Irrelevant CAR
Irrelevant CAR
Irrelevant CAR
Working Paper
Fallacies, irrelevant facts, and myths in the
discussion of capital regulation: Why bank equity is
not expensive
Preprints of the Max Planck Institute for Research on Collective Goods, No. 2010,42
Suggested Citation: Admati, Anat R.; DeMarzo, Peter M.; Hellwig, Martin; Pfleiderer, Paul
(2010) : Fallacies, irrelevant facts, and myths in the discussion of capital regulation: Why bank
equity is not expensive, Preprints of the Max Planck Institute for Research on Collective Goods,
No. 2010,42, Max Planck Institute for Research on Collective Goods, Bonn
Die Dokumente auf EconStor dürfen zu eigenen wissenschaftlichen Documents in EconStor may be saved and copied for your
Zwecken und zum Privatgebrauch gespeichert und kopiert werden. personal and scholarly purposes.
Sie dürfen die Dokumente nicht für öffentliche oder kommerzielle You are not to copy documents for public or commercial
Zwecke vervielfältigen, öffentlich ausstellen, öffentlich zugänglich purposes, to exhibit the documents publicly, to make them
machen, vertreiben oder anderweitig nutzen. publicly available on the internet, or to distribute or otherwise
use the documents in public.
Sofern die Verfasser die Dokumente unter Open-Content-Lizenzen
(insbesondere CC-Lizenzen) zur Verfügung gestellt haben sollten, If the documents have been made available under an Open
gelten abweichend von diesen Nutzungsbedingungen die in der dort Content Licence (especially Creative Commons Licences), you
genannten Lizenz gewährten Nutzungsrechte. may exercise further usage rights as specified in the indicated
licence.
Preprints of the
Max Planck Institute for
Research on Collective Goods
Bonn 2010/42
Anat R. Admati
Peter M. DeMarzo
Martin F. Hellwig
Paul Pfleiderer
Anat R. Admati
Peter M. DeMarzo
Martin F. Hellwig
Paul Pfleiderer
Anat R. Admati
Peter M. DeMarzo
Martin F. Hellwig
Paul Pfleiderer*
Comments Welcome
*
Admati, DeMarzo and Pfleiderer are from the Graduate School of Business, Stanford University; Hellwig is from
the Max Planck Institute for Research on Collective Goods, Bonn. We are grateful to Viral Acharya, Tobias Adrian,
Jürg Blum, Patrick Bolton, Michael Boskin, Christina Büchmann, Darrell Duffie, Bob Hall, Bengt Holmström,
Christoph Engel, Charles Goodhart, Hanjo Hamann, Ed Lazear, Hamid Mehran, Francisco Perez-Gonzales, Isabel
Schnabel, Hyun Shin, Chester Spatt, Ilya Strebulaev, Anjan Thakor, Jean Tirole, Jim Van Horne, and Theo
Vermaelen for useful discussions and comments. Contact information: [email protected];
[email protected]; [email protected]; [email protected].
We examine the pervasive view that “equity is expensive,” which leads to claims that high
capital requirements are costly and would affect credit markets adversely. We find that
arguments made to support this view are either fallacious, irrelevant, or very weak. For example,
the return on equity contains a risk premium that must go down if banks have more equity. It is
thus incorrect to assume that the required return on equity remains fixed as capital requirements
increase. It is also incorrect to translate higher taxes paid by banks to a social cost. Policies that
subsidize debt and indirectly penalize equity through taxes and implicit guarantees are distortive.
Any desirable public subsidies to banks’ activities should be given directly and not in ways that
encourage leverage. Finally, suggestions that high leverage serves a necessary disciplining role
are based on inadequate theory lacking empirical support.
We conclude that bank equity is not socially expensive, and that high leverage is not
necessary for banks to perform all their socially valuable functions, including lending, taking
deposits and issuing money-like securities. To the contrary, better capitalized banks suffer fewer
distortions in lending decisions and would perform better. The fact that banks choose high
leverage does not imply that this is socially optimal, and, viewed from an ex ante perspective,
high leverage may not even be privately optimal for banks.
Setting equity requirements significantly higher than the levels currently proposed would
entail large social benefits and minimal, if any, social costs. Approaches based on equity
dominate alternatives, including contingent capital. To achieve better capitalization quickly and
efficiently and prevent disruption to lending, regulators must actively control equity payouts and
issuance. If remaining challenges are addressed, capital regulation can be a powerful tool for
enhancing the role of banks in the economy.
Keywords: capital regulation, financial institutions, capital structure, capital regulation, “too big
to fail,” systemic risk, bank equity, contingent capital, Basel.
1. Introduction ................................................................................................................................1
3.2. Equity Capital Requirements and the Return on Equity (ROE) .......................................11
5.3. Is High Bank Leverage Evidence that Bank Equity is Socially Costly? ..........................33
References ................................................................................................................................55
Executive Summary
There is a pervasive sense in discussions of bank capital regulation that “equity is expensive”
and that equity requirements, while beneficial, also entail a cost. The arguments we examine,
which represent many of those most often made in this context, are fallacious, irrelevant, or very
weak. Our analysis leads us to conclude that significantly higher equity requirements entail large
social benefits and minimal, if any, social costs. We list below some of the arguments made
against high equity requirements and explain why they are either incorrect or unsupported.
Increased equity requirements would force banks to “set aside” or “hold in reserve” funds
that can otherwise be used for lending. This argument confuses liquidity requirements and
capital requirements. Capital requirements refer to how banks are funded and in particular the
mix between debt and equity on the balance sheet of the banks. There is no sense in which
capital is “set aside.” Liquidity requirements relate to the type of assets and asset mix banks
must hold. Since they address different sides of the balance sheet, there is no immediate
relation between liquidity requirements and capital requirements.
Increased equity requirements would increase banks’ funding costs because equity requires a
higher return than debt. This argument is fallacious, because the required return on equity,
which includes a risk premium, must decline when more equity is used. Any argument or
analysis that holds fixed the required return on equity when evaluating changes in equity
capital requirements is fundamentally flawed.
Increased equity requirements would lower the banks’ Return on Equity (ROE), and this
means a loss in value. This argument is also fallacious. The expected ROE of a bank
increases with leverage and would thus indeed decline if leverage is reduced. This change
only compensates for the change in the risk borne by equity holders and does not mean that
shareholder value is lost or gained. Shareholders willing to take additional risk can increase
their average return by buying stock on margin.
Increased equity requirements would increase banks’ funding costs because banks would not
be able to borrow at the favorable rates created by tax shields and other subsidies. It is true
that, through taxes and implicit guarantees, debt financing is subsidized and equity financing
is effectively penalized. Policies that encourage high leverage are distorting and paradoxical,
because high leverage is a source of systemic risk. The subsidies come from public funds. If
some activities performed by banks are worthy of public support, subsidies should be given
directly to those activities.
Increased equity requirements would be costly since debt is necessary for providing “market
discipline” to bank managers. While there are theoretical models that show that debt can
i
sometimes play a disciplining role, arguments against increasing equity requirements that are
based on this notion are very weak. First, high leverage actually creates many frictions. In
particular, it creates incentives for banks to take excessive risk. Any purported benefits
produced by debt in disciplining managers must be measured against frictions created by
debt. Second, the notion that debt plays a disciplining role is contradicted by the events of the
last decade, which include both a dramatic increase in bank leverage (and risk) and the
financial crisis itself. There is little or no evidence that banks’ debt holders provided any
significant discipline during this period. Third, many models that are designed to attribute to
debt a positive disciplining role completely ignore the potential disciplining role that can be
played by equity or through alternative governance mechanisms. Fourth, the supposed
discipline provided by debt generally relies upon a fragile capital structure funded by short
term debt that must be frequently renewed. Reduced fragility, which is a key goal of capital
regulation, would be at odds with the functioning of this purported disciplining mechanism.
Finally, one must ask if there are no less costly ways to solve governance problems.
