or attempt to construct a grouping that slall assign
them to their proper class on the basis of some assumed inherent
nature. The former would possess no special interest for those
whose principal concern is with the problems rather than with the
grouping of particular answers to those problems, the latter
would almost certainly produce a new surge of barren dialectic
with no end' and little purpose. What is needed is a critical ex-
amination of current thinking on these problems in order that we
may discover exactly what we are doing at each stage of their
discussion, whether that discussion be approached from the point
of view of philosophy or science. There is no need for further
general definitions of legal philosophy and legal science, and this
not because those that we already have are adequate but because
those that we are likely to get are quite unlikely to be more so.
There is, however, considerable need for examining and analyz-
ing the steps in our thinking about the problems assigned to
Jurisprudence, not for the purpose of developing a new theory
of knowledge or adapting existing theories to this special case,
but for that of becoming fully aware of the process in the hope
that that may forestall a too assertive dogmatism. The remainder
of the discussion will consider that problem.
The character and function of philosophy have been de-
scribed in terms of varying degrees of inclusiveness and vagueness.
Its orthodox representatives have usually been intent upon unify-
ing and interpreting the totality of phenomena, not for the mere
purpose of a more effective organization of our experience or our
knowledge thereof, but with that of discovering an absolute,
variously conceived. The aim has been to penetrate beyond
phenomenal existence to a realm of essence or being, generally by
'Gray, The Nature and Sources of Law.
2Salmond, Jurisprudence.
aBoth of these have been translated into English as volumes in the
Modem Legal Philosophy Series.
MINNESOTA LAW REVIEW
to the problem of the nature of law was not to outline the con-
cepts thereby developed, its aim was to contrast what its adherents
were professing to do with what they were in fact doing. It is
such contrasts that help us to discover the points at which dog-
matism creeps in in the form of unconsciously adopted asstimp-
tions. There is no doubt that these abstract logical methods for
deriving the concept of law have produced ideas of real value,
and have focussed attention on the point that reflective thinking
can be aided by employing principles not wholly given by expe-
rience. Its error lay in failing to recognize that in so doing we
are making an hypothesis, not discovering an ultimate reality
These thinkers, professing to be discovering an ultimate unchang-
ing reality, were in fact constructing from the data of experience
an instrument for organizing their knowledge thereof, to which
they attributed the former character by assuming that the product
of logical thinking possesses that quality
The illustration just discussed shows clearly the danger of
dogmatism inherent in the failure to analyze completely the proc-
esses of our thinking about juristic problems. That danger arises
not from the fact that we make assumptions, without which in-
deed thinking on any general scale is practically impossible. It
lies rather in the failure to make explicit the fact that we make
them, the particular point in the process at which they occur, and
what they are. It is a failure that has especially serious conse-
quences when dealing with what may be called the normative
problem of legal philbsophy since that raises those evaluative ques-
tions that involve most directly the points of contact between law
and life. A brief statement of what that problem involves may
help in understanding the subsequent discussion of some of its
answers. It is an indubitable fact that the objects and events in
,our experience present themselves to us as having qualities that
we describe as good, bad, just, unjust, and so on. It is probably
impossible to discover the ultimate why of this fact, but the fact
itself has a fundamental importance for the normative problem
of law In so far as it becomes an object of our thinking it pro-
duces judgments of value, i.e., judgments that subsume the par-
ticular events of experience under certain more inclusive and
general categories that may as well be called value-standards as
by any other name such as ends. The statement, for example,
that a law is just is no more than a judgment that it possesses the
characteristics that we have set up as the essentials of the value-
standard called justice. It involves something more than an as-
JURISPRUDENCE. PHILOSOPHY OR SCIENCE
in the sense that they are elements in the intellectual and emotional
experience of men cannot be denied, and it is equally indubitable
that they present themselves for the time being as entitled in their
own right not only to measure the actual but also to exercise over
men that compulsion in the direction of their own actualization
that is expressed in the idea that it is men's duty to realize them.
The question arises whether they are or exist in any other sense.
