Categorical Proposition Lecture Note
Categorical Proposition Lecture Note
Compiled by : Mohammed Z
Originated by Aristotle, the concept of categorical propositions has
constituted one of the core topics in logic for over 2,000 years. It remains
important even today because many of the statements we make in
ordinary discourse are either categorical propositions as they stand or
are readily translatable into them. Standard form categorical propositions
represent an ideal of clarity in language, and a familiarity with the
relationships that prevail among them provides a backdrop of precision
for all kinds of linguistic usage.
OUTLINE
● Categorical Propositions
○ The Components of Categorical Propositions
○ Attributes of Categorical Propositions: Quality, Quantity, and Distribution
○ Representing Categorical Propositions
■ Venn Diagrams
■ Boolean and Aristotelian Square of Oppositions
● Evaluating Immediate Inferences: Venn Diagrams and Square of Oppositions
● Logical Operations: Conversion, Obversion, and Contraposition
● Translating Ordinary Language Statements into Categorical Form
Objectives:-
By the end of this chapter, you will be able to:
1. Define and identify categorical propositions:
• Understand the fundamental structure of categorical propositions, including their subjects, predicates, and copulas.
• Distinguish between affirmative and negative propositions, as well as universal and particular propositions.
• Recognize the four basic forms of categorical propositions (A, E, I, O).
2. Explain the key components of categorical propositions:
• Analyze the roles of subjects, predicates, copulas, and quantifiers within propositions.
• Understand the concepts of quality, quantity, and distribution, and their impact on the meaning of propositions.
• Explain how categorical propositions categorize subjects and predicates.
3. Represent categorical propositions using various formats:
• Construct Venn diagrams to visually represent the relationships between subjects and predicates in propositions.
• Apply the Boolean and Aristotelian square of oppositions to categorize and compare different propositional forms.
• Translate propositions from ordinary language into formal categorical form.
4. Evaluate immediate inferences from categorical propositions:
• Use Venn diagrams and the square of oppositions to identify valid immediate inferences from given propositions.
• Recognize valid inferences like conversion, obversion, and contraposition.
• Analyze the limitations of immediate inferences and their dependence on propositional form.
5. Apply logical operations to transform propositions:
• Perform conversion, obversion, and contraposition on categorical propositions to derive new valid conclusions.
• Understand the conditions under which each operation is valid and the limitations involved.
• Utilize logical operations to analyze and manipulate arguments based on categorical propositions.
The Components of Categorical Propositions
● A categorical proposition is a statement that establishes a relationship between two classes or
categories. The subject term represents one class, while the predicate term represents another class.
The proposition asserts that either the entire subject class or a portion of it is either included in or
excluded from the predicate class.
● Given that a categorical proposition asserts the inclusion or exclusion of the subject class in relation to
the predicate class, we can identify four distinct types of standard form of categorical propositions:
1. Universal Affirmative: These propositions assert that the entire subject class is included in the
predicate class. For example, "All birds can fly" states that every member of the subject class (birds) is
part of the predicate class (things that can fly).
2. Particular Affirmative: These propositions assert that only a portion of the subject class is included
in the predicate class. For instance, "Some dogs are friendly" indicates that at least some members of
the subject class (dogs) fall into the predicate class (friendly animals).
3. Universal Negative: These propositions assert that the entire subject class is excluded from the
predicate class. An example would be "No insects are mammals," which states that no member of the
subject class (insects) is part of the predicate class (mammals).
4. Particular Negative: These propositions assert that a portion of the subject class is excluded from
the predicate class. For instance, "Some fruits are not citrus" indicates that at least some members of
the subject class (fruits) do not belong to the predicate class (citrus fruits).
5
A categorical proposition that expresses these relations with complete clarity is called a
standard-form categorical proposition. A categorical proposition is in standard form if
and only if it is a substitution instance of one of the following four forms:
1. All S are P.
2. No S are P.
3. Some S are P.
4. Some S are not P
Many categorical propositions, of course, are not in standard form because, among
other things, they do not begin with the words “all,” “no,” or “some.”
6
● Quantifiers are words that specify the extent to which the subject class is
included in or excluded from the predicate class. The quantifiers "all," "no," and
"some" play this role in categorical propositions.
● The use of "all" indicates that the entire subject class is included in the
predicate class, while "no" asserts that the entire subject class is excluded from
the predicate class. On the other hand, the word "some" always signifies that at
least one member of the subject class is involved.
● To represent these propositions symbolically, the subject term is represented
by the letter S, and the predicate term is represented by the letter P. The words
"are" and "are not" serve as the copula, linking or connecting the subject term
with the predicate term.
● quantifiers such as "all," "no," and "some" specify the quantity or extent of
inclusion or exclusion between the subject and the predicate classes in a
categorical proposition. The copula, represented by "are" and "are not," acts as
the linking word that couples the subject term and the predicate term together.