Increased equity requirements would force or cause banks to cut back on lending and/or
other socially valuable activities. First, higher equity capital requirements do not
mechanically limit banks’ activities, including lending, deposits taking and the issuance of
liquid money-like securities. Banks can maintain all their existing assets and liabilities and
reduce leverage through equity issuance and the expansion of their balance sheets. That said,
because equity issuance improves the position of existing creditors, and may also be
interpreted as a negative signal on the bank’s health, banks might privately prefer to pass up
lending opportunities if they must fund them with equity. However, this “debt overhang”
problem can be alleviated if regulators require undercapitalized banks to recapitalize quickly
by restricting equity payouts and mandating new equity issuance. Once better capitalized,
banks would make better lending and investment decisions, because they would have
reduced incentives to take excessive risk and indeed would be less affected by distortions due
to debt overhang.
The fact that banks tend to fund themselves primarily with debt and have high levels of
leverage implies that this is the optimal way to fund bank activities. It does not follow that
just because financial institutions choose high leverage, this form of financing is privately or
socially optimal. Instead, this observed behavior is the result of factors unrelated to social
concerns, such as tax incentives and other subsidies, and to frictions associated with conflicts
of interests and inability to commit in advance to certain investment and financing decisions.
Recommendations
Recognizing, as we have argued, that bank equity is not expensive, regulators should use
equity requirements as a powerful, effective, and flexible tool with which to maintain the
health and stability of the financial system. High leverage is not required in order for banks
ii
to perform all their socially valuable functions, such as providing credit and creating deposit
services. High leverage is in fact quite harmful to their ability to do so and leads to socially
suboptimal lending decisions.
Regulators should routinely use restrictions on equity payouts and the removal of discretion
with respect to equity issuance to help banks, and to assure that they achieve and maintain
adequate equity capitalization. Prohibiting, for a period of time and for all banks, any
dividends and other equity payouts, and possibly imposing equity issuance on a pre-specified
schedule, is an efficient way to help banks build their equity capital quickly and efficiently
without leading to the contraction of credit. If done under the force of regulation, withholding
payouts or issuing additional equity would not lead to negative inferences about the health of
any particular bank. It would also alleviate the debt overhang distortion that might lead banks
to reduce lending.
If certain activities of the banking sector are deemed to require subsidies, then subsidies
should be given in direct ways that alleviate market frictions and not through a system that
encourages high leverage. Tax shields and implicit government guarantees subsidize debt
finance and effectively penalize equity as a form of financing banks. This policy is
undesirable given the systemic risk and additional frictions brought about by high leverage.
Better resolution procedures for distressed financial institutions, while necessary, should not
be viewed as alternatives to having significantly better capitalized banks. Since such
procedures are not likely to eliminate the cost of financial distress, reducing the likelihood
that a resolution procedure is needed is clearly important, and higher equity requirements are
the most effective way to do so.
Approaches based on equity are superior to those that allow contingent capital to be
considered part of capital regulation, because there does not seem to be a compelling case
that contingent capital has social value relative to equity. Contingent capital is complicated
to design and to value. Preserving the tax benefits of debt is not a legitimate reason for the
“debt-like” feature of contingent capital, and the potential role of contingent capital in
resolving any frictions has not been established. Simple approaches based on equity would
provide more reliable cushions.
iii
1. Introduction
As the financial crisis of 2007-2008 has compellingly shown, highly leveraged financial
institutions create negative externalities. When a bank is highly leveraged, even a small decrease
in asset value can lead to distress and potential insolvency. In a deeply interconnected financial
system, this can cause the system to freeze, ultimately leading to severe repercussions for the rest
of the economy.1 To minimize social damage, governments may feel compelled to spend large
amounts on bailouts and recovery efforts. Even when insolvency is not an immediate problem,
following a small decrease in asset values, highly-leveraged banks may be compelled to sell
substantial amounts of assets in order to reduce their leverage; such sales can put strong pressure
on asset markets and prices and, thereby, indirectly on other banks.
Avoidance of such “systemic risk” and the associated social costs is a major objective of
financial regulation. Because market participants, acting in their own interests, tend to pay too
little attention to systemic concerns, financial regulation and supervision are intended to step in
and safeguard the functioning of the financial system. Given the experience of the recent crisis, it
is natural to consider a requirement that banks have significantly less leverage, i.e., that they hold
relatively more equity to absorb inevitable variations in asset values.
A pervasive view that underlies most discussions of capital regulation is that “equity is
expensive,” and that equity requirements, while having substantial benefits, also impose costs on
the financial system. Bankers have mounted a campaign against increasing equity requirements.
Policy makers and regulators are particularly concerned by assertions that increased equity
requirements would restrict bank lending and would impede economic growth. Possibly as a
result of such pressure, the proposed Basel III requirements, while moving in the direction of
increasing capital, still allow banks to remain very highly leveraged.2 We consider this very
troubling, because, as we show below, the view that equity is expensive is flawed in the context
of capital regulation.
We will examine various arguments that are made to support the notion that there are social
costs, and not just benefits, associated with increased equity requirements. Our conclusion is that
the social costs of significantly increasing equity requirements for large financial institutions
would be, if there were any at all, very small. All the arguments we have encountered that
suggest otherwise are very weak when examined from first principles and in the context of
optimal regulation. They are based either on fallacious claims, on a confusion between private
costs to banks and social costs to the public, or on models that are inadequate from both a
theoretical and an empirical perspective.
1
Similar observations are made, for example, Adrian and Shin (2010) and Adrian and Brunnermeier (2010).
2
The proposed requirements set minimal equity levels to be between 4.5% and 7% of “risk weighted” assets.
1
The discussion is often clouded by a confusion between capital and liquidity requirements.
This confusion has resulted in routine references in the press to capital as something banks must
“set aside” or “hold in reserve.”3 Capital requirements refer to how banks are funded and in
particular the mix between debt and equity on the balance sheet of the banks. There is no sense
in which capital is “set aside.” Liquidity requirements relate to the type of assets and asset mix
banks must hold. Since they address different sides of the balance sheet, there is no immediate
relation between liquidity requirements and capital requirements. The discussion that follows is
focused on capital requirements.
We begin by showing that equity requirements need not interfere with any of the socially
valuable activities of banks, including lending, deposit taking, or the creation of “money-like”
liquid securities that investors value. In fact, banks’ ability to provide social value might be
enhanced by increased equity requirements, because they would be likely to make more
economically appropriate lending decisions, since, among other things, better capitalized banks
are less inclined to make excessively risky investments that benefit shareholders and managers at
the expense of debt holders or the government.
Despite the fact that equity has a higher required return than debt because it is riskier, the use
of more equity funding need not change the overall funding cost of banks. A bank that uses more
equity financing lowers the riskiness of its equity (and perhaps also of its debt). Unless those
who fund the bank are fooled so that securities are mispriced, simply shifting the way that risk is
borne by different investors need not have any direct effects on the overall funding cost of the
bank.4
Various distortions and frictions in the economy do affect banks’ cost of debt and equity
finance. Some of the most important frictions and distortions are actually created by public
policy. For example, most tax systems give an advantage to debt financing and penalize equity
financing. Some of the arguments against higher equity capital requirements are based on the
“costs” banks would incur if they had to give up some of this subsidized debt financing. From a
public policy perspective these arguments are wrong since they inappropriately focus on private
costs to the bank rather than social costs. Ideally, taxes should be structured to minimize the
3
For example, the Wall Street Journal reported on September 13, 2010 (“Banks Get New Restraints,” p. 1) that as a
result of the proposed capital requirements banks would face “… tougher requirements on the capital they are
required to hold in reserve to guard against future losses.” The New York Times editorial on September 14 also
stated that “…banks will … try to …reduce the amount of capital they must set aside.” These statements are
erroneous in reference to capital requirements; Basel III liquidity requirements have yet to be announced.
4
These observations constitute some of the most basic insights in corporate finance. Yet, numerous statements in the
policy debate on this subject fail to take them into account and therefore are based on faulty logic Thus, in many
studies of the impact of increased equity requirements, including, for example, BIS (2010), the required return of
return on equity is taken to be a constant number; yet this required return must go down if banks have more equity.
