w3 - Enoch Why I'm An Objectivist About Ethics
w3 - Enoch Why I'm An Objectivist About Ethics
w3 - Enoch Why I'm An Objectivist About Ethics
- 18
208
Why 1Am an Objectivist about Ethics (And Why You Are, Too) 209
Enoch carefully presents each criticism and then offers sharp replies to
the objections.
grew up in the twentieth-century West and who believes that the earth
revolves around the sun. Also, she reports to be happy she wasn't born
in the Middle Ages, "because had 1 grown up in the Middle Ages, I
would have believed that the earth is in the center of the universe, and
that belief is false!" ,
To my ears, the joke doesn't work in this latter version (try it on your
friends!). The response in the earth-revolves-around-the-sun case sounds
perfectly sensible, precisely in a way in which the analogous response does
not sound sensible in the spinach case.
We need one last case. Suppose someone grew up in the United States
in the late twentieth century and rejects any manifestation of racism as
morally wrong. He then reports that he's happy that that's when and where
he grew up. "because had I grown up in the eighteenth century, I would
have accepted slavery and racism. And these things are wrong'" How
funny is this third, last version of the joke? To my ears, it's about as (un)
funny as the second one, and nowhere nearly as amusing as the first. The
response to the question in this last case (why he is happy that he grew up
in the twentieth century) seems to me to make perfect sense, and I suspect
it makes sense to you too. And this is why there's nothing funny about it.
OK, then, why is the spinach version funny and the others are not?
Usually, our attitude towards our own likings and dislikings (when it
comes to food, for instance) is that it's all about us. If you don't like spin-
ach, the reason you shouldn't have it is precisely that you don't like it. So
if we're imagining a hypothetical scenario in which you do like it, then
you no longer have any reason not to eat it. This is what the child in the
6rst example gets wrong: he's holding fixed his dislike for spinach, even
in thinking about the hypothetical case in which he likes spinach. But
because these issues are all about him and what he likes and dislikes, this
makes no sense.
But physics is different: What we want, believe or do-none of this
affects the earth's orbit. The fact that the earth revolves around the sun is
just not about us at all. So it makes sense to hold this truth fixed even when
thinking about hypothetical cases in which you don't believe it. And so it
makes sense to be happy that you aren't in the Middle Ages, since youa
then be in a situation in which your beliefs about the earth's orbit would be
false (even if you couldn't know that they were). And because this makes
sense, the joke isn't funny.
And so we have the spinach test: About any relevant subject matter,
formulate an analogue of the spinach joke. If the joke works. this seems
Why J Am an Objectivist "bout Btllks (And Why YOli Arc, 1(10) 211
to indicate that the subject matter is all about us and our responses. our
likings and dislikings, our preferences, and so on. If the joke doesn't work.
the subject matter is much more objective than that, as in the astronomy
case. And when we apply the spinach test to a moral issue (like the moral
status of racism), it seems to fall squarely on the objective side.
(Exercise: 'Think about your taste in musk, and formulate the spinach
test for it. Is the joke funny?)
Disagreement and Deliberation
We sometimes engage in all sorts of disagreements. Sometimes, for
instance. we may engage in a disagreement about even such silly things
as whether bitter chocolate is better than milk chocolate. Sometimes we
disagree about such things as whether human actions influence global
warming. But these two kinds of disagreement are very different. One way
of seeing this is thinking about what it feels like from the inside to engage
in such disagreements. ]n the chocolate case. it feels like stating one's own
preference, and perhaps trying to influence the listener inlO getting his
own preferences in line. In the global warming case, though. it feels like
trying to get at an objective truth, one that is there anyway, independently
of our beliefs and preferences. (Either human actions contribute to global
warming, or they don't, right?)
And so another test suggests itself, a test haVing to do with what it feels
like to engage in disagreement (or, as we sometimes say, with the phenom-
enology of disagreement).
