The Separation of Powers in A Post-Apartheid South Africa
The Separation of Powers in A Post-Apartheid South Africa
The Separation of Powers in A Post-Apartheid South Africa
Volume 8
Article 11
Issue 2 Vol 8. #2/3 Winter/Spring 92/93
1993
Recommended Citation
Ellmann, Stephen. "The Separation of Powers in a Post-Apartheid South Africa." American University International Law Review 8 no.
2/3 (1993): 455-482.
This Symposium or Conference is brought to you for free and open access by the Washington College of Law Journals & Law Reviews at Digital
Commons @ American University Washington College of Law. It has been accepted for inclusion in American University International Law Review by
an authorized administrator of Digital Commons @ American University Washington College of Law. For more information, please contact
[email protected].
THE SEPARATION OF POWERS IN
A POST-APARTHEID SOUTH AFRICA
Stephen Ellmann"
* Associate Professor of Law, New York Law School. I thank Philip Kurland,
Louis Henkin, Nancy Rosenbloom, and Peter Strauss for their comments on an earlier
draft of this paper.
1. Debate continues in this country over such issues as whether our existing
governmental arrangements separate powers too thoroughly, or not thoroughly enough;
whether the constitutional role of the president is being undermined by Congress, or
the other way around; whether the primary mission of the courts in adjudicating sepa-
ration of powers cases should be to adjust our venerable constitution to modern reali-
ties, or instead to rescue the insights of the founders from the distortions of modern
governmental maneuvering; and whether the courts should intervene in separation of
powers cases at all, or should rather leave the political branches of the government to
resolve their conflicts through political struggle. The resolution of these American
debates is not my concern here, but I will explore certain elements of these ongoing
arguments in the course of this essay.
456 AM. U.J. INT'L L & POL'Y [VOL. 8:455
new United States lacked the Framers' confidence that this system by
itself would preserve their liberties, and their insistence on a Bill of
Rights led to its speedy adoption in the first years of the Constitution's
life. But the principles of the separation of powers, and of checks and
balances, have remained important themes of American constitutionalism.
It has never been our constitutional strategy to protect liberty simply by
relying on a Bill of Rights and an independent judiciary to block the
wrongdoing of politicians.
Our experience offers good reason to believe in the importance of
judicial enforcement of a Bill of Rights, but it confirms the Framers'
belief that structural restraints are also needed. Even in a constitutional
state, lawmakers have tremendous discretion. Our Bill of Rights is large-
ly a negative one, forbidding certain government actions while requiring
few and authorizing many-but the point would be essentially the same
even if South Africa were to adopt the kinds of affirmative socioeco-
nomic rights that the ANC's draft bill of rights proposes. How the gov-
ernment acts within the immense zone of the "permissible but not re-
quired" is extremely important to human liberty broadly understood.
Lawmakers who escape the perils of judicial statutory interpretation
(roughly as potent a source of judicial authority in this country as in
yours) are free to act in this zone without constitutional constraint. In
this country, for example, Congress is largely free to decide that welfare
benefits will not be increased in proportion to the increasing number of
children in a family receiving those benefits-or to decide the opposite.'
What Congress decides makes a great difference to the families receiv-
ing those benefits, and perhaps to other people as well, but the Constitu-
tion as currently read will not normally prescribe an answer.s
In addition, the dimensions of what is or is not unconstitutional will
not be subject to wholly apolitical adjudication. The decisions of the
United States Supreme Court, or of South Africa's Appellate Division,
offer ample evidence of the breadth of the judges' discretion and the
degree to which the judges' perspectives on their world affect their deci-
sions.' This is not to disparage the ideal of an impartial judiciary, but
4. See Dandridge v. Williams, 397 U.S. 471, 482 (1970) (holding that a state
welfare regulation limiting the maximum family grant does not violate the Equal
Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment, so long as it is "rationally based and
free from invidious discrimination"). A comparable standard would apply to federal
action, which would be evaluated in this respect under the Fifth Amendment.
5. Ma
6. See STEPBEN ELLAtkNN, IN A TiLE OF TROUBLE: LAW AND LBERrY' iN
SOUTH AFRICA'S STATE OF EMERGENCY (1992) (discussing the influences on the
458 AM. U.J. INT'L L & POL'Y [VOL. 8:455
South African Appellate Division's decisions in cases dealing with the state of emer-
gency).