While the fact that the required return would fall is mentioned in the text of BIS (2010), the empirical analysis still
assume a constant required return on equity, and this rate is also used inappropriately in other parts of the study. The
study by IIF also suffers from such shortcomings.
2
overall distortions they induce, which means that they should encourage behavior that generates
positive externalities and discourage behavior that generates negative externalities. A tax system
that encourages banks to take on socially costly excessive leverage is highly distortionary and
dysfunctional. If the banking system needs to be subsidized, more effective and less costly ways
must be found to do that. Taking the tax code as given is inappropriate in this context; all
relevant aspects of public policy should be considered.
Implicit government guarantees associated with a “too big to fail” status constitute another
distortion that favors debt over equity financing for many financial institutions. This
phenomenon has been dubbed “privatization of profits and socialization of costs,” and banks
benefit from it by being able to borrow more cheaply than they otherwise would. Although
politicians are fond of saying that bailouts should never happen, it is impossible, and not even
desirable, for governments to commit to never bail out a financial institution. It is true that fully
charging banks for the guarantees would remove this subsidy, but it is extremely difficult for the
government to do this, and incentives to take excessive risk remain a problem with any type of
insurance plan. A more prudent approach is to require banks to have significantly less leverage,
so as to lower the social cost associated with any implicit (or underpriced) guarantees and to
minimize the likelihood of bank failure that would necessitate resolution or bailout. Again, if
subsidizing banks is desirable, the government should find other, more direct ways, to do so
without directly encouraging leverage.
Some have argued that higher equity capital requirements would be costly because debt plays
a positive role in reducing frictions due to governance and asymmetric information. For example,
it has been suggested that debt serves as a “disciplining device” to prevent managers from
wasting or diverting funds. Short term debt, or long term debt when some of it needs to be
renewed periodically, is said to provide “market discipline” because the fear that it might be
withdrawn or not renewed leads managers to act more in line with the preferences of creditors,
and even avoid taking excessive risk. Our assessment is that the theoretical and empirical
foundations of these claims are very weak, and that the models that are used to support them are
simply inadequate for guiding policy regarding capital requirements. Among other things,
leverage in fact creates significant frictions and governance problems that distort the lending and
investment decisions of financial institutions. These frictions are exacerbated in the presence of
implicit guarantees, which also blunt any potential discipline of debt by removing the incentives
of debt holders to engage in monitoring. Moreover, we argue that the events of the recent
financial crisis are in fact quite difficult to reconcile with the notion that debt plays a positive
role in providing ex ante discipline to bank managers. Finally, even if it debt can play a positive
role in governance, we argue that in many cases additional equity would not interfere with this
function, and also that debt is not uniquely able to provide discipline. We discuss a number of
alternative ways to achieve the same results without resorting to socially costly leverage.
3
Another argument against higher equity capital requirements is based on the claim that equity
is costly for banks to issue. Issuing equity can be costly if the banks shares are undervalued by
the market or if the market interprets the decision to issue equity as a negative signal. We argue
that these considerations are not valid reasons for not requiring banks to have significantly more
equity. First, the negative signal that might be associated with the bank selling shares can be
reduced or removed if banks have less discretion with respect to equity issuance. Similar to how
large banks were all forced, or at least pressured, to accept TARP funds during the recent crisis,
to help banks build capital, regulators can impose a time table for equity issuance so as to
remove possible negative stigma associated with such issuance. Second, better capitalized banks
need less external finance, as they have more retained earnings with which to fund their growth.
Finally, better capitalized banks incur proportionately lower costs when issuing additional
equity.
Since banks are actually highly leveraged, there is a temptation to conclude that such high
leverage must be the optimal solution to some problem banks face. We argue that there is no
justification for this inference. First, government subsidies give incentives to banks to use high
levels of debt financing. In this regard, high leverage might be privately optimal for the banks,
but this clearly does not make it socially optimal. Second, there are numerous reasons to
conclude that high leverage is not even privately optimal for banks.5 High leverage can be the
result of banks’ inability to make commitments regarding future investments and financing
decisions. Given continual incentives to increase leverage and shorten its maturity to usurp prior
creditors, a bank’s capital structure, as it evolves over time, is likely to have leverage that is
excessive even from the narrow perspective of what is good for the bank and its shareholders.
How would significantly higher equity capital requirements affect the lending activities of
banks? We argue that, since highly leveraged banks are subject to distortions in their lending
decisions, better capitalized banks are likely to make better lending decisions, which are less
subject to incentives for taking on risk or to problems related to “debt overhang” that can
actually prevent banks from making valuable loans. There is indeed no reason for banks to
refrain from any socially valuable activity, since these activities would not become more costly
once any required subsidies are set at an appropriate level. Thus, there is no reason to believe
that, if overall public policy forces banks to operate with significantly higher equity levels and
significantly reduce their leverage, and if any subsidies are set in a socially responsible way,
banks would refrain from making any loans that would lead to growth and prosperity. Highly
leveraged banks might respond to increased capital requirements by restricting loans because of
the “debt overhang” problem mentioned above, but this will be alleviated once banks are better
capitalized. In the transition, regulators can forbid equity payouts and possibly mandate equity
5
Consistent with this, Mehran and Thakor (2010) find that various measures of bank value are positively correlated
with bank capitalization in the cross section. Berger and Bouwman (2010) show that higher bank capital is important
in banks’ ability to survive financial crises.
4
issuance to make sure this does not happen. Additional equity also enhances the bank’s ability to
provide money-like securities that investors may value, since such securities become even less
risky and more “informationally insensitive” when they are backed by additional equity.
We show that adding equity to banks’ balance sheets need not have any negative effect on
the aggregate production activities or asset holdings in the economy. In particular, if additional
equity is used by banks to buy marketable securities, this does not affect the undertaking of all
productive activities in the economy or the portfolios of final investors. If the banks buy
securities that are liquid, the liquidity of the bank’s assets will be enhanced, which is a potential
additional benefit.
Finally, we argue that the case for contingent capital, i.e., debt that converts to equity under
some conditions, has not been made against alternatives such as increased equity. Contingent
capital is very complicated in terms of design and valuation. We do not see a compelling
rationale for introducing it as part of capital regulation when simple equity will provide a more
reliable cushion. Preserving the tax benefits of debt is not a legitimate reason, and the potential
role of contingent capital in resolving frictions associated with governance has not been
established.
A clear recommendation that emerges from our analysis is that prohibiting, for a period of
time, dividend and other equity payouts for all banks is a prudent and efficient way to help banks
build capital. If done under the force of regulation, these payout suspensions would not lead to
any negative inference on the health of any particular bank. In addition, as mentioned above,
regulators can remove the stigma associated with equity issuance, as well as frictions related to
debt overhang, by requiring banks to issue equity on a pre-specified schedule.
Our discussion focuses on the social costs and benefits of using common equity as a way to
fund banks. We do not consider other types of claims to be useful in providing a reliable cushion.
Indeed, the recent crisis has shown that Tier 2 capital, i.e., subordinated debt, does not provide a
reliable cushion. Proposals have been made to substitute “contingent capital,” i.e., a debt-like
security that converts to equity under some conditions, for subordinated debt to or using “bail-in”
mechanisms to try to improve the cushion provided by Tier 2 capital. Our view is that, since
there is no compelling case that the debt-like features of these securities provide social value,
capital regulation should focus entirely on equity.
We do not address all the issues that regulators confront in regulating financial institutions.
In particular, we do not discuss in detail which banks or financial institutions should be
regulated, the distinction between large and small banks, or the issue of micro vs. macro
prudential regulation. Our discussion applies most urgently to those institutions whose leverage
imposes negative externalities on the financial system as a whole, i.e., “systemic risk” and which
5
are “too important” or “too interconnected” to fail. However, a workable definition of such
“systemic” institutions raises a host of additional questions, which go beyond the scope of this
paper. Another issue we do not elaborate on here is the risk weights currently used to determine
the size of asset base against which equity is measured. As discussed in Brealey (2006) and
Hellwig (2010), this system is easily manipulable and can lead to distortions in the lending and
investment decisions of banks. Proposing a way to track the riskiness of banks’ assets on an
ongoing basis is a challenge that at this point is beyond the scope of the current paper.