But now think of some serious moral disagreement-about the mo....d
status of abortion. say. Suppose, then, that you are engaged in such dis-
agreement. (It's important to imagine this from the inside, as it were. Don't
imagine looking from the outside at two people arguing over abortion;
think what it's like to be engaged in such argument yourself-if not about
abortion, then about some other issue you care deeply about.) Perhaps
you think that there is nothing wrong with abortion. and you're arguing
with someone who thinks that abortion is morally wrong. What does such
disagreement feel like? In particular. does it feel more like disagreeing over
which chocolate is better. or like disagreeing over factual matters (such as
whether human actions contribute to global warmingH
Because this question is a phenomenological one (that is, it's about what
something feels like from the inside). I can't answer this question for you.
You have to think about what it feels like fi)r you when you are engagt>d in
moral disagreement. But I can say that in my case such moral disagreement
212 MliTAld'IIICS
feels exactly like the one about global warming-it's about an objective
matter of fact, that exists independently of us and ollr disagreement. It is in
no way like disagreeing over the merits ofdifferent kinds of chocolate. And I
think I can rather safely predict that this is how it feels for you too.
So ()n the phenomenology-of-disagreement test as well, morality
seems to taU on the objective side.
In fact. we may be able to take disagreement out of the picture entirely.
Suppose there is no disagreement-perhaps because you're all by yourself
trying to make up your mind about what to do next. In one case, you're
thinking about what kind of chocolate to get. In another, you're chOOSing
between buying a standard car and a somewhat more expensive hybrid car
(whose effect on global warming, if human actions contribute to global
warming, is less destructive). Here, too, there's a difference. In the first
ca.r;e, you seem to be asking questions about yourself and what you like
more (in general, or right now). In the second case, you need to make up
your mind about your own action, of course, but you're asking yourself
questions about objective matters of fact that do not depend on you at
all-in particular, about whether human actions affect global warming.
Now consider a third case, in which you're trying to make up your mind
about having an abortion, or advising a friend who is considering an abor-
tion. So you're wondering whether abortion is wrong. Does it feellik.e asking
about your own preferences or like an objective matter offaet? Is it more like
the chocolate case or like the hybrid car case? If. like me, you answer that it's
much more like the hybrid car case, then you think, like me, that the phe-
nomenology of deliberation too indicates that morality is objective.
(Exercise: think about your taste in music again. In terms of the phe-
nomenology of disagreement and delibenltion. is it on the objective sider)
Would It Still Have Been Wrong If ... ~
Top hats are out of fashion. 1 his may be an interesting. perhaps even practi-
cally relevant, fact-it may, for instance, give you reason to wear a top hat
(if you want to be special) or not to (if not). Hut think about the follOwing
question: Had our fashion practices been very different-had we all worn
top hats, thought they were cool. and so on-would it still have been true
that top hats are out offashion? '[he answer. it seems safe to assume, is "no:'
Smoking causes canc:er. 'Ihis is an interesting, practically relcV'ant,
fact-it most certainly gives you a reason not to smoke, or perhaps to stop
smoking. Now. had our releV'cmt practices and beliefs regarding smoking
been different-had we been OK with it, had we not banned it, had we
Wit)' I Am a" Objectivist IInvlIl Htlrifs (AtIIJ WI,), \'ou Are, '/0(/) 2\3
What's At Issue~
We have, then, three tests for objectivity-the spinach test, the
phenomenology-of-disagreement-and-deliberatioJl test, and the c()UI1-
terfactual test. And though we haveJl't yet said much about wh.tt
214 Ml!TAI·.TIIIC~
objectivity comes to, these tests test for something that is recognizably in the
vicinity of what we're after with our term "objectivity."
Objectivity. like many interesting philosophical terms, can be under-
stood in more than one way. As a result, when philosophers affirm or
deny the objectivity of some subject matter, it's not to be taken for granted
that they're asserting or denying the same thing. But we don't have to go
through a long list of what may be meant by morality's objectivity. It will
be more productive, I think, to go about things in a different way. We can
start by asking, why does it matter whether morality is objective? If we
have a good enough feel for the answer to this question, we can then use it
to find the sense of objectivity that we care about.
I suggest that we care about the objectivity of morality for roughly the
reasons specified in the previous section. We want morality's objectivity
to support our responses in those cases. We want morality's objectivity
to vindicate the phenomenology of deliberation and disagreement, and
our relevant counterfactual judgments. We want morality'S objectivity to
explain why the moral analogue of the spinach test isn't funny.