The answer of those who believe in theories of absolute justice is
clearly that they do, their existence is, in the case of the meta-
physical schools, usually conceived as supra-phenomenal or
rational. Such views are open to the same objections already
mentioned in discussing the various formal theories of law There
is no way of either proving or disproving such theories, since
they involve an assumption that cannot be tested by experience.
There is the same inadequacy in those theories that profess a
more scientific, or at least empirical, basis such as Duguit's theory
of Objective Law 8 There are schools, such as the sociological,
that have never explicitly dealt with this question. The reason
for every attempt to give the value-standard the character of ob-
jective reality is plainly the desire to avoid the instability of
anarchic subjectivism. Those who have attempted to escape this
result have not proved their case, but the plight of those who
have made no attempt whatever is no better Del Vecchio states
that the conception of absolute justice is one of the fundamental
needs of the human mind.9 That may be questioned, but it is cer-
tainly true that man has an inveterate habit of postulating value-
standards that transcend those actully experienced, conceiving
them as those that ought to be realized, and viewing them as at
least not wholly arbitrary The quest for the absolute seems fore-
doomed to failure. Does it follow, however, that the only alter-
native is a complete and arbitrary subjectivism? And if not.
by what process is it to be avoided? These are problems that
will have to be explicitly acknowledged and frankly faced if we
are to make an intelligent appraisal of the competing value-stan-
dards that are offered. That has not yet been done. The result
is a measure of concealed dogmatism in them all. It is not a qlues-
tion of how near we can approach the absolute, but of becoming
consciously aware we are making an assumption when we predi-
cate of something that it ought to be. Every theory of justice or
8See chapters by Duguit in Modern French Legal Philosophy (The
Modern Legal Philosophy Series).
9Del Vecchio, Formal Bases of Law, chapter iii.
JURISPRUDENCE. PHILOSOPHY OR SCIENCE
is not to be construed as implying a theory that the desire for any given
value is derived from reason, instinct and emotion probably play a much
more important part in that activity. The use of the term "rational" is
intended to denote no more than that the desire to give our choices the
appearance of being influenced, even if not completely determined, by
reason is probably the most important factor operative when our experi-
ence'is made an object of intellectual activity. The writer, while recogniz-
MINNESOTA LAW REVIEW
the ideal law of the natural law theorists, it is the value scale of
another such person that is implicit in the theories of sociological
jurisprudence. It is quite natural that this should be so since
those who reflect on such matters at all wish their conduct and
thinking to appear not only reasonable but rational, as the wide-
spread existence of rationalization in its modern sense with its
dubious connotations so strikingly proves.' 3 It represents, more-
over, a sound instinct since it is a device that forces us to make
our critique intelligent and intelligible instead of a mere inarticu-
late process. It remains, however, an hypothesis that appears as
*a premise in our reasoning in this field.
There exists a considerable disparity between the legal value-
standards of the natural law and the sociological jurists. This is
due to the fact that they postulate rational thinking beings that are
somewhat dissimilar; that is, they proceed on the basis of different
hypotheses. I am not now concerned with comparing them, but
with the preliminary question whether there is any way of compar-
ing them that is not itself wholly arbitrary, and, if so, what it is.
In the 5hysical sciences the issue between rival hypothesis is de-
cided by the test of experiment, including therein those less pre-
cise methods of consulting experience that comprise observation.
Resort to that method implies that we can determine the solution
that each of the rival hypotheses would give to the problem that
is the subject of the experiment, and that such solutions are not the
qame for all those being thus tested. This requires that they be
sufficiently definite so that their implications and consequences
can be developed by applying to them an equally definite and
known technique. The question is whether the method is available
in deciding between rival theories of justice or the end of law,
and, if so, in what sense and within what limits. The physical
sciences use it in order to discover whether a suggested generaliza-
tion can be accepted as a basis for making predictions, i.e., as a
practical device for passing from the known to the unknown.
Theories of justice and the end of law are frequently advanced as
answers to the questions, What is Justice, and What is the end of
Law The prevailing generalizations on these matters can scarce-
ly be claimed to help us to predict what will actually happen, al-