Leiter Paper
Leiter Paper
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
The University of Chicago Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Ethics.
http://www.jstor.org
I. INTRODUCTION
Nietzsche has long been one of the dominant figures in twentieth-
century intellectual life. Yet it is only recently that he has come into
his own in Anglo-American philosophy, thanks to a renewed interest
in his critical work in ethics.' This new appreciation of Nietzsche is
250
8. See Stephen Darwall, Allan Gibbard, and Peter Railton, "Toward Fin de siecle
Ethics: Some Trends," PhilosophicalReview 101 (1992): 115-89, p. 181. This forms the
subject matter of normativetheory, which these authors, following Baier, identify as the
primary target of those I am calling the Theory Critics.
9. See Jonathan Dancy, "Ethical Particularism and Morally Relevant Properties,"
Mind 92 (1983): 530-47.
10. Bernard Williams, Ethicsand theLimitsof Philosophy(Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard
University Press, 1985), pp. 16-17, cited hereafter in the text as ELP; Thomas Nagel,
"The Fragmentation of Value," reprinted in Mortal Questions(Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1979), pp. 131-32; Charles Larmore, Patterns of Moral Complexity
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987), p. 138; Charles Taylor, "The Diversity
of Goods," reprinted in Philosophyand the Human Sciences:PhilosophicalPapers 2 (Cam-
bridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985). Elsewhere in Ethics and the Limits of Philoso-
phy, Williams worries about a different kind of reductionism, i.e., the attempt to reduce
all practical reasoning and all obligation to moral reasoning and moral obligation. See
esp. chap. 10.
11. Bernard Williams, "Preface," in Moral Luck (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1981), p. x; Larmore, p. ix, chap. 1; Taylor. Something similar seems to be
Annette Baier's target in "Theory and Reflective Practices," and "Doing without Moral
Theory?" (reprinted in Posturesof the Mind, pp. 228-45), esp. in her talk of the theorist's
hierarchical ordering of more principles "in which the less general are derived from
the more general" ("Doing without Moral Theory?" p. 232) on the model of a legal
system ("Theory and Reflective Practices," p. 214) (where the latter is thought of, in
a pre-Legal Realist sense, as involving the deduction of particular decisions from
general rules).
12. Taylor aptly calls this the ambition for a "single-consideration procedure," a
label which suggests the unity of Reduction and Mechanical Decision, and objects that
such a procedure cannot do justice to "the real diversity of goods that we recognize"
(pp. 245, 247).
13. See Baier, "Theory and Reflective Practices" and "Doing without Moral The-
ory?"; and Williams, Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy,esp. pp. 115-17, 127, 202.
14. For example, Baier argues for ethical reflection without "normative theory
in the Kantian sense" while noting that "reflectiveness about our practices requires
at the very least noting whether they are counterproductive to their expressed aims"
("Theory and Reflective Practices," p. 226). Williams wonders throughout Ethics and
the Limits of Philosophy "why reflection should be taken to require theory" (p. 112)
and claims that "philosophy in the modern world cannot make any special claim to
reflectiveness" (p. 3). Taylor goes further and concedes that even if there are a
plurality of goods, "people ... are faced with the job of somehow making them
compatible in their lives" (p. 236) and that, as a result, "the demand for a unified
theory" is a "demand we cannot totally repudiate"- (p. 245).
15. This is clearest in the case of writers like Nagel and Larmore, who explicitly
affirm both the tenability of moral theory and the indispensable role of something like
Aristotle's practical wisdom orjudgment in our moral life. See Nagel, "The Fragmenta-
tion of Value," pp. 135-37; and Larmore, chap. 1, p. 151 ("My intention ... has not
been to deny the possibilities or importance of moral theory. I do not believe that
the complexity of morality is so great, so boundless, that it baffles any attempt at
systematization.").
21. A third difficulty is that some writers construe demands of, e.g., partiality and
integrity to be essentially moral demands, apart from their role in deontological and
consequentialist theories. See David Brink, "Utilitarian Morality and the Personal Point
of View," Journal of Philosophy83 (1986): 417-38, pp. 418- 19; Larmore, pp. 132-33.