7
Exercise
In the following categorical propositions identify the quantifier, subject term,
copula, and predicate term.
1. All electric vehicles are cars that reduce greenhouse gas emissions..
2. Some social media platforms are websites that promote misinformation..
3. No fast food chains that use sustainable packaging are companies that
contribute to plastic pollution.
4. Some renewable energy sources are technologies that harness solar power.
5. All online learning platforms are tools that provide accessible education.
6. Some self-driving cars are vehicles that improve road safety.
8
Quality, Quantity, and Distribution
9
● The quality of a categorical proposition refers to whether it affirms or denies class membership.
Categorical propositions can be classified as either affirmative or negative based on their quality.
○ Affirmative propositions state that there is a connection or inclusion between the subject and
predicate classes. For example, "All S are P" and "Some S are P" are affirmative propositions.
They affirm that there is a relationship between the subject class (S) and the predicate class (P).
○ Negative propositions deny the class membership or connection between the subject and
predicate classes. Examples of negative propositions include "No S are P" and "Some S are not
P." These propositions express the absence of a relationship or inclusion between the subject class
(S) and the predicate class (P).
● The quantity of a categorical proposition refers to whether the statement applies universally or only to a
portion of the subject class.
○ Universal propositions make a claim about every member of the subject class. Both "All S are P"
and "No S are P" are universal propositions, as they assert something about every member of the
subject class (S).
○ Particular propositions, on the other hand, assert something about one or more members of the
subject class without making a claim about all of them. "Some S are P" and "Some S are not P" are
particular propositions since they refer to at least one member of the subject class (S), without
encompassing the entire class.
10
● It is important to note that the quantity of a categorical proposition can often be determined by
examining the quantifier used. The words "all" and "no" immediately imply universal quantity, while
the word "some" implies particular quantity. However, it is worth mentioning that categorical
propositions do not have a specific "qualifier" term.
● In universal propositions, the quality is determined by the quantifier used. For example, in the
proposition "All S are P," the quantifier "all" indicates universal quantity, and the proposition is
affirmative. Similarly, in the proposition "No S are P," the quantifier "no" implies universal quantity,
and the proposition is negative.
● In particular propositions, the quality is determined by the copula, which is the linking verb between
the subject and predicate terms. For instance, in the proposition "Some S are P," the copula "are"
indicates particular quantity, and the proposition is affirmative. In contrast, in the proposition "Some S
are not P," the copula "are not" suggests particular quantity, and the proposition is negative.
● To provide a concise way of denoting the four different kinds of categorical propositions, they are
commonly designated by letter names corresponding to the first four vowels of the Roman alphabet:
A, E, I, and O.
- The universal affirmative proposition is represented by an A proposition.
- The universal negative proposition is represented by an E proposition.
- The particular affirmative proposition is represented by an I proposition.
- The particular negative proposition is represented by an O proposition.
11
The material presented thus far in this section may be summarized as follows:
12
● Distribution is an attribute that applies to the terms (subject and predicate) of categorical
propositions, unlike quality and quantity which are attributes of the propositions
themselves.
● A term is considered distributed if the proposition makes a statement about every member
of the class indicated by that term. In other words, a term is distributed if the proposition
assigns or attributes something to every member of the class it represents. On the other
hand, if the proposition does not make an assertion about every member of the class, the
term is considered undistributed.
● To remember the rule for distribution, it can be helpful to use a mnemonic: "Unprepared
Students Never Pass." By focusing on the first letter of each word in this phrase, one can
recall that Universals (A and E statements) distribute Subjects, while Negatives (E and O
statements) distribute Predicates.
● In summary, distribution is an attribute of the terms in categorical propositions, and it
determines whether the proposition makes a statement about every member of a class.
Universal statements distribute their subject terms, and negative statements distribute their
predicate terms.
13
Another mnemonic that accomplishes the same purpose is “Any Student Earning
B’s Is Not On Probation.” In this mnemonic the first letters may help one recall that
A statements distribute the Subject, E statements distribute Both terms, I
statements distribute Neither term, and O statements distribute the Predicate
14
Exercise
identify the letter name, quantity, and quality. Then state whether the subject and
predicate terms are distributed or undistributed.
1. Some entrepreneurs are innovators who disrupt traditional industries with their groundbreaking ideas..
2. All renewable energy sources are alternatives that reduce dependence on fossil fuels.
3. Some social media platforms are tools that facilitate global communication and networking.
Change the quality but not the quantity of the following categorical propositions:
1. Some slumlords are people who eventually wind up in jail.
2. Some scientific discoveries are breakthroughs that revolutionize our understanding of the universe.
3. No addictive substances that are consumed in excess are beneficial to long-term health
Change the quantity but not the quality of the following categorical propositions:
1. Some prescription medicines are substances hazardous to human health
2. Some shelter animals are not good prospects for adoption.
3. No tax proposals that favor the rich are fair proposals.
15
Venn Diagrams and the Boolean (modern) Square of Opposition
● The main objective of our investigation into categorical propositions is to understand their role
in constructing arguments. However, universal propositions (A and E) can be interpreted in
two distinct ways, and depending on which an argument may be valid or invalid. Therefore,
before analyzing arguments, we need to explore the two possible interpretations of universal
propositions. Our exploration will primarily focus on a concept known as existential import.