7. Ingo Miller, in his fierce history of German law under the Nazis, notes that
the judges of the German Empire "whose conscience would not permit them to serve
the republic instead of the kaiser were offered early retirement by the government,
with full consideration of their material needs. Less than 0.15 percent of judges took
advantage of this opportunity, however." INGO MOLLER, HITLER'S JUSTICE: TIlE
COURTS OF THE THIRD REICH 10 (Deborah Lucas Schneider trans. 1991). Even
though the remaining judges swore their loyalty to the nation, Mifller maintains that
the judges "kept their distance from the republic and continued to take what remained
of the old values as their point of orientation." Id Miller also argues that as the
Nazis rose to prominence during the Weimar republic years, "[i]n many trials...
the courts continued to take the Nazi side of the ongoing political struggle, sometimes
openly, sometimes behind the fagade of legal maneuvers." Id. at 17. See also David
A.J. Richards, Terror and the Law, 5 HuM. RTs. Q. 171, 179 (1983) (discussing the
"authoritarian bias" of the Weimar judiciary, including its opposition to "legal action
against . . . the Nazi authoritarian terror of the right").
8. See Philip B. Kurland, The Rise and Fall of the "Doctrine" of Separation of
Powers, 85 MICH. L. REv. 592, 604-13 (1986). Kurland argues that "[w]ith the
1993] POST-APARTHEID SOUTH AFRICA 459
compromise between the slave states and the free, or freer, states, and
this compromise proved untenable." The nation could not hold together
while the institution of slavery divided it. The resolution of this issue
led the nation through secession and civil war to a revised Constitution
which declared the abolition of slavery, commanded the states no longer
to deny to their people, black and white alike, the equal protection of
the laws, and laid the groundwork for the federal government's enforce-
ment of these principles. 3 I do not mention this piece of history in
order to attribute our Civil War to particular defects in the allocation of
power, though I suspect the elements of our separation of powers did
play their part in shaping the politics of the antebellum years. Rather,
my point is a larger one: a society with intolerable injustices enshrined
or protected by its constitution will not survive. Put more bluntly, unless
a new South African government has the constitutional power to right
the wrongs of apartheid, there will be little reason for optimism about
South African stability or freedom.' 4
These are very broad lessons indeed: that checks on power besides a
bill of rights are needed, and that ineffectual or unjust government must
be avoided. But they do have concrete relevance to South Africa. They
counsel against a system of government in which the only constraints on
majority will are those of the bill of rights as interpreted by the courts.
They also counsel against a government so hamstrung by the need for
consensus among people of sharply different views that it is unable to
respond to the problems South Africa faces. Put more concretely still,
they counsel against both pure majoritarianism and thoroughgoing
12. See DON FEHRENBACHER, THE DRED ScoTr CASE: ITS SIGNIFICANCE IN
AMERICAN LAW AND POLITIcS 26-27 (1978) (noting that though the Constitution
never uses the word "slavery," it nonetheless plainly "acknowledg[es] the legitimate
presence of slavery in American life"). Perhaps the most notorious of its euphemistic
acknowledgements was the "three-fifths clause," which provided for the apportionment
of congressional representation and of direct taxes among the states based on figures
determined by the states' free population and "three fifths of all other Persons." U.S.
CoNsT. art. I, § 2.
13. These guarantees are the promise of the Thirteenth and Fourteenth Amend-
ments.
14. Herman Cohen, then Assistant Secretary of State, made a similar point when
he reported to a congressional subcommittee that a future South African constitution
"'should avoid overly complex arrangements intended to guarantee a share of power
to particular groups which will frustrate effective governance. Minorities have the right
to safeguards. . . . They cannot expect a veto.'" Jim Lobe, South Africa: U.S.
Against White Veto in New Government, INTER PREss SERv., July 23, 1992, available
in LEXIS, Nexis Library, Wires File.
1993] POST-APARTHEID SOUTH AFRICA 461
15. See Reynolds v. Sims, 377 U.S. 533, 568 (1964) (holding "that, as a basic
constitutional standard, the [Fourteenth Amendment's] Equal Protection Clause requires
that the seats in both houses of a bicameral state legislature must be apportioned on
a population basis"). That representation in bicameral legislatures is proportional to
population is probably more the result of the series of Supreme Court reapportionment
decisions beginning with Reynolds than it is the product of decisions initiated by the
states themselves. Nonetheless, the judicial imposition of a duty of equal representa-
tion has not triggered any movement among the states to abandon bicameralism.
462 AM. U.J. INT'L L & POL'Y [VOL. 8:455
22. See Farber & Sherry, supra note 2, at 112-34 (tracing and offering excerpts
from the Convention debates on this issue).
23. Farber & Sherry, supra note 2, at 119.
24. The framers' debates on this score depart dramatically from the image of
gentlemanly colloquy which Americans often take to have been the reality of the
Constitutional Convention. In particular, George Bedford, a delegate from the small
state of Delaware, declared that:
[The large states] insist that although the powers of the general government will
be increased, yet it will be for the good of the whole; and although the three
great States form nearly a majority of the people of America they never will
hurt or injure the lesser states. I do not, gentlemen, trust you. If you possess
the power, the abuse of it could not be checked; and what then would prevent
you from exercising it to our destruction?