This construal is not, I think, suggested by the writings of most Morality Critics them-
selves and, in any event, can be dealt with in the way suggested in the text.
22. Nagel speaks of morality posing "a serious threat to the kind of personal life
that many of us take to be desirable" (Viewfrom Nowhere, p. 190). Wolf claims that the
"moral saint" cannot realize "a great variety of forms of personal excellence" (p. 426).
Bernard Williams argues that both Kantian and utilitarian theories will sometimes
require us to abandon our "ground projects," those projects "which propel [a person]
in the future, and give him (in a sense) a reason for living" ("Persons, Character, and
Morality," in The Identities of Persons, ed. A. Rorty [Berkeley: University of California
Press, 1976], pp. 209- 10). See Bernard Williams, "A Critique of Utilitarianism," in J.
J. C. Smart and Bernard Williams, Utilitarianism:For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1973), pp. 77-150, esp. pp. 115-17, and Ethics and the Limits of
Philosophy, esp. pp. 181-82 (worrying that a Kantian notion of obligation can "come
to dominate life altogether"). Slote argues that a commitment to morality would require
us to "deplore and disavow" (p. 85) certain otherwise admirable traits like "single-minded
devotion to aesthetic goals or ideals" (p. 80)-because of their essential tendency also
41-60, p. 41). Note that for at least Williams, morality already does its damage-in
the form of "alienation"-once it asks us to view our personal projects as up for grabs
in moral deliberation (whether or not morality ultimately requires us to abandon them).
25. On the "objective purview" response: see, e.g., Peter Railton, "Alienation,
Consequentialism and the Demands of Morality," reprinted in Consequentialismand Its
Critics, ed. S. Scheffler (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1988), pp. 93-133, esp. pp.
113-17; see also Sarah Conly, "Utilitarianism and Integrity," Monist 66 (1983):
298-311, esp. p. 303. This general point is often put by saying that Utilitarianism
provides a criterion or standard of rightness, not a decision procedure. See Henry
Sidgwick, The Methods of Ethics, 7th ed. (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1981), bk. 4, chap. 1,
sec. 1, and chap. 3, sec. 3; R. E. Bales, "Act-Utilitarianism: Account of Right-Making
Characteristics or Decision-Making Procedure?" American Philosophical Quarterly 8
(1971): 257-65; Brink. On the "supererogation" response: see, e.g., Nagel, Viewfrom
Nowhere, pp. 203-4; Stephen Darwall, "Abolishing Morality," Synthese72 (1987): 71-89,
esp. pp. 78-83. Note that for the "Kantians," the ability of morality to accommodate
personal goods also derives from morality's objective or impersonal point of view. As
Nagel explains it, "The appearance of supererogation in a morality is a recognition
from an impersonal standpoint of the difficulties with which that standpoint has to
contend in becoming motivationally effective in the real life of beings of whom it is
only one aspect" (p. 204). In contrast, Barbara Herman argues that Kantianism indeed
does not permit "unconditional attachment"to personal projects irrespective of their
morality and that "it does not seem rational to want it otherwise." She claims further
that such unconditionalattachments are not even essential to one's character or integrity
(Barbara Herman, "Integrity and Impartiality," Monist 66 [1983]: 233-50, p. 243). See
also Conly's related response to Williams on behalf of Utilitarianism at pp. 305-11, p.
308 ("as much emotional attachment [to personal projects] as Williams wants, admittedly
more than utilitarianism allows, gives not so much integrity as something like solip-
sism"); and Marcia Baron's response to Slote in "On Admirable Immorality," Ethics 96
(1986): 557-66, esp. pp. 563-64 (single-minded devotion [to a project] that knows no
bounds is not admirable and is rightly prohibited by morality). I return to these issues
in n. 51, below.
