Cs103x Notes
Cs103x Notes
Cs103x Notes
Lecture Notes
Vladlen Koltun1
Winter 2008
1
Computer Science Department, 353 Serra Mall, Gates 374, Stanford University, Stanford, CA
94305, USA; [email protected].
Contents
2 Induction 5
2.1 Introducing induction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 5
2.2 Strong induction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 7
2.3 Why is the induction principle true? . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 8
4 Divisibility 15
4.1 The division algorithm . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 15
4.2 Remainders . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 16
4.3 Greatest common divisors . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 17
4.4 Greatest common divisors and linear combinations . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 18
5 Prime Numbers 21
5.1 The fundamental theorem of arithmetic . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 21
5.2 The infinity of primes . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 22
6 Modular Arithmetic 25
6.1 Congruences . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 25
6.2 Modular division . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 27
8 Mathematical Logic 37
8.1 Propositions and predicates . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 37
8.2 Quantifiers . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 37
i
8.3 Negations . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 38
8.4 Logical connectives . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 39
8.5 Tautologies and logical inference . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 41
9 Counting 43
9.1 Fundamental principles . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 43
9.2 Basic counting problems . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 44
10 Binomial Coefficients 49
10.1 Basic properties . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 49
10.2 Binomial theorem . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 50
13 Asymptotic Notation 61
13.1 Definitions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 61
13.2 Examples and properties . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 62
14 Graphs 65
14.1 Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 65
14.2 Common graphs . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 65
14.3 Some important concepts . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 66
14.4 Kinds of graphs . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 67
16 Trees 75
16.1 Basic properties of trees . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 75
16.2 Spanning trees . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 77
17 Planar Graphs 79
17.1 Drawing graphs in the plane . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 79
17.2 Euler’s formula . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 80
17.3 Coloring planar graphs . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 83
17.4 Concluding remarks . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 84
ii
Chapter 1
A set can be defined by simply listing its members inside curly braces. For example,
the set {2, 4, 17, 23} is the same as the set {17, 4, 23, 2}. To denote membership we
use the 2 symbol, as in 4 2 {2, 4, 17, 23}. On the other hand, non-membership is
denoted as in 5 62 {2, 4, 17, 23}.
If we want to specify a long sequence that follows a pattern, we can use the ellipsis
notation, meaning “fill in, using the same pattern”. The ellipsis is often used after two
or more members of the sequence, and before the last one, as follows: {1, 2, . . . , n}.
The pattern denoted by the ellipsis should be apparent at first sight! For instance,
{1, . . . , n} is generally regarded as underspecified (that is, too ambiguous). Of course,
even {1, 2, . . . , n} is still ambiguous—did we mean all integers between 1 and n, all
powers of two up to n, or perhaps the set {1, 2, 25, n}?—but is generally sufficient,
unless you really do mean all powers of two up to n, in which case {20 , 21 , 22 , . . . , 2k }
for an appropriate k is a better choice. The ellipsis can also be used to define an
infinite set, as in the following.
To avoid ambiguities it is often useful to use the set builder notation, which lists
on the right side of the colon the property that any set element, specified on the left
side of the colon, has to satisfy. Let’s define the positive integers using the set builder
notation:
N+ = {x : x 2 N and x > 0}.
1
This is a matter of taste. In general, use the form that will be easiest for the reader
of your work to understand. Often it is the least “cluttered” one.
Ok, now onto the integers:
Z = {x : x 2 N or x 2 N}.
Z = {. . . , 2, 1, 0, 1, 2, . . .}.
Remember, when you write mathematics, you should keep your readers’ perspective
in mind. For now, we—the sta↵ of this course—are your readers. In the future it
might be your colleagues, supervisors, or the readers of your published work. In
addition to being reasonably formal and unambiguous, your mathematical writing
should be as clear and understandable to your intended readership as possible.
Here are the rational numbers:
na o
Q= : a 2 Z, b 2 Z, b 6= 0 .
b
Instead of a 2 Z, b 2 Z, you can write a, b 2 Z, which is more concise and generally
more readable. Don’t go overboard, though, with writing something like a, b 6= 0 2 Z,
this is way too confusing and does not say what you want it to.
Finally, the set of real numbers is denoted by R. All the reals that are not rational
are
p called irrational. These include the familiar ⇡ = 3.1415926..., e = 2.7182818...,
2, and infinitely many others. (How do we know that p these numbers are irrational,
do you ask? Actually, we will see a proof of this for 2 shortly. The proofs for ⇡ and
e require mathematical analysis and are outside our scope.)
On being formal. Were the above definitions formal enough? The answer is: it
depends. For example, defining the natural numbers is an important and non-trivial
accomplishment of mathematics. After all, what do these symbols “1”, “2”, “3”,
actually mean? These numbers can be formally defined in terms of sets. Even more
involved is the formal definition of the reals, usually covered in a first mathematical
analysis course.
Here we cannot a↵ord to cover everything in complete detail, which would have to
include, among other things, basic algebra and trigonometry. Furthermore, the vast
majority of mathematical works, while considered to be “formal”, gloss over details
all the time. For example, you’ll be hard-pressed to find a mathematical paper that
goes through the trouble of justifying the equation a2 b2 = (a b)(a + b). In e↵ect,
every mathematical paper or lecture assumes a shared knowledge base with its readers
or listeners. It is extremely important for an author of mathematics, such as yourself
during this course, to estimate this shared knowledge base correctly!
In CS103X we will assume most of high-school mathematics, including perhaps
some AP math like single-variable calculus, as our shared knowledge base. Thus
notions and techniques from this base will generally not be justified in lecture, and
can be used freely in your homework and exams. Furthermore, once we develop certain
2
notation or prove some theorem in class, you can use these freely in your homework
and exams, provided that you clearly cite the appropriate theorems. In writing and
speaking mathematics, a delicate balance is maintained between being formal and
not getting bogged down in minutia.1 This balance usually becomes second-nature
with experience. You should all get the hang of it by the end of the quarter.
Given a set A, the cardinality of A, also known as the size of A, is simply the number
of elements in A. The cardinality of A is denoted by |A|. For example, if A =
{2, 4, 17, 23}, then |A| = 4.
1
Of course, what is considered minutia di↵ers from subfield to subfield, and from classroom to
classroom.
3
1.3 More sets
The empty set is denoted by ;. It is the unique set without elements. It holds that
; ✓ A for any set A. Why? By definition, this holds if every element of ; is also an
element of A. Since ; has no elements, all possible statements about the elements of
; are true! In particular, all elements of ; are also elements of A. If this is confusing
don’t worry, we will go into such matters more rigorously when we get to logic. (For
now, you can ponder the following: If we know for a fact that there are no unicorns
<Gasp!>, then it is definitely true that all unicorns have soft light-blue fur.)
A set can contain sets as its elements. For example, {{2, 4}, {17}, 23} is a per-
fectly valid set with three elements, two of them sets. (The second element is
a singleton, a set with one element.) Note that {2, 4} 2 {{2, 4}, {17}, 23}, but
{2, 4} ✓ {2, 4, 17, 23}, and that 17 62 {{2, 4}, {17}, 23}, but {17} 2 {{2, 4}, {17}, 23}.
Also, {;} is not the empty set. (Think about it.)
The power set of a set A is the set of all subsets of A, and is denoted by 2A . That
is,
2A = {S : S ✓ A}.
For example, for A = {2, 4, 17, 23}, we have
⇢
A
2 = ;, {2}, {4}, {17}, {23}, {2, 4}, {2, 17}, {2, 23}, {4, 17}, {4, 23}, {17, 23},
{2, 4, 17}, {2, 4, 23}, {2, 17, 23}, {4, 17, 23}, {2, 4, 17, 23} .
The cardinality of this set is 16, and 16 = 24 . This is not a coincidence: As we shall
see when we get to combinatorics and counting, for a set A with n elements, the
cardinality of 2A is 2n . This is in fact the reason for the power set notation.
4
Chapter 2
Induction
• If k 2 A then k + 1 2 A.
Then all positive integers belong to A. (That is, A = N+ .)
Here are two simple proofs that use the induction principle:
Theorem 2.1.1. Every positive integer is either even or odd.
Proof. By definition, we are required to prove that for every n 2 N+ , there exists
some l 2 N, such that either n = 2l or n = 2l + 1. The proof proceeds by induction.
The claim holds for n = 1, since 1 = 2 · 0 + 1. Suppose the claim holds for n = k.
That is, there exists l 2 N, such that k = 2l or k = 2l + 1. We prove that the claim
holds for n = k + 1. Indeed, if k = 2l then k + 1 = 2l + 1, and if k = 2l + 1 then
k + 1 = 2(l + 1). Thus the claim holds for n = k + 1 and the proof by induction is
complete.
Theorem 2.1.2. Every positive integer power of 3 is odd.
5
Proof. By definition, we are required to prove that for every n 2 N+ , it holds that
3n = 2l + 1, for some l 2 N. The proof proceeds by induction. For n = 1, we have
3 = 2 · 1 + 1, so the claim holds. Suppose the claim holds for k, so 3k = 2l + 1, for
some l 2 N. Then
and the claim also holds for k + 1. The proof by induction is complete.
Proof tip: If you don’t know how to get a proof started, look to the definitions,
and state formally and precisely what it is that you need to prove. It might not be
obvious how to prove that “Every positive integer power of 3 is odd”, but a bit easier
to proceed with proving that “for every n 2 N+ , it holds that 3n = 2l + 1, for some
l 2 N.” If you need to prove an implication (that is, a claim of the form “if . . . then
. . .”), then formally state all the assumptions as well as what you need to prove that
they imply. Comparing the two might lead to some insight.
Proof technique: Induction. The induction principle is often used when we are
trying to prove that some claim holds for all positive integers. As the above two proofs
illustrate, when we use induction we do not need to explicitly refer to the set A from
the statement of the induction principle. Generally, this set is the set of numbers for
which the claim that we are trying to prove holds. In the first proof, it was the set of
numbers n that are either even or odd. In the second proof, it was the set of numbers
n for which 3n is odd. Suppose we want to show that some claim holds for all positive
integers. Here is a general template for proving this by induction:
(a) State the method of proof. For example, “The proof proceeds by induction.”
(b) Prove the “induction basis”. That is, prove that the number 1 satisfies the
claim. (This step is often easy, but is crucially important, and should never be
omitted!)
(c) Assume the “induction hypothesis”. That is, state the assumption that the
claim holds for some positive integer k.
(d) Prove, using the induction hypothesis, that the claim holds for k + 1. The proof
should consist of a chain of clear statements, each logically following from the
previous ones combined with our shared knowledge base. The final statement
in the chain should state that the claim holds for k + 1.
(e) Conclude the proof. For example, “This completes the proof by induction.”
n(n + 1)
1 + 2 + ··· + n = .
2
6
1·2
Proof. The proof proceeds by induction. For n = 1, we have 1 = 2
and the claim
holds. Assume 1 + 2 + · · · + k = k(k + 1)/2. Then
S
Sigma and Pi notations. JustP as the symbol can be used to compactly express
the union of many sets, the symbol can be used to express summations. For
example,
Xn X X
1 + 2 + ··· + n = i= i= i.
i=1 1in i2{x : 1xn}
P
You should not assume just because appears that there is an actual
Pn summation,
or that thereP are any summands at all. For example, when n = 1, i=1 i = 1, and
when n 0, ni=1 i = 0 ! Q
Similarly, products can be expressed using the symbol, as in
n
Y
0 1 2 n
2 · 2 · 2 · ... · 2 = 2i .
i=0
1
Y Y
i = i = 1.
i=3 i 2 {2, 4, 10, 14}
i is odd
P Q
A single or symbol can also be used to describe the sum or product over
more than one variable. For example,
X n X
X n
(i + j) = (i + j).
1i,jn i=1 j=1
7
Strong Induction Principle: Given a set A of positive integers, suppose the fol-
lowing hold:
• 1 2 A.