Very well, then, in what sense must morality be objective in order for
the phenomenology of disagreement and deliberation and our counterfac-
tual judgments to be justified? lhe answer, it seems to me, is that a subject
matter is objective if the truths or facts in it exist independently of what we
think or feel about them.
'This notion of objectivity nicely supports the counterfactual test. If
a certain truth (say, that smoking causes cancer) doesn't depend on our
views about it, then it would have been true even had we not believed it.
Not so for truths that do depend on our beliefs, practices, or emotions
(such as the truth that top hats are unfashionable). And if moral truths are
similarly independent of our beliefs, desires, preferences, emotions, points
of view, and so on-if, as is sometimes said, moral truths are response-
independent-then it's clear why gender-based discrimination would have
been wrong even had we approved of it.
Similarly, if it's our responses that make moral claims true, then in
a case of disagreement. it seems natural to suppose that both sides may
be right. Perhaps, in other wl>rds. your responses make it the case that
abortion is morally permissible ("for you:' in some sense of this very
weird phrase?). and your friend's responses make it the case that abor-
tion is morally wrong ("tor her"?). But if the moral status of abortion is
response-independent, we understand why moral disagreement feels like
factual disagreement-only one of you is right, and it's important to find
Wiry 1 Am an Obj''''lit,jst "bout Ethks (AIUI Wily You Are, 100) 215
out who. And of course. the whole point of the spinach test was to distin-
guish between caring about things just because we care about them (such
as not eating spinach, if you find it yucky) and caring about things that
seem to us important independently of us caring about them (such as the
wrongness of racism).
Another way of making the same point is as follows: Objective facts
are those we seek to discover. not those we make true. And in this respect
too. when it comes to moral truths. we are in a position more like that of
the scientist who tries to discover the laws of nature (which exist indepen-
dently of her investigations) than that of the legislator (who creates laws).
Now. in insisting that morality is objective in this sense-for instance,
by relying on the reasons given in the previous section-it's important to
see what has and what has not been established. In order to see this. it
may help to draw an analogy with religious discourse. So think of your
deeply held religious beliefs. if you have any. Of. like me, you do not. try to
think what it's like to be deeply committed to a religious belief. or perhaps
think of your commitment to atheism.) And try to run our tests-does it
make sense to be happy that you were brought up under the religion in
which you deeply believe. even assuming that with a difterenl education
you would have believed another religion. or no religion at all? What do
you think of the phenomenology of religious deliberation and disagree-
ment? And had you stopped believing, would the doctrines of your faith
still have been true?
Now, perhaps things are not obvious here. but it seems to me that
for many religiOUS people, religious discourse passes all these objectiv-
ity tests. But from this it does not follow that atheism is false, much less
that a specific religion is true. When they are applied to some specific
religious discourse. the objectivity tests show that such discourse aspires
to objectivity. In other words. the tests show what the world must be
like for the commitments of the discourse to be vindicated: if (say) a
Catholic's religious beliefs are to be true, what must be the case is that
the doctrines of the Catholic Church hold objectively, that is, response-
independently. This leaves entirely open the question whether these
doctrines do in fact hold.
Back to morality, then. Here too, what the discussion of objec-
tivity (tentatively) establishes is just something about the aspirations
of moral discourse: namely, that it aspires to objectivity. If our moral
judgments are to be true. it must be the case that things have value. that
people have rights and duties, thai there are better and worse ways to
216 MtiTAETtIlCS
live our lives-and all of this must hold objectively, that is, response-
independently. But establishing that moral discourse aspires to objec-
tivity is one thing. Whether there actually are objective moral truths is
quite another.
And now you may be worried. Why does it matter, you may wonder,
what morality's aspirations are, if (for all I've said so far) they may not
be met? I want to offer two replies here. First. precisely in order to check
whether morality's aspirations are in fact fulfilled, we should understand
them better. If you are trying to decide, for instance, whether the com-
mitments of Catholicism are true, you had better understand them first.