There have been hundreds of papers on capital regulation in the last decade, and particularly
since the financial crisis. We cite here some papers that make recommendations similar or
related to those we make here. Closest to us are Harrison (2004) and Brealey (2006) who also
conclude that there are no compelling arguments supporting the claim that bank equity has a
social cost.6 Poole (2009) identifies the tax subsidy of debt as distorting, a concern we share.
However, he goes on to suggest that long term debt (possibly of the “contingent capital” variety)
can provide both a meaningful “cushion” and the so-called “market discipline.” As we explain
especially in Sections 5.1 and 8, we take issue with this part of his assessement. Turner (2010)
and Goodhart (2010) also argue that a significant increase in equity requirements is the most
important step regulators should take at this point. Acharya, Gujral, and Shin (2009), Acharya,
Mehran and Thakor (2010) and Goodhart et al. (2010) suggest, as we do, that regulators use
restrictions on dividends and equity payouts as part of prudential capital regulation. We take this
recommendation a step further by suggesting the possibility of mandatory equity issuances as
well, not just to control the actions of distressed institutions, but rather as a way to proactively
help overcome informational frictions and avoid negative inferences associated with new issues.
Such mandates are particularly important in managing a transition to a regime with significantly
higher equity requirements. Finally, Kotlikoff (2010) proposes what he calls Limited Purpose
Banking, in which financial intermediation is carried out through mutual fund structures. His
proposal, like ours, is intended to reduce systemic risk and distortions, especially those associate
with excessive risk taking. Our recommendations differs from his in that we allow for financial
intermediation to be performed by the same type of structures that currently exist, i.e.,
intermediaries that can make loans, take deposits and issue other “money-like” claims.
Before examining the arguments that purport to show that increased capital requirements are
costly, it is important to review some of the significant benefits associated with better capitalized
banks. The recent financial crisis, as well as ones that have preceded it, have made it very clear
that systemic risk in the financial sector is a great concern. Financial distress in one large
6
Many authors, including King (1990), Schaefer (1990), Berger, Herring and Szego (1995), Miller (1995), Brealey
(2006), Hellwig (2009b), and French et al. (2010), have emphasized that the Modigliani-Miller Theorem must be the
starting point of any discussion of capital regulation.
6
institution can rapidly spill over into others and cause a credit crunch or an asset price implosion.
The effects of systemic risk events such as the one just experienced are not confined to the
financial sector of the economy. As history has repeatedly demonstrated, these events can have
extremely adverse consequences for the rest of the economy and can cause or deepen recessions
or depressions. Lowering the risk of financial distress among those institutions that can originate
and transmit systemic risk produces a clear social benefit.7
An obvious way to lower systemic risk is to require banks to have equity capital cushions
that are significantly larger than what they had before the last crisis unfolded.8 In the build up to
the last crisis important parts of the financial sector had become very highly leveraged. Indeed,
several banks had balance sheets in which equity was only two or three percent of assets.9 Such a
thin cushion obviously leaves little room for error. Even a moderate shock that reduces asset
values by one or two percent puts such thinly capitalized banks on the brink of insolvency. Even
if it is not actually insolvent, suspicions of its exposure may stop other institutions from
providing the short-term funding that it relies on. In the last crisis, even before the breakdown of
Lehman Brothers, there were several instances during which interbank markets froze because of
such distrust among market participants. With greater capital cushions, there would be less risk
of such systemic breakdowns from mutual distrust.
7
Indeed, BIS (2010) estimates that a 2% increase in capital ratios will reduce the probability of a financial crisis by
2.9%. The Bank of Canada (2010) estimates the gains that this would produce for the Canadian economy alone as
equivalent to an annual benefit on the order of 2% of GDP.
8
It is interesting to note that banks in the U.S. and in the U.K. were not always as highly leveraged as they have
been in recent decades. According to Berger, Herring and Szego (1995), in 1840 equity accounted for over 50% of
bank total value, and the increase in leverage can be traced to additional measures to create a “safety net” for banks.
Moreover, until the establishment of the FDIC in 1944, the liability of the equity issued by banks was not limited as
it is today. Instead, bank equity had double, triple and sometimes unlimited liability, which meant that equity holders
had to cover losses and pay back debt even after losing the entire amount they invested. Haldane (2009) shows a
similar pattern in the U.K. For Germany, a similar decline is documented by Holtfrerich (1981); not surprisingly,
however, the evolution here mirrors historical discontinuities associated with the two World Wars and the inflation
of 1914-1923, as well as the long-term trend which set in long before 1914.
9
Of course, banks appeared to be better capitalized in percentage terms when their capital was measured relative to
“risk weighted assets.” The risk weightings used in these measures are highly problematic. Banks have exploited the
freedom given them by the risk-calibrated approach to determining capital requirements in order to dramatically
expand the activities supported by the equity they had. Many of the risks that materialized in the crisis, however, had
not even been considered in risk weights beforehand. Moreover, true leverage was often masked through accounting
maneuvers, especially in connection with the so-called shadow banking system. On the shadow banking system, see
Pozsar et al (2010). On the use of the risk-calibrated approach to expand activities supported by a given level of
equity, see Hellwig (2009, 2010). Hellwig (2010) suggests that notions of measurement of risks that underlie the
risk-calibrated approach are largely illusionary.
7
The extent of deleveraging depends on what the bank’s capital position is. If bank capital is 3%
of the balance sheet, then following a loss of 1 million dollars, the bank attempting to deleverage
must liquidate more than 30 million dollars worth of assets just to re-establish that 3% ratio. The
systemic repercussions on asset prices and on other institutions will be accordingly large. Capital
requirements based on higher equity ratios would reduce the chances that such chain reactions
occur, and would dampen those that do occur.
If governments see the need to avoid the social costs of systemic crises by stepping in to
support their banking sectors, then an additional benefit of increased equity requirements comes
from reducing the burden on taxpayers. This benefit is produced in two ways. First, increased
equity requirements reduce the probability that bailouts will be necessary, since the equity
cushion of the bank can absorb more substantial decreases in the asset value without triggering a
default. Second, if a bailout does become necessary, the amount of required support would
generally be lower with a larger equity cushion, since a larger portion of losses would be
absorbed by the equity. Both the diminished probability of a systemic event and the decreased
amount of support required in the event of a crisis significantly reduce the costs to taxpayers.
There are additional benefits of higher equity capital requirements beyond the major ones
just given. These are generally related to the reduction in conflicts of interest and the more
aligned incentives that are created with less leverage. In particular, more equity capital reduces
the incentives of equity holders (and managers working on their behalf or compensated by return
on equity (ROE)) to undertake excessively risky investments. This will be discussed in more
detail in Sections 4.2 and 5.1 below.
10
This and other quotes cited in the paper are intended to be representative of common arguments that have entered
the policy debate on capital regulation. They may not reflect the complete or current views of those cited.
8
“The British Bankers' Association … calculated that demands by international
banking regulators in Basle that they bolster their capital will require the UK's
banking industry to hold an extra pounds 600bn of capital that might otherwise
have been deployed as loans to businesses or households.” The Observer (July 11,
2010)
Statement: “Increased capital requirements force banks to operate at a suboptimal scale and to
restrict lending.”
Assessment: To the extent that this implies balance sheets must be reduced in response to
increased equity requirements, this is false. By issuing new equity if necessary, banks can
respond to increased capital requirements without affecting any of their profitable or socially
valuable activities. Capital requirements do not require any capital to be set aside; rather, once
any liquidity requirements are satisfied, all bank capital can be productively deployed to make
loans or otherwise invest and earn market-determined (or higher) returns.
Statements such as the ones above predict that potentially dire consequences would result
from increasing capital requirements, and these have received the attention of regulators and
policy makers. While one should be concerned about the effect proposed regulations might have
on the ability of banks to carry out their core business activities, increasing the size of the equity
cushion does not in any way mechanically limit the ability of a bank to lend.