● To illustrate the concept of existential import, let's consider the following pair of
propositions:
○ All Tom Cruise's movies are hits.
○ All unicorns are one-horned animals.
● In everyday conversation, the first proposition implies that Tom Cruise has indeed made
some movies. In other words, the statement carries existential import. It suggests that one or
more movies associated with Tom Cruise actually exist. On the contrary, the second
statement does not make such an implication. Although the statement can be considered true
because unicorns, by definition, have a single horn, it does not imply the actual existence of
unicorns.
16
● The question arises as to how universal propositions should be interpreted in
terms of implying the actual existence of the entities being discussed. Two
different approaches have been taken by logicians in response to this question.
● From an Aristotelian standpoint, it is held that universal propositions about
existing entities do carry existential import. In other words, such propositions
imply the existence of the entities being referred to. For example:
○ "All pheasants are birds" implies the existence of pheasants.
○ "No pine trees are maples" implies the existence of pine trees.
○ "All satyrs are vile creatures" does not imply the existence of satyrs because they are
mythical beings.
● In this viewpoint, the first two statements have existential import because their
subject terms denote entities that actually exist. However, the third statement
has no existential import because satyrs do not exist.
17
From a Boolean standpoint:
"All trucks are vehicles" does not imply the existence of trucks.
"No roses are daisies" does not imply the existence of roses.
"All werewolves are monsters" does not imply the existence of werewolves.
The Aristotelian standpoint is receptive or open to existence. It
acknowledges the existence of things, and universal statements about
those things carry existential import, existence holds significance within
this perspective. On the contrary, the Boolean standpoint is closed or
unreceptive to existence. It does not recognize the existence of things,
even when they do exist. Therefore, universal statements about those
things do not carry existential import. It is important to note that neither
the Aristotelian nor the Boolean standpoint recognizes the existence of
things that do not exist. In such cases, the Aristotelian standpoint aligns
with the Boolean standpoint.
18
● The Aristotelian standpoint and the Boolean standpoint differ only in their
treatment of universal (A and E) propositions. However, they are identical when
it comes to particular (I and O) propositions. Both standpoints acknowledge that
particular propositions assert the existence of entities. For instance, from both
standpoints, the statement "Some cats are animals" affirms the existence of at
least one cat that is an animal. Likewise, from both standpoints, "Some fish are
not mammals" asserts the existence of at least one fish that is not a mammal.
Thus, the term "some" implies existence according to both standpoints.
● Due to its closed stance on existence, the Boolean standpoint is simpler
compared to the Aristotelian standpoint, which recognizes existential
implications. Therefore, our focus will initially be on arguments analyzed from the
Boolean standpoint.
19
Venn Diagrams
From the Boolean standpoint, the four kinds of categorical propositions have the
following meaning. Notice that the first two (universal) propositions imply nothing
about the existence of the things denoted by S:
● All S are P.= No members of S are outside P.
● No S are P. = No members of S are inside P.
● Some S are P. = At least one S exists that is a P.
● Some S are not P. = At least one S exists that is not a P.
20
A Venn diagram is a visual representation that uses overlapping circles to depict the classes indicated by
the terms in a categorical proposition. Since every categorical proposition consists of two terms, a Venn
diagram for a single proposition comprises two circles that intersect. Each circle is labeled to represent
one of the terms in the proposition. By convention, the circle on the left represents the subject term, while
the circle on the right represents the predicate term. The diagram is typically illustrated as follows:
The individuals belonging to the class represented by each term should be envisioned as being located
within their respective circles. Consequently, if there are any members in the S class (if it exists), they will
be situated inside the S circle. Similarly, if there are any members in the P class (if it exists), they will be
positioned inside the P circle. If there are individuals located within the region where the two circles
overlap, it signifies that these individuals belong to both the S class and the P class. Lastly, individuals
situated outside both circles are not members of either the S class or the P class.
21
Venn diagrams can be utilized to visually represent the information conveyed by
the four types of categorical propositions. In order to do this, specific marks are
employed in the diagram. Two types of marks are used: shading an area and
placing an X in an area. Shading an area indicates that the shaded region is
devoid of any elements, while placing an X in an area signifies the existence of at
least one element within that region. The X can be understood as representing
that particular element. If no mark is present in an area, it indicates that no
information is known about that region; it may contain members or it may be
empty.