Second, and more importantly. one of the things we are trying to do here
is to gain a better understanding of what we are already committed to. You
may recall that I started with the hypothesis that you may think you're a
relativist or a subjectivist. But if the discussion so far gets things right (if,
that is. morality aspires to this kind of objectiVity), and if you have any
moral beliefs at all (don't you think that some things are wrong! do we
really need t(l give gruesome examples!), then it follows that you your-
self are already committed to morality's objectivity. And this is already an
interesting result. at least for you.
That morality aspires in this way to objectivity also has the impli-
cation that any full metaethical theory-any theory, that is, that offers a
full description and explanation of moral discourse and practice-has to
take this aspiration into account. Most likely, it has to accommodate it.
Less likely, but still pOSSibly, such a theory may tell us that this aspiration
is futile, explaining why even though morality is not objective, we tend
to think that it is, why it manifests the marks of objectivity that the tests
above catch on, and so on. What no metaethical theory can do, however, is
ignore the very strong appearance that morality is objective. I get back to
this in the final section. below.
WhyNot~
As I already mentioned. we cannot rule out the possibility that under argu-
mentative pressure we're going to have to revise even some of our most
deeply held beliefs. Philosophy, in other words, is hard. And as you can
imagine, claims about morality's objectivity have not escaped criticism.
Indeed. perhaps some such objections have already occurred to you. In
this section. I qUickly mention some of them, and hint at the ways in
which I think they can be coped with. But let me note how incomplete the
Why I Am all Objectivist about Htlli,'s (Arid Why YOIl Are, '1('0) 217
discussion here is. lhere are, of course, other objections, objections that I
don't discuss here. More importantly, there are many more things to say-
on both sides-regarding the objections that I do discuss. The discussion
here is meant as an introduction to these further discussions, no more
than that. (Have I mentioned that philosophy L'i hard?)
Disagreement
I have been emphasizing ways in which mond disagreement may motivate
the thought that morality is objective. But it's very common tu think that
something about moral disagreement actually goes the other way. For if
there are perfectly objective moral truths. why is there so much disagree-
ment about them? Wouldn't we expect, if there are such objective truths,
to see everyone converging on them? Perhaps such convergence cannot be
expected to be perfect and quick. but still-why is there so much persis-
tent, apparently irreconcilable disagreement in mc.uality. but not in subject
matters whose objectivity is less controversial? If there is no answer to this
question. doesn't this count heavily against morality's objectivity?
It is not easy to see exactly what this objection comt.'S to. (Exercise:
Can you try and formulate a precise argument here?) It mOlY be necessary
to distinguish between several possible arguments. Naturally, different
ways of understanding the objection will call for different responses. But
there are some things that can be said in general here. First, the objection
seems to underrate the extent of disagreement in subject matters whose
objectivity is pretty much uncontroversial (think c.lf the causes and effects
of global warming again). It may also overrate the extent of disngreement
in morality. Still, the requirement to explain the scope and nature of moral
disagreements seems legitimate. Bul objectivity-friendly explanations
seem possible.
Perhaps. for instance, moral disagreement is sometimes best explained
by noting that people tend to accept the moral judgments that it's in their
interest to accept. or that tend to show their lives and practices in good
light. Perhaps this is why the poor tend to believe in the welfare state, and
the rich tend to beJieve in property rights.
Perhaps the most important gcnercd lesson here is that not all dis-
agreements count against the objectivity of the relevant discourse. So what
we need is a criterion to distinguish between objectivity-undermining and
non-objectivity-undermining disagreements. And then we need an argu-
ment showing that moral disagreement is of the former kind. Jdun't know
of a fully successful way of filling in these details here.
218 METAE1'IIICS
Notice, by the way, that such attempts are going to have to overcome
a natural worry about self-defeat. Some theories defeat themselves, that is,
roughly, fail even by their own lights. Consider, for instance, the theory
"All theories are false," or the belief "No belief is justified." (Exercise: Can
you think of other self-defeating theories?) Now, disagreement in phi-
losophy has many of the features that moral disagreement seems to have.
In particular, so does metaethical disagreement. Even more in particular,
so does disagreement about whether disagreement undermines objectivity.