• If {1, 2, . . . , k} ✓ A then k + 1 2 A.
Then all positive integers belong to A.
The versatility of induction. We have seen in the proof of Theorem 2.2.1 that
if we want to prove a statement concerning all positive integers equal to or greater
than 2, we can use induction (or strong induction) with 2 as the base case. This holds
for any positive integer in the place of 2. In fact, induction is an extremely versatile
technique. For example, if we want to prove a property of all even positive integers,
we can use 2 as the base case, and then prove that if the property holds for k, it will
also hold for k + 2. Generally we will just assume that such variations are ok, there
is no need to state a separate induction principle for each of these cases.
Fairly subtle variations of induction are often used. For example, if we can prove
that a statement holds for 1 and 2, and that if it holds for k it will also hold for
k + 2, we can safely conclude that the statement holds for all the positive integers.
However, don’t get carried away with variations that are simply incorrect, like using
1 as a base case, proving that if a statement holds for k then it also holds for k + 2,
and then claiming its validity for all positive integers.
8
illusions: we see, very clearly, what isn’t really there. Our mind plays tricks on us too,
just like our eyes sometimes do. So in mathematics, we are after proving everything.
To be mathematically correct, every statement has to logically follow from previously
known ones. So how do we prove the induction principle?
The answer lies in the previous paragraph. We said that every statement has
to logically follow from other statements that we have proven previously. But this
cannot go on forever, do you see? We have to start from some statements that we
assume to be true. Such statements are called axioms. For example, why is it true
that for any two natural numbers a, b, c, it holds that a+(b+c) = (a+b)+c? Because
we assume it to be so, in order to build up the rest of mathematics from this and a
small number of other such axioms.
This is also what we do with the induction principle: We accept it as an axiom.
And if we accept the induction principle, strong induction can be proved from it, as
you’ll discover in the homework.
9
10
Chapter 3
Proof. We have seen previously that every integer is either even or odd. That is, for
every n 2 Z there exists k 2 Z, such that either n = 2k or n = 2k + 1. Now, if n = 2k
then n2 = (2k)2 = 4k 2 = 2 · (2k 2 ), which means that if n is even then n2 is also even.
On the other hand, if n = 2k +1 then n2 = (2k +1)2 = 4k 2 +4k +1 = 2·(2k 2 +2k)+1,
so if n is odd then n2 is also odd. p
We nowp proceed with a proof by contradiction. Assume that 2 is rational,
that is, 2 2 Q. (This is the assumption that should lead to a contradiction.) By
definition, this means that there exist two numbers p, q 2 Z, with q 6= 0, such that
p p
= 2,
q
and thus ✓ ◆2
p
= 2.
q
We can assume that p and q have no common divisor, since all common divisors can
be divided out to begin with. We have
p2 = 2q 2 .
This shows that p2 is even, and consequently p must be even; that is, p = 2k for some
k 2 Z. Then
p2 = 4k 2 = 2q 2 ,
11
so
2k 2 = q 2 .
This shows that q 2 is even, and consequently that q is even. Thus both p and q are
even, contradicting the fact that p and q have no common divisor. We have reached
a contradiction, which completes the proof.
(b) State the assumption that should lead to the contradiction. For example, “As-
sume statement A does not hold.”
(c) Proceed with a chain of clear statements, each logically following from the
previous ones combined with our shared knowledge base. The final statement
in the chain should be a contradiction, either of itself (as in, 0 6= 0), or of some
previous statement in the chain, or of part of our shared knowledge base.
(d) Conclude the proof. For example, “We have reached a contradiction, which
completes the proof.”
Theorem 3.1.2. log2 3 is irrational.
Proof. The proof proceeds by contradiction. Assume that log2 3 is rational. By
definition, there exist two numbers p, q 2 Z, with q 6= 0, such that
p
log2 3 = ,
q
which means that p
2 q = 3,
and thus
2p = 3q .
We can assume that p, q > 0. (Indeed, if p/q > 0 then we can just work with |p| and
|q|, and if p/q 0 we reach a contradiction of the form 3 = 2p/q 20 = 1.) Now, any
positive integer power of 2 is even, because it has 2 as a divisor, so 2p is even. On the
other hand, a positive integer power of 3 is odd, as we’ve seen previously. We have
reached a contradiction.
12
Consider the following well-known puzzle question. Take the usual 8⇥8 chessboard
and cut out two diagonally opposite corner squares. Can the remaining 62 squares be
tiled by domino-shaped 2⇥1 tiles, each covering two adjacent squares of the board?
(That is, each tile can be placed either horizontally or vertically, so as to precisely
cover two squares of the board.)
Proof. Every tile covers one white square and one black square. Thus in any tiling as
above, the number of white squares covered is the same as the number of black ones.
The two removed squares have the same color, hence the number of white squares left
on the board is not the same as the number of black ones. So the remaining squares
cannot be tiled.
The above proof can also be phrased as a proof by contradiction, or even in terms
of induction. However, even though such a phrasing might appear more formal, it is
rather unnecessary, as the above proof is already logically sound (which is critical!),
and better conveys the power (and dare I say, the beauty) of the argument.
Proof Technique: Direct proof. Here is a common template for direct proofs:
(a) Provide a chain of clear statements, each logically following from our shared
knowledge base and the previous ones. The final statement in the chain should
be the claim we need to prove.
(b) (Optional.) Conclude the proof. For example, “This completes the proof.”
13
14
Chapter 4
Divisibility
Theorem 4.1.1. If a and b are integers and b 6= 0, then there is a unique pair of
integers q and r, such that a = qb + r and 0 r < |b|.
Proof. We need to prove two things: that there is some such pair q, r (existence) and
that this pair is unique (uniqueness).
Let’s begin with existence. First we show that there is a pair q, r 2 Z that satisfies
a = qb + r for some r 0. This is easy after some playing around: Take q = |ab|/b
and r = a + |ab|. Since |b| 1, it holds that r 0. Now we need to show that such
q, r 2 Z exist with r in addition being smaller than |b|. For this, consider the set
S of all r 2 N that satisfy a = qb + r for some q 2 Z. We’ve just shown that S is
nonempty, so it must have a smallest element, call it r0 . We have a = q0 b + r0 . If
r0 < |b| we’re done. Otherwise, we have a = (q0 b + |b|) + (r0 |b|), which means that
r0 |b| is a smaller element of S than r0 , leading to a contradiction. This completes
the existence proof.
To prove uniqueness, suppose that a = qb + r = sb + t, with 0 r, t < |b|. Thus
(q s)b + (r t) = 0. Since 0 r, t < |b|, we have |r t| < |b|, hence |(q s)b| < |b|
and |q s| < 1. Since q and s are integers, this implies q = s. From this we have
r = t and the uniqueness proof is complete.
Proof tip: When we need to prove that some mathematical object exists and is
unique, it is useful to approach in two stages. First prove that at least one such object
exists. This can be done either by directly constructing an object and demonstrating
15
that it fulfills the requirements, or by assuming that no such object exists and reaching
a contradiction. Then show that any two such objects must be the same.
4.2 Remainders
A more algorithmic view of Theorem 4.1.1 is as follows: If we divide the equation
a = qb + r
by b we get
a r
=q+ .
b b
⌅ ⇧
Since 0 r < |b|, we get that if b > 0, then 0 rb < 1 and thus q = ab , the ⌃greatest
⌥
integer less than or equal to ab . If b < 0, then 0 r
b
> 1 and thus q = ab , the
least integer greater or equal to ab . This can be used to calculate q, from which we
can derive r.
In Theorem 4.1.1, we call q the quotient and r the remainder. We use the notation
r = a rem b to denote that r is the remainder when a is divided⌅ a ⇧ by ⌃b.a ⌥There is no
need for a special notation for quotient, since we can just use b and b , depending
on the sign of b.
16
(b) If b|a and a 6= 0 then |b| |a|.
(a) Since b|a, there exists an integer q, such that a = qb. Similarly, there exists an
integer r, such that b = rc. Thus a = qb = qrc. Since qr is an integer, it holds
that c|a.
(b) Since b|a, there exists an integer q, such that a = qb. This implies |a| = |q| · |b|.
Assume for the sake of contradiction that a 6= 0 but |b| > |a|. Then |q| · |b| < |b|.
Since |b| > |a| > 0, we can divide by |b| to get |q| < 1, implying q = 0. Thus
a = qb = 0, which is a contradiction.
P
(c) Consider a linear combination u = ni=1 ci ai . Since b|ai , there exists an integer
qi , such that ai = qi b, for all 1 i n. Thus
n
X n
X n
X
u= c i ai = c i qi b = b · c i qi .
i=1 i=1 i=1
Pn
Since i=1 ci qi is an integer, we have b|u.
(d) For the “if” statement, note that if a = ±b then b = qa and a = qb, for q = ±1,
so a|b and b|a. To prove the “only if” statement, assume that a|b and b|a. This
implies the existence of integers q and r, such that b = qa and a = rb. Thus
b = qrb. If b = 0 then a = 0 and the claim that a = ±b holds. Otherwise we
can divide by b to get qr = 1. Note that in this case q, r 6= 0. Part (b) of the
theorem implies that |q| 1 and |r| 1. Thus q, r = ±1 and the claim that
a = ±b follows.
Proof tip: Often we need to prove that a proposition A holds if and only if some
other proposition B holds. Such an “if and only if” (sometimes abbreviated as “i↵”)
statement is really composed of two implications, each of which needs to be proved.
It is often useful to decouple these and prove them separately. First prove that “If A
then B,” and then prove that “If B then A.” Another strategy is to prove that “If A
then B” and “If not A then not B.”
17
common divisor of a and b is not greater than max(|a|, |b|). Thus the set of common
divisors of a and b has a largest element, called the greatest common divisor of a and
b, or gcd(a, b). This is the integer d that satisfies the following two criteria:
Note that when a = b = 0, there is no greatest common divisor, since any integer
divides 0. When a and b are not both 0, we often want to compute gcd(a, b) efficiently.
Note that the set of divisors of a and a is the same, and similarly for b and b.
Furthermore, if a = 0 then gcd(a, b) = b, and if a = b then gcd(a, b) = a = b. Thus it
suffices to concentrate on the case a > b > 0, without loss of generality.
Since 1 gcd(a, b) b, we can just test all integers between 1 and b and choose
the largest one that divides both a and b. However, there is a much more efficient
way to find greatest common divisors, called Euclid’s algorithm. This algorithm, one
of the earliest in recorded history, is based on the following lemma.
Proof. By Theorem 4.2.1(c), all common divisors of b and r also divide a, since a is
a linear combination of b and r. Thus a common divisor of b and r is also a common
divisor of a and b. Similarly, since r = a qb, a common divisor of a and b also
divides r, so it is a common divisor of b and r. Thus a, b and b, r have the same set
of common divisors, and in particular the same greatest common divisor.
With this lemma in our toolbelt, Euclid’s algorithm is easy to describe. To find
gcd(a, b), use the division algorithm (Theorem 4.1.1) to represent a = qb + r, where
0 r < b. (Remember that we are assuming that a > b > 0.) If r = 0 then b|a and
gcd(a, b) = b. Otherwise gcd(a, b) = gcd(b, r) and b > r > 0. We can thus repeat the
above procedure recursively with the pair b, r. Every recursive call strictly reduces
both numbers in the pair, so after at most b steps the algorithm will terminate with
a valid greatest common divisor of a and b. You will formally prove the correctness
of the algorithm in the homework.
Theorem 4.4.1. For two integers a and b that are not both 0, gcd(a, b) is a linear
combination of a and b.
18
Proof. As above, we can concentrate on the case a > b > 0. The proof proceeds by
strong induction on the value of a. In the base case, a = 2, b = 1, and gcd(a, b) =
1 = 0 · a + 1 · b. Assume that the theorem holds for all pairs a, b with 0 < b < a k.