24
If two propositions are related by the contradictory relation, they necessarily
have opposite truth value. Thus, if a certain A proposition is given as true, the
corresponding O proposition must be false. Similarly, if a certain I proposition is
given as false, the corresponding E proposition must be true. But no other
inferences are possible. In particular, given the truth value of an A or O
proposition, nothing can be determined about the truth value of the corresponding
E or I propositions. These propositions are said to have logically undetermined
truth value. Similarly, given the truth value of an E or I proposition, nothing can be
determined about the truth value of the corresponding A or O propositions. They,
too, are said to have logically undetermined truth value.
25
Testing Immediate Inferences
26
Arguments of this sort are called immediate inferences because they have only one
premise. Instead of reasoning from one premise to the next, and then to the
conclusion, we proceed immediately from the single premise to the conclusion. To test
this argument for validity, we begin by assuming that the premise, which is an O
proposition, is true, and we enter this truth value in the square of opposition. We then
use the square to compute the truth value of the corresponding A proposition. By the
contradictory relation, the A proposition is false. Since the conclusion claims that the A
proposition is false, the conclusion is true, and therefore the argument is valid.
Arguments that are valid from the Boolean standpoint are said to be unconditionally
valid because they are valid regardless of whether their terms refer to existing things.
27
From the Boolean standpoint, the existential fallacy is a formal fallacy that occurs whenever an argument is invalid merely
because the premise lacks existential import. Such arguments always have a universal premise and a particular conclusion.
The fallacy consists in attempting to derive a conclusion having existential import from a premise that lacks it.
Existential fallacy
All A are B.
No A are B.
28
Note: while all of these forms proceed from a universal
premise to a particular conclusion, it is important to see that
not every inference having a universal premise and a
particular conclusion commits the existential fallacy. For
example, the inference “All A are B; therefore, some A are not
B” does not commit this fallacy. This inference is invalid
because the conclusion contradicts the premise. Thus, to
detect the existential fallacy, one must ensure that the
invalidity results merely from the fact that the premise lacks
existential import.
29
Exercise
Draw Venn diagrams for the following propositions
1. Some political campaigns are mere attempts to discredit opponents.
2. All novels are works of fiction.
3. No tax audits are pleasant experiences for cheaters
4. Some birds are not creatures that can fly.
5. All bicycles are vehicles that rely on pedal power.
use the modern square of opposition to determine whether the following immediate inferences
are valid or invalid from the Boolean standpoint.
1. It is false that some computers are devices that process information electronically. Therefore, no
computers are devices that process information electronically.
2. No fertility drugs are solutions to every problem. Therefore, it is false that all fertility drugs are
solutions to every problem.
3. It is false that no credit cards are things that contain holograms. Therefore, some credit cards are
things that contain holograms.
30
Conversion, Obversion, and Contraposition
Conversion, obversion, and contraposition are operations that can be performed on a
categorical proposition, resulting in a new statement that may or may not have the
same meaning and truth value as the original statement. Venn diagrams are used to
determine how the two statements relate to each other.
Conversion
The simplest of the three operations is conversion, and it consists of switching the
subject term with the predicate term. For example, if the statement “No foxes are
hedgehogs” is converted, the resulting statement is “No hedgehogs are foxes.” This
new statement is called the converse of the given statement. To see how the four
types of categorical propositions relate to their converse, compare the following sets of
Venn diagrams:
31
32
Obversion
More complicated than conversion, obversion requires two steps: (1) changing the quality
(without changing the quantity), and (2) replacing the predicate with its term complement. It
consists in changing “No S are P” to “All S are P” and vice versa, and changing “Some S are
P” to “Some S are not P” and vice versa.
The second step requires understanding the concept of class complement. The complement
of a class is the group consisting of everything outside the class. For example, the
complement of the class of dogs is the group that includes everything that is not a dog (cats,
fish, trees, and so on). The term complement is the word or group of words that denotes the
class complement. For terms consisting of a single word, the term complement is usually
formed by simply attaching the prefix “non” to the term. Thus, the complement of the
term “dog” is “nondog,” the complement of the term “book” is “nonbook,” and so on.
33
34
As is the case with conversion, obversion can be used to supply the link between the premise and the
conclusion of immediate inferences. The following inference forms are valid:
All A are B
Therefore, no A are non-B.
No A are B
Therefore, all A are non-B
Some A are B
Therefore, some A are not non-B
35
Contraposition
Like obversion, contraposition requires two steps: (1) switching the
subject and predicate terms and (2) replacing the subject and predicate
terms with their term complements. For example, if the statement “All
goats are animals” is contraposed, the resulting statement is “All non-
animals are nongoats.” This new statement is called the contrapositive of
the given statement. To see how all four types of categorical propositions
relate to their contrapositive, compare the following sets of diagrams:
36
37
Exercise
The question below provide a statement, its truth value in parentheses, and a new
statement. Determine how the new statement was derived from the given
statement and supply the truth value of the new statement.