If moral disagreement undermines the objectivity of moral conclusions,
metaethical disagreement seems to undermine the objectivity of meta-
ethical conclusion..~, including the conclusion that disagreement of this
kind undermines objectivity. And this starts to look like self-defeat. So
if some disagreement-objection to the objectivity of morality is going to
succeed, it must show how moral disagreement undermines the objec-
tivity of morality, but metaethical disagreement does not undermine the
objectivity of metaethical claims. Perhaps it's possible to do so. But it's not
going to be easy.
Who Decidest
Still. even if moral knowledge is not especially protllematic, even if moral
disagreement can be explained in objectivity-friendly ways, and even if
there are perfectly objective moral truths, what should we do in cases of
disagreement and conflict? Who gets to decide what the right way of pro-
ceeding is? Especially in the case of intercultural disagreement and con-
tliet, isn't saying something like "We're right and you're wrong about what
is objectively moraJly required" objectionably dogmatic, intolerant, per-
haps an invitation to fanaticism?
Well, in a sense. no one decides. In another sense. everyone does. The
situation here is precisely as it is everywhere else: no one gets to decide
whether smoking causes cancer, whether human actions contribute to
global warming, whether the earth revolves around the sun. Our decisions
do not make these claims true or false. But everyone gets (roughly speak-
ing) to decide what they are going to believe about these matters. And this
is so for moral claims as well.
How about intolerance and fanaticism? If the worry is that people are
likely to become dangerously intolerant if they believe in objective morality,
then first, such a prediction would have to be established. After all, many
social reformers (think. for instance, of Martin Luther King. Jr.) who fought
against intolerance and bigotry seem to have been inspired by the thuught
220 MHAUHlt:S
that their vision of equality and justice was objectively correct. Further,
even if it's very dangerous for people to believe in the objectivity of their
moral convictions, this doesn't mean that morality isn't objective. Such
danger would give us reasons not to let people know about morality's objec-
tivity. It would not give us a reason to believe that morality is not objective.
(Compare: even if it were the case that things would go rapidly downhill
if atheism were widely believed, this wouldn't prove that atheism is false.)
More importantly, though, it's one thing to believe in the objectivity
of morality, it's quite another to decide what to do about it. And it's quite
possible that the right thing to do. given morality's objectivity, is hardly
ever to respond with "I am simply right and you are simply wrong!" or
to be intolerant. In fact, if you think that it's wrong to he intolerant, aren't
you committed to the objectivity of this very claimr (Want to run the three
tests again?) So it seems as ifthe only way of accommodating the impor-
tance of toleration is actually to accept morality's objectivity, not to reject it.
Conclusion
As already noted, much more can be said-about what objectivity is,
ahout the reaSOllS to think that morality is objective, and about these
(and many other) objections to morality'S objectivity. Much more work
remains to be done.
And one of the ways in which current literature addresses some of
these issues may sound surprising, for a major part of the debate assumes
something like morality's aspiration to objectivity in the sense above, but
refuses to infer from such observations quick conclusions about the nature
of moral truths and facts. In other words. many metaethicists today deny
the most straightforward objectivist view of morality, according to which
moral facts are a part of response-independent reality, much like math-
ematical and physical facts. But they do 110t deny morality'S objectivity-
they care, for instance, about passing the three tests above. And so they
attempt to show how even on other metaethical views, morality's objec-
tivity can be accommodated. As you can imagine. philosophers disagree
about the success (actual and potential) of such accommodation projects.
Naturally, such controversies also lead to attempts to better under-
stand what the objectivity at stake exactly is, and why it m,lUers (if it
matters) whether morality is objective. As is often the case, attempts to
evaluate answers to a question make us better understand-or wonder
about-the question itselt:
Why I Am ,in Objectivijt t1bo11t lithii:s (An,I WIiy fou Are, loo) 221
Nothing here, 1hen, is simple. But I hope that you now see how you
are probably a moral objectivist, at lea�t in your intuitive starting point.
Perhaps further philosophical reflection will require that you abandon this
starting point. But this will be an abandoning, and a very strong reason is
needed to justify it. Until we get such a conclusive argument against moral
objectivity, then, objectivism should be the view to beat.