26. Some cautionary notes about the distinction developed in this section between
Theory and Morality Critics are in order. There is, of course, a real distinction here,
but it may not be as easy to mark as I have so far suggested. Take, e.g., Susan Wolf's
remark that "the basic problem with any of the models of moral sainthood ... is that
they are dominated by a single, all-important value under which all other possible values
must be subsumed" (p. 431). As a freestanding complaint, this could be made by a
Theory Critic as well as a Morality Critic: for the former, it would come in the context
of an attack on the reductionist aims of Theory based on the real "diversity of goods";
for the latter, it would serve to show that the reason the ("perfect master's") Moral Life
is incompatible with the Good Life is that it privileges some type of moral value at the
expense of other, nonmoral values. Quite generally, it is easy to see how, e.g., objections
to the reductionist aims of Theory based on the plurality of values can quickly start to
sound like objections to Morality for wrongly overriding other distinct sources of value.
The difference here may only be a matter of emphasis, though it is a difference that
is real enough: the Theory Critic invokes the plurality of values to emphasize the
inadequacy of a theoretical framework which excludes so much, while the Morality
Critic invokes the plurality of values in order to emphasize the costs of morality's OT
and to argue against it. The ease with which we might move from one sort of criticism
to the other should not obscure the fact, however, that many writers lodge themselves
firmly in one camp rather than the other-in fact, only Williams and Foot seem to
take both sorts of critical positions. Wolf, e.g., is explicit in distancing herself from any
critique of theory per se: "The flaws of a perfect master of a moral theory need not
reflect flaws in the intramoral content of the theory itself" (p. 435). Rather, for Wolf,
such flaws show only the need for moretheory, a theory of "reasons that are independent
of moral reasons for wanting ourselves and others to develop our characters and live
our lives in certain ways" (p. 437).
27. A different question is whether he offers an ethical theory more akin to ancient
ones-say, a type of virtue ethics, as some recent writers have suggested. See, e.g.,
John Casey, Pagan Virtue:An Essay in Ethics (Oxford: Clarendon, 1990), esp. pp. 79-83;
Lester Hunt, Nietzscheand the Origin of Virtue(London: Routledge, 1991). The difficulties
with Hunt's account will serve to highlight the problems confronting this interpretation
of Nietzsche. According to Hunt, Nietzsche's theory of virtue is "procedural": "it speci-
fies which traits are virtues by indicating a certain process and declaring that any trait
that arises from this process is virtuous" (p. 145). The relevant process is given by
Nietzsche's "experimentalism," which requires us to experiment with different goals
until we find those which bring about "a complete integration of the psyche" (p. 141),
such that "one part of the self imposes order on other, potentially chaotic parts by
successfully orienting the subordinate parts towards its own purposes" (p. 128). The
traits that are conducive to the integrating goals are, says Hunt, virtues for Nietzsche.
There is certainly something broadly right about this picture, though its vagueness is
only one of its several problems. First, the theory seems not so much procedural as
substantive, since it employs a substantive criterion (integration of the self) for identi-
fying which goal-oriented activities involve virtues. Second, it seems to stretch
Nietzsche's ambitions considerably to attribute to him something called a "procedural
theory of virtue." Third, Hunt gives almost none of the detail about particular virtues
that interest most contemporary writers (including, e.g., Casey), even relegating
Nietzsche's own specific virtue lists to an endnote (p. 187, n. 4). While Hunt has a
multitude of interesting things to say about Nietzsche, it is not clear that his account
makes Nietzsche a virtue theorist of much practical or philosophical help.
28. For a more substantial discussion of these oft-neglected themes in Nietzsche's
work, see Brian Leiter, "The Paradox of Fatalism and Self-Creation in Nietzsche," in
Willing and Nothingness: Schopenhaueras Nietzsches Educator, ed. C. Janaway (Oxford:
Oxford University Press, in press).