Consider a pair a0 , b0 with 0 < b0 < a0 = k + 1. If b0 |a0 then gcd(a0 , b0 ) = b0 and the
theorem trivially holds. Otherwise use the division algorithm to express a0 = qb0 + r,
where 0 < r < b0 . By the induction hypothesis, there exist coefficients u and v, such
that gcd(b0 , r) = ub0 + vr. Lemma 4.3.1 shows that gcd(a0 , b0 ) = gcd(b0 , r), therefore
gcd(a0 , b0 ) = ub0 + vr = ub0 + v(a0 qb0 ) = va0 + (u vq)b0 . This shows that gcd(a0 , b0 )
is a linear combination of a0 and b0 and completes the proof by induction.
Bezout’s identity implies that the set of linear combinations of a and b is the same
as the set of multiples of their greatest common divisor (!):
Proof. By Theorem 4.2.1(c), since gcd(a, b) divides both a and b, it divides any linear
combination z of a and b, and thus z is a multiple of gcd(a, b). On the other hand, we
know by Bezout’s identity that there are coefficients u and v, such that gcd(a, b) =
ua + vb, so if z = c · gcd(a, b), then z = c(ua + vb) = (cu)a + (cu)v.
19
20
Chapter 5
Prime Numbers
2, 3, 5, 7, 11, 13, 17, 19, 23, 29, 31, 37, 41, 43, 47, 53, 59, 61, 67, 71, 73, 79, 83, 89, 97.
(b) The proof proceeds by induction. The case k = 1 is trivial and k = 2 is handled
in part (a). So we assume that the claim
Qk+1 holds for some kQ> 1 and prove that it
k
also holds for k + 1. Given that p| i=1 ai , we put b = i=1 ai . Since p|bak+1 ,
part (a) implies that either p|ak+1 or p|b. In both cases the claim holds, in the
latter case by the induction hypothesis. This completes the proof by induction.
21
Theorem 5.1.1 can be used to derive a fundamental theorem of number theory. It
is so fundamental it has “fundamental” in its name.
Theorem 5.1.2 (Fundamental Theorem of Arithmetic). Every positive integer can
be represented in a unique way as a product of primes,
n = p1 p2 · · · pk (p1 p2 . . . pk ).
Proof. We first prove existence and then uniqueness. Actually, we already proved
existence in one of the previous lectures as an illustration of strong induction, but
give the prove here again for completeness. So, to prove that every integer can be
represented as a product of primes we use strong induction. The base case n = 1
holds because the empty product, as we previously discussed, is defined to equal 1.
The induction hypothesis assumes that for some n > 1, all positive integers k < n
can be represented as a product of primes. If n is prime, then it is trivially a product
of primes. Otherwise it can be written as n = ab, for 1 < a, b < n. By the induction
hypothesis, both a and b are products of primes, so their product n is also a product
of primes. This proves existence.
The proof that the above representation is unique proceeds by contradiction. As-
sume then that there exists some positive integer that can be represented as a product
of primes in (at least) two ways. By the well-ordering principle, there is a smallest
such integer n. It holds that n = p1 p2 · · · pk = q1 q2 · · · ql , where p1 p2 . . . pk ,
q1 q2 . . . ql , and pi 6= qi for some i. By Theorem 5.1.1(b), since pi |q1 q2 · · · ql ,
there must exist some qj for which pi |qj . Since qj is prime and pi > 1, this can
only occur when pi = qj . Thus we can eliminate pi and qj from the equation
p1 p2 · · · pk = q1 q2 · · · ql and get two distinct representations of the positive integer
number n/pi as a product of primes. This contradicts the assumption that n is the
smallest positive integer with this property, and concludes the proof of uniqueness.
p = p1 p2 . . . pn + 1.
22
n 1
Theorem 5.2.2. The n-th prime pn satisfies pn 22 for all n 1.
0
Proof. We proceed using strong induction. For the base case, the first prime is 2 = 22 .
Assume that the claim holds for all primes p1 through pk . Consider p = p1 p2 . . . pk +1.
As in the above proof, p has a prime factor that is not one of the first k primes. This
prime factor is thus at least as large as pk+1 , which implies
0 1 k 1
pk+1 p = p1 p2 . . . pk + 1 22 22 · · · 22 +1
1+2+4+...+2k 1
= 2 +1
k
= 22 1 + 1
1 2k
= 2 +1
2
k
22 .
This is precisely the induction step we needed, and concludes the proof by strong
induction.
Denote by ⇡(x) the number of primes p x.
Proof. Plugging n = blog log xc + 1 into Theorem 5.2.2 implies that the n-th prime
is at most x. Thus there are at least n primes below x.
For general education, you should know that this is by far not the best possible
estimate. A celebrated achievement in number theory is the Prime Number Theorem
due to Hadamard and de la Vallée Poussin, which states that x/ ln x (here we use the
natural logarithm) is the “right” bound, in the sense that
⇡(x)
lim ! 1.
x!1 x/ ln x
23
24
Chapter 6
Modular Arithmetic
6.1 Congruences
We usually associate arithmetic with the infinite set of integer numbers. However,
modular arithmetic on finite sets is commonly used in our daily life. As an example,
if it is now 1 am and we let 1000 hours pass, what time will it be? We can use the
division algorithm to see that 1000 = 41 ⇥ 24 + 16 and conclude that adding 1000
hours is like adding 16 hours, since the clock returns to the same position every 24
hours. So after 1000 hours it will be 5 pm (17 hours after midnight).
There are many examples in which it is natural and useful to limit our number
system to a finite range of integers, such as 0 through n 1, for some n. This number
system is denoted by Zn . Days of the week, hours of the day, minutes in an hour
are all familiar examples of finite number systems, as are numbers in microprocessor
registers, commonly limited to 32 binary digits.
Modular arithmetic allows us to add, subtract, multiply, and sometimes divide
numbers while staying within the finite set Zn . The number n is called the modulus.
A central notion in modular arithmetic is congruence. We say that two integers are
congruent modulo n if they leave the same remainder when divided by n. Here is the
formal definition:
25
that a = q1 n + r1 and b = q2 n + r2 . Thus (q1 q2 )n + (r1 r2 ) = nd, and r1 r2 =
(q2 q1 + d)n. Thus n|(r1 r2 ). However, |r1 r2 | < n, so necessarily r1 r2 = 0,
which implies that a rem n = b rem n, and a ⌘n b.
You should use the definition to verify that for any a, b, c 2 Z,
• a ⌘n a. (Reflexivity.)
• If a ⌘n b then b ⌘n a. (Symmetry.)
a +n b = (a + b) rem n
a n b = (a b) rem n
a ·n b = (ab) rem n
(b) (a rem n) ⌘n a
(f ) If a1 ⌘n a2 and b1 ⌘n b2 then
a1 + b1 ⌘n a2 + b2
a1 b1 ⌘n a2 b2
a1 b1 ⌘n a2 b2
Proof. (b) is just a restatement of (a). To prove these we need to show that n|(a
(a rem n)). Put r = a rem n. By the division algorithm, there exists q 2 Z, such that
a = qn + r. Thus a r = qn, which implies that n|a r and concludes the proof.
(d) is a restatement of (c), and (e) can be proved from (d) by induction. To prove
(c) we need to show that n|(ab (a rem n)(b rem n)). Use the division algorithm to
represent a = q1 n + r1 and b = q2 n + r2 . Then
26
which implies the claim.
We now prove (f). We know that n|(a1 a2 ) and n|(b1 b2 ). That is, there exist
integers q and s, such that a1 a2 = qn and b1 b2 = sn. Adding these equations gives
(a1 + b1 ) (a2 + b2 ) = (q + s)n, which yields the first part of the claim. Subtracting
similarly gives the second part. Writing a1 = a2 +qn and b1 = b2 +sn and multiplying
the equations gives
a1 b1 = a2 b2 + b2 qn + a2 sn + qsn2
a1 b 1 a2 b2 = (b2 q + a2 s + qsn)n,
which yields the third part.
27
• For every a 2 S there exists an additive inverse a 2 S for which a + ( a) = 0.
All the number systems we have encountered so far are rings, including Z, Q, R,
and Zn . However, some of them possess additional structure that allows the division
operation. Namely, a ring is said to be a field if, in addition to the above, the following
holds
1
• For every a 2 S, such that a 6= 0, there exists a multiplicative inverse a 2S
for which a · a 1 = 1.
The number systems R and Q, as well as Zp when p is prime, are fields. In fields
the division operation is well-defined, and b/a = b · a 1 , as can be verified by plugging
x = b · a 1 into the equation ax = b. A field with a finite number of elements is called
a Galois field, after the French mathematician Evariste Galois. (A feisty young man
who died in a duel at the age of 20, after making significant enough contributions
to mathematics to have a whole field (sic) named in his honor!) Anyway, now that
we know what fields are, let’s see why Zp is one. In fact, we prove something more
general:
Theorem 6.2.1. If a and n are coprime then there exists exactly one x 2 Zn for
which ax ⌘n b, for any b 2 Z.
Corollary 6.2.2. For a prime p and any a, b 2 Z, such that a 6⌘p 0, there exists
exactly one x 2 Zp for which ax ⌘p b.
The fact that division is well-defined in Zp when p is prime also means that
cancelations become valid. Thus if a 6⌘p 0 and ab ⌘p ac we can safely conclude that
b ⌘p c.
We now know that b/a is well-defined in Zp , but how do we find it? That is, how
do we find x 2 Zp , for which ax ⌘p b. This question is particularly important when p
is large and it takes too long to simply enumerate all the elements of Zp . Fortunately,
the following result, known as Fermat’s Little Theorem, can help us:
ap 1
⌘p 1.
28
However, each element of S is congruent to some element of Zp . Since there are p 1
elements in S and p 1 nonzero elements in Zp , the elements of S must be congruent
to each of 1, 2, . . . , (p 1) in some order. Therefore,
1 · 2 · · · · · (p 1) ⌘p 1a · 2a · · · · · (p 1)a,
or
1 · 2 · · · · · (p 1) ⌘p 1 · 2 · · · · · (p 1) · ap 1 .
We can cancel each of 1, 2, . . . , (p 1) from both sides of the congruence, obtaining
ap 1 ⌘p 1.
Fermat’s Little Theorem allows us to quickly perform division in Zp . The element
x 2 Zp for which ax ⌘p b is simply (ap 2 b rem p).
29
30
Chapter 7
This notion can be extended naturally to define an ordered n-tuple as the ordered
counterpart of a set with n elements.
Give two sets A and B, their cartesian product A ⇥ B is the set of all ordered pairs
(x, y), such that x 2 A and y 2 B:
A ⇥ B = {(x, y) : x 2 A, y 2 B}.
A2 = A ⇥ A = {(x, y) : x, y 2 A}.
An = (x1 , x2 , . . . , xn ) : x1 , x2 , . . . , xn 2 A .
For example, R2 is the familiar cartesian plane, and Rn is often referred to as the
n-dimensional Euclidean space. If we omit the parentheses and the commas, {a, b}4
is comprised of child babble and a 70s pop band:
{aaaa, baba, abab, baaa, baab, aaab, aaba, abaa, abba, bbaa, bbba, bbbb, aabb, abbb, babb, bbab}.
Proposition 7.1.1. (A [ B) ⇥ C = (A ⇥ C) [ (B ⇥ C)
Proof. Recall that for two sets X and Y , X = Y if and only if X ✓ Y and Y ✓ X.
Consider any element (u, v) 2 (A [ B) ⇥ C. By definition, u 2 A [ B and v 2 C.
Thus, u 2 A or u 2 B. If u 2 A then (u, v) 2 A ⇥ C and if u 2 B then (u, v) 2 B ⇥ C.
31
Thus (u, v) is in A ⇥ C or in B ⇥ C, and (u, v) 2 (A ⇥ C) [ (B ⇥ C). This proves
that (A [ B) ⇥ C ✓ (A ⇥ C) [ (B ⇥ C).
