Merrell-WritingForkingPaths 1997
Merrell-WritingForkingPaths 1997
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
Borges Center, University of Pittsburgh is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and
extend access to Variaciones Borges
he could now be quite certain of each and every step as an atom unto
itself and divorced from the complex (intertextual) whole, he could
know nothing of the whole, that is, without throwing himself once
again into the unruly ocean of uncertainty.
to our world: at all costs we would like to fear not the possibility of our
signs and our world becoming hopelessly chaotic. Consequently, we
would be quite homeless and totally lost in Funes's world. It would
appear to us to be somewhat in the order of a Buddhist flash-dance
where everything is always already different. For Funes, what is be
coming isn't yet, and since it isn't yet, then once it is, it's already be
coming something else, but it isn't yet. What it will be, that is what it is
becoming, is the dissipation of what it was in the last moment, and
what it will have been becoming in the next moment. That is, at each
moment it is what it is, but it actually is not what it is because it is al
ways already transforming itself into something other than what it is.
But actually, in light of the above sections there is no guarantee that we
have any certainty we can put our fingers on than our hapless friend,
Funes. In fact, inspired by Funes's world, it would be possible for us to
imagine and invent new terms of all sorts at the drop of a hat, and we
would never cease to be surprised, awed, dumbstruck, and even either
shocked or numbed by the plethora of new signs we found ourselves
spewing forth. Funes, who can see only particulars, sees, in the sense of
the four levels of the "Garden," sees nothing but points. But a point is a
point, capable of containing many points, in fact, of containing all
points. The gazer of Borges's "Aleph" and the protagonist of the
"Garden" would like to think they perceive and conceive of everything
that is. In an abstract way of putting it, they perceive and conceive of a
concoction of points, which in its totality in in essence no more than a
point. Is their perceptual and conceptual grasp really superior to that of
Funes? What advantage, really, can they possibly have anyway? Are
they not trapped within the "hypertext" just as much as is Funes? Can
the same not be said of us?
that window, there is the open sea or the ramparts or one of the inner
courtyards of the fortress" (137). This affords him no more than a tun
nel perspective, or better, a funnel perspective. Since the funnel is inor
dinately long, it is possible that the walls could contain another cell
between his cell and the outside, and between this inner cell and the out
side, and the inner cell and his own cell, there could be two more cells,
and so on, a situation reminiscent of the "Menger sponge" of fractal dy
namics (for a discussion, see Stewart).2 It is also the image of a static
form of "intertextuality," the "hypertext" timelessly there for all time.
This being the case, the number of cells in the prison is unforseeable, as
is the total length of the walls of these cells. Moreover, if the "Menger
sponge" were complete, its virtually innumerable walls would finally
dissolve into space and the "sponge" would be completely empty.
Consequently, our prisoner would have no way of knowing how much
of the prison consists of walled cells and how much of unconfined
space. That is to say, if the "Menger sponge" prison were extrapolated
to its ultimate, it would consist of pure space, hence it would be no
prison at all but would allow for pure freedom. The walls would be in
finitely thin, no more than a mathematical imaginary line. Yet, the sum
of the area of the walls of the cells would be infinite, so at the infinite
stretch of things the prison, this cosmic prison, would in a sense be
more confining than ever, paradoxically. It would be a plenum.
In the dank darkness of his dungeon, the narrator's perception is more
auditory than visual, even with intractable elements of tactile, olfactory,
and gustatory imagery. He pricks up his ears at the faint sounds in
dicative of jagged spaces and forms around him. He tries to infer "the
network of the corridors, the turns, the openings, the straight lines bro
ken by the dragging of the kettle to the threshold of each cell and by
the creak of the locks," but succeeds "only in fixing a succession of
points in time, without any correspondence in space" (138). He be
comes obsessed with escape. But in order to realize his goal he must
first know the whole plan, the pattern, of the edifice. But he cannot
know the whole, for, like the human library rats in Borges's "Library of
Babel," he is caught within a minuscule portion of it.
Abbé Faria, another prisoner, has perforated the walls of the edifice in
every direction. His itineraries wind around themselves like a ball of
yarn or a "strange attractor." As a consequence, he long ago lost his
2 Indeed, we read that "the cell, the aperture, the corridors along which the jailer
comes twice a day with the soup and the bread could be simply tiny pores in a rock
of spongy consistency" (T Zero 138).
Faria even has trouble distinguishing one cell from another. As such,
the fortress has no favored point, no center. Or better, like Borges's
"Library," every point can be conceived as the center, and its circum
ference can therefore be construed as everywhere. In other words, it
appears to follow diverging, converging, convoluted, involuted, non
linear lines to nowhere and everywhere. In a strange way, it is rhizomic
(i.e. "hypertextual" in the most perverse way). And time, within this
"block" universe, is not that McTaggart A-Series time as a flow from
the past into the future along the knife-edge of the "now," but rather, it
is B-Series time consisting of static befores and afters with nothing in
between; it is "complex time," mathematical or "imaginary" time based
on the function of V-1, which is actually timelessness from the perspec
tive of our own subjective time.