29. For further discussion, see ibid.
30. See esp. Brian Leiter, "Morality in the Pejorative Sense: On the Logic of
Nietzsche's Critique of Morality," British Journal for the History of Philosophy 3 (1995):
113-45, and also Leiter, "Beyond Good and Evil," History of Philosophy Quarterly 10
(1993): 261-70. The former sets out the affinities and differences my account has with
those common in the secondary literature.
31. For some nonpejorative uses of the word 'morality', see, e.g., TI, IV, sec. 4
(where he speaks of the possibility of a "healthy morality" [gesundeMoral]), and BGE,
202 ("higher moralities" [Morale]). On the nature and content of such a morality, see
my "Beyond Good and Evil."
35. See D, 163; BGE, 62, 212; GM, III, sec. 14; A, 5, 24; EH, IV, sec. 4; WP, 274,
345,400, 870, 879, 957. For example, in a work of 1880 he writes, "Our weak, unmanly,
social concepts of good and evil and their tremendous ascendancy over body and soul
have finally weakened all bodies and souls and snapped the self-reliant, independent,
unprejudiced men, the pillars of a strong civilization" (D, 163). While in a posthumously
published note of 1885 he remarks that "men of great creativity, the really great men
according to my understanding, will be sought in vain today" because "nothing stands
more malignantly in the way of their rise and evolution ... than what in Europe today
is called simply 'morality"' (WP, 957). Similarly, in a late note of 1888, he observes (in
a passage plainly echoing the preface of GM), "Whoever reflects upon the way in which
the type man can be raised to his greatest splendor and power will grasp first of all that
he must place himself outside morality; for morality has been essentially directed to the
opposite end: to obstruct, or destroy that splendid evolution wherever it has been going
on" (WP, 897).
36. I should not be construed here as endorsing the idiosyncratic view defended
in the last chapter of Nehamas. According to Nehamas, Nietzsche does not describehis
ideal person-his "higher man"-but rather "exemplifies" such a person in the form
of the "character" that is constituted by and exemplified in his literary corpus. Nietzsche,
however, describesat great length and in many places (see D, 201; GS, 55; BGE, 287;
WP, 943) the types of persons he admires, and he also describes himself as such a
person (see EH, I, sec. 2). For further criticism of Nehamas on this and other points,
see my "Nietzsche and Aestheticism."
37. This type of simplifying move, however, does not obviously help us get a fix
on who "lower men" are supposed to be. Yet not saying more about "lower men" is not
necessarily problematic for my project here of characterizing Nietzsche's conception of
MPS. For the heart of Nietzsche's complaint is simply that MPS has a deleteriouseffect
on higher types(i.e., those who manifest human excellence). It is true that Nietzsche also
seems to think that MPS is in the interests of other persons- "lower men"-but this
by itself is not objectionable; recall that Nietzsche says, "The ideas of the herd should
rule in the herd-but not reach out beyond it" (WP, 287). It is this "reaching out
beyond," then, that is at issue because it is this that harms "higher men." If there were
a social order in which MPS existed-and in which it served the interests of "lower"
types-without having any effects on potentially "higher men," then one would imagine
that Nietzsche should have no objections. In that case, one could leave the issue of who
"lower men" are pleasantly vague without any cost to the analytical task of getting clear
about Nietzsche's critique of morality.
38. So an agent who says, colloquially speaking, "I would gladly lead my life again,
except for the time in my thirties when I was ill and depressed," would not affirm life
in the requisite sense.
39. For example, EH, III, Z-1: "The idea of the eternal recurrence, this highest
formulation of affirmation that is at all attainable" (cf. BGE, 56).
40. Some writers (e.g., Richard Schacht, Nietzsche[London: Routledge, 1983]) have
argued that Nietzsche objects to MPS centrally because it is harmful to "life." The main
difficulty with this approach, even as it is typically developed, is its vagueness: as Mark
Platts remarks, "Moralityversus life is not the best defined of battle lines" (Moral Realities
[London: Routledge, 1991], p. 220). I argue elsewhere that when Nietzsche speaks of
morality being harmful to "life," he really means harmful to "higher men"; see my
"Morality in the Pejorative Sense," pp. 132-34. Other writers (including Schacht again)
have suggested that Nietzsche criticizes morality by reference to his preferred standard
of "value" as "will to power." I ignore this possibility here, because it seems to make
the notion of "will to power" more central to Nietzsche's mature thought than recent
43. One problem with this view is that its endpoint-the abolition of suffering
and the reign of happiness-is an impossibility because Nietzsche holds that "happiness
and unhappiness are sisters" (GS, 338), that we must have both in order to have either.