Id.at 125 (quoting Bedford, as reported in the notes of fellow delegate Robert Yates)
(emphasis in original). Perhaps the lowest point was reached when Bedford moved
from distrust to threats:
The Large States dare not dissolve the Confederation. If they do the small ones
will find some foreign ally of more honor and good faith, who will take them
by the hand and do them justice.
Id.
25. NATIONAL PARTY FRAMEWORK, supra note 16.
26. NATIONAL PARTY FRAMEWORK, supra note 16, at 11.
1993] POST-APARTHEID SOUTH AFRICA 465
31. THE FEDERALIST No. 47, at 301 (James Madison) (Clinton Rossiter ed.,
1961).
32. THE FEDERALIST NO. 51, at 322 (James Madison) (Clinton Rossiter ed.,
1961).
33. CONVENTION FOR A DEMOCRATIC SOUTH AFRICA, DECLARATION OF INTENT I
5(d) (adopted at the first meeting of CODESA, Dec. 20-21, 1991), reprinted in NE-
GOTIATION NEws, Apr. 24, 1992, at 16 [hereinafter CODESA DECLARATION].
34. See THE FEDERALIST No. 47, at 301 (James Madison) (Clinton Rossiter ed.,
1961) (commenting that during the debates over ratification of our Constitution, "[o]ne
of the principal objections inculcated by the more respectable adversaries to the Con-
stitution [was] its supposed violation of the political maxim that the legislative, exec-
utive, and judiciary departments ought to be separate and distinct").
35. ANC PRINCIPLES, supra note 16, 1 3.2, at 21.
36. NATIONAL PARTY FRAMEWORK, supra note 16, at 13.
1993] POST-APARTHEID SOUTH AFRICA
37. For a detailed analysis of the British system (an analysis on which I rely
here), see Wilson supra note 18.
38. That is, the Prime Minister is "the person best able to form and maintain a
majority in the House of Comrnmons,"-the leader of the majority party when, as is
the case today, a single party does hold a majority.
39. Wilson, supra note 18.
40. Constitutional convention obliges Ministers to "publicly maintain complete
loyalty to the government's policies," and binds the other majority party Members of
Parliament (the "backbenchers") "to comply with their leaders' wishes on specific
votes." Id. Lest these conventions be violated (as can happen, id. at 138 n. 78), the
Prime Minister enjoys, inter alia, "enormous powers of patronage" with which to
bend resistant party members to his or her will. ladat 141-42.
41. See Wilson, supra note 18, at 140-41; Lloyd M. Cutler, To Form a Govern-
ment, reprinted in REFO M NG AmRICAN GOvERNmrES. THE BICENTENNIAL PAPERS
OF THE COMVY1rrrEE ON THE CONSTITUTIONAL SYSTEM 11, 14 (Donald L Robinson
ed., 1985) [hereinafter REFORMING AMERICAN GOVERNMENT].
42. See Wilson, supra note 18, at 139 (explaining that "upon a vote of no confi-
dence, the backbenchers can force the Prime Minister to resign or dissolve Parlia-
ment"). The latter course, the dissolution of parliament, results in the election of a
new Parliament. I&
43. See GRETCHEN CARPENTER, INTRODUCTION TO SOUTH AFRICAN CONST"U-
TiONAL LAW 74 (1987).
44. The 1983 Constitution created a tricameral Parliament for South Africa, in
which whites, "Coloureds," and Indians-but not Africans--each have a House). See
Republic of South Africa Constitution Act of 1983, §§ 37, 52. Whites, however, and
468 AM. U.J. INT'L L & POL'Y [VOL. 8:455
in particular the National Party as the majority party in the white "House of Assem-
bly," remain preeminent. National Party discipline has historically been strong, see
HERMANN GIMOMEE, Afrikaner Politics: How the System Works, in HERIBERT ADAM
& HERMANN GIIOMEE, ETHNIC POWER MOBILIZED: CAN SOUTH AFRICA CHANGE?
200-01 (1979), and so this party controls the results of votes in the House of Assem-
bly. Even without the members it has recently gained in the other houses, the Nation-
al Party's control over the whites' house has been enough to insure its control over
the government as a whole. If the Coloured house (the "House of Representatives")
or the Indian house (the "House of Delegates") rejects proposed legislation which the
House of Assembly has approved (or vice-versa), then the State President may choose
to submit the disagreement for resolution to a body known as the President's Council.