38
The Traditional (Aristotelian) Square of Opposition
Up until now, we have been utilizing the Boolean standpoint, and we have observed
how the modern square of opposition remains valid regardless of whether the
propositions pertain to actual existing entities. In this section, we will now adopt the
Aristotelian standpoint, which acknowledges that universal propositions concerning
existing entities carry existential implications. For such propositions, the traditional
square of opposition becomes applicable. Similar to the modern square, the
traditional square of opposition is a configuration of lines that demonstrates logically
necessary relationships among the four types of categorical propositions. However,
due to the Aristotelian standpoint's recognition of the additional factor of existential
import, the traditional square enables more inferences than the modern square. It is
visually represented as follows:
39
40
Testing Immediate Inferences
Next, let us see how we can use the traditional square of opposition to test immediate inferences for validity. Here
is an example:
All Rolex watches are works of art. Therefore, it is false that no Rolex watches are works of art.
We begin, as usual, by assuming the premise is true. Since the premise is an A proposition, by the contrary
relation the corresponding E proposition is false. But this is exactly what the conclusion says, so the argument is
valid. Here is another example:
Some viruses are structures that attack T cells. Therefore, some viruses are not structures that attack T cells
Here the premise and conclusion are linked by the subcontrary relation. According to that relation, if the premise
is assumed true, the conclusion has logically undetermined truth value, and so the inference is invalid. It commits
the formal fallacy of illicit subcontrary. Analogously, inferences that depend on an incorrect application of the
contrary relation commit the formal fallacy of illicit contrary, and inferences that depend on an illicit application of
subalternation commit the formal fallacy of illicit subalternation.
41
Existential Fallacy
existential fallacy is committed from the Aristotelian standpoint when and only
when contrary, subcontrary, and subalternation are used (in an otherwise correct
way) to draw a conclusion from a premise about things that do not exist. All such
inferences begin with a universal proposition, which has no existential import, and
they conclude with a particular proposition, which has existential import. The
existential fallacy is never committed in connection with the contradictory relation,
nor is it committed in connection with conversion, obversion, or contraposition, all
of which hold regardless of existence. The following inferences commit the
existential fallacy from the Aristotelian standpoint:
42
All witches who fly on broomsticks are fearless women. Therefore, some
witches who fly on broomsticks are fearless women.
The first depends on an otherwise correct use of the subalternation relation, and
the second on an otherwise correct use of the contrary relation. If flying witches
and magical wizards actually existed, both arguments would be valid. But since
they do not exist, both arguments are invalid and commit the existential fallacy. In
regard to the second example, recall that the conclusion, which asserts that an A
proposition is false, is actually a particular proposition. Thus, this example, like the
first one, proceeds from the universal to the particula
43
Conditionally Valid
conditionally valid applies to an inference after the Aristotelian standpoint has been
adopted and we are not certain if the subject term of the premise denotes actually existing
things. For example, the following inference is conditionally valid:
All students who failed the exam are students on probation. Therefore, some students who failed the exam are students on probation.
The validity of this inference rests on whether there were in fact any students who failed the
exam. The inference is either valid or invalid, but we lack sufficient information about the
meaning of the premise to tell which is the case. Once it becomes known that there are
indeed some students who failed the exam, we can assert that the inference is valid from the
Aristotelian standpoint. But if there are no students who failed the exam, the inference is
invalid because it commits the existential fallacy.
Similarly, all inference forms that depend on valid applications of contrary, subcontrary, and
subalternation are conditionally valid because we do not know if the letters in the
propositions denote actually existing things.
44
Exercise
Use the traditional square of opposition to find the answers to these problems. When a statement is given as false, simply
enter an “F” into the square of opposition and compute (if possible) the other truth value.
If “All cats are products of genetic engineering” is true, what is the truth value of the following statements?
If “All cars are powered by solar energy” is false, what is the truth value of the following statements?
If “All athletes are afraid of heights” is false, what is the truth value of the following statements?
46
The diagrams for the I and O statements are the same from the Aristotelian
standpoint as they are from the Boolean:
47
Testing Immediate Inferences using Aristotelian standpoint
Since any inference that is valid from the Boolean standpoint is also valid from the
Aristotelian standpoint, testing the inference from the Boolean standpoint is often
simpler. If the inference is valid, then it is valid from both standpoints. But if the
inference is invalid from the Boolean standpoint and has a particular conclusion,
then it may be useful to test it from the Aristotelian standpoint. Let us begin by
testing an inference form for validity:
All A are B. Therefore, some A are B. First, we draw Venn diagrams from the
Boolean standpoint for the premise and conclusion:
48
The information of the conclusion diagram is not represented in the premise diagram,
so the inference form is not valid from the Boolean standpoint. Thus, noting that the
conclusion is particular, we adopt the Aristotelian standpoint and assume for the
moment that the subject of the premise (A) denotes at least one existing thing. This
thing is represented by placing a circled X in the open area of that circle:
Now the information of the conclusion diagram is represented in the premise diagram.