Although the unity of apparent opposites is a recurring theme in Nietzsche, it is not
central to his objection to this aspect of MPS. A useful discussion of this theme can be
found in Nehamas, pp. 209-11.
44. Nietzsche no doubt construes the doctrine thus uncharitably because he thinks
that the "British utilitarians ... walk clumsily and honorably in Bentham's footsteps"
and that they have "not a new idea, no trace of a subtler version or twist of an old idea"
(BGE, 228). Mill, of course, was at pains to develop a subtler hedonistic doctrine than
Bentham's, though it is an open question whether in the process he does not pour all
the content out of the notion of "pleasure." In any event, Nietzsche drew no distinction
between Bentham and Mill-referring to the latter (in an especially intemperate spirit)
as "the flathead John Stuart Mill" (WP, 30).
45. Compare GS, pref. 3: "Only great pain is the ultimate liberator of the spirit....
I doubt that such pain makes us 'better'; but I know that it makes us more profound."
46. For a general account, see Ronald Hayman, Nietzsche:A CriticalLife (New York:
Penguin, 1980).
47. Compare this letter of January 1880, quoted ibid., p. 219: "My existence is a
fearful burden. I would have thrown it off long ago if I had not been making the
most instructive tests and experiments on mental and moral questions in precisely this
condition of suffering and almost complete renunciation."
48. Nietzsche, in fact, reverses the MPS valuation, commenting, "Never have I felt
happier with myself than in the sickest and most painful periods of my life" (EH, III,
HAH-4).
50. Indeed, even among Morality Critics we sometimes hear echoes of the specifi-
cally Nietzschean worry, e.g., in the famous Gauguin case, where it is supposed that
the Moral Life would undermine "great creativity," or in Wolf's worry that the moral
saint cannot achieve "any of a great variety of forms of personal excellence" (p. 426).
Moreover, we have already noted that there is clearly an element of extremism running
through Nietzsche's critical position; e.g., we can be sure that Nietzsche would not
agree with Wolf that a critique of morality does not show "that moral value should not
be an important, even the most important, kind of value we attend to in evaluating and
improving ourselves and our world" (p. 438). Yet we can live (probably happily) with
these differences of degree and still think that Nietzsche joins cause with the Morality
Critics, quite broadly, in accepting the truth of IT and rejecting OT.
51. See the literature cited above in n. 25. As we saw earlier, there are really two
strands in the responses to the Morality Critics: what we might call "Bullet Biters" and
"Accommodationists." Bullet Biters like Conly, Herman, and Baron simply "bite the
bullet" on the challenge of the Morality Critics: yes, these writers concede, morality is
incompatible with a certain sort of commitment to personal projects-but so much the
better, the Bullet Biters claim. For the sort of ability of personal projects to override
morality that the Critics envision is not appealing, admirable, or central to a person's
character or integrity. By contrast, Accommodationists like Railton, Nagel, and Darwall
accept the force of the Critics' challenge but claim that morality can, contrary to IT,
accommodate the sorts of personal projects that the Morality Critics care about. It is
the response of the Accommodationists that is analogous to the challenge posed by the
Harm Puzzle. (Needless to say, the line between the two types of theory defenders is
not hard and fast. See Railton's account of why "alienation is not always a bad thing,"
pp. 106-8, and compare with the position of the Bullet Biters.)
52. For doubts that this is, in fact, an adequate response, see Wolf, p. 428. For
related discussion of the important political dimension of these issues, see Railton, pp.
