Skodo Braudel
Skodo Braudel
Skodo Braudel
Fil. mag. M. Res. Admir Skodo, f. 1984, är doktorand i historia vid Europeiska univer-
sitetsinstitutet i Florens där han forskar om den moderna brittiska idéhistoriens och
historiefilosofins historia. Han är medredaktör för ”Companion to R.G. Collingwood”
(under utgivning) och som exempel på publicerade artiklar kan nämnas ”Outline of a
theory of the person for historical-biographical study”, The international journal of the
humanities (20 09).
Adress: Admir Skodo, European University institute, Department of history and civ-
ilization, Badia Fiesolana, Via dei Roccettini 9, 50 014 San Domenico di Fiesole, Italien
E-post: [email protected]
. Institutionally Lauritz secured Lund, Curt Gothenburg, and their student, the famous Erik
Lönnroth, Uppsala. Birgitta Odén, ”Det moderna historisk-kritiska genombrottet i svensk historisk
forskning”, Scandia 41:1 (1975) p. 5–29.
. To my knowledge it is still a matter of debate about whether, or perhaps to what extent,
Seignobos influenced the brothers Weibull. Rolf Torstendahl is convinced that this is the case. See
Rolf Torstendahl, ”Curt Weibull: en anteckning”, Scandia 58:2 (19 92) p. 151–156.
. For Braudel’s background see e.g. J. H. Hexter, ”Fernand Braudel and the Monde Braudelien…”,
Journal of modern history 44:4 (1972) p. 480–539; Traian Stoianovich, French historical method: the
Annales paradigm: with a foreword by Fernand Braudel (Ithaca & London 1976); Georg G. Iggers,
New directions in European historiography: revised edition (Middletown 19 84); and Fernand Braudel,
”Personal testimony”, The journal of modern history 44:4 (1972) p. 448–467.
10. Braudel was in Algeria because he was assigned his first teaching post there in 1923. See
Paule Braudel, ”Les origines intellectuelles de Fernand Braudel: un témoignage”, Annales: histoire,
sciences sociales 47:1 (19 92) p. 237–244, 239.
11. Braudel (19 92) p. 237.
12. Though Henri Berr and Marc Bloch are two essential actors for the formation of the Annales
School, Braudel always held Febvre closest to his heart. In Braudel (1972) he writes that Febvre came
to be like a father to him and that he would never have managed to finish La Méditerranée without
his support and help. Cf. Braudel (19 92).
13. Braudel (19 92) p. 243.
14. Fernand Braudel, ”Histoire et sciences sociales: la longue durée”, Annales: économies, sociétés,
civilisations 13:4 (1958) p. 725–753.
15. This is perhaps why the later generations of Annales historians affirmed their commitment
to studying persons by turning to biography.
16. Fernand Braudel, ”Les responsabilités de l’histoire”, in Roselyn de Ayala & Paule Braudel
(ed.), Les écrits de Fernand Braudel: II: les ambitions de l’histoire (Paris 19 97) p. 97–117, 102. ”’Les
hommes font l’histoire’. Non, l’histoire fait aussi les hommes et façonne leur destin – l’histoire
anonyme, profonde et souvent silencieuse […]”.
17. Braudel (1958) p. 746, ”l’expérience sociale dont tout doit partir, où tout doit revenir”. Con-
sider what was written in the Annales in 1951, quoted and translated by Hexter (1972) p. 491: It is
”[m]an living, complex, confused, as he is”, that “les sciences humaines must seek to understand”, this
”[m]an whom all the social sciences must avoid slicing up, however skilful and artistic the carving”.
18. This probably explains why there are no graphs or tables to be found in the first edition. The
second one, in contrast, is full of them.
19. Braudel (1958) p. 748, ”J’ai personnellement, au cours d’une captivité assez morose, beaucoup
lutté pour échapper à la chronique de ces années difficiles (1940-1945). Refuser les événements et
le temps des évenéments, c’était se mettre en marge, à l’abri, pour les regarder d’un peu plus loin,
les mieux juger et n’y point trop croire”. See also Braudel (1978) p. 453–454.
