Bertrand Russell and The End of Nationalism
Bertrand Russell and The End of Nationalism
Bertrand Russell and The End of Nationalism
LOUIS GREENSPAN
McMaster University
of the former Yugoslavia and the former Soviet Union, when in reality
we are contending with the nationalism of the former czarist empire,
the former Austro-Hungarian empire, and the former Turkish empire.
Had Russell been alive, he would have experienced uncanny deja vu.
At the moment, Russell’s writings on nationalism are the ones that
connect him to our own world.
Another reason that commentators might have been reluctant to
subject his writings on nationalism to close critical scrutiny is that
nationalism is a subject in which Russell’s moral passions seem to
overwhelm his philosophical calm. For many readers of Russell’s
work, his views on nationalism are so straightforward, his abhorrence
for it so outspoken, that there seems to be little reason to include them
in any discussions about his philosophy or his science of society
Contemporary readers trained in the distinctions fostered in our
social sciences between fact and value might be taken aback by the
moral passion that Russell exhibits in almost all of his writing about
modem society but especially in his writing about nationalism. He
makes no attempt to observe the moral neutrality that so often is cited
as the sine qua non of the social scientist, and he has no compunction
about allowing the rhetoric of outrage to subvert any attempt at calm,
coolheaded analysis. Nationalism seems to be a topic set apart in
Russell’s mind in that it was the one subject that never seemed open
to further revision. Often he seemed to be in the grips of a personal
obsession as persistent as that which gripped the Elder Cato about the
menace of Carthage to Rome. Russell frequently alludes to national-
ism as a form of lunacy and to nationalists as a collection of homicidal
psychopaths. Even before the catastrophe of World War I, Russell
admitted that his opposition to nationalism and support for interna-
tionalism was rooted in fundamental ethical principles rather than in
observations concerning its empirical consequences. When in 1903 he
campaigned on behalf of the internationalist Free Traders against
Joseph Chamberlain’s scheme for an imperial tariff, he wrote to the
French historian Elie Hal6vy that free trade was an ethical issue and
that tariff reform, far from being a merely economic matter, &dquo;had
placed England morally on trial.&dquo;5 To his friend Lucy Donnelly, he
wrote, &dquo;We are wildly excited about free trade; it is to me the last piece
of sane internationalism left, and if it went I should feel inclined to
slit my throat.&dquo;6 In later years, he constantly wrote on nationalism as
if he were a prophet reviling idolatry rather than a coolheaded analyst
weighing the pros and cons of a particular ideology.’
space, that endows its members with identity and purpose.&dquo;&dquo; Such
an approach is supported by the reality of ethnic entities, such as the
claim to national status of the nineteenth-century Poles. Russell’s
theories of the nation resemble those of Gellner and Hobsbawm in
important respects but still retain some of the claims of the ethnicists.
had perished in the Civil War.... Now, however, a very large propor-
tion of the population of America consists of people whose nationalist
feelings are still European-Slavs, Italians, Germans, and even to a
large extent, the Irish. Such people cannot have towards the United
States the kind of intimate, passionate, narrow sentiment that they have
towards the nations from which they come.26
But neither has their sentiment for the old country remained strong.
America, Russell argued, is a country in which mobility and dyna-
mism have eroded the roots of nationalism; it was in effect a postna-
tionalist nation, a model of what the rest of the world would become.
One could easily argue that Russell must, at that time, have been
deliberately blind to the mounting xenophobia that was gripping
America as it was getting ready to enter the war. On the other hand,
it could be argued that Russell had anticipated the reality that so grips
America (and Canada, for that matter) of a multiethnic state whose
diversity has diluted any sense of common purpose.
In the years following the end of the war, Russell, among others,
came to the view that the European nations had learned nothing and
that the postwar world order had simply reconstituted the conditions
that had made the war inevitable. This had not been a war to end all
wars and certainly was not a war to end nationalism. The tinge of
among liberals and the left for a policy of support for national self-
CONCLUSIONS
first into a problem that will plague this school constantly, namely that
declarations of &dquo;the End of Nationalism&dquo; are constantly rebutted by
spirited reappearances of movements of national independence. The
end of nationalism is a prophecy that is never fulfilled. Moreover, in
the course of his investigation, Russell found that the sources of
nationalism-sources that he originally found to be atavistic, mori-
bund remainders from previous forms of society-are bom in the
womb of modernity. This in itself indicates that the thesis of the
artificiality of nationalism must be restated.
Second, Russell promised to the internationalists that there is no
sense in waiting for nationalism to end in itself; rather, it can only
come when nationalism is subdued by force either economic, politi-
confident that he has uncovered the reasons for the continuing appeal
of nationalism.
Russell seems to have abandoned the quest for a resolution to these
various dialectics. In the 1960s, in the last decade of his life, he
supported the national uprisings of the Czechs (against the Soviets)
and the Vietnamese, calling for an understanding of the patriotism
behind both of these national movements.&dquo; He had returned to the
position of liberals of the mid-nineteenth century, of distinguishing
between progressive and reactionary nationalisms, the position that
he had rejected at the end of World War I.