To see this, consider a very simple example. Assume that capital requirements are initially
set at 10%: a bank’s equity must be at least 10% of the value of the bank’s assets.11 For
concreteness, suppose that the bank has $100 in loans, financed by $90 of deposits and other
liabilities, and $10 of equity, as shown in the initial balance sheet in Figure 1.
Now assume that capital requirements are raised to 20%. In Figure 1 we consider three ways
in which the bank balance sheet can be changed to satisfy the higher capital requirement, fixing
the value of the bank’s current assets.12 One possibility is shown in Balance Sheet A, where the
bank “delevers” by significantly scaling back the size of its balance sheet, liquidating $50 in
assets and using the proceeds to reduce total liabilities from $90 to $40. In Balance Sheet B, the
bank satisfies the higher 20% capital requirement by recapitalizing, issuing $10 of additional
equity and retiring $10 of liabilities, and leaving its assets unchanged. Finally, in Balance Sheet
11
To keep the examples straightforward, we consider simplified versions of capital requirements. Actual current
capital requirements are based on risk adjustments and involve various measures of the bank’s capital (e.g., Tier 1
and Tier 2). The general points we make throughout this article apply to more complex requirements.
12
In this example, we are focusing on the mechanics of how balance sheets can be changed to meet capital
requirements. We are intentionally ignoring for now tax shields and implicit government guarantees associated with
a bank’s debt financing, as well as how changes in a bank’s capital structure alter the risk and required return of the
bank’s debt and equity. We discuss these important issues in detail in subsequent sections.
9
C, the bank expands its balance sheet by raising an additional $12.5 in equity capital and using
the proceeds to acquire new assets.
Initial Balance Sheet Revised Balance Sheet with Increased Capital Requirements
New Assets:
12.5
Equity:
22.5
Equity: 10
Equity: 20
Note that only when the bank actually shrinks its balance sheet, as shown in A, is the bank
reducing the amount of lending it can undertake. In both B and C the bank can support the same
amount of lending as was supported by the original balance sheet.
In balance sheet B some liabilities are replaced with equity. Specific types of liabilities, such
as deposits, are part of a bank’s “production function” in the sense that their issuance is related to
the provision of transactions and other convenience services that the bank provides to its
customers. Cutting back on these securities may not be desirable, as the provision of associated
services may be both profitable for the bank and beneficial for the economy.13 That said, it is
likely that at least a portion of a bank’s liabilities play a pure financing role, and replacing these
liabilities with equity will increase bank capital without reducing its productive lending and
deposit-taking activity.14
13
For example, Gorton (2010), Gorton and Metrick (2009), Stein (2010) and others argue that short-term liabilities
and deposits command a “money-like” convenience premium based on their relative safety and the transactions
services that safe claims provide. Gorton and Pennacchi (1990) and Dang, Gorton and Holmstrom (2010) stress the
importance of the “information insensitivity” of these claims in providing these services.
14
According to the FDIC website, as of March 31st, 2010, domestic deposits at U.S. commercial banks totaled
$6,788 billion, which represented 56.2% of total assets, while equity represented 10.9% of assets. This leaves 32.9%
of the assets, which is almost $4 trillion in non-deposit liabilities. Quite possibly, some of these liabilities can be
converted to equity without affecting the provision of important bank services.
10
Balance Sheet C meets the higher capital requirements while keeping both the original assets
(e.g. loans) and all of the original liabilities of the bank in place. Additional equity is raised and
new assets are acquired. In the short run, these new assets may simply be cash or other
marketable securities (e.g. Treasuries) held by the bank. As new, attractive lending opportunities
arise, these securities provide a pool of liquidity for the bank to draw upon to expand its lending
activity. One might worry that it would be costly or inefficient for the bank to hold additional
securities or one might be concerned about the impact of such a change on the overall demand
and supply of funding. We discuss these issues in detail in Section 7 and comment on
implementation issues in the concluding remarks (Section 9).
To summarize, in terms of simple balance sheet mechanics, the notion that increased equity
capital requirements force banks to reduce lending activities is simply false. Capital requirements
do not force banks to “set aside” any capital. Banks can preserve or even expand lending
activities by changing to Balance Sheets B or C. So, if higher capital requirements are to reduce
lending activities, it must be that these changes involve some additional costs, or that certain
frictions lead the bank to pass up profitable loans. In the sections that follow, we examine
various arguments that are put forward in support of the notion that increased equity capital
requirements entail higher costs or create distortions in lending decisions.
“Banks… do not want to hold too much capital because by so doing they will
lower the returns to equity holders.” Mishkin and Aekin (2009, p. 444)
Statement: “Increased equity requirements will hurt bank shareholders since it would lower the
banks return on equity (ROE).”
Assessment: This is false; a reduction in ROE does not indicate decreased value added. While
increased capital requirements can lower the Return on Equity (ROE) in good times, they will
raise ROE in bad times, reducing shareholder risk.
One concern about increasing equity capital requirements is that such an increase will lower
the returns to the bank’s investors. In particular, the argument is often made that higher equity
capital requirements will reduce the banks’ Return on Equity (ROE) to the detriment of their
shareholders. 15
15
Accounting ROE is defined as net income / book value of equity. A related financial measure is the earnings
yield, which is net income / market value of equity, or equivalently, the inverse of the bank’s P/E multiple. The
discussion in this section applies equally well to the earnings yield, replacing book values with market values
throughout.
11
This argument presumes that ROE is a good measure of a bank’s performance. Since ROE
(or any simple measure of the bank’s return) does not adjust for scale or risk, there are many
potential pitfalls associated with this presumption. Using ROE to assess performance is
especially problematic when comparisons are made across different capital structures. The focus
on ROE has therefore led to much confusion about the effects of capital requirements on
shareholder value.
25%
ROE
20% (Earnings Yield) Initial
10% Capital
15%
10% Recapitalization
to 20% Capital
5%
0%
3% 4% 5% 6% 7%
-5%
16
More precisely, ROE = (ROA×A – r×D)/E = ROA + (D/E)(ROA – r), where ROA is the return on assets, A is the
total value of the firm’s assets, E is equity, D is debt, and r is the (after-tax) interest rate on the debt.
17
If the bank had met the higher capital requirements by expanding its assets rather than recapitalizing (Case C in
Figure 1), the “break-even” ROE would be the after-tax return of the new assets acquired by the bank.
12
For a given capital structure, ROE does reflect the realized profitability of the bank’s
assets. But when comparing banks with different capital structures, ROE cannot be used
to compare their underlying profitability.18
Higher equity capital requirements will tend to lower the bank’s ROE only in good times
when ROE is high. They will raise the ROE in bad times when ROE is low. From an ex
ante perspective, the high ROE in good times that is induced by high leverage comes at
the cost of having a really low ROE in bad times.
On average, of course, banks hope to (and typically do) earn ROE well in excess of the return
on their debt. In that case, the “average” effect on ROE from higher equity capital requirements
would be negative. For example, if the bank expects to earn a 6% return on its assets, then it
would expect a 15% ROE on average with 10% capital, and only a 10% ROE on average with
20% capital. Is this effect a concern for shareholders?
The answer is no. Because the increase in capital provides downside protection that reduces
shareholders’ risk, shareholders will require a lower expected return to be willing to invest in a
better capitalized bank. This reduction in the required return for equity will offset the reduction
in the average ROE, leading to no net change in the value to shareholders (and thus the firm’s
share price). Indeed, in the above example, if the equity investors required a 15% expected return
initially, we would expect their required return to fall to 10% due to the reduction in risk with the
increase in the firm’s capital.19 Because shareholders continue to earn their required return, there
is no cost associated with the increase in equity capital.20
18
For example, a manager who generates a 7% ROA with 20% capital will have an ROE of 15%. Alternatively, a
less productive manager who generates a 6.5% ROA yet has 10% capital will have an ROE of 20%. Thus, when
capital structures differ, a higher ROE does not necessarily mean a firm has deployed its assets more productively.
19
To see why, note from Figure 2 that doubling the bank’s capital cuts the risk of the bank’s equity returns in half
(the same change in ROA leads to ½ the change in ROE). Thus, if shareholders initially required a 15% average
return, which corresponds to a 10% risk premium to hold equity versus safe debt, then with twice the capital,
because their sensitivity to the assets’ risk (and thus their “beta”) has been halved, they should demand ½ the risk
premium, or 5%, and hence a 10% required average return.