Thus, the inference form is conditionally valid from the Aristotelian standpoint. It is
valid on condition that the circled X represents at least one existing thing.
49
The steps involved in testing an immediate inference from the Aristotelian standpoint may
now be summarized:
1. Reduce the inference to its form and test it from the Boolean standpoint. If the
form is valid, proceed no further. The inference is valid from both stand points.
2. If the inference form is invalid from the Boolean standpoint and has a particular
conclusion, then adopt the Aristotelian standpoint and look to see if the left hand
premise circle is partly shaded. If it is, enter a circled X in the unshaded part and
retest the form.
3. If the inference form is conditionally valid, determine if the circled X represents
something that exists. If it does, the condition is fulfilled, and the inference is valid
from the Aristotelian standpoint. If it does not, the inference is invalid, and it
commits the existential fallacy from the Aristotelian standpoint.
50
Exercise
51
Translating Ordinary Language Statements into Categorical Form
● The process of translating ordinary language statements into categorical form
does not have a fixed set of rules that can account for every possible way of
expressing a statement. However, there is one general rule that always applies:
you need to understand the meaning of the given statement and then re-
express it in a new statement that includes a quantifier, subject term, copula,
and predicate term.
52
1. Terms Without Nouns
When translating categorical propositions, it is vital to ensure that both the subject and predicate terms consist of either a
plural noun or a pronoun that represents the class being referred to. Nouns and pronouns are used to denote classes, while
adjectives and participles express attributes. In cases where a term consists solely of an adjective, it is necessary to
introduce a plural noun or pronoun to ensure that the term is denotative and refers to a class of objects or entities.
In this proposition, the subject term "roses" already consists of a plural noun, denoting the class of flowers. However, the predicate term "red"
is an adjective. To ensure that it denotes a class, we introduce the plural noun "flowers" to properly represent the class of objects being
referred to.
2. All tigers are carnivorous. ----> All tigers are carnivorous animals.
In this example, both the subject term "tigers" and the predicate term "carnivorous" are already represented by plural nouns. However, to
emphasize that tigers belong to the class of carnivorous entities, we add the noun "animals" to the predicate term.
By ensuring that both the subject and predicate terms contain plural nouns or pronouns representing the classes being
referred to, we maintain clarity and accuracy in translating categorical propositions.
53
2. Nonstandard Verbs
In standard form categorical propositions, the only allowed copulas (verbs that link the subject and predicate) are
"are" and "are not." However, in ordinary language usage, statements often use different forms of the verb "to be."
These statements can still be translated into standard form categorical propositions by explicitly stating the
relationship between the subject and predicate.
In this statement, we have the subject "college students" and the predicate "will become educated." To translate it
into standard form, we can rephrase it as "Some college students are people who will become educated." Here, we
explicitly state that the college students are a subset of people who will become educated.
In this statement, the subject is "dogs" and the predicate is "would rather bark than bite." To express it in standard
form, we can say "Some dogs are animals that would rather bark than bite." This translation clarifies that the dogs
being referred to are a subset of animals that prefer barking over biting.
By adding the necessary information, we make the translations conform to the standard form categorical
propositions, where only "are" and "are not" copulas are used.
54
3. Singular Propositions
A singular proposition or statement is one that makes a specific assertion about a particular person, place, thing, or time. When we translate
singular propositions into universals, we often introduce a parameter that modifies the form of the statement without changing its meaning.
The parameters we can use for this translation include:
Let's look at an example to better understand this process. Consider the statement "Socrates is mortal." To translate this singular proposition
into a universal proposition, we can use the parameter "people identical to." The translation would be "All people identical to Socrates are
people who are mortal." In this translation, we introduce the parameter "people identical to" to modify the form of the statement, indicating that
it applies to all individuals who are identical to Socrates. Since there is only one person who is identical to Socrates (Socrates himself), the
phrase "people identical to Socrates" represents the class that includes Socrates as its sole member.
It's important to note that when translating singular statements, we must distinguish between the parameter "people identical to" and
expressions like "people similar to" or "people like." While there may be many people who are similar to Socrates, there is only one person
who is identical to Socrates. The parameter "people identical to" specifically refers to individuals who are exactly the same as the subject.
Furthermore, we should avoid using parameters when the term in question already includes a plural noun (or pronoun) that represents the
intended class. In such cases, it is unnecessary to introduce a parameter because the term itself already denotes the intended group.
55
4. Adverbs and Pronouns
When a statement includes a spatial adverb like "where," "wherever," "anywhere," "everywhere," or "nowhere," or a temporal adverb like "when,"
"whenever," "anytime," "always," or "never," it can be translated in terms of "places" or "times" respectively. Similarly, statements that contain
pronouns such as "who," "whoever," "anyone," "what," "whatever," or "anything" can be translated in terms of "people" or "things" respectively.