NOTES
1. German Social Democracy is a study of the then largest Marxist party in the world.
Russell criticizes the party because its addiction to Marxist notions of class war and
revolution has isolated it from the masses, but he congratulates the party for its
resolute internationalism—its readiness to reject the nationalism and imperialism of
the Second Reich—not noticing that this too might have isolated the party from the
masses.
2. For an extended discussion of this important episode, see R. Rempel, "From
Imperialism to Free Trade: Couturat, Halévy, and Russell’s First Crusade," Journal of the
History of Ideas, 40 (July 1979): 423-43.
3. For Russell’s full discussion on this theme, see Bertrand Russell, Freedom and
Organization (London: Allen and Unwin, 1934), and Bertrand Russell, A History of
Western Philosophy (New York: Scribner, 1945). The latter is the only history of philoso-
phy that treats Byron as one of the key figures in the development of modem thought.
4. For example, the victories of the Israelis in 1967 created a crisis in Poland because
Polish officers indiscreetly celebrated the victories of "our Jews" against "their [the
Soviet] Arabs."
5. See Richard A. Rempel, Andrew Brink, and Margaret Moran, Collected Papers of
Bertrand Russell, vol. 12: Contemplation and Action, 1902-1914 (Allen and Unwin, 1985),
182.
6. Ibid., 182.
7. For an interesting discussion on the relationship between Russell’s ethical views
and his writings on politics and society, see Bart Schultz, "Bertrand Russell in Ethics
and Politics," Ethics 102 (April 1992): 594-634.
8. Russell’s fear of madness is one of the compelling themes in Ray Monk, Bertrand
Russell: The Spirit of Solitude (London: Jonathan Cape, 1996), esp. 23ff.
9. Bertrand Russell, Power: ANew Social Analysis (London: Allen and Unwin, 1938),
contains an extended discussion of power philosophies, and Bertrand Russell, "Ances-
try of Fascism," in Bertrand Russell, In Praise of Idleness (London: Allen and Unwin,
1935), traces the evolution of fascism from the idealism of Fichte through Hegel and
Nietzsche.
10. Alan Ryan has astutely pointed to Russell’s connection to the sociological
tradition in Alan Ryan, Russell: A Political Life (London: Allen Lane, Penguin, 1989), 98.
11. Russell weaves nationalism and internationalism, the struggle between global-
ism and global disintegration, in a manner that connects his work to works such as
Benjamin Barber, Jihad vs. Mcworld (Toronto: Random House, 1995).
12. See John Hutchison, Modern Nationalism (London: Fontana, 1994), and the
collection John Hutchison and Anthony D. Smith, eds., Nationalism (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1994).
13. See Ernest Gellner, Nations and Nationalism (Oxford: Blackwell, 1983), and Eric
Hobsbawm, Nations and Nationalism (London: Clarendon, 1990).
14. Hutchison, 8.
15. Ibid.
16. Ernest Gellner, "Nationalism and High Culture," in Gellner, Nations and Nation-
alism, 65.
17. See Bertrand Russell, "Is Nationalism Moribund?" in Richard Rempel, Louis
Greenspan, Beryl Haslam, Albert Lewis, and Mark Lippincott, The Collected Papers of
Bertrand Russell, vol. 14: Pacifism and Revolution (London: Routledge, 1995), 317. This is
the first time that Russell’s seminal essay on nationalism has been reproduced since it
was first published in The Seven Arts.
18. Bertrand Russell, "Pros and Cons of Nationalism," in Bertrand Russell, Fact and
Fiction (New York: Simon & Schuster, 1962), 133.
19. Sir Norman Angell’s The Great Illusion: A Study of the Relation of Military Power in
Nations to Their Economic and Social Advantage (Toronto: McLelland & Goodchild, 1911),
revised in 1933, was a runaway best-seller and was translated into many languages.
20. Russell, "Is Nationalism Moribund?" 322.
21. A recent volume, Jean-Marie Eliott, The End of the Nation State (Minneapolis:
University of Minnesota Press, 1995). At the time of this writing, Eliott was France’s
ambassador to the European Union. The opening pages of this volume present an
argument that is very similar to Russell’s (although updated) in "Is Nationalism
Moribund?"
22. Russell, "Is Nationalism Moribund?" 316.
23. Ibid., 320.
24. Ibid.
25. Ibid, 321.
26. Ibid., 318.
27. Ibid., 68.
28. Bertrand Russell in collaboration with Dora Russell, The Prospects of Industrial
Civilization (London: Allen and Unwin, 1923), 101-2.
29. Ibid., 65.
30. Ibid., 89-90.
31. Russell, Freedom and Organization, 403.
32. Ryan, Russell: A Political Life, 178-80, provides a lengthy discussion of Russell’s
proposals to threaten the Soviet Union with atomic war, providing evidence of Russell’s
seriousness in making this proposal, including readiness to absorb millions of casualties
in the event that Russia invaded Western Europe.
33. Bertrand Russell, "Zionism and the Peace Settlement," The New Palestine 33 (11
June 1943): 5.
34. Ibid., 6.
35. Ibid., 7.
36. Russell, "Pros and Cons," 127.
37. Ibid., 131.
38. I have dealt with this subject in Louis Greenspan, The Incompatible Prophecies:
Bertrand Russell on Science and Liberty (Oakville, Ontario: Mosaic Press, 1978), 72-73.