Now consider any element (u, v) 2 (A ⇥ C) [ (B ⇥ C). This implies that (u, v) 2
A ⇥ C or (u, v) 2 B ⇥ C. In the first case u 2 A and v 2 C and in the second case
u 2 B and v 2 C. Thus u 2 A [ B and v 2 C, which implies (u, v) 2 (A [ B) ⇥ C.
7.2 Relations
Given a set A, a relation on A is some property that is either true or false for any
ordered pair (x, y) 2 A2 . For example, “greater than” is a relation on Z, denoted
by >. It is true for the pair (3, 2), but false for the pairs (2, 2) and (2, 3). In more
generality,
Definition 7.2.1. Given sets A and B, a relation between A and B is a subset of
A ⇥ B.
By this definition, a relation R is simply a specification of which pairs are related
by R, that is, which pairs the relation R is true for. For the relation > on the set
{1, 2, 3},
> = {(2, 1), (3, 1), (3, 2)}.
This notation might look weird because we do not often regard the symbol “>” as a
meaningful entity in itself. It is, at least from the vantage point of the foundations of
mathematics: This symbol is a particular relation.
The common usage of the symbol “>” (as in 3 > 2) is an instance of a useful
notational convention: For a relation R, (a, b) 2 R can also be specified as aRb.
Thus, in the above example, (2, 1) 2 > can be written as 2 > 1. How convenient!
Common mathematical relations that will concern us include <, >, , , =,
6=, |, ⌘n , ⇢, ✓, etc. For example, the relation = on the set Z is precisely the set
{(n, n) : n 2 Z} and the relation on R is the set {(x, x + |y|) : x, y 2 R}.
The concept of a relation is as general as the concept of a set, and is not limited to
strictly mathematical settings. For instance, we can define the relation likes between
the set {Anna,Britney,Caitlyn} and the set {Austin,Brian,Carlos}, such that
likes = (Britney,Austin),(Caitlyn,Austin),(Britney, Carlos),(Anna,Austin),(Caitlyn,Brian) .
In this setting we can write Britney likes Austin.
32
Equivalence relations. A relation that is reflexive, symmetric, and transitive is
called an equivalence relation. Clearly, the common relation = on the set R, say, is an
equivalence relation. Also, we have seen earlier that the congruence relation ⌘n on
the set Z is reflexive, symmetric, and transitive, thus it is also an equivalence relation.
The similarity relation on the set of triangles in the plane is another example.
Equivalence relations are special in that they naturally partition the underlying
set into equivalence classes. For example, the relation ⌘2 partitions the integers into
even and odd ones. These are, respectively, the integers that are related (by ⌘2 ) to
0, and the ones related to 1. Let’s formalize these concepts.
Definition 7.3.1. A partition of a set A is a set X ✓ 2A \ {;}, such that
(a) Each a 2 A belongs to some S 2 X .
(b) If S, T 2 X , either S = T or S \ T = ;.
Stated di↵erently, this definition says that the set A is the union of the members
of X , and these members are disjoint. Now, given an equivalence relation R on A,
the equivalence class of a 2 A is defined as
R[a] = {b 2 A : aRb}.
Theorem 7.3.2. Let R be an equivalence relation on a set A. Then {R[a] : a 2 A}
is a partition of A.
Proof. Consider an equivalence relation R on A. Due to reflexivity, every element
a 2 A belongs to R[a], which implies (a). Now, consider two equivalence classes
R[a] and R[b]. If aRb, then for any c 2 R[a], by transitivity and symmetry, bRc and
c 2 R[b]. This shows R[a] ✓ R[b]. We can symmetrically argue that R[b] ✓ R[a],
which together implies R[a] = R[b].
/ then consider some c 2 R[a]. If c 2 R[b] then aRc and bRc,
Otherwise, if aRb
which imply, by transitivity and reflexivity, aRb, leading to a contradiction. Thus no
element of R[a] belongs to R[b] and R[a] \ R[b] = ;. This shows (b) and concludes
the theorem.
33
• For all a, b, c 2 A, aRb and bRc implies aRc. (Transitivity.)
• Given a, b 2 A, exactly one of the following holds (and not the other two): aRb,
bRa, a = b.
The familiar < and > relations (on R, say) are examples of strict orders.
R|S = (a, b) 2 R : a, b 2 S .
(a) T is transitive.
(b) T is the smallest transitive relation that contains R. (That is, if U is a transitive
relation on A and R ✓ U , then T ✓ U .)
34
7.5 Functions
The general concept of a function in mathematics is defined very similarly to relations.
In fact, as far as the definitions go, functions are relations, of a special type:
A function is sometimes called a map or mapping. The set A in the above definition
is the domain and B is the codomain of f .
A function f : A ! B is e↵ectively a special kind of relation between A and B,
which relates every x 2 A to exactly one element of B. That element is denoted by
f (x).
If the above definition is followed rigidly, particular functions should be defined
by specifying all the pairs (x, f (x)). This is often cumbersome and unnecessary, and
we will mostly continue describing a function from A to B as we did before: as a rule
for picking an element f (x) 2 B for every element x 2 A. As in, “Consider a function
f : R ! R, where f (x) = x2 for all x 2 R.”
35
Another result that is sometimes used is the following: If f : A ! B and g : B !
C are bijections then g f : A ! C is a bijection, and
1 1
(g f ) =f g 1.
Bijections and cardinality. Bijections allow us to rigorously define when two sets
are of the same cardinality:
Definition 7.5.2. Two sets A and B have the same number of elements if and only
if there exists a bijection f : A ! B.
36
Chapter 8
Mathematical Logic
8.2 Quantifiers
Given a predicate P (x) that is defined for all elements in a set A, we can reason about
whether P (x) is true for all x 2 A, or if it’s at least true for some x 2 A. We can
state propositions to this e↵ect using the universal quantifier 8 and the existential
quantifier 9.
• 8x 2 A : P (x) is true if and only if P (x) is true for all x 2 A. This proposition
can be read “For all x 2 A, P (x).”
37
• 9x 2 A : P (x) is true if and only if P (x) is true for at least one x 2 A. This
proposition can be read “There exists x 2 A such that P (x).”
Given a predicate in more than one variable we can quantify each (or some) of
the variables. For example, the statement “For every real x and y, it holds that
x2 y 2 = (x y)(x + y)” can be formalized as
8.3 Negations
Given a proposition P , the negation of P is the proposition “P is false”. It is true if
P is false, and false if P is true. The negation of P is denoted by ¬P , read as “not
P .” If we know the meaning of P , such as when P stands for “It will rain tomorrow,”
the proposition ¬P can be stated more naturally than “not P ,” as in “It will not rain
tomorrow.” The truth-value of ¬P can be represented by the following truth table:
P ¬P
true false
false true
A truth table simply lists the truth values of particular statements in all possible
cases. Something interesting can be observed in we consider the truth values of ¬¬Q,
which can be obtained by using the above table once with P = Q and once with
P = ¬Q:
Q ¬Q ¬¬Q
true false true
false true false
38
We see that the statements Q and ¬¬Q have the same truth values. In this case
we say that the two statements are equivalent, and write Q , ¬¬Q. If A , B we
can freely use B in the place of A, or A instead of B in our logical derivations.
Negation gets really interesting when the negated proposition is quantified. Then
we can assert that
These can be interpreted as the claim that if P (x) is not true for all x 2 A then it
is false for some x 2 A and vice versa, and the claim that if P (x) is not false for any
x 2 A then it is true for all x 2 A and vice versa. What this means, in particular,
is that if we want to disprove a statement that asserts something for all x 2 A, it is
sufficient to demonstrate one such x for which the statement does not hold. On the
other hand, if we need to disprove a statement that asserts the existence of an x 2 A
with a certain property, we actually need to show that for all such x this property
does not hold.
Looked at another way, the above equivalences imply that if we negate a quantified
statement, the negation can be “pushed” all the way inside, so that no negated
quantifiers are left. Indeed, leaving any negated quantifiers is often considered a
mark of poor style. Here is how how this elimination is done in a particular example:
¬8n 2 Z 9m 2 Z : m > n ,
9n 2 Z ¬9m 2 Z : m > n ,
9n 2 Z 8m 2 Z : m n
This can be read as “There exists an integer that is greater or equal to any other
integer,” which is the proper negation of the original statement.
39
P Q P ^Q P _Q P Q P !Q P $Q
T T T T F T T
T F F T T F F
F T F T T T F
F F F F F T T
P is false, then P ! Q is true. One way this can be justified is by remembering that
we expect a proposition to be either false or true. Now, P ! Q being false says that
P does not imply Q, which means precisely that P is true but Q is still false. In all
other cases we expect P ! Q to be true. (Did I succeed in turning something obvious
into a confusing mess? Well, we all know what is paved with good intentions...)
Now, there is another statement involving P and Q that is false precisely when
P is true and Q is false. It is, of course, ¬P _ Q. As the following truth table
demonstrates, the proposition ¬P _ Q is equivalent to P ! Q:
P Q P ! Q ¬P _ Q
T T T T
T F F F
F T T T
F F T T
This means something rather interesting: We can replace a proposition that in-
volves implication by an equivalent one that instead has negation (¬) and disjunction
(_). Also, since P ! Q is false only when P is true and Q is false, the proposition
¬(P ! Q) is equivalent to P ^ ¬Q:
¬(P ! Q) , P ^ ¬Q.
This means that in a negated implication, the negation can be “pushed inside”,
somewhat like with quantifiers. In fact, similar equivalences exist for other negated
compound statements, as can be verified using truth tables (do it!):
¬(P _ Q) , ¬P ^ ¬Q
¬(P ^ Q) , ¬P _ ¬Q
These are the famous DeMorgan’s laws. What they mean is that we can eliminate
negated compounds (sounds like a military operation, doesn’t it?) just as we can
eliminate negated quantifiers.
Here is another important logical equivalence: The implication P ! Q is equiva-
lent to the contrapositive implication ¬Q ! ¬P :
(P ! Q) , (¬Q ! ¬P ).
This is demonstrated by the following truth table:
40
P Q P ! Q ¬Q ¬P ¬Q ! ¬P
T T T F F T
T F F T F F
F T T F T T
F F T T T T
P ¬P P _ ¬P P ^ ¬P
T F T F
F T T F
Note that by our definition of logical equivalence, all tautologies are equivalent.
It is sometimes useful to keep a “special” proposition T that is always true, and a
proposition F that is always false. Thus any tautology is equivalent to T and any
contradiction is equivalent to F.
Here is another tautology: (P ^ Q) ! P :
P Q P ^ Q (P ^ Q) ! P
T T T T
T F F T
F T F T
F F F T
41
In general, any tautology of the form A ! B can be used to “manufacture” the
inference rule A ) B that says that if we know A we can conclude B. Similarly,
a tautology of the form A $ B can be converted into the equivalence A , B,
which can be regarded as two inference rules, A ) B and B ) A. A particularly
important inference rule is called modus ponens, and says that if we know that P and
P ! Q are both true, we can conclude that Q is true. It follows from the tautology
(P ^ (P ! Q)) ! Q:
P Q P ! Q P ^ (P ! Q) (P ^ (P ! Q)) ! Q
T T T T T
T F F F T
F T T F T
F F T F T
(¬P ! F) , P
(P $ Q) , (P ! Q) ^ (Q ! P )
(P $ Q) , (P ! Q) ^ (¬P ! ¬Q)
These three rules are of particular importance. The first formally establishes the
validity of proofs by contradiction, and the second and third provide two means for
proving “if and only if” statements. We’ve been using these all along, but now we
know why they are justified.
42
Chapter 9
Counting
• How many ways are there to seat n couples at a round table, such that each
couple sits together?
• How many ways are there to express a positive integer n as a sum of positive
integers?
There are a number of basic principles that we can use to solve such problems.
The sum principle: Consider n sets Ai , for 1 i n, that are pairwise disjoint,
namely Ai \ Aj = ; for all i 6= j. Then
n
[ n
X
Ai = |Ai | .
i=1 i=1
For example, if there are n ways to pick an object from the first pile and m ways to
pick on object from the second pile, there are n+m ways to pick an object altogether.