The State President may also choose not to submit the disagreement to the Council,
thereby preventing the bill in question from becoming law. See Republic of South
Africa Constitution Act of 1983, §§ 32, 78. The State President, to whom this deci-
sion is entrusted, is effectively elected by the white majority party, id § 7; HAROLD
G. RUDOLPH, Constitutional Law, in ANNUAL SURVEY OF SOUTH AFRICAN LAW 1983
1, 4 (1985), and is, in fact, the leader of this party. Moreover, the President's Coun-
cil is so composed that the National Party and the State President can readily ensure
that this Council too works the will of the Nationalists-though this party will not
necessarily consider it expedient to override opposition in the other Houses. See Re-
public of South Africa Constitution Act § 70. See Rudolph, supra, at 1-9 (offering
comprehensive treatment of these and other features of the 1983 Constitution).
45. Normally the President is chosen by popular election (more precisely, by
"electors" selected in each state based on the popular vote for President in that state);
only in the event that no candidate wins election by this process does the House of
Representatives select the President. See U.S. CONST. art. H, § 1, amended by U.S.
CONST. amend. XII.
46. Id. art. I, § 6.
47. Id. art. I, §§ 2, 3; Id. art. II, § 1.
1993] POST-APARTHEID SOUTH AFRICA 469
other party, nor does Congress have any authority to remove the Presi-
dent from office on the basis of a vote of "no confidence."' Yet while
Congress and the President are so plainly capable of having very differ-
ent perspectives on public policy, the passage of legislation generally
requires the two branches to concur. If the President vetoes a bill passed
by Congress, it will not become law unless a two-thirds majority votes
to override the veto. 9 This system is meant to prevent government ac-
tion-not all government action, to be sure, but that action which is the
product of what Madison called "faction," of segments of the communi-
ty, even majority segments of the community, acting in a way that is
unjust or unwise for the community as a whole.'
There have been powerful criticisms of the American system from
respected observers of, and participants in, our government. You will
hear from one of these critics, Lloyd Cutler, tomorrow. Mr. Cutler can
speak for himself, and from a wealth of experience, but let me outline
part of his critique in order to pursue my own argument here. Cutler
has argued that in our system of divided and mutually resistant authority
the President cannot, in his words, "form a government" and enact a
legislative program. Though he does not urge that this country adopt a
parliamentary system, he has written admiringly of such systems, in
which a slim majority can work its will, subject of course to the ulti-
mate test of the voters' approval or disapproval at the next elections.
Cutler maintains that on many issues of our day consensus is unattain-
able; indeed, even when the President's party holds a congressional
majority, consensus on the President's proposals is far from automatic.
Effective government therefoer requires that action should not await the
consensus that our system makes so important. In essence, Cutler main-
tains that the Framers succeeded too well; at least in our day, the sys-
tem they designed may avoid the dominance of faction only by weaken-
ing the government at a time when we need, as perhaps the Framers did
not, to have the government in action."
48. Congress can only remove the President from office by impeachment for
"Treason, Bribery, or other high Crimes and Misdemeanors." L. art. I § 4. No
President has ever been removed from office this way.
49. Id. art. I, § 7.
50. See THE FEDERALIST No. 10 (James Madison); GEOFFREY R. STONE, Louis
M. SEIDMAN, CASS R. SUNSTEIN, AND MARK V. TUsHNEr, CONSTITUTIONAL LAW 12-
14 (2d ed. 1991).
51. See Cutler, supra note 41; LLOYD N. CUTLER, Political Parties and a Work-
able Government, in A WORKABLE GOVERNMIENT? THE CONSTITUTION AFrER 200
YEARS 49-58 (Burke Marshall ed., 1987). For similar critiques of the American con-
470 AM. U.J. INT'L L & POL'Y [VOL. 8:455
parties a distinct capacity to resist policies that they dislike." This does
not make this system perfect for either those who share the views of the
National Party or those who share the views of the ANC. Nonetheless,
it may make it a useful compromise. Furthermore, the details of the
American structure need not be your blueprint; it is open to the parties
in South Africa, as some Americans urge we should do here at home, to
modulate the separation of powers, with a view to enhancing the power
of government to act. No doubt you have already begun looking at the
various solutions that other countries, from Germany to Namibia, have
devised to address these concerns.5
3. The Structure of the Executive Branch: One of the central doctrinal
points of American law governing separation of powers is that our Con-
stitution provides for a "single executive." There is one President, and
55. See HOROWrIZ, A DEMOCRATIC SOUTH AFRICA?, supra note 30, at 205, 214
(endorsing a "separate, directly elected executive" for South Africa in part on the
ground that this structure limits the chance that any single group can "capture the
state permanently by merely capturing a majority in parliament"). Horowitz also main-
tains that if the electoral system is properly designed the election of the President can
be an "arena for intergroup conciliation." Id at 205.