122-23; and Nagel, ViewfromNowhere, pp. 206-7. For a very different perspective on
this debate, however, see the scathing critique of the Morality Critics (including Wolf)
in Catherine Wilson, "On Some Alleged Limitations to Moral Endeavor," Journal of
Philosophy90 (1993): 275-89.
53. Of course, the theorist might object that, even if Nietzsche were right, all this
would show is that our cultural practices need correction by a suitable moral theory,
one that will permit nascent Nietzsches to suffer and the like. I shall postpone this
worry for now and consider it, and several other objections to Nietzsche's position, in
the final section of this paper.
54. Compare Lawrence Becker's observation that defenders of morality's commit-
ment to impartiality try to show that the "purported inadequacies [of impartiality] ...
are not really attributable to a propertheoreticalcommitmentto impartiality" ("Impartiality
and Ethical Theory," Ethics 101 [1991]: 698-700, p. 700, emphasis added). See also
Stocker: "[The phenomenon of] admirable immorality ... show[s] how immorality and
defect can and must be allowed for in ethical theory" (Michael Stocker, Plural and
Conflicting Values [Oxford: Clarendon, 1990], p. 50).
55. Indeed, one might pick out various points where the Morality Critics seem to
echo Nietzsche. Compare Wolf: "A moral saint will have to be very, very nice. It is
important that he not be offensive. The worry is that, as a result, he will have to be
dull-witted or humorless or bland" (p. 422); cf. BGE, 260: "the good human being
[according to slave morality] has to be undangerous ... : he is good-natured, easy to
deceive, a little stupid perhaps, un bonhomme.Wherever slave morality becomes prepon-
derant, language tends to bring the words 'good' and 'stupid' closer together."
56. The reader may wonder in what sense Nietzsche's claims are empirical, since
they are hardly the upshot of systematic investigation into, say, the psychology and
etiology of genius. They are empirical, however, in the sense that Nietzsche seems to
have reached these conclusions from certain sorts of observation: first, and most im-
portant, of himself and his own development (note that the theme only appears in his
work in the very late 1870s, when he is about thirty-five and has already been ill for
several years); second, of various historical figures and cultures with which he was
acquainted through his studies and reading. As I note at the end, though, the case for
his critique really requires a more sustained empirical examination.
57. Compare Annette Baier's complaints about the irrelevance of moral theory,
of its "construction of private fantasy moral worlds" ("Doing without Moral Theory?"
p. 235; cf. p. 234).
61. See Nehamas, pp. 202-3; Philippa Foot, "Nietzsche's Immoralism," New York
Review of Books 38 (June 13, 1991), p. 19, reprinted in Nietzsche, Genealogy,Morality.
62. Nietzsche's polemic against Christianity in TheAntichristis framed in the starkest
Calliclean terms, with Nietzsche describing "the cross as the mark of recognition for
the most subterranean conspiracy that ever existed-against health, beauty, whatever
has turned out well, courage, spirit, graciousness of the soul, against life itself" (A, 62);
see also WP, 400: "In the history of morality a will to power finds expression, through
which now the slaves and oppressed, now the ill-constituted and those who suffer from
themselves, now the mediocre attempt to make those value judgments prevail that are
favorable to them."
63. Nietzsche also often blames "Christianity," but we must remember that for
Nietzsche Christianity was simply "the most prodigal elaboration of the moral theme
to which humanity has ever been subjected" (BT, pref. 5).
64. Foot, "Nietzsche: The Revaluation of Values," p. 168.
65. To say that they take the demands of MPS "seriously" is not to say that they
understand them in the way a philosophical theory would; it is only to say that they
are more likely to take these unsystematic and inchoate demands constitutive of morality
as weighing seriously upon them.
66. See the earlier quotations from Zarathustra's description of the last man.
67. In his Calliclean moods, of course, Nietzsche believes that morality really aims
to undermine the Extraordinary Life, but one might reject the Callicleanism and still
think there is something to the underlvinz causal claim.
68. Robert Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia (New York: Basic, 1974), p. 247.