The product principle: If we need to do n things one after the other, and there
are c1 ways to do the first, cQ 2 ways to do the second, and so on, the number of
possible courses of action is ni=1 ci . For example, the number of possible three-
letter words in which a letter appears at most once that can be constructed using the
English alphabet is 26 · 25 · 24: There are 26 possibilities for the first letter, then 25
possibilities for the second, and finally 24 possibilities for the third.
43
and to count the number of elements in B. Often there is no need to explicitly specify
the bijection and prove that it is such: At this point in the course, you can omit some
low-level details from the written proofs in your homework solutions, as long as you
are certain that you could reproduce these details if asked to do so. For example, you
can simply state and use the observation that the number of ways to seat n people
in a row is the same as the number of ways to order the integers 1, 2, . . . , n, which
is the same as the number of n-element sequences that can be constructed from the
integers 1, 2, . . . , n (without repetition), which is the same as the number of bijections
f : A ! A, for A = {1, 2, . . . , n}. You should always make sure that you yourself
fully understand why such equalities hold whenever you use them! Obviously, if you
don’t, you’ll end up relying on equalities that are simply not true, which is not such
a great idea. If in doubt, write down a complete proof to make sure your reasoning
is correct.
Theorem 9.2.1. Given sets A and B, such that |A| = k and |B| = n, the number of
functions f : A ! B is nk .
Proof. Induction on k. If k = 0 the set A has no elements and there is only one
mapping from A to B, the empty mapping. (Recall that a function f : A ! B is a
subset of A ⇥ B, and if A = ; then A ⇥ B = ;.) We suppose the claim holds for
|A| = m and treat the case |A| = m + 1. Consider some element a 2 A. To specify a
function f : A ! B we can specify f (a) 2 B and a mapping f 0 : A \ {a} ! B. There
are n possible values of f (a) 2 B, and for each of these there are nm mappings f 0 by
the induction hypothesis. This results in nm+1 mappings f and completes the proof
by induction.
44
and so on. Overall we get that the desired quantity is
k
Y1
n(n 1) · · · (n k + 1) = (n i).
i=0
This is called a falling factorial and denoted by (n)k or nk . We again provide a more
formal proof by induction, observing that the number of ways to pick an ordered
sequence of k objects from a collection of n distinct ones without replacement is
equal to the number of one-to-one functions f : A ! B, where |A| = k and |B| = n.
Theorem 9.2.2. Given sets A and B, such that |A| = k and |B| = n, the number of
one-to-one functions f : A ! B is (n)k .
Proof. Induction on k. When |A| = 0, there is one mapping f as described, the
empty mapping, and (n)k is the empty product, equal to 1. Suppose the claim holds
for |A| = m and consider the case |A| = m + 1. Fix an element a 2 A. To specify
f we specify f (a) and a mapping f 0 : A \ {a} ! B. There are n possible values for
f (a) 2 B. Consider a specific such value f (a) = b. Since f is one-to-one, no element
of A \ {a} can be mapped to b. Thus f 0 has to be a one-to-one-mapping from A \ {a}
to B \ {b}. By the induction hypothesis, the number of such mappings is (n 1)m .
The number of possible mappings f is thus n · (n 1)m = (n)m+1 .
Permutations. How many ways are there to arrange n people in a row? How many
ordered n-tuples are there of integers from the set {1, 2, . . . , n}? Haw many distinct
rearrangements are there of the integers 1, 2, . . . , n? How many bijections are there
from the set {1, 2, . . . , n} to itself? The answer to these questions is the same, and
follows from Theorem 9.2.2. A bijection from a set A to itself is called a permutation
of A. The number of permutations of the set {1, 2, . . . , n} is precisely the number of
one-to-one functions from this set to itself, and this number is (n)n = n·(n 1) · · · 2·1.
This quantity is called “n factorial” and is denoted by n!. We can now observe that
n!
(n)k = .
(n k)!
It is important to remember that 0! = 1, since 0! is the empty product. Here is a list
of values of n! for 0 n 10:
1, 1, 2, 6, 24, 120, 720, 5040, 40320, 362880, 3628800
Seating at a round table. We’ve arranged n people in a row, now it’s time to sit
them down. So how many ways are there to seat n people at a round table? Let’s
be precise about what we mean: Two seating arrangements are considered identical
if every person has the same neighbor to her right. In other words, rotations around
the table do not matter. Here is how this problem can be tackled: Fix one person a
and sit her down anywhere. This now fixes n 1 possible positions for the others:
“first person to the right of a”, “second person to the right of a”, and so on until
“(n 1)-st person to the right of a”. The number of ways to arrange the others in
these n 1 positions is (n 1)!, which is also the answer to the original question.
45
Choosing an unordered collection of distinct objects without repetition.
How many ways are there to pick a set of k objects from a set of n objects? Since we
are picking a set, we do not care about order, and there are no repetitions. Notice
that every such set can be ordered in k! ways. That is, each set corresponds to k!
distinct ordered k-tuples. Now, we know that the number of ordered k-tuples that
can be picked from a collection of n distinct objects is (n)k . Thus if we denote by X
the number of sets of cardinality k that can be picked from a collection of n distinct
objects, we get
X · k! = (n)k
(n)k
X =
k!
n!
X = .
k!(n k)!
The number of subsets. We have seen that the number of k-element subsets of
an n-element set is nk . How many subsets of an n-element set are there overall, of
any size? Yes, it is time to prove the neat formula we’ve been using all along:
Proof. By induction. When |A| = 0, A = ;. Hence, A has only one subset (itself)
and the formula holds since 20 = 1. Assume the formula holds when |A| = k and
consider the case |A| = k + 1. Fix an element a 2 A. A subset of A either contains
a or not. The subsets of A that do not contain a are simply subsets of A \ {a} and
their number is 2k by the induction hypothesis. On the other hand, each subset of
A that does contain a is of the form {a} [ X, for X ✓ A \ {a}. Thus there is a
bijective mapping between subsets of A that contain a and subsets of A \ {a}. The
number of such subsets is again 2k . Overall we get that the number of subsets of A
is 2k + 2k = 2k+1 , which completes the proof by induction.
Here is another instructive way to prove Theorem 9.2.3: Consider the set of func-
tions f : A ! {0, 1}. These functions assign a value of 0 or 1 to every element of A.
In this way, such a function f uniquely specifies a subset of A. Namely, the elements
x for which f (x) = 1 are the elements that belong to the subset of A specified by
f . This defines a bijection between such functions f and subsets of A. By Theorem
9.2.1, the number of functions f from A to {0, 1} is 2|A| , which proves Theorem 9.2.3.
46
We can use Theorem 9.2.3 to derive an interesting identity. We now know that
the overall number of subsets of an n-element set is 2n . Previously we have seen that
the number of k-element subsets of an n-element set is nk . By the sum principle, we
get
X n ✓ ◆
n
= 2n .
i=0
i
47
48
Chapter 10
Binomial Coefficients
✓ ◆ Qk 1
n n! (n i)
= = i=0 .
k k!(n k)! k!
The quantities nk are called binomial coefficients because of their role in the Binomial
Theorem, apparently known to the 11th century Persian scholar Omar Khayyam.
Before we state and prove the theorem let us consider some important identities
that involve binomial coefficients. One that follows immediately from the algebraic
definition is
✓ ◆ ✓ ◆
n n
= .
k n k
✓ ◆ ✓ ◆ ✓ ◆
n n n+1
+ = .
k 1 k k
49
This can be easily proved algebraically:
✓ ◆ ✓ ◆
n n n! n!
+ = +
k 1 k (k 1)!(n + 1 k)! k!(n k)!
n!k n!(n + 1 k)
= +
k!(n + 1 k)! k!(n + 1 k)!
n!k + n!(n + 1 k)
=
k!(n + 1 k)!
(n + 1)!
=
k!(n + 1 k)!
✓ ◆
n+1
= .
k
We only give a combinatorial argument for this one. We are counting the number of
ways to choose an l-element subset of an (m + n)-element set A. Fix an m-element
subset B ✓ A. Any l-element subset S of A has k elements from B and l k elements
from A \ B, for some 0 k l. For a particular value of k, the number of k-element
subsets of B that can be part of S is mk
and the number of (l k)-element subsets
n
of A \ B is l k . We can now use the sum principle to sum over the possible values
of k and obtain the identity. An interesting special case is
X n ✓ ◆2 ✓ ◆
n 2n
= .
k=0
k n
50
Proof. By induction on n. When n = 0 both sides evaluate to 1. Assume the claim
holds for n = m and consider the case n = m + 1.
k=1
k 1 k=1
k
X m ✓✓ ◆ ✓ ◆◆
m m
= xm+1 + y m+1 + + xk y m+1 k (10.7)
k=1
k 1 k
X m ✓ ◆
m+1 m+1 m + 1 k m+1 k
= x +y + x y (10.8)
k=1
k
X ✓m + 1◆
m+1
= xk y m+1 k . (10.9)
k=0
k
and (8) follows from (7) by Pascal’s rule. The other steps are simple algebraic ma-
nipulation. This completes the proof by induction.
The binomial theorem can be used to immediately derive an identity we have seen
before: By substituting x = y = 1 into the theorem we get
n ✓ ◆
X n
= 2n .
k=0
k
51
This implies
X ✓n ◆ X ✓n ◆
= = 2n 1 .
k odd
k k even
k
This means that the number of odd-size subsets of an n-element set A is the same
as the number of even-size subsets, and equals 2n 1 . This can be proved by a com-
binatorial argument as follows: Fix an element a 2 A and note that the number of
subsets of A \ {a} is 2n 1 . There is a bijective map between subsets of A \ {a} and
odd-size subsets of A, as follows: Map an odd-sized subset of A \ {a} to itself, and
map an even-sized subset B ✓ A \ {a} to B [ {a}. Observe that this is a bijection
and conclude that the number of odd-sized subsets of A is 2n 1 . Even-size subsets
can be treated similarly, or by noting that their number is 2n minus the number of
odd-size ones.
52
Chapter 11
However, with more information we can do better. For a concrete example, con-
sider a group of people, 10 of whom speak English, 8 speak French, and 6 speak both
languages. How many people are in the group? We can sum the number of English-
and French-speakers, getting 10 + 8 = 18. Clearly, the bilinguals were counted twice,
so we need to subtract their number, getting the final answer 18 6 = 12. This argu-
ment can be carried out essentially verbatim in a completely general setting, yielding
the following formula:
|A [ B| = |A| + |B| |A \ B|.
What if there are three sets? Suppose in addition to the above English and French
speakers, we have 14 German-language enthusiasts, among which 8 also speak English,
5 speak French, and 2 speak all three languages. How many people are there now?
We can reason as follows: The sum 10 + 8 + 14 = 32 counts the people speaking two
languages twice, so we should subtract their number, getting 32 6 8 5 = 13.
But now the trilinguals have not been counted: They were counted three times in
the first sum, and then subtracted three times as part of the bilinguals. So the final
answer is obtained by adding their number: 13 + 2 = 15. In general,
53
In the case of arbitrarily many sets we obtain the inclusion-exclusion principle:
n
[ n
X X
Ai = ( 1)k 1
|Ai1 \ Ai2 \ . . . Aik | .
i=1 k=1 1i1 <i2 <···<ik n
S
Proof. Each element in ni=1 Ai is counted exactly once on the left side of the formula.
Consider such an element a and let the number of sets Ai that contain a be j. Then
a is counted ✓ ◆ ✓ ◆ ✓ ◆
j j j 1 j
+ . . . + ( 1)
1 2 j
times on the right side. But recall from our exploration of binomial coefficients that
j
X ✓ ◆ X j ✓ ◆ j
X ✓ ◆
j
i i 1 j i 1 j
( 1) = ( 1) = 1+ ( 1) = 0,
i=0
i i=0
i i=1
i
which implies
✓ ◆ ✓ ◆ ✓ ◆
j j j 1 j
+ . . . + ( 1) = 1,
1 2 j
meaning that a is counted exactly once on the right side as well. This establishes the
inclusion-exclusion principle.