Let's go through some examples to illustrate this:
In this example, the statement includes the temporal adverb "always," which indicates that the action of wearing a suit occurs every time
he goes to work. To translate it into a more generalized form, we rephrase it to say that all times he goes to work are times he wears a
suit. Here, we replace the specific instances of going to work with the more general concept of "times."
In this case, the adverb "always" indicates that the person is consistently clean-shaven. To translate it into a more universal statement,
we express it as "all times are times he is clean-shaven." Here, we replace the specific instances of time with the more general concept
of "times."
By using the translations in terms of "places" or "times" for spatial or temporal adverbs, and "people" or "things" for pronouns, we generalize the
statements to apply universally, removing the specific referents and focusing on the broader concepts.
56
5. Unexpressed Quantifiers
In ordinary language usage, many statements contain implied quantifiers that are not explicitly expressed. When introducing these
quantifiers, one must rely on the most likely or probable meaning of the statement. Here are some examples:
Emeralds are green gems. ----> All emeralds are green gems.
In this case, the implied quantifier is "all." The statement asserts that every emerald (without exception) is a green gem.
There are lions in the zoo. ----> Some lions are animals in the zoo.
The implied quantifier here is "some." The statement suggests that at least a few lions (not necessarily all of them) can be found
in the zoo.
The implied quantifier is "all." The statement implies that every tiger belongs to the category of mammals.
In this case, the implied quantifier is "no." The statement indicates that no fish (none of them) fall into the category of mammals.
When translating these statements, it is important to infer the appropriate quantifier based on the intended
meaning and context.
57
6. Non-Standard Quantifiers
In certain ordinary language statements, the quantity or extent of the assertion is indicated by words other than the three standard form
quantifiers ("all," "some," and "no"). These words can include "few," "a few," "not every," "anyone," and various other forms. Additionally,
a problem arises when the quantifier "all" is combined with the copula "are not." As we have seen before, statements in the form of "All S
are not P" are not considered standard form categorical propositions. Depending on their intended meaning, they should be translated as
either "No S are P" or "Some S are not P."
When the intended meaning is "Some S are not P," this can be indicated by placing oral emphasis on the word "all." For example, the
statement "All athletes are not superstars" means "Some athletes are not superstars." Here are some further examples:
In this case, the quantifier "a few" is equivalent to "some." The statement suggests that there exist at least a small number of soldiers who are
considered heroes.
Here, the word "anyone" implies that every person who votes (without exception) is considered a citizen.
Not everyone who votes is a Democrat. ----> Some voters are not Democrats.
The phrase "not everyone" indicates that there are individuals who vote but are not affiliated with the Democratic party.
In these cases, it is important to analyze the intended meaning and context to determine the appropriate translation and quantifier to use.
58
7. Conditional Statements
When a conditional statement has the antecedent and consequent referring to the same class, it can often be
translated into categorical form. In such cases, the statements are always translated as universals. The
language following the word "if" is placed in the subject term of the categorical proposition, while the language
following "only if" is placed in the predicate term. Here's an example:
1. If it's a mouse, then it's a mammal. ----> All mice are mammals.
In this example, the conditional statement asserts that if something is a mouse, it must be a mammal. The translation expresses the universal
proposition that all mice (without exception) belong to the class of mammals.
Similarly, conditional statements with a negated consequent are typically best translated as E propositions, which
assert that there are no instances of the subject term that fall under the predicate term. Here's an example:
2. If it's a turkey, then it's not a mammal. ----> No turkeys are mammals.
Here, the conditional statement states that if something is a turkey, it cannot be a mammal. The translation as an E proposition asserts that
there are no turkeys that are mammals.
The word "unless" is equivalent to "if not." Therefore, statements containing "unless" are translated as categorical
propositions with negated subject terms. Here's an example:
3. Tomatoes are edible unless they are spoiled. ----> All unspoiled tomatoes are edible tomatoes.
The conditional statement suggests that unless tomatoes are spoiled, they are edible. The translation as a categorical proposition states that all
unspoiled tomatoes (without exception) are edible.
59
8. Exclusive Propositions
Many propositions that include words like "only," "none but," "none except," and "no...except" are considered exclusive
propositions. When attempting to translate these propositions into categorical form, there is often a risk of confusing the subject term with
the predicate term. To avoid such confusion, it is important to remember that the language following "only," "none but," "none except," and
"no...except" should be placed in the predicate term of the categorical proposition.
For example, let's consider the statement: "Only executives can use the silver elevator." The correct translation would be: "All people who
can use the silver elevator are executives." If we were to translate it as "All executives are people who can use the silver elevator," the
translation would be incorrect.
1. Only elected officials will attend the convention. ----> All people who will attend the convention are elected officials.