Finally, as Faria opens another breach in a wall—or perhaps the floor
or the ceiling—he bursts into Alexandre Dumas's study, where the
author is in the process of writing a novel about the narrator in the for
tress. As it turns out, in this concentric fortress Dumas's desk contains
the narrator, and all the other prisoners as well, along with the treas
ure, and even the "supernovel" Monte Cristo, "with its variants and
combinations of variants in the nature of billions of billions but still in a
finite number" (T Zero 150).3 And we once again become trapped
within that paradox plaguing the four levels of the "Garden." Might we
call it the "intertext paradox," the "interdoxal paratext" (or perhaps
simply the "hypertext")?
3 We have read this story before, of course, from the narrator of Borges's "Library of
Babel" who is in the Library and in the act of writing the short story about the Li
brary which the reader is in the act of reading, also, presumably, from within that
selfsame Library.
4 Infinity, I must clarify at this juncture, comes in two shapes: actual infinity and po
tential infinity. We tend to experience a chalk mark on a blackboard as continuous
(an actual infinity) but it is not, for it merely fails to reveal noticeable gaps to the
naked eye. It is no more than the visible expression of a potential. Zeno's paradoxes
are predicated on the concept of a potential infinity (a never-ending succession of
steps). However, since the implication of actual infinity underlies this concept, Zeno
is not a finitist, and finitistic arguments, which merely banish the idea of the actual
infinite altogether, cannot legitimately dispel him (Benardete, Infinity 13-20).
were less than infinity, and yet if that number is virtually unfathom
able—as was the number of pages in the book for the narrator—then
there is no way one can know without a shadow of a doubt whether
the book is of infinite or finite length. What is more, there is no know
ing where the beginning and ending of the book are to be found, or
where one is when opening the book to a particular page. This is the
same dilemma that confounded the inhabitants of Borges's "Library."
For ages it has also been the dilemma we have confronted in this laby
rinth we call the universe. Is the universe infinite or finite? Orderly or
disorderly? If infinite and either orderly or disorderly, we cannot know
that it is so until and unless we reach the infiniteth point, which we
cannot do, so we cannot know. If it is finite and orderly, we can at least
in principle know it is so, but according to the latest scientific reports it
is more disorderly (chaotic) than orderly. Still, we cannot know, ulti
mately know.
Significantly, in this light, astrophysicist David Layzer ("Arrow" 68)
has put forth the radical hypothesis that not only can we, from our
"microcosmic" vantage, not know where we are in the universe, such
information would be impossible even at the "macrocosmic" level, for:
The order is unknowable even in principle. Imagine an unbounded
stack of playing cards, topless and bottomless, deck piled on deck
without limit. Information about the order of the cards in one section
of the stack is of no help, because any given sequence is repeated an
infinite number of times elsewhere, in the same way that patterns of
stars and galaxies are repeated throughout the universe. It is mean
ingless to say that you are at such and such a place in the stack, even
when you have full information about the order of the cards and that
place. You still don't know whereabouts you are in the stack, any more
than the typical observer knows whereabouts he is in the cosmos.
again, how can I say it, that's all words, they're all I have, and not
many of them, the words fail, the voice fails, so be it" (Molloy 413). The
protagonist of How It Is painfully inches forth in the ooze within which
he finds himself, having departed from an irretrievable beginning and
with no possible end in sight. If that last word could have come gur
gling from his mouth, from the depths of his body and mind, it would
have been virtually no word, perhaps a mere syllable, perhaps even
less, surely even less. It would have been well-nigh nothing, no-thing,
at the end of the Zenoesque infinitely stretched asymptote. It would be
itself and nothing but itself. It would be one pearl of the entire Buddhist
string of pearls each of which mirrors the whole. It would be a cosmic
black hole, or a "naked singularity"—or Borges's "Aleph"—containing
everything and every event in the entire history of the universe. In a
footnote at the conclusion of Borges's "Library" we read of a comparable
phenomenon. It consists of the hypothesis that, "rigorously speaking, a
single volume would be sufficient" (Labyrinths 58). The middle page of
this solitary, all-encompassing volume would have no reverse because it
would be the equivalent of "0," that marvelous state of absolute noth
ingness, whose origin lies in Buddhist philosophy and the Sanskrit lan
guage, separating the positive integers from the negative integers. It
would have no reverse side, for there would be nothing (no-thing) to see,
since an infinite series will not tolerate an existent final term.5
But actually, what have we in our infinite series if not the ultimate of
complexity? Of asymmetry, disequilibrium, fluctuation, dissipation,
fractal geometry, virtual chaos, that is, "hypertext"? And at the same
time, what is this complexity that we may somehow know it if it is not
the ultimate of simplicity? It must be of the most simple of simples, if,
ineffable though it is, we can nevertheless, and with great effort, some
how know it. From within this whole any part of which is tantamount
to the whole itself, perhaps the best we can do is create impoverished
images or struggle with our hopelessly inadequate language: Calvino's
"Prison," Borges's "Garden," that Buddhist string of pearls, the fractal
image of chaos that can be generated on the supersensitive monitor.
Ah, yes, the monitor, and its ubiquitous "internet," product of the most
recent monumental achievements of Western technology: its brilliant
hues dazzle us, perhaps allowing us to think we can gently lift the veil
somehow to perceive beyond. Beyond? No. Sheer illusion. There is no
beyond, for everything is within itself.
What are we, simple and fallible knowers, that we may somehow know
complexity and its concomitant chaos, and what is complexity
("hypertext") that it may somehow be known by us, minuscule parts of
that which is simply known?
Floyd Merrell
Purdue University
References