11.2 Derangements
Given a set A = {a1 , a2 . . . , an }, we know that the number of bijections from A to
itself is n!. How many such bijections are there that map no element a 2 A to itself?
That is, how many bijections are there of the form f : A ! A, such that f (a) 6= a
for all a 2 A. These are called derangements, or bijections with no fixed points.
We can reason as follows: Let Si be the set of bijections that map the i-th element
of A to itself. We are the looking for the quantity
n
[
n! Si .
i=1
Consider an intersection Si1 \ Si2 \ . . . \ Sik . Its elements are the permutations that
map ai1 , ai2 , . . . , aik to themselves. The number of such permutations is (n k)!, hence
|Si1 \ Si2 \ . . . \ Sik | = (n k)!. This allows expressing the number of derangements
54
as
n
X X n
X ✓ ◆
k 1 k 1 n
n! ( 1) (n k)! = n! ( 1) (n k)!
k=1 1i1 <i2 <···<ik n k=1
k
n
X ✓ ◆
n k
= ( 1) (n k)!
k=0
k
n
X n!
= ( 1)k
k=0
k!
Xn
( 1)k
= n! .
k=0
k!
P k
Now, nk=0 ( k!1) is the beginning of the Maclaurin series of e 1 . (No, you are not
required to know this for the exam.) This means that as n gets larger, the number
of derangements rapidly approaches n!/e. In particular, if we just pick a random
permutation of a large set, the chance that it will have no fixed points is about 1/e.
Quite remarkable, isn’t it!?
55
56
Chapter 12
Basic form. If m objects are put in n boxes and n < m, then at least one box
contains at least two objects. The one-line proof is by contradiction: If every box
contains at most one object, there are at most n · 1 = n objects. A more rigorous
formulation of the principle is as follows: Given two sets A and B, with |A| = m >
n = |B|, for any function f : A ! B there exists b 2 B such that
{x 2 A : f (x) = b} > 1.
General form. If m objects are put in n boxes, then at least one box contains at
least dm/ne objects. The proof is again by contradiction: If every box contains at
most dm/ne 1 < m/n objects, there are less than n(m/n) = m objects. The more
rigorous formulation is: Given two sets A and B, for any function f : A ! B there
exists b 2 B such that lmm
{x 2 A : f (x) = b} .
n
Dijkstra’s form. For a nonempty finite collection of integers (not necessarily dis-
tinct), the maximum value is at least the average value. It is a good exercise to verify
that this is equivalent to the general form above.
57
First application. There are two San Franciscans with the exact same number
of hairs on their heads. Indeed, according to P&G Hair Facts, the average person’s
head has about 100,000 hairs, while “some people have as many as 150,000.” So it
seems safe to bet that every San Franciscan has at most 700,000 hairs on his or her
head. On the other hand, the year 2000 US Census counted 776,733 San Francisco
residents. The pigeonhole principle implies that at least two of them have the exact
same number of hairs.
Second application. At a cocktail party with six or more people, there are three
mutual acquaintances or three mutual strangers. Indeed, pick an arbitrary person a.
By the pigeonhole principle, among the other five or more people, either there are
three of a’s acquaintances, or three people who are strangers to a. Let’s say there
are three that are a’s acquaintances, the other case is analogous. If those three are
mutual strangers we are done. Otherwise there are two among them, call them b and
c, who know each other. Then a, b and c are mutual acquaintances and we are done.
58
ai1 > ai2 > · · · > aim in general, giving us a decreasing subsequence of length at least
n + 1.
Here is another pigeonhole gem, the last one for today:
P
This collection has size n+1 and its first element is the empty sum 0i=1 ai = 0. There
are only n possible remainders modulo n, thus by the pigeonhole principle, there are
two numbers
Pl in the above
Pk collection of size n + 1 that leave the same remainder. Let
these be i=1 ai and i=1 ai , with l < k. By a lemma we once proved, it follows that
k l
!
X X
n ai ai ,
i=1 i=1
which implies
k
X
n ai .
i=l+1
59
60
Chapter 13
Asymptotic Notation
13.1 Definitions
Analysis of algorithms is concerned with estimating how many steps various algo-
rithms make while solving problems of various sizes. In particular, given an algorithm,
we want to make statements like “For input of size n, the algorithm will terminate in
at most f (n) steps.” If we try to accurately estimate the number of steps, a cumber-
some bound like
1 1
f (n) = n3 + 12n2 + 15 n + log3 n + 17
11 2
might arise. Such precision only complicates matters and does not add to our under-
standing of the algorithm’s efficiency. The following notational convention allows to
simplify bounds by concentrating on their “main terms.”
Definition 13.1.1. For two functions f, g : N+ ! R,
• f (n) = O(g(n)) if and only if there exists a positive constant c 2 R and a
constant n0 2 N, such that |f (n)| c|g(n)| for all n n0 .
• f (n) = ⌦(g(n)) if and only if g(n) = O(f (n)).
• f (n) = ⇥(g(n)) if and only if f (n) = O(g(n)) and f (n) = ⌦(g(n)).
Asymptotic notation does wonders to the above ugly bound: We can now say that
f (n) = ⇥(n3 ), which makes it easier to see how the number of steps performed by
the algorithm grows as n gets larger and larger. Notice how the asymptotic notation
swallowed all the constants and lower-order terms! To prove that f (n) = ⇥(n3 ) we
need to show that there exist positive constants c1 , c2 2 R and a constant n0 2 N,
such that c1 n3 f (n) c2 n3 for all n n0 . (We dropped the absolute values that
come from Definition 13.1.1 since f (n) and n3 are nonnegative for n 2 N+ .) We can
1 1 3
take n0 = 1, c1 = 11 , and c2 = 45.6. For the lower bound, clearly f (n) 11 n when
n 2 N . For the upper bound, note that in this range n
+ 3
n 2
n log3 n, and
n3 1. All these inequalities can be proved by elementary algebraic manipulation.
Thus we get
1 1
f (n) n3 + 12n3 + 15 n3 + n3 + 17n3 45.6n3 .
11 2
61
We can also perfectly well say that f (n) = O(n4 ) or that f (n) = O(n25 ); these
bounds are considerably less informative but correct. On the other hand, the bound
f (n) = O(n2 ) (or even f (n) = O(n2.99 )) is not correct. Indeed, we have seen that
f (n) 11 n . On the other hand, for any positive constant c 2 R, 11
1 3 1 3
n cn2 for all
n 11c. Thus there is no positive constant c 2 R and a constant n0 2 N so that
f (n) cn2 for all n n0 .
Asymptotic notation is asymmetric, so we never write a statement like O(g(n)) =
f (n); the O, ⌦, and ⇥ are always present on the right side of the equality sign.
(However, we can write n2 + O(n) = ⇥(n2 ), for example.) The right way to think
of statements like f (n) = O(g(n)) and f (n) = ⌦(g(n)) is as inequalities; always
remember what the notation means according to Definition 13.1.1.
• For any real constants b > 1 and p, np = O(bn ). (“An exponential swallows a
power.”)
• For any real constants q > 0 and p, (ln n)p = O(nq ). (“A power swallows a
logarithm.”)
• For any real constants a, b > 1, loga n = ⇥(logb n). This implies that we can
write bounds like O(log n), O(n log n), etc., without specifying the base of the
logarithm. (“Asymptotic notation swallows bases of logarithms.”)
(b) If f (n) = O(h(n)) and g(n) = O(w(n)) then f (n)+g(n) = O(max(|h(n)|, |w(n)|)).
62
(c) If f (n) = O(h(n)) and g(n) = O(w(n)) then f (n) · g(n) = O(h(n) · w(n)).
(a) If f (n) = O(g(n)) then there exists a positive constant c 2 R and a constant
n0 2 N, such that |f (n)| c|g(n)| for all n n0 . Thus for p 2 N, |p · f (n)| =
p|f (n)| (pc)|g(n)| for all n n0 , and by Definition 13.1.1, p · f (n) = O(g(n)).
(b) If f (n) = O(h(n)) and g(n) = O(w(n)) then there exist two positive constants
c1 , c2 2 R and constants n1 , n2 2 N, such that |f (n)| c1 |h(n)| for all n n1
and |g(n)| c2 |w(n)| for all n n2 . Then
(c) If f (n) = O(h(n)) and g(n) = O(w(n)) then there exist two positive constants
c1 , c2 2 R and constants n1 , n2 2 N, such that |f (n)| c1 |h(n)| for all n n1
and |g(n)| c2 |w(n)| for all n n2 . Then
|f (n) · g(n)| = |f (n)| · |g(n)| (c1 |h(n)|) · (c2 |w(n)|) = (c1 c2 )|h(n) · w(n)|
for all n max(n1 , n2 ), and by Definition 13.1.1, f (n) · g(n) = O(h(n) · w(n)).
63
64
Chapter 14
Graphs
14.1 Introduction
A graph G is an ordered pair (V, E), where V is a set and E is a set of two-element
subsets of V . That is,
E ✓ {x, y} : x, y 2 V, x 6= y .
Elements of V are the vertices (sometimes called nodes) of the graph and elements of
E are the edges. If e = {x, y} 2 E we say that x and y are adjacent in the graph G,
that y is a neighbor of x in G and vice versa, and that the edge e is incident to x and
y.
What are graphs good for? Graphs are perhaps the most pervasive abstraction in
computer science. It is hard to appreciate their tremendous usefulness at first, because
the concept itself is so elementary. This appreciation comes through uncovering the
deep and fascinating theory of graphs and its applications.
Graphs are used to model and study transportation networks, such as the net-
work of highways, the London Underground, the worldwide airline network, or the
European railway network; the ‘connectivity’ properties of such networks are of great
interest. Graphs can also be used to model the World Wide Web, with edges corre-
sponding to hyperlinks; Google uses sophisticated ideas from graph theory to assign a
PageRank to every vertex of this graph as a function of the graph’s global properties.
In this course we will introduce the basic concepts and results in graph theory, which
will allow you to study and understand more advanced techniques and applications
in the future.
65
Paths. A path on n vertices, denoted by Pn , is the graph Pn = (V, E), where
V = {1, 2, . . . , n} and E = {{i, i + 1} : 1 i n 1}. The number of edges in Pn is
n 1. The vertices 1 and n are called the endpoints of Pn .
Size. The number of edges of a graph is called it size. The size of an n-vertex graph
is at most n2 , achieved by the n-clique.
Degree. The degree (or valency) of a vertex v in a graph G = (V, E), denoted by
dG (v), is the number of neighbors of v in G. More formally, this degree is
dG (v) = {u 2 V : {v, u} 2 E} .
A graph in which every vertex has degree k is called k-regular and a graph is said to
be regular if it is k-regular for some k.
The following is sometimes called the Handshake lemma. It can be interpreted as
saying that the number of people at a cocktail party who shake hands with an odd
number of others is even.
66
Proof. For a graph G = (V, E), consider the sum of the degrees of its vertices:
X
s= dG (v).
v2V
Observe that this sum counts every edge e twice, once for each of the vertices incident
to e. Thus s = 2|E|, and, in particular, s is even. Subtracting from s the degrees of
even-degree vertices of G, we see that the resulting quantity is the sum of the degrees
of odd-degree vertices and is still even. This implies the proposition.
E ✓ (x, y) : x, y 2 V, x 6= y .
Directed graphs are suitable for modeling one-way streets, non-reflexive relations,
hyperlinks in the World Wide Web, and so on. The notion of degree as defined above
67
is no longer applicable to a directed graph. Instead, we speak of the indegree and the
outdegree of a vertex v in G, defined as |{u 2 V : (u, v) 2 E}| and |{u 2 V : (v, u) 2
E}|, respectively.