20
As we have seen, because of ROE’s failure to account for both risk and capital structure, it is not a useful measure
of a manager’s contribution to shareholder value. Most management experts prefer alternatives such as the firm’s
economic value added (EVA) or residual income. Residual income is defined as (ROE – rE)×E, where rE is the
firm’s risk-adjusted equity cost of capital, and E is the firm’s equity. Residual income thus adjusts both for the risk
and scale of the shareholders’ investment. Simple changes in capital structure will not alter the firm’s residual
income.
13
providing full protection against even extreme events. Unfortunately, the
suppliers of capital ask for high returns because their role, by definition, is to bear
the bulk of the risk from a bank’s loan book, investments and operations” Elliott
(2009, p. 12).
Statement: “Increased equity requirements increase the funding costs for banks because they
must use more equity, which has a higher required return.”
Assessment: This is false. Although equity has a higher required return, this does not imply that
increased equity capital requirements would raise the banks’ overall funding costs.
The example of the previous section exposes a more general fallacy regarding equity capital
requirements. Because the required expected rate of return on equity is higher than that on debt,
some argue that if the bank were required to use more of this “expensive” form of funding, its
overall cost of capital would increase.
This reasoning reflects a misunderstanding of the way in which risks affect the cost of
funding. While it is true that the required return on equity is higher than the required return on
debt and it is also true that this difference reflects the greater riskiness of equity relative to debt,
it is not true that by “economizing” on equity one can reduce capital costs. “Economizing” on
equity itself has an effect on the riskiness and, therefore, on the required expected return of
equity. This effect must be taken into account when assessing the implications of increased
equity capital requirements for banks’ cost of capital.
Figure 2 indicates that the random fluctuations in the bank’s ROE that are induced by a given
fluctuation in earnings are greater the less equity the bank has. When the bank has relatively
more equity capital, a given earnings risk translates into less risk for its shareholders. Reflecting
this reduction in risk, the risk premium in the expected ROE will be lower. If the additional
equity capital serves to reduce the bank’s bankruptcy risk, the interest rate on its debt will also be
lower. These reductions of risk premia in required rates of return counteract the direct effects of
shifting from debt finance to equity finance, from an instrument with a low required rate of
return to an instrument with a higher required rate of return. The net effect need not increase the
total funding costs of the bank at all. 21
One of the fundamental results of corporate finance (Modigliani and Miller, 1958) states that,
absent additional considerations such as those involving tax advantages or public subsidies to
debt, increases in amount of financing done through equity simply re-distributes the total risk
that must be borne by investors in the bank, i.e., the holders of debt and equity and any other
21
Continuing our earlier example (see fn. 11), given 10% equity capital the required return was 15% for equity and
5% for debt, for an average cost of 10%×15% + 90%×5% = 6%. With 20% equity capital the required return for
equity falls to 10% (with a 5% cost of debt), leading to the same average cost of 20%×10% + 80%×5% = 6%.
14
securities that the bank may issue. The total risk itself is given by the risks that are inherent in the
bank’s asset returns. In a market in which risk is priced correctly, an increase in the amount of
equity financing lowers the required return on equity in a way that, absent subsidies to bank debt
and other frictions, would leave the total funding costs of the bank the same.
In light of this result, the following critically important insights should be the starting point
of any discussion about capital requirements.22
If changes in a bank’s capital structure do affect the bank’s cost of funding, it must be
because of some frictions or distortions involved in issuing various securities, not simple
risk changes. It is important to understand what these frictions and distortions are when
considering the effects of changes in capital requirements.
The Modigliani-Miller analysis is often dismissed on the grounds that it does not apply to
banks, which get much of their funding in the form of deposits, and, moreover, the assumptions
underlying this analysis are said to be highly restrictive. Given that depositors get some of their
returns through the convenience of transactions services, there is some truth to the notion that
deposits are different. This observation does not, however, mean that banks are altogether
different. The erosion of the equity of major banking institutions over the past two decades has
not been a result of increased deposit finance of these institutions. It has, rather, been the result
of tremendous growth in wholesale market finance (much, in particular, in the form of short-term
repo borrowing; see Adrian and Shin (2010)). There is no reason for presuming that this form of
borrowing in wholesale markets is exempt from the logic articulated above.
22
Extensive discussions of this result and various proofs can be found in any basic corporate finance textbook. See,
for example, Allen, Brealey and Myers (2008), Berk and DeMarzo (2008), and Ross, Westerfield and Jaffe (2008).
23
See, for example, Hanson, Kashyap, and Stein (2010).
15
The assumptions underlying the Modigliani-Miller analysis are in fact the very same
assumptions underlying the quantitative models that banks use to manage their risks, in
particular, the risks in their trading books. Anyone who questions the empirical validity and
relevance of an analysis that is based on these assumptions is implicitly questioning the
reliability of these quantitative models and their adequacy for the uses to which they are put –
including that of determining required capital under the model-based approach for market risks.
If we cannot count on markets to correctly price risk and adjust for even the most basic
consequences of changes in leverage, then the discussion of capital regulation should be far more
encompassing than the current debate.
In practice, changing the capital structure of a bank (or any firm) does more than shift how
risk is distributed among those who fund its operations. For example, alterations in a bank’s
capital structure can change how much the bank pays in taxes and can influence how investment
and other decisions are made by bank managers. In this and the following sections we address
the potential costs and benefits of equity capital requirements when various distortions and
frictions are taken into account.
In this section we address distortions and frictions that involve the interaction between banks
and the government. There are two important ways in which government policy affects the
investment and financing decisions of banks. The first involves taxes, mentioned above, and is
common to banks and other corporations. In most countries where corporations must pay
corporate taxes, interest payments on debt are considered a tax deductible expense. This gives
debt financing an advantage over equity financing, because the more debt a profitable firm has,
the lower its tax bill, other things being equal.
The second important feature of the interactions of banks and governments involves debt
guarantees that the government may provide – in particular to banks that are deemed too
important to fail. When investors believe that the government might step in to bail out banks in
times of distress, banks can borrow at a lower rate than they would absent the possibility of a
bailout. Unless the bank is forced to pay the government a fair insurance premium upfront, the
government guarantee works like a subsidy that results in lower funding costs when debt, not
equity, is used to finance a bank’s operation.24
24
Explicit guarantees such as through FDIC insurance, are different in that banks are supposedly charged for them
upfront. Such insurance is only provided to deposits that are considered socially valuable and where the threat of
inefficient runs is great. See further discussion of this at the end of Section 4.2
16
As a result of both tax and implicit guarantees (for which they are not charged upfront),
banks find debt a very attractive form of financing. It is therefore not surprising that bankers
argue that equity capital requirements will increase their funding costs, since indeed more equity
will reduce their ability to benefit from these subsidies. However, we argue below that this is not
a legitimate reason for regulators to refrain from increasing capital requirements. In fact, it is
quite paradoxical that the government subsidizes the leverage of the banks at the same time that
it recognizes that this leverage is socially very costly and considers imposing stricter capital
requirements to prevent the banks from taking advantage of this subsidy. If there are specific
frictions that banks encounter in their activities and which prevent them from lending at a
socially optimal level, the government might wish to resolve such frictions using subsidies.
However, policies that encourage leverage should be avoided.
4.1 Taxes
“In the real world of tax biases in favor of debt… there clearly is a private cost
penalty to higher equity requirements, and the case that tighter [capital]
requirements increase the cost of long-term credit provision appears fairly clear.”
Turner (2010, p. 25)
Statement: “Increased equity requirements increase the funding costs for banks because they
reduce the ability of banks to benefit from the tax shield associated with interest payments on
debt.”
Assessment: If debt has a tax advantage over equity, this is true. However, it is irrelevant to
capital regulation in the sense that both capital regulation and taxes are matters of public policy.