In short, Braudel does not believe that ”the only actors making noise are
the most authentic ones”, because (notice again the silence of history) ”there
are others, silent ones; but who did not know that already”?2 6 By way of
concluding this section, I wish to point out that I share with Braudel the
following: it is with the concept of the person that an analysis has to deal,
and it is the understanding of particular persons that historical research
should result in. Where we differ is that I explicitly follow through on such
presuppositions, whereas Braudel goes on to construct presuppositions
standing in contradiction to and even derision of them. Let us, then, take
a closer look at these presuppositions of Braudel’s.
27. See Carl G. Hempel, ”The Function of General Laws in History”, Journal of Philosophy 39:2
(1942) p. 35–48. It is worthwhile to notice that Hempel postulates the object of historical explana-
tion to be either a specific personality, or something that is the result of human behaviour. He
believes that such objects can be reduced to a certain type of event, which can be explained through
the application of universally conditional hypotheses.
28. Braudel (1958) p. 734, ”parlent le même langage ou peuvent le parler”.
29. For history, see e.g. François Dosse, Histoire du structuralisme: le champ du signe, 1945–19 66
(Paris 19 91).
30. Braudel (19 97) p. 102, ”héros quintessenciés”.
31. Braudel (1958) p. 740, ”des forms inconscientes du social”, ”un inconscient social”, ”cette
demi-obscurité”.
32. Braudel’s father was a mathematician I note in passing, and, according to testimony, a very
strict man. See Braudel (19 92).
33. Braudel (1958) p. 740. ”à travers de temps et espace”.
34. Braudel (1958) p. 740. ”varient à l’infini suivant le tempérament, le calcul ou le but des
utilisateurs”.
35. Braudel (1958) p. 728. ”la plus capricieuse, la plus trompeuse des durées”.
36. Fernand Braudel, ”L’histoire des civilisations: le passé explique le présent”, in Roselyn de
Ayala & Paule Braudel (ed.), Les écrits de Fernand Braudel: II: les ambitions de l’histoire (Paris 19 97)
p. 197–243, 224.
This article was first published in 1959 in volume 20 of L’Encyclopédie française, edited by
Febvre.
37. Braudel quoted in Stoianovich (1972) p. 121. ”impossible science globale de l’homme”.
38. Cf. Peter Burke, ”History of events and the revival of narrative”, in Peter Burke (ed.), New
perspectives on historical writing: second edition (Cambridge 20 01) p. 283–301, p. 287.
39. Braudel (1958) p. 731, ”les cadrex mentaux, aussi, sont prisons de la longue durée”.
40. Braudel (1958) p. 727, ”la valeur exceptionelle du temps long”.
41. Braudel (1958) p. 731, ”une réalité que le temps use mal et véhicule trés longuement”.
42. Braudel (1958) p. 727, ”l’histoire aux cents visages”.
saw them”. He cannot say ”I’m going to show you some facts contradicting
your claim yesterday, and you’ll be ashamed when you see them yesterday”.
The closest thing to such an expression he can come, and there is really no
closeness here, is ”Yesterday I showed you that you’re contradicted, and you
were ashamed of it”. But this presupposes that he has already uttered ”I’m
going to show you some facts which contradict your claim, and you’re going
to be ashamed when you see them”. In turn, this presupposes, expressed in
the intentionality of the expression, that you have as a matter of conscious
perception seen this fact and been ashamed. But for you to be able to say
and believe ”yes, I saw them, and I was ashamed”, it is necessarily presup-
posed that your seeing and feeling ashamed was stored in your memory,
and that the memory in a subsequent situation was brought to your consci-
ousness essentially representing the content of the utterance that you see
them and are ashamed of it.