A graph that is not simple can have multi-edges and self-loops. Multi-edges are
multiple edges between the same pair of vertices. (Their presence means that the
collection of edges is no longer a set, but a so-called multiset.) A self-loop is an edge
to and from a single vertex v.
Finally, a graph can also be weighted, in the sense that numerical weights are
associated with edges. Such weights are extremely useful for modeling distances in
transportation networks, congestion in computer networks, etc. We will not dwell on
weighted graphs in this course. In fact, unless specified otherwise, the word “graph”
will continue to refer to undirected, unweighted, simple graphs.
68
Chapter 15
69
(a) v1 = vn+1
(b) n = |E|
Proof of (a). Assume for the sake of contradiction that v1 6= vn+1 . Then the number
of edges of T incident to v1 is odd. (After T first leaves v1 , it enters and leaves
it an even number of times.) Since the degree of v1 in G is even, there is an
edge e of G that is incident to v1 but not part of T . We can extend T by this
edge, obtaining a contradiction.
Proof of (b). We can assume that v1 = vn+1 . Suppose V (T ) 6= V . Consider a
vertex v 2 V \ V (T ) and a vertex u 2 V (T ). Since G is connected, there
is a path P between v and u in G. Consider the first time a vertex of T is
encountered along P ; this vertex is vi for some 1 i n. Let e0 = {v 0 , vi } be
the edge along which P arrives at vi and note that v 0 62 V (T ). This implies that
we can augment T by v 0 and e0 , and obtain a longer tour T 0 , namely
T 0 = (v 0 , e0 , vi , ei , . . . , vn , en , v1 , e1 , . . . , vi 1 , ei 1 , vi ).
T 0 is longer than T by one edge, which is a contradiction that proves the theo-
rem.
70
course, we can just assign a new wavelength to every user, but that would be waste-
ful if some users are far apart. So what’s the least number of wavelengths we can get
away with?
We can model the users as vertices in a graph and connect two vertices by an edge
if the corresponding users are sufficiently close. A coloring of this graph G = (V, E)
is an assignment of colors to vertices, such that no two adjacent vertices get the same
color. The above question can now be restated as asking for the minimum number of
colors that are needed for a coloring of G.
Let us be a bit more precise in defining colorings: A k-coloring of G is said to
be a function c : V ! {1, 2, . . . , k}, such that if {v, u} 2 E then c(v) 6= c(u). The
smallest k 2 N for which a k-coloring of G exists is called the chromatic number of
G. If a k-coloring of G exists, the graph is said to be k-colorable. There are many
deep results concerning colorings and the chromatic number. At this point we only
give the simplest one:
Proposition 15.2.1. If the degree of every vertex in a graph G is at most k, then
the chromatic number of G is at most k + 1.
Proof. By induction on the number of vertices in G. (The degree bound k is fixed
throughout the proof.) If G has a single vertex, then the maximal degree is 0 and
the graph is 1-colorable. Since 1 k + 1, the proposition holds. Suppose every graph
with at most n vertices and all vertex degrees at most k is (k + 1)-colorable. Consider
a particular graph G = (V, E) with n + 1 vertices, and all degrees at most k. Let
G0 be the graph obtained from G by deleting a particular vertex v and all the edges
incident to v. That is, G0 is the incident subgraph of G on the vertices V \ {v}. G0
has n vertices, all of degree at most k, and is thus (k + 1)-colorable. Let c0 be such a
coloring of G0 . We extend it to a coloring c of G as follows. For every vertex u 2 G
such that u 6= v we define c(u) = c0 (u). The vertex v has at most k neighbors in G
and there is at least one color i among {1, 2, . . . , k + 1} that has not been assigned
to any of them. We define c(u) = i. This is a (k + 1)-coloring, and the proposition
follows.
E ✓ {{u, u0 } : u 2 U and u0 2 V \ U }.
The sets U and V \ U are called the classes of G. A complete bipartite graph Km,n is
a graph in which all the edges between the two classes are present. Namely, Km,n =
(V, E), where V = {1, 2, . . . , m+n} and E = {{i, j} : 1 i m, m+1 j m+n}.
The number of edges in Kn is mn. From the definition of coloring, it follows that
a graph is bipartite if and only if it is 2-colorable. (Check!) Here is another useful
characterization of bipartite graphs:
71
Proposition 15.3.1. A graph is bipartite if and only if it contains no cycle of odd
length.
Proof. For one direction of the claim, let G be a bipartite graph and let C =
(v1 , v2 , . . . , vn , v1 ) be a cycle in G. Suppose without loss of generality that v1 2 U ,
where U is as in the definition of bipartiteness. Then by simple induction that we
omit, vi 2 U for every odd 1 i n. Since {vn , v1 } 2 E, vn 2 V \ U and thus n is
even. It follows that the number of edges in C is even.
Before proving the other direction, we need a simple lemma.
Lemma 15.3.2. Given a graph G = (V, E), let P = (v1 , v2 , . . . , vn ) be a shortest path
between two vertices v1 and vn in G. Then for all 1 i < j n, Pi = (vi , vi+1 , . . . , vj )
is a shortest path between vi and vj .
Proof. Proof by contradiction. Let Qi = (vi , u1 , u2 , . . . , ul , vj ) be a shortest path
between vi and vj . Assume for the sake of contradiction that Qi is shorter than Pi .
Consider the walk
Q = (v1 , v2 , . . . , vi , u1 , u2 , . . . , ul , vj , vj+1 , . . . , vn ).
We prove that no two vertices in U are adjacent; the proof for V \ U is similar.
Consider for the sake of contradiction an edge e = {u, u0 } 2 E, such that u, u0 2 U .
Denote a shortest path from v to u by P1 and a shortest path from v to u0 by P2 .
Given two vertices s and t on a path P , let P s,t be the part of P that connects s and
t. Consider a vertex w that lies on both P1 and P2 . The above lemma implies that
P1v,w and P2v,w are shortest paths between v and w and thus have the same length,
which we denote by l(w). Consider the vertex w⇤ shared by P1 and P2 that maximizes
⇤ w⇤ ,u0
l(w) among all such w. The paths P1w ,u and P 2 share no vertex in common other
⇤ w⇤ ,u
than w . Furthermore, the length of P1 is the length of P1 minus l(w⇤ ) and the
w⇤ ,u0
length of P2 is the length of P2 minus l(w⇤ ). Since the lengths of P1 and P2 are
72
⇤ ⇤ 0
both even, the lengths of P1w ,u and P2w ,u have the same parity (that ⇤is, they are
either both even or both odd). Now consider the cycle C composed of P1w ,u , the edge
⇤ 0 ⇤ ⇤ 0
{u, u0 }, and P2w ,u . Since P1w ,u and P2w ,u share no vertex in common other than
⇤ ⇤ 0
w⇤ , C really is a cycle in G. Moreover, since the lengths of P1w ,u and P2w ,u have the
same parity, the number of edges in C is odd! We have reached a contradiction that
completes the proof.
Bipartite graphs are particularly useful to model symmetric relations from one
set to another. For example, given a collection of boys and girls, we could model the
relation “wants to go to the prom with” by a bipartite graph. Given such preferences,
an interesting question is whether we can pair the boys up with the girls, so that they
all end up going to the prom with someone they actually want to go with. It turns
out that this question has a very precise answer. To state the theorem we need to
define the notion of matching:
Consider now a set B of boys, a set G of girls, and a symmetric relation P from B
to G. Define a graph W = (B [ G, {{b, g} : (b, g) 2 P }). The above question simply
asks to characterize when there exists a perfect matching in W . The below result,
known as Hall’s theorem, provides such a characterization. To state the theorem, we
use another piece of notation: Given a subset S of the vertices of W , we let (S) be
the set of vertices of W adjacent to at least one of the vertices of S.
Theorem 15.3.4. A bipartite graph W = (V, E) with classes B and G has a perfect
matching if and only if |B| = |G| and | (S)| |S| for all S ✓ B.
Proof. One direction is easy: Assume W has a perfect matching and consider a
set S ✓ B. Every element of S is matched to a distinct element of G and hence
| (S)| |S|. In particular, |G| |B|. By a symmetric argument we get that
|B| |G| and thus |B| = |G|.
For the other direction, assume that |B| = |G| and that | (S)| |S| for all
S ✓ B. We prove that there exists a perfect matching in W by strong induction on
|B|. For the base case, if |B| = |G| = 1, the matching consists of the single edge of
W . Assuming that the claim holds for all graphs with |B| k, consider a graph W
as above with |B| = k + 1. We distinguish between two possibilities:
(a) If for every S ⇢ B, | (S)| > |S|, we take an arbitrary x 2 B and match it with
an adjacent y 2 G. Then for every subset S 0 of B \ {x}, it still holds that the
number of vertices of G \ {y} adjacent to at least one of the vertices of S 0 is at
least |S 0 |. We can thus match the vertices of B \ {x} with the vertices of G \ {y}
by the induction hypothesis.
(b) If for some S ⇢ B, | (S)| = |S|, we note that for every S 0 ✓ S, the number
of vertices in (S) adjacent to at least one of the vertices of S 0 is at least |S 0 |.
73
Thus we can match S with (S) by the induction hypothesis. Now we need to
show that we can match B \ S with G \ (S). Consider a set S 0 ✓ B \ S and
the set T 0 of its neighbors in G \ (S). Note that the set of neighbors of S [ S 0
in G is (S) [ T 0 . Thus |S [ S 0 | | (S) [ T 0 |. Since |S| = | (S)|, we get that
|S 0 | |T 0 |. Thus by the induction hypothesis we can also match B \ S with
G \ (S).
This shows that in both cases all the vertices of B can be matched with vertices of
G as required, and concludes the proof.
74
Chapter 16
Trees
An extensive theory of trees has been developed, and we give the tip of the iceberg
below: Four additional characterizations that each could have been used to define
trees.
Theorem 16.1.2. Given a graph G = (V, E), the following conditions are equivalent:
(a) G is a connected graph with no cycles. (Thus G is a tree by the above definition.)
(b) For every two vertices u, v 2 V , there exists exactly one path from u to v.
(c) G is connected, and removing any edge from G disconnects it. (Thus G is a
minimal connected graph.)
(d) G has no cycles, and adding any edge to G gives rise to a cycle. (Thus G is a
maximal acyclic graph.)
Proof. We will prove for each of the conditions (b)–(e) in turn that it is equivalent to
condition (a). This implies the equivalence of all the conditions. The proof proceeds
by induction on the number of vertices |V | in G, and we relate a tree with n + 1
vertices to a tree with n vertices in the inductive step by “tearing o↵” a leaf. We
begin by proving two lemmas that will be useful in this process.
Lemma 16.1.3. Each tree with at least 2 vertices contains at least 2 leaves.
75
Proof. Given a tree T = (V, E), consider a path P of maximum length in T . We
claim that the two end-points of P are leaves of T . Indeed, assume for the sake of
contradiction that an end-vertex u of P has degree greater than 1 in T . Thus there
exists an edge {u, u0 } 2 E that is not part of P . If u0 belongs to P then T contains
a cycle. Otherwise we can extend P by the edge {u, u0 } and P is not a longest path
in T . This contradiction proves the lemma.
Proof. Assume that G is a tree and consider two vertices u, w 2 V \ {v}. u and w
are connected by a path P in G. Every vertex of P other than u and w has degree
at least 2, and thus v cannot be a vertex of P . Therefore P is a path in G0 , which
proves that G0 is connected. Since G does not contain a cycle, G0 cannot contain a
cycle and is thus a tree.
For the other direction, assume that G0 is a tree. Since a cycle only contains
vertices with degree at least 2, a cycle in G must also be a cycle in G0 . Therefore
there are no cycles in G. Also, any two vertices of G other than v can be connected
by the same path as in G0 , and v can be connected to any vertex u in G by a path
that consists of the edge e and a path in G0 between v 0 and u. Thus G is a tree.