The current tax code creates distortions by subsidizing leverage. These distortions can be
eliminated, while preserving the same level of bank tax shields, at the discretion of the
government. This would neutralize the tax impact of increased equity requirements.
Since, as discussed above, tax shields effectively subsidize debt financing, requiring banks to
use less debt financing can raise banks’ cost of capital.25 From a public-policy perspective,
however, this effect is irrelevant as it concerns only the distribution of public money. The tax
savings that a bank obtains by relying on debt rather than equity finance reduce the government’s
tax revenue and require either a reduction in spending on public goods or an increase in taxes
elsewhere. While the bank gains from the debt tax shield, the public loses, and ultimately, the
argument concerns the optimal structure of taxation. Taxes should be structured to minimize the
25
Note, however, this effect is mitigated if dividends or capital gains on shares are taxed at a lower rate than interest
income at the level of personal income taxation. Whether debt actually has a tax advantage depends on whether the
sum of corporate and investor-level taxes on equity income exceeds or falls short of interest income taxes at the
personal level.
17
overall distortions they induce. In addition, taxes (and subsidies) should be set so as to encourage
behavior that generates positive externalities and to discourage behavior that generates negative
externalities.
By these criteria, refraining from requiring banks to have more equity capital on the grounds
that this would raise their taxes makes no sense. If the prospect of saving on corporate income
taxes induces banks to be highly leveraged, this generates a negative externality because the
increase in leverage raises the probability of a bank failure, weakening the financial system and
raising the possibility of taxpayer bailouts. Given these externalities associated with high
leverage of financial institutions, tax policy should not encourage leverage. If anything, tax
policy should be designed to make banks internalize the social costs imposed by high leverage.
Even abstracting from the external effects of default, a tax subsidy to debt finance induces a
distortion in the allocation of funds between corporations that can borrow extensively and
corporations that use more equity finance. Banks that can be highly leveraged because of implicit
government guarantees enjoy an additional advantage over other firms, because high leverage
allows them to capture a greater tax subsidy. While some of this advantage may be passed on to
the firms to which banks provide loans, there is no reason to believe that this suffices to
neutralize the distortion.
Whether the tax code should be changed with respect to corporate taxation more broadly or
whether the distortions should be corrected at the level of the banking industry, , the current
situation is clearly undesirable.
Some considerations of optimal tax theory actually suggest that corporate income should not
be taxed (at least in expectation). In that sense the current tax code can be thought of as
penalizing equity rather than subsidizing debt. (See Mankiw, Weinzierl, and Yagan (2010), as
well as Boskin (2010)). Poole (2009) estimates that reducing the corporate tax rate to 15% and
not allowing financial institutions to deduct interest would result in the same total corporate tax
expense as was actually incurred by these institutions.
More generally, even without fundamentally changing the tax code, it is quite straightforward
to neutralize the impact of increased equity capital requirements on the tax liabilities of banks.
Any tax subsidies lost due to a reduction in leverage can be easily replaced with alternative
deductions or tax credits. For example, the subsidy to small-business lending that may be seen as
being implicit in the tax advantage of banks could be replaced by a tax subsidy at the level of the
small businesses themselves, where the subsidy would be much better targeted and therefore
much more effective.
18
4.2 Bailouts and Implicit Government Guarantees
Statement: “Increased equity requirements increase the funding costs for banks because they
prevent banks from being able to borrow at the low rates implied by the presence of government
guarantees.”
Assessment: This is again a statement about private and not social costs. Government guarantees
that allow banks to enjoy cheap debt financing create numerous distortions and encourage
excessive leverage and excessive risk taking. Because of the distorted incentives as well as the
difficulty for governments to commit never to bail out banks, it is challenging to neutralize this
effect by charging banks for the true cost of the guarantees on an ongoing basis. Equity cushions
are particularly valuable, since they reduce the likelihood and cost of the guarantees.
Explicit or implicit government guarantees immunize the banks’ creditors against the
consequences of a default by the bank. As a result, the default risk premium in the interest rates
demanded by the bank’s creditors is lower and may even be zero. Institutions that benefit from
such guarantees, e.g., institutions that are deemed to be “too big to fail,” are therefore able to
borrow at lower interest rates. The savings in capital costs that are thereby achieved are the
larger the more leverage the bank has.
From a public policy perspective, this effect of increased equity requirements is not relevant
because, similar to the case of the tax advantage of debt, it concerns private, rather than social
costs of bank capital. The lower borrowing rates benefiting banks and their shareholders have a
counterpart in the default risks borne by the taxpayer. Any consideration of social costs must
encompass the costs of these risks to taxpayers. Once this is taken into account, one sees that the
effects of government guarantees on borrowing rates provide no reason to refrain from requiring
banks to have more capital. By the same argument as before, if lower borrowing rates based on
government guarantees induce banks to be highly leveraged, this imposes a negative externality
on the rest of the economy because the increase in leverage raises the probability of distress and
the resulting systemic risk.
The negative externalities here are likely to be even larger than with those associated with the
tax benefits of debt finance. The tax benefits of debt finance are largest when the bank does well
and makes profits. The subsidy from government guarantees is worth most when the bank does
poorly and is unable to service its debt. From an ex ante perspective, this makes it attractive for
the bank to engage in strategies that involve a positive default risk. Of course, some default risk
may be unavoidable, but to the extent that there is a choice, the availability of explicit or implicit
government guarantees of bank debt creates a bias towards choosing risky strategies to exploit
the guarantees, providing shareholders with nice returns if they succeed and saddling the
government with the losses if they fail.
19
As is well known, such a bias towards choosing an excessively risky strategy is present even
without government guarantees. The mere existence of debt, with a payment obligation that is
independent of the bank’s asset returns, creates incentives for the bank’s shareholders, or for its
managers acting on the shareholders’ behalf, to take risks according to the principle “heads, I
win, tails, the creditor loses.” Under these strategies, increases in default probabilities or default
returns, which hurt the creditors, are traded for increases in returns in the event where everything
goes well, which benefit shareholders. From the perspective of the debt holders, this is a moral
hazard problem, i.e., it is a hazard that is not due to natural perils outside of the participants’
sphere of influence , but due instead to the behavior of the banks and the bank’s managers who
control the use of the funds.
In the absence of any government guarantees, the bank’s creditors would try to limit such
moral hazard. If it were possible to write contracts so that the bank’s strategy choices are fully
committed ex ante, the parties would mutually agree to put such covenants into their contracts. If
such commitments are ineffective, the creditors will ask for higher rates or even refuse to provide
the bank with funds altogether. In all of those cases in which effective covenants cannot be
written, the moral hazard will prevent the partners from choosing a fully efficient arrangement,
but, given the constraints imposed by the bank’s inability to fully commit its strategy ex ante, the
arrangement they come up with may be presumed to be second best.
Explicit or implicit government guarantees can greatly reduce the need for the creditors to
worry about their bank’s strategy choices and default prospects. If the government can be
expected to step in when the bank defaults, the creditor generally has no reason to refrain from
lending to the bank or to demand a significant default risk premium. The resulting arrangement
may be far from even second best.
Politicians are fond of saying that we must make sure bailouts never happen. In fact, it is
extremely difficult, if not impossible, to commit never to bail out a financial institution. Indeed, it
may not even be desirable to make such a commitment, since a bailout might be the preferred
course of action during a crisis. For this reason the focus must be on structuring financial
regulations to minimize or ideally eliminate the possibility that institutions will need to be bailed
out. Some recent proposals for financial regulation involve the creation of a “resolution
authority” that will have funds ready to help banks and other financial institutions in situations of
financial distress. If the government charged a fee (a form of “bank tax”) for the protection it is
giving through this mechanism, and if this fee always reflected the true cost of the guarantees,
then the subsidy associated with implicit guarantees would be removed. However, adapting the
fee to the risks that are actually taken would be challenging. More importantly, if it is difficult to
monitor risks, then individual banks would have incentives to take on additional risks. This
20
approach is not as effective as requiring significant increases in equity requirements. Equity, as a
form of self insurance, will be priced based on its risk directly by financial markets.26
It should be pointed out that systems providing “safety nets” to banks that are based on
deposit insurance, the Fed’s discount window, and central banks serving as a “lender of last
resort” can and do play a very positive role as a stabilizing force, particularly in preventing bank
runs that have plagued banks in prior years. We are not arguing that these should be removed.
