Excerpt 001
Excerpt 001
Excerpt 001
Introduction
fully free criticism from the notions and values that had been asso-
ciated with creativity at least since Romanticism. Instead, interest in
creativity reappeared, sometimes with a vengeance, in the context of
reflections on the critic’s own achievements: Geoffrey H. Hartman’s
Derrida-inspired book, Criticism in the Wilderness, is an influential exam-
ple of a case in which a prominent professor of literature proclaimed
that the critic’s own artistic ambitions should replace the scholar’s
more traditional epistemic aims.5 Within the post-structuralist move-
ment, critics or communities thereof were said to play the active role of
endowing texts with meaning and value, thereby constituting those
“signifying practices” of which a culture is composed. In some of the
bolder speculations, it was the reader and not the author who was
thought to do the job of endowing a text with its very status as litera-
ture. Thus Barthes wrote that “only the critic executes the work.”6 And
as Stanley Fish put it, “it is not that the presence of poetic qualities
compels a certain kind of attention but that the paying of a certain
kind of attention results in the emergence of poetic qualities.”7 Any
“piece of language” can become a member of the class of literary texts
provided that some sufficiently influential group of readers provides
the requisite poetical attention. And anecdotal self-reference became
a veritable mannerism in the vein of criticism marketed as the New
Historicism. Having rightly castigated biographical critics for seeking
to explain what happens in fictions by identifying anecdotal sources in
the author’s childhood and fantasies, the post-structuralist critic comes
full circle by inserting the story of her own private life into “readings”
of the work of art.8
The influence of these tendencies in criticism helps explain the ne-
glect of the topic of the creation of art within philosophical aesthetics.
New Criticism revitalised formalism within philosophy, Beardsley play-
ing a prominent role here. The belief in the autonomy of art and
the anti-intentionalist stance inevitably made inquiry into creation
and the creative process seem aesthetically irrelevant. Philosophers
had previously often discussed the creative process in art as central
to the process of understanding art, R. G. Collingwood’s theory of art
as expression being perhaps the most influential of these twentieth-
century theories.9 In a paper on the creation of art, Beardsley attacked
Collingwood’s theory, but more importantly, having developed his
own thoughts on the process of artistic creation, concluded that such
the same novelty has been produced by any or many other individuals
before.”30
One response to such disagreements is to distinguish between dif-
ferent senses of “creativity.” Margaret Boden distinguishes historical
from psychological creativity (H- and P-creativity, as she calls them).
An idea is P-creative if it is valuable and “the person in whose mind
it arises could not have had it before”; the relation holds whether or
not the idea has ever been had before.31 To be H-creative, the idea
must be not only P-creative, but also must never have been had by
anyone else in all of human history. This is, we may note in passing,
a rather strong condition, and weaker, tradition and context-specific
alternatives could be formulated.
Boden’s reference to ideas that could not have been had before
brings us to a second source of disagreement about creativity: how to
specify the degree of originality that it requires. If originality simply
meant that something is new in some respect or other, then almost
any idea or product would count as original. Boden’s modal condition
attempts to specify the relevant difference. It does not express some
form of metaphysical necessity, but rather a relation between the val-
ued idea and the generative rules that structure a person’s productive
activities. For example, Boden holds (pace Chomsky) that the gener-
ation of previously unheard-of well-formed phrases in English is not
an instance of P-creativity, because such utterances are covered by the
grammar of the language, and thus in a sense could have been pro-
duced before. Genuine P-creativity requires a “change of conceptual
space” in which something emerges that would have been impossible
had the agent’s activity remained determined by the generative rules
which obtained before. It requires dropping one or more of the rules
that structure the conceptual space; and the “deeper” the rule that is
dropped (i.e., the more fundamental the role which the rule plays in
structuring the system), the more radically P-creative is the result.
David Novitz has criticized this criterion. Goodyear invented vulcan-
isation by dropping various substances into liquid rubber until he came
across the correct one by trial and error. He altered the conceptual
space for thinking about rubber, but his achievement was not creative;
so satisfaction of the modal criterion is insufficient for creativity. Nor
is it necessary: Jenner invented vaccination and should be counted as
creative, but there existed no conceptual space concerning vaccination