We are now ready to employ induction to prove that condition (a) implies each of
(b)–(e). For the induction basis, all five conditions hold for the graph with a single
vertex. Consider a graph G = (V, E) with |V | = n 2 and assume that (a) holds for
G. By Lemma 16.1.3, G has a leaf v 2 V that is incident to an edge e = {v, v 0 } 2 E.
By Lemma 16.1.4, condition (a) holds for G0 . The inductive hypothesis states that
condition (a) implies conditions (b)–(e) for the graph G0 = (V \ {v}, E \ {e}). We
now need to prove that conditions (b)–(e) also hold for G.
Condition (b) holds for G by a similar argument to the one employed in the proof
of Lemma 16.1.4. Condition (c) holds for G since removing any edge other than e
disconnects G by the induction hypothesis, and removing e disconnects the vertex v
from the rest of the graph. Condition (d) holds since G cannot have cycles by an
argument similar to the proof of Lemma 16.1.4; adding an edge that is not incident
to v creates a cycle by the inductive hypothesis, and adding an edge {v, u}, for some
u 2 V \ {v} creates a cycle that consists of the edge {v, u}, the path from u to v 0 ,
and the edge e. Finally, condition (e) holds since G is obtained from G0 by adding
one vertex and one edge.
We now prove that each of (b)–(d) imply (a). Conditions (b) and (c) on G each
imply connectedness of G. By contrapositive, assume that G contains a cycle. Then
taking two distinct vertices u, w on the cycle, there are two paths from u to w along
the cycle, which implies (b) ) (a). Furthermore, removing one edge of the cycle does
not disconnect G, which implies (c) ) (a). Condition (d) implies that G does not
contain a cycle. By contrapositive, assume that G is disconnected. Then there are
two vertices u and w that have no path connecting them and we can add the edge
{u, w} to G without creating a cycle. This implies (d) ) (a).
76
To prove (e) ) (a) we use induction on the number of vertices of G. The induction
basis is the graph with one vertex and the claim trivially holds. For the induction
hypothesis, assume that the claim holds for all graphs with |V | 1 vertices. For
the inductive step, assume that condition (e) holds for G and hence |E| = |V | 1.
Therefore the sum of the degrees of the vertices of G is 2|V | 2, and thus there is
some vertex v 2 V of degree 1. The graph G0 = (V \ {v}, E \ {e}) is connected and
satisfies |E \ {e}| = |V \ {v}| 1. By the induction hypothesis, G0 is a tree. Lemma
16.1.4 now implies that G is a tree, which completes the proof.
Definition 16.2.1. Consider a graph G = (V, E). A tree of the form (V, E 0 ), where
E 0 ✓ E is called a spanning tree of G.
77
78
Chapter 17
Planar Graphs
As we have seen in class, graphs are often visualized by drawing them in the plane—
vertices are drawn as points, and edges as curved segments (called arcs) that connect
the corresponding points. A graph together with a drawing of it in the plane is called
a topological graph.
A graph is called planar if there exists a drawing of it in which the interior of any
arc does not touch or intersect any other arc. That is, two distinct arcs are either
disjoint or touch at endpoints that they share. A planar graph together with a planar
drawing of it is called a plane graph.
It is easy to verify that paths, cycles and trees of any size are planar. Transporta-
tion networks often provide examples of planar graphs, and graph planarity became
important in computer science due to a connection with VLSI circuit design. Planar
drawings are often considered superior when visualizing graphs, as they have no edge
crossings that can be mistaken for vertices. In fact, a whole subfield of computer
science called graph drawing is devoted to the study of various kinds of drawings of
graphs.
It might not be obvious at first that there are any nonplanar graphs at all. There
are, but we’ll have to do some work to prove this, and we’ll need two preliminary
steps just to approach this issue. The first is to define the faces of a plane graph and
the second is to mention the (in)famous Jordan curve theorem.
Let us begin with faces. Define an equivalence relation on the plane as follows:
Two points a, b 2 R2 are equivalent if they can be connected by an arc that does not
intersect the edges of a given plane graph G. Then the set of all points that belong
to a particular equivalence class of this relation are said to be a face of G. Intuitively,
if we draw G on a white sheet of paper with a black pencil, the faces are the white
regions; alternatively, if we cut the paper along the edges of the drawing, the faces
are the resulting pieces. Note that faces are defined for plane graphs, but not for
planar graphs without a drawing: Di↵erent drawings of the same graph can produce
di↵erent sets of faces!
The second piece of mathematical equipment we’ll need to study planar graphs
79
is the Jordan curve theorem.1 It is a classical example of a mathematical statement
that is intuitively obvious, but exceedingly difficult to prove. (Related specimens
that arguably fall into this category are Kepler’s conjecture and the Kneser-Poulsen
conjecture.)
To see why the Jordan curve theorem is not so easy to prove recall that there are
some crazy curves out there—just think about fractals like the Koch snowflake. How
would you go about proving that such monsters have “interior” and “exterior”?
The following corollary follows from the Jordan curve theorem by routine argu-
ments.
Corollary 17.1.2. Consider a plane graph G and an edge e that is part of a cycle in
G. Then e lies on the boundary of exactly two faces of G.
Theorem 17.2.1 (Euler’s formula). Let G be a connected plane graph with n vertices,
e edges, and f faces. Then
n e + f = 2.
Note that the theorem need not hold if the graph is not connected—Just think of
a collection of isolated vertices. On the other hand, the formula remains true even
for (non-simple) graphs with multiple edges and self-loops.
Proof. The proof proceeds by induction on the number of edges. If there are none,
the graph consists of a single vertex, the drawing has one face, and the formula holds
as 1 0 + 1 = 2. Assume that the formula holds for all plane graphs having k edges.
Consider a plane graph G = (V, E) with n vertices, f faces, and k + 1 edges. We
distinguish between two cases:
80
G has a cycle C. Take an edge e that lies on C and consider a plane graph G0 =
(V, E \ {e}), whose vertices and edges are drawn as in G. By Corollary 17.1.2,
the edge e is adjacent to two faces of G, and these faces “merge” into one in G0 .
Thus G0 has n vertices, f 1 faces, and k edges. By the induction hypothesis,
n k + (f 1) = 2, hence n (k + 1) + f = 2.
This completes the proof by induction.
Euler’s formula implies that the number of faces of a plane graph does not depend
on the drawing, so even though the faces themselves are only defined for a particular
drawing, their number is fixed a priori for any planar graph! The formula has a
number of other consequences that are frequently used in theoretical computer science.
These consequences say that planar graphs have few edges, and always have at least
one low-degree vertex. As they make abundantly clear, not only are not all graphs
planar, but most graphs aren’t. (Do you understand the sense in which the theorem
below implies this?)
Theorem 17.2.2. For any simple planar graph G with n vertices and e edges:
(a) If n 3 then e 3n 6. If e = 3n 6 then every face of G is a 3-cycle (a
“triangle”) and G is called a triangulation.
On the other hand, each face has at least three edges on its boundary, so
X
↵(t) 3f.
t
e 3n 6.
81
P
a vertex x in G. The sum x dG (x), ranging over the vertices x of G, counts
every edge twice, so X
dG (x) = 2e.
x
As we have seen, e 3n 6, so
X
dG (x) 6n 12.
x
6n 6n 12,
An intuitive way to think about Theorem 17.2.2(a) is that once a graph has too
many edges, there is no more room for them in the plane and they start intersecting.
This gives a way to prove that a particular graph is not planar. Take K5 , for example.
It has 5 vertices and 10 edges, and 10 > 3 · 5 6. Thus K5 is not planar! In fact, no
Kn is planar for n 5, since they all contain K5 as a subgraph. On the other hand,
Kn is planar for n 4, as can be demonstrated by their simple planar drawings. This
illustrates a point that might be obvious by now: proving a graph to be planar is
often easier than proving the opposite. (Just draw it!tm )
How about complete bipartite graphs? It is easy to verify that Ki,j is planar when
i 2 or j 2. The smallest remaining suspect is K3,3 . Playing around with drawings
doesn’t help: There seems to be no way to draw K3,3 without intersections. Let’s try
the trick that worked for K5 : The number of vertices of K3,3 is 6, its number of edges
is 9, and 9 3 · 6 6. No luck. We need a stronger tool, and here it is:
Proposition 17.2.3. For any simple planar graph G with n vertices and e edges, if
G does not contain a cycle of length 3 then e 2n 4.
Proof. We can assume that G is connected as in Theorem 17.2.2. Let f be the number
of faces of G and let ↵(t) be the number of edges adjacent to a face t. These edges
make up aPcycle in G, and thus their number is at least 4, implying ↵(t) 4. Consider
the sum t ↵(t), over all faces t of G. Each edge is adjacent to at most two faces,
thus X
4f ↵(t) 2e.
t
With this result we’re finally in business: K3,3 does not contain an odd cycle since
it is bipartite, thus every cycle in the graph has length at least 4. Since 9 > 2 · 6 4,
K3,3 is not planar. Let’s summarize what we’ve learned.
82
Theorem 17.2.4. Kn is planar if and only if n 4 and Ki,j is planar if and only if
i 2 or j 2.
At this point we have laid the groundwork for one of the most striking results
concerning planar graphs, known as Kuratowski’s theorem. To state it we need the
following definition:
Kuratowski’s theorem says that not only are K5 and K3,3 non-planar, but every
non-planar graph contains either a subdivision of K5 or a subdivision of K3,3 . That
is, the graphs K5 and K3,3 characterize the whole family of non-planar graphs!
83
in the coloring of G0 . Assign to v the color that is not used by its neighbors. Since
the degree of v is at most five, such a color exists. This specifies a valid coloring of
G.
Proof. The proof proceeds by induction on the number n of vertices of G. The base
case is trivial. Assume every planar graph with at most k vertices can be colored with
5 colors or less, and consider a graph G = (V, E) with k +1 vertices. Let v be a vertex
of G with degree at most 5. If dG (v) < 5 we can produce a 5-coloring of G as in the
proof of Theorem 17.3.1. Assume dG (v) = 5 and let c : (V \ {v}) ! {1, 2, 3, 4, 5} be
a 5-coloring of the induced subgraph G0 of G on the vertices V \ {v}. This coloring
exists by the induction hypothesis.
We consider a particular drawing of G in the plane and henceforth regard G as a
plane graph. Let v1 , v2 , v3 , v4 , v5 be the neighbors of v in the order they appear around
v in G. (That is, according to one of the circular orders in which the corresponding
edges emanate from v in G.) Without loss of generality, assume that c(vi ) = i for
1 i 5. (Note that if some color is unused by v1 , v2 , v3 , v4 , v5 , we can simply assign
that color to v.) We distinguish between two cases: Either there does not exist a
path between v1 and v3 in G that uses only vertices of colors 1 and 3, or there does.
There is no such path. In this case consider the subgraph G00 of G that is the
union of all paths that begin at v1 and use only vertices with colors 1 and 3.
Note that neither v3 nor its neighbors belong to G00 . We produce a 5-coloring
of G as follows: All the vertices of G00 of color 1 are assigned the color 3, all the
vertices of G00 of color 3 are assigned the color 1, the vertex v is assigned the color
1, and all other vertices of G keep the color assigned by c. No monochromatic
edges are created by this assignment and the coloring is valid.
There is such a path. Consider a path P from v1 to v3 that uses only vertices with
colors 1 and 3. Together with the edges {v, v1 } and {v, v3 } this forms a cycle.
The vertices v2 and v4 lie on di↵erent sides of this cycle. (Here we use the
Jordan curve theorem.) Therefore there is no path between v2 and v4 that uses
only vertices with colors 2 and 4, and we can apply the reasoning of the previous
case.
84
are straight line segments. Koebe’s theorem says that every planar graph is in fact
isomorphic to an “incidence graph” of a collection of nonoverlapping discs in the plane.
(The vertices of this graph correspond to the discs, and two vertices are adjacent if
and only if the corresponding disks are tangent.) Fáry’s theorem is an immediate
consequence of Koebe’s theorem, although they were discovered independently. Both
are remarkable.
85