Rather, we are observing that larger equity cushions are an effective way to increase the safety of
the system and make it less reliant on implicit “too-big-to-fail” guarantees that are both costly
and provide distorted incentives. Indeed, the entire system of capital regulation is the result of
the recognition that incentives to take excessive risk arise as a result of demand deposit and other
elements of the safety net of banks.
The distortions and frictions discussed in the previous section are the result of government
policies that provide subsidies to banks by lowering their cost of debt financing. These
distortions and frictions unambiguously encourage banks to take on high leverage that is socially
costly. The clear implication is that these distortions and frictions should be removed or
neutralized through changes in public policy. In this section, by contrast, we focus on frictions
that are inherent to the environment in which banks operate and are therefore largely
unavoidable. These frictions arise because different participants, including bank managers,
various creditors, and equity holders, are likely to have different information, preferences, and
control over the banks’ investment and financing decisions, and because it is difficult or costly
for the various participants to write complete contracts or make credible commitments to actions
that will be taken in the future.
Over the last 40 years, a large literature in finance and economics has studied these types of
frictions. The parts of this literature that are most relevant to the debate on bank capital
regulation are those having to do with financial contracting and the role that different types of
securities play in either reducing or increasing these frictions. In this section we consider claims
that debt has a positive role to play in alleviating informational and governance frictions, and that
for this reason it might be costly to increase equity capital requirements.
In Section 5.1 we consider the claim that debt imposes discipline on bank managers and thus
alleviates information and governance problems. We consider this claim to be unconvincing.
First, this claim neglects the very significant frictions and governance problems that debt and
26
Deposit insurance is, of course, a system that collects insurance fees and explicitly insures deposits. Extending
this system to additional deposits can be considered and might make sense. However, this should only be
appropriate for the type of deposits that create an important social benefit and not to all bank debt. In any event, this
should not be viewed as an alternative to significant increases in capital requirements.
21
leverage actually create. These include, among other things, problems created by incentives to
take excessive risk and the funding problems associated with “debt overhang,” problems that
quite often lead to inefficient investment decisions. Second, the notion that debt provides
discipline to managers simply does not fit the facts of the last decade.
In Section 5.2 we discuss the claim that information asymmetries between investors and
managers might make it difficult or costly for banks to issue new equity. While acknowledging
the validity of this claim, we argue that such concerns are in fact alleviated if banks have more
equity to begin with. We also discuss how the transition to higher equity ratios might be handled
by regulators.
Finally, in Section 5.3 we address the notion that observed financing patterns should be
regarded as optimal private-sector responses to whatever frictions there are, i.e., that, because we
observe banks to be highly leveraged, it follows that this high leverage is privately and perhaps
even socially desirable. We point out that, even from a private perspective, contracting can only
be optimal relative to the given constraints and, in particular, the given commitment possibilities.
Because existing leverage generates incentives to issue additional debt, the high leverage that we
observe is at least partly due to the banks’ inability to commit themselves to a leverage bound ex
ante. In this situation, statutory equity requirements might provide a substitute for the missing
ability to commit and in doing so may improve on private contracting even from the participants’
perspective.
Statement: “Debt, as a hard claim that must be periodically renewed, is necessary to provide
market discipline that enhances corporate governance and prevents bank managers from taking
excessive risk or mismanaging the firm.”
Assessment: While correct in some specialized theoretical models, this statement is false
because the models on which it is based are inadequate for the purpose of the discussion of
capital regulation. Debt finance actually generates and exacerbates governance and agency
problems, and these problems can be quite severe. Moreover, the mechanisms that allow debt to
deliver discipline do not actually work well for large financial institutions, and/or they are
extremely costly as they depend on fragility and default. Debt is also not unique it its ability to
provide discipline; alternative mechanisms exist that allow equity capital to be increased without
22
sacrificing the potential governance benefits of debt. Finally, discipline by debt holders did not
appear to be effective in the events leading up to the financial crisis of 2007-2008.
A central problem of corporate governance is to ensure that the outside financiers of firms
(including banks) can expect to get appropriate returns. This problem is difficult because
management has control over the company’s activities and has better information over what is
going on. With a bank, the difficulty is compounded by the fact that certain assets, e.g., loans to
small businesses, are particularly opaque and difficult to assess from the outside. Other assets
may be much easier to assess because they can be traded in liquid markets, but then, this very
tradability provides managers with the scope for reshuffling the bank’s positions quickly, to their
own personal advantage and, possibly, outside investors’ disadvantage.27
For non-financial firms, the most important governance concern seems to be about
management wasting resources for their own private benefits or for empire-building. For
financial firms, concerns about theft and concerns about risk management play a much bigger
role. Given the ease with which financial assets can be moved around, theft is a major problem
unless there is suitable surveillance ensuring that assets are not diverted; the Madoff case has just
been the latest example. Surveillance prohibiting theft, however, might be easier than
surveillance concerning excessive risk taking. Given the difficulty of assessing risk (even ex
post), the ability to amplify risk via leverage, and the ease with which risk can be transformed
through trading activities, it is crucial that managerial incentives be properly set.
The problem of excessive risk taking is compounded by the fact that it may be supported by
shareholders. Equity holders have no interest in disciplining it and might even be complicit in
undermining mechanisms to do so.28 As already mentioned in Section 4.2, the presence of debt
creates incentives for management, acting on behalf of shareholders, to engage in strategies that
yield high returns when successful and negative returns when unsuccessful, increasing the
likelihood and the extent of distress and insolvency.29 Given the fixity of their claims, debt
holders do not participate in the high returns in the event of success, but are burdened with the
increased risk and increased cost of default (or, to the extent they are bailed out by the
government, the burden will be shared with taxpayers). In contrast, shareholders benefit from the
27
Opaqueness as a natural by-product of the bank’s own activities in monitoring its loan clients is discussed in
Diamond (1984), while the “paradox” of asset liquidity as enhancing transparency while expanding the scope for
manipulations by bank management is the subject of Myers and Rajan (1998). More generally, models where debt
contracts emerge as optimal are more appropriate for describing why the banks themselves structure their financing
the businesses they loan to in the form of debt contracts. (Such models are sometimes called “costly state
verification” models.) As we argue, these models do not imply that debt or high leverage are optimal as the way to
finance the banks themselves, particularly in the context where such leverage produces systemic risk.
28
Bolton, Mehran and Shapiro (2010) develop a model that includes shareholders, debtholders, depositors and an
executive in which this problem can be seen. They propose debt-like compensation schemes that might be helpful.
29
Bhagat and Bolton (2010), and Bebchuk, Cohen and Spamann (2010) show that incentives created by executive
compensation led to excessive risk-taking by banks in the years leading to the financial crisis. Bebchuk and
Spamann (2010) propose regulating bankers’ pay in light of this problem.
23
high returns in the event of success but do not suffer from the increase in insolvency costs, since
their liability is limited. The same is true of managers who are compensated based on equity
holder returns. The phrase “heads, I win, tails, the creditor or the taxpayer loses” captures the
essence of a problem that has led to many banking crises of the past.30
With non-financial firms, the governance problem of excessive risk-taking is not so severe.
First, because overall leverage is much lower, incentives to engage in excessive risk taking are
generally much weaker. Second, debt holders impose restrictive covenants, monitor these
covenants and intervene if the covenants are broken. Quite often, these debt holders are financial
institutions with significant holdings so that there is no question about their incentives (and
ability) to engage in the requisite monitoring activities.
With banks, matters are different. First, their leverage is much higher. Second, their debt
holders tend to be more dispersed so that the public-good aspects of management discipline
generated by monitoring are more important. Third, depositors who are insured do not have an
incentive to spend resources on monitoring anyway. These features of bank finance reflect the
fact that bank deposits provide an important “money like” transactions function in the economy,
with many small depositors caring about the convenience of having funds available for
transactions and being unable or unwilling to engage in effective monitoring. Fourth