In this case, the proposition implies that the only individuals who will be present at the convention are elected officials. The correct
translation expresses the universal proposition that all people attending the convention (without exception) are elected officials.
2. None but the brave deserve the fair. ----> All people who deserve the fair are brave people.
The proposition suggests that only brave individuals deserve the fair. The translation as a categorical proposition asserts that all people
who deserve the fair (without exception) are brave people.
3. He owns only blue-chip stocks. ----> All stocks he owns are blue-chip stocks.
This proposition indicates that the individual exclusively possesses blue-chip stocks. The translation expresses the universal proposition
that all stocks owned by him (without exception) are blue-chip stocks.
60
9. “The Only”
Statements that begin with the words "the only" are translated differently compared to those that begin with "only."
When a statement starts with "the only," it signifies a different translation approach. For example, the statement
"The only cars that are available are Chevrolets" can be understood as "If a car is available, then it is a Chevrolet."
This, in turn, is translated as "All cars that are available are Chevrolets." In other words, the language following "the
only" is placed in the subject term of the categorical proposition.
Here are some examples to illustrate this translation:
1. The only animals that live in this canyon are skunks. ----> All animals that live in this canyon are skunks.
This statement implies that skunks are the exclusive inhabitants of the canyon. The translation as a categorical proposition asserts that all
animals living in this canyon (without exception) are skunks.
2. Accountants are the only ones who will be hired. ----> All those who will be hired are accountants.
In this case, the proposition states that only accountants will be recruited. The translation expresses the universal proposition that all individuals
who will be hired (without exception) are accountants.
Statements involving "the only" are similar to those involving "only" in one respect: when the statement refers to an
individual, two statements are needed to accurately translate it. For instance, the statement "The only person who
painted a picture is Megan" means that Megan painted a picture, and no other person did. The meaning of the
statement is equivalent to "Only Megan painted a picture." Therefore, it is translated as "All people identical to
Megan are people who painted a picture, and all people who painted a picture are people identical to Megan."
61
10. Exceptive Propositions
Propositions in the form of "All except S are P" and "All but S are P" are classified as exceptive propositions. These
propositions cannot be translated as single categorical propositions but require pairs of conjoined categorical
propositions to accurately represent their meaning.
In this proposition, it is stated that everyone except students is invited. The correct translation involves two conjoined categorical propositions.
The first proposition negates the inclusion of students among the invited people, while the second proposition affirms the inclusion of all non-
students as the invited people.
2. All but managers must report to the president. ----> No managers are people who must report to the president, and all non-
managers are people who must report to the president.
This proposition indicates that everyone except managers is required to report to the president. Again, two conjoined categorical propositions
are necessary for translation. The first proposition negates the inclusion of managers among those who must report to the president, while the
second proposition affirms the inclusion of all non-managers as individuals who must report to the president.
It is important to note that exceptive propositions cannot be translated into single categorical propositions. Therefore, many of
the simple inferences and operations applicable to categorical propositions cannot be applied to exceptive propositions.
On the other hand, statements that contain the phrase "none except" are classified as exclusive (not exceptive) propositions.
"None except" is synonymous with "none but."
62
Exercise
Translate the following into standard form categorical propositions.
1. Any bank that makes too many risky loans will fail.
2. Bromine is extractable from seawater.
3. Terrorist attacks succeed whenever security measures are lax.
4. If it’s a halogen, then it isn’t chemically inert.
5. None but pirate ships fly the Jolly Roger.
6. A few organic silicones are used as lubricants.
7. Comets are the only heavenly bodies with tails
8. No shellfish except oysters make pearls.
9. All passengers must have a valid ticket, except for children under the age of 5.
63
References
• Logic Matters by P. D. Magnus and Gordon Schorn: This friendly and engaging text presents logic in
a practical and relevant way, with chapters dedicated to categorical propositions and their properties.
• Introduction to Logic by Irving Copi and Carl Cohen: This classic textbook is a comprehensive
resource for all aspects of logic, including detailed explanations of categorical propositions, Venn
diagrams, and syllogisms.
• Symbolic Logic, 12th Edition by Irving Copi and Carl Cohen: This updated edition builds on the
foundation of the classic text, delving deeper into advanced topics like Boolean Algebra and the Square
of Oppositions.
• An Introduction to Formal Logic by Irving Copi and Carl Cohen: This advanced textbook delves into
formal logic systems, including detailed discussions of quantifiers, propositional logic, and predicate
logic, which provide a deeper understanding of the structure of categorical propositions.
• The Art of Reasoning by David Kelley: This engaging book combines theory and practice, offering
clear explanations of logical concepts alongside puzzles and exercises to test understanding. It features
a dedicated chapter on categorical propositions, Venn diagrams, and the Square of Oppositions.
• Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy website has a
comprehensive entry on categorical propositions, providing in-depth analysis and historical
context. (https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle-logic/)
64