56. See Lloyd N. Cutler, Modern European Constittions and Their Relevance in
the American Context, in REFORMING AMERICAN GOVERNNT, supra note 41, at
299-312 (discussing the structures of government that have evolved in the United
Kingdom, France and Germany). Namibia's recently adopted Constitution establishes a
President who is elected directly by the people, and can only be removed by the
legislature by impeachment, a procedure which requires a two-thirds majority in both
houses of the legislature. See NAMIBIA CONST. arts. 28, 29. In these respects,
Namibia's system closely resembles that of the United States. Namibia ties the Pres-
ident somewhat more closely to Parliament than does the United States, however, for
Namibia authorizes the President to dissolve the National Assembly (the popularly
elected house of Parliament) "if the Government is unable to govern effectively," and
that step must be followed by new elections for both the National Assembly and the
President. Id art. 57. Even when the President exercises this power, however, the link
between the fate of the executive and legislative branches is not complete, for the
second house of Parliament, the National Council, is not subject to dissolution by the
President. See id (making no provision for dissolution of the National Council). Nor
are the Council's members elected directly by the people, as are the President and
the members of the Assembly. I, art. 69. The powers of the National Council are
not as great as those of the National Assembly, but they include the ability, in cer-
tain circumstances, to block the passage of legislation in the absence of a two-thirds
majority in the Assembly. NAMIBIA CONST. arts. 74, 75(5).
57. See Peter L. Strauss, The Place of Agencies in Government: Separation of
Powers and the Fourth Branch, 84 COLUM. L. REv. 573, 599-600 (1984) ("the Con-
vention clearly and consciously chose a single and independent executive over a colle-
gial body subject to legislative direction").
472 AM. U.J. INT'L L & POL'Y [VOL. 8:455
one only, and that person is vested with the "executive Power."58 This
decision, a fundamental choice made by the Framers after considering
alternative structures,59 rests on the belief that vesting power in a single
executive will make government both more effective and more ac-
countable than would a more diffuse system of executing the laws.'
This decision is frankly inconsistent with the National Party proposal.
That proposal stated "that the office of head of state and of government
should be vested in a collective body known as the Presidency," to
"consist of the leaders of the three largest parties" in the lower ("First")
house of Parliament, making decisions "by consensus," with the chair-
manship of this collective entity and the position of "State President" (if
such a position is actually established) changing hands on a rotating
basis."' Since no one member of the Presidency will be able to control
its decisions, this proposal is dangerously likely to impede effective
executive action and dissipate executive accountability.' It will also
deprive South Africa of the symbol of national unity, and source of
national leadership, that a single executive can provide-as we have
seen in this country, and as you have seen, not least under F.W. de
Klerk, in yours.
But American experience by no means counsels that each and every
element of the execution and administration of the law must be under
the control of a single person. This may seem paradoxical, given what I
have just said about the Framers' decision in favor of a single exec-
utive. Whether or not it is paradoxical, it is certainly controversial;
recent years have seen both court opinions and scholarly commentary
focused on explicating just how powerful the President must be. 3 I will
Synar, 478 U.S. 714, -721-734 (1986); Richard J.Pierce, Jr., Morrison v. Olson, Sepa-
ration of Powers, and the Structure of Government, 1988 SUP. Cr. REv. 1; Miller,
supra note 11; Strauss, supra note 57.
64. ANC PRINCIPLES, supra note 16, at 26, 5.
65. Id at 31, 14; NATIONAL PARTY FRAmeWORK, supra note 16, at 7.
66. Id.
67. See Wilson, supra note 18, at 129 (maintaining that 'the powers to hire and
fire largely determine constitutional structures"). I use the term "subordinates" some-
what loosely, since, as Professor Kurland suggested in his comments when this paper
was presented, the more the President's power to hire, fur, and direct an official is
constricted the less "subordinate" that official is. Cf. Mordson v. Olson, 487 U.S.
654, 719-23 (1988) (Scalia, J., dissenting) (distinguishing between "subordination" and
mere differences "in station or rank").