Our discloser of facts is fully aware that your memory is gone, and is
thereby committed to accepting the possibility that he either did not see
you at all yesterday; or, that he saw you, presented the facts, but that they
did not contradict your claim, nor made you feel ashamed, that is, he is
committed to accepting that he cannot change, as he wants, what has once
occurred. Consider what would happen if he was to think, act and speak
consistently with the belief that he could do whatever his heart desired
with objects ontologically determined. He would then say ”I have no food
today, but I had some yesterday, so I’ll eat yesterday”. Or, ”I humiliated him
two weeks ago, and he killed himself, but I’ll not humiliate him two weeks
ago, so he won’t kill himself”.
If our fact shower would be consistent in his thinking this way he would
not be able to make himself understood to others, nor would he be able
to live in a social community. To only nominally deny ontological deter-
mination is a paradox or self-contradiction; to deny it in actual use is a
disaster.
However, even if some past person has actualized a particular num-
ber of possibilities of thought and action, it is nonetheless the case that
our understanding of that person is epistemologically underdetermined,
that is, we cannot give a complete description of some past person. It is a
matter of presupposition that several logically incompatible descriptions
of the same object can exist. But consider that even if this ontological
determination is presupposed, if that object existed in the past. In order
44. Language and logic too have their history, which of course overlaps. ”Logic” is not just logic,
but predicate logic, propositional logic, deontic logic, set theory, modal logic, meta-logic. All these
certainly share family resemblances, but does one entail all the others? Does each one entail every
other?
45. Bear in mind that the distinctions drawn in what follows are of a logical kind and do not
purport to enounce anything about temporal priority and succession.
46. I of course take it for granted that historical understanding is not possible without evidence,
linguistic or otherwise, which embodies past person’s activities. I also take for granted that histori-
ans know how to go about finding relevant evidence and judging its worth for research.
47. Due to practical reasons I will say nothing of the grammatical and lexical form of these
logically distinct attitudes.
48. Here I draw on R. G. Collingwood, The idea of history: revised edition (Oxford 19 94); Lud-
wig Wittgenstein, Philosophical investigations (Oxford 19 68); H. P. Grice, ”Utterer’s meaning and
intention”, The philosophical review 40:2 (19 6 9) p. 147–177; Mark Bevir, The logic of the history of
Ideas (Cambridge 19 9 9); and A. P. Martinich, ”Four Senses of ‘Meaning’ in the history of ideas.
Quentin Skinner’s theory of historical interpretation”, Journal of the philosophy of history 3:3 (20 0 9)
p. 225–245. The distinctions can be made finer, as is done by Martinich and Grice, but for my
purposes the ones drawn will suffice.
49. In some cases however I believe that it might be appropriate to invoke the notion of mecha-
nism to understand the behaviour produced, perhaps to the dismay of the anti-naturalists. I will
not go into this aspect here. See my ”Outline of a theory of the person for historical-biographical
study”, The international journal of the humanities 7:1 (20 0 9) p. 59–70.
50. See the collection of his philosophical pieces in Visions of politics: volume I: regarding method
(Cambridge 20 02). I review Skinner in my ”Post-analytic philosophy of history”, Journal of the phi-
losophy of history 3:3 (20 0 9) p. 308–333, 30 9–314.
54. For this reason, although he goes too far, I have sympathy with Ankersmit’s Sublime historical
experience (Stanford 20 05), because he acknowledges it.
55. I could give many many more, but alas, the space does not allow it.
56. I would have chosen Braudel, but unfortunately I did not have the time to dig deeper into
the connections between his personal life and his work.
57. Depression is (and I do not mean to sound opinioned in saying this) a condition that we find
abounds among great thinkers and artists. Another example is William James, who in a lecture
drew on his depression to formulate a philosophical question – namely, how to convince someone
who wants to kill himself that he should go on living. Indeed, I too ask myself that. The lecture is
published in On a certain blindness in human beings (London 20 0 9).
58. David Macey, Michel Foucault (London 20 04) p. 29–30.