68. According to Buckley v. Valeo, 424 U.S. 1, 126 (1976), "any appointee exer-
cising significant authority pursuant to the laws of the United States is an 'Officer of
the United States,'" who must be appointed in accordance with the appointments
clause of the Constitution, U.S. CONST. art II, § 2, cl. 2. This clause by its terms
AM. U.J. INT'L L & POL'Y [VOL. 8:455
cide when appointments can be made. For example, Congress may pro-
vide by legislation that holders of an office serve a term longer than
that of the President, and thereby can delay or even eliminate the
President's chance to fill the office in question.' When appointments
are made, moreover, the Constitution requires Senatorial advice and con-
sent for all appointments of principal officers. The Constitution also
permits Congress to require this procedure for all officers of the United
States- a very wide category of officials." Congress has also enacted
legislation limiting the President's choice of appointees, by requiring the
President to appoint from, or at least consider, lists of nominees pre-
pared by others, or by specifying that those appointed must have partic-
ular credentials (such as political party membership).7' In addition, Con-
gress can decide to vest the appointments of "inferior officers" in the
heads of executive departments rather than in the President." Congress
can also place the appointment of at least some "inferior officers," in-
cluding even officials as powerful as independent prosecutors appointed
to prosecute government wrongdoing, outside of the executive branch
altogether and into the hands of the courts.'" Finally, the Constitution
does not expressly limit Congress' authority to control the appointment
of those other government employees who do not wield enough authori-
ty to count as "officers of the United States."' At the very least, it
authorizes the President to "nominate, and by and with the Advice and Consent of
the Senate .... appoint" the most senior of these officials. Lesser, or "inferior,"
officers can be appointed in the same way, or Congress may choose to alter the pro-
cess, by vesting these appointments "in the President alone, to the Courts of Law, or
in the Heads of Departments"-but Congress' discretion does not extend to making
these appointments itself. Id
69. This device was first used within a few years of the nation's founding. In
Marbury v. Madison, 5 U.S. 137, 162 (1803), Chief Justice Marshall appeared to take
for granted that Congress could constitutionally provide for the appointment of justices
of the peace to hold office for five-year terms-one year longer than the term of the
incoming President).
70. U.S. CONST. art. II, § 2, cl.2.
71. See Metropolitan Washington Airports Auth. v. Citizens for the Abatement of
Aircraft Noise, 111 S. Ct. 2298, 2319 (1991) (White, J., dissenting) (citing instances
in which the Supreme Court voiced no objection to statutory requirements that the
President consider lists of candidates); see also Miller, supra note 11, at 51 (noting
that "the independent regulatory commissions .. . almost uniformly . .. [have] politi-
cal criteria for appointment, with no more than a majority allowed to come from one
party").
72. See supra note 68 (discussing the appointment of officials).
73. See Morrison v. Olson, 487 U.S. 654, 670-77 (1988) (holding that Congress
may vest the authority to appoint an independent counsel to a special federal court).
74. The appointments clause speaks explicitly only to the appointment of "offi-
1993] POST-APARTHEID SOUTH AFRICA 475
seems clear that Congress can direct that these lesser officials be hired
through civil service procedures over which the president's control is
restricted."
Similarly, limiting the President's power to fire officials also con-
strains Presidential authority. Again, our Constitution is currently un-
derstood to deny Congress authority to fire executive "officers" except
through the rarely used mechanism of formal impeachment." But that
does not mean that the President has unchallenged power in this sphere.
Where appointment is not vested in the President but in lesser offi-
cials-as would be the case for a great many civil service
appointments-Congress has long been thought to have authority to
regulate the conditions of discharge." Even where the President ap-
points, his or her freedom to discharge may be constrained. At one time,
the Supreme Court seemingly held the view that the President was con-
stitutionally entitled to fire a wide range of officials at will.' Subse-
quent cases, however, including one very recently, have decidedly cir-
cunscribed this notion.' If the President cannot fire "at will" but only
for "cause," presidential power is reduced. If the President cannot treat
as "cause" a subordinate's refusal to comply with presidential policy
80. For an argument that the power to remove "for cause" should be interpreted
to allow the removal of policymaking officials when they "fail[] to comply with any
valid policy decision made by the President or his agent," see Pierce, supra note 63,
at 24-35. See also Miller, supra note 11, at 44-45, 50-97 (contending that the Presi-
dent must be able "to remove a policy-making official who has refused an order of
the President to take an action within the officer's statutory authority").
81. For example, it will make a difference whether the President has a right to
be informed of lesser officials' planned actions before they are undertaken; without
such an authority, as Peter Strauss argues, the President is less able to coordinate
policy and less able to bring political pressure to bear on officials who seek to chart
a course with which the President disagrees. See Strauss, supra note 57, at 646-47.
On this score, the Constitution somewhat obscurely provides that the President "may
require the Opinion, in writing, of the principal Officer in each of the executive
Departments, upon any Subject relating to the Duties of their respective Offices." U.S.
CONsT. art. II, § 2, cl. 1. See Strauss, supra note 57, at 646-47 (providing a broad
interpretation of this clause).
So, too, it matters whether the President has the prerogative of communicating
with other officials confidentially, or whether instead the legislature can insist on
being provided with full accounts of internal executive deliberations. See id. at 653-
62. The Constitution contains no express grant of an "executive privilege," but the
Supreme Court has declared that this "privilege of confidentiality of Presidential com-
munications" is "fundamental to the operation of Government and inextricably rooted
in the separation of powers under the Constitution"-although it is not absolute. Unit-
ed States v. Nixon, 418 U.S. 683, 705, 708 (1974).
19931 POST-APARTHEID SOUTH AFRICA 477
Although the president might well find such a person, the process of
doing so would-and in comparable circumstances actually did, during
the unraveling of the Watergate scandal-exact a political cost.'
By channeling or limiting the President's appointment and removal
powers, and by vesting particular duties in specified subordinate offi-
cials, legislation in this country has been able to place important ele-
ments of executive power to some degree outside the President's control.
It deserves mention that legislation on these issues also has often at-
tempted to insure that particular areas of government policy were to
some extent beyond partisan control by either political party-in partic-
ular by offering members of both the majority and the minority party
some input into decision-making. Such nonpartisan policy-making seems
to be an aspiration of statutes that divide seats on administrative agen-
cies between the Democratic and Republican parties, although American
political parties are so ideologically inclusive that such systems are not
in themselves likely to deny the President the chance to select people,
from either party, with whose views he or she is largely content.' If
the South African Constitution that is now being written is to limit
executive power, and ensure that minority views are heard in the pro-
cess of policy-making, such steps may prove helpful. So, for example, a
Judicial Service Commission might be required to have representation
from each of the major parties, and the President required to pick judges
from nominees submitted by the Commission.' Such structures could
restrain the power of the single executive without the drastic inroads on
governmental efficacy that the consociational model risks.
4. Preserving in practice what you set out on paper. Benjamin
Franklin, already a venerable statesman when he served as a member of
the Constitutional Convention, supposedly was asked after the Conven-
tion what kind of government the Framers had shaped for the American
82. See Peter L. Strauss, Letter to the Editors of the Harvard Law Review, May
22, 1992 (copy on file with the author); Strauss, supra note 57, at 605 (suggesting
that Congress has considerable discretion to "plac[e] ultimate responsibility for deci-
sion" on particular matters with subordinate officials rather than with the President).
See also Miller, supra note 11, at 58-59 (similarly observing that it was "accepted
early on that Congress could not only create executive departments but could make
action by the agency head a precondition of the effective exercise of the power").
83. I am grateful to Peter Strauss for this point.
84. See NAMIBIA CONST. arts. 82, 85 (providing that the President is to appoint
judges "on the recommendation of the Judicial Service Commission"; two of the five
members of the Judicial Service Commission are appointed by organizations of the
legal profession rather than by the president).
478 AM. U.J. INT'L L & POL'Y [VOL. 8:455
people. He answered, "A republic, if you can keep it."" Keeping your
republic, or democracy, must be as great a concern for you as it was,
and is, for Americans. The record of African states on this score is not
good, and South Africa itself has a dreary record of oppression of hu-
man rights. Designing a system that will hold up over time is by no
means easy.
United States history demonstrates this proposition-if any proof is
needed. The Framers of our Constitution are revered as unusually far-
sighted and wise, but they evidently failed to predict that so fundamen-
tal an institution as the political party would become an important fea-
ture of the new United States.' It was only a few years after the Con-
stitutional Convention when many of them began to form the political
party system which has been a critical part of our polity ever since.
Similarly, many of the Framers viewed the greatest danger to republican
liberty as coming from the legislatureY Today, many Americans are
convinced that the executive branch has long since overmatched the
Congress in the struggle for power. So, too, the Framers apparently
anticipated a rather straightforward, and modest, role for the courts."
Modem Americans live in a world in which concern about judicial
power undermining democratic self-government is a recurrent theme.
And, as you have already heard, the Framers anticipated a relatively
small central government, carrying out relatively confined functions,89
but the reality of modem American life is far removed from this. Not
only does the federal government do vastly more and the states relative-
85. See Kurland, supra note 8, at 613 and n.51 (citing 3 THE RECORDS OF THE
FEDERAL CONVENTION OF 1787 85 (Max Farrand ed., 1911).
86. See Kurland, supra note 8, at 599; see also James MacGregor Burns, THE
DEADLOCK OF DEMOCRACY: FOUR-PARTY POLITICS IN AMERICA 27 (rev. ed. 1963)
(noting that "most Americans in the early 1790s did not want parties").
87. See THE FEDERALIST No. 48 (James Madison). Other delegates to the Consti-
tutional Convention, however, may have seen the executive branch as the greatest
source of peril. See Kurland, supra note 8, at 598 (discussing the fears of some at
the Constitutional Convention about concentrated power in the executive branch).
88. Kurland, supra note 8, at 599. In his defense of the new Constitution's pro-
visions for the judiciary, Hamilton was able both to insist on the courts' power to
declare statutes unconstitutional and to characterize the judiciary as the branch "least
dangerous to the political rights of the Constitution," and "incontestably . . . beyond
comparison the weakest of the three departments of power." THE FEDERALIST No. 78,
at 465-66 (Alexander Hamilton) (Clinton Rossiter ed., 1961).
89. See THE FEDERALIT No. 45, at 292 (James Madison) (Clinton Rossiter ed.
1961) (contrasting the powers of the federal government, which are "few and de-
fined," with the states' "numerous and indefinate" powers).
1993] POST-APARTHEID SOUTH AFRICA 479
90. See JESSE FL CHOPER, JUDICIAL REVIEW AND THE NATIONAL POLITICAL
PROCESS: A FUNCTIONAL RECONSIDERATION OF THE ROLE OF THE SUPREME COURT
287 (1980) (commenting that "at least before the tenure of President Nixon, the re-
cord demonstrates that an effective functioning of the relationship between the legisla-
tive and executive branches has been almost wholly accomplished without the partic-
ipation of the national judiciary").
91. See id. at 275 (arguing that "[e]ach branch-legislative and executive-has
tremendous incentives jealously to guard its constitutional boundaries and assigned
prerogatives against invasion by the other. If either branch perceives a constitutional
violation of this kind, not only will it be encouraged to respond vigorously but each
department possesses an impressive arsenal of weapons to demand observance of
constitutional dictates by the other"). See i& at 275-314 (detailing the "strictures on
ultra vires executive action").
92. See ROBERT M. COVER, JUSTICE ACCUSED: ANTISLAVERY AND TIM JUDICIAL
PROCESS 132 (1975) (commenting on "the growing sanctity of the Constitution" by
the beginning of the nineteenth century and noting that "[f(or most Americans, and,
certainly for the legal profession, the Constitution was supreme law but had a moral
authority beyond its supremacy as positive law").
480 AM.U.J. INT'L L & POL'Y [VoL. 8:455
93. At least some of the flexibility of our constitutional structure seems to have
been intended. As Peter Strauss has commented, "[o]ne scanning the Constitution for
a sense of the overall structure of the federal government is immediately struck by its
silences." Strauss, supra note 57, at 597. In particular, the Constitution says scarcely
anything about the structure of the executive branch below the Presidency. Strauss
concludes that "a determination was made to eschew detailed prescription as a means
of underscoring presidential responsibility and preserving congressional flexibility with-
in the constraints of the judgments that had been made." Id.at 599. Moreover, he
argues, "[t]he imprecision inherent in the definition and separation of the three gov-
ernmental powers contributes to the tensions among them," and this very tension helps
protect the liberty of the people. Id. at 603.
Even if such flexibility was not intended, however, our patterns of constitution-
al interpretation have often found room in the constitutional text for the infusion of
modern perspectives. Terrance Sandalow maintains that although the framers "set us
on the path" to our present constitutional understandings, "[tihe entirety of [our) histo-
ry, together with current aspirations that are both shaped by it and shape the meaning
derived from it, far more than the intentions of the framers, determine what each
generation finds in the Constitution." Terrance Sandalow, Constitutional Interpretation,
79 MicH. L. REv. 1033, 1042, 1050 (1981). "Ultimately," he believes, "the values to
which constitutional law gives expression are more nearly those of the present than
those of the past." It.at 1039. It is possible to deny the legitimacy of such reinter-
pretation of the largely unamended language of our Constitution, but very hard to
deny that it has often taken place.
94. See Immigration and Naturalization Service v. Chadha, 462 U.S. 919 (1983)
(holding the congressional veto provision in the Immigration and Naturalization Act
unconstitutional). In Chadha, the Supreme Court insisted on what it saw as the
Constitution's limits on Congress' exercise of legislative power. In the process, it
appeared to say that Congress is exercising legislative power when its action has "the
purpose and effect of altering the legal rights, duties, and relations of persons . . .
outside the Legislative Branch." Id. at 952. As a definition of legislative power, this
formulation is clearly ill-formed, since it would encompass a wide variety of actions
by courts and executive agencies as well. For Critical assessments of this aspect of
Chada's definition of legislative power, see Peter L. Strauss, Was There a Baby in
the Bathwater? A Comment on the Supreme Court's Legislative Veto Decision. 1983
DUKE L.J. 789, 794-98; E. Donald Elliott, INS v. Chadha: The Administrative Consti-
1993] POST-APARTHEID SOUTH AFRICA
tution, the Constitution, and the Legislative Veto, 1983 S. Cr. REv. 125, 134-38.
95. See Morrison v. Olson, 487 U.S. 654, 726 (1988) (Scalia, J., dissenting) (dis-
cussing the danger of further congressional interference with the President's power to
remove subordinates because "[t]here are now no lines" within which Congress must
stay).
96. See Choper, supra note 90, at 263 (stating this position, the "Separation
Proposal"); id. at 260-379 (discussing and defending this proposal).
97. For critical assessments of Choper's proposal, see Redish & Cisar, supra note
52, at 492-94; Strauss, supra note 57, at 620-21, n.194.
482 AM. U.J. INT'L L & POL'Y [VOL. 8:455
yours. I hope this dip into American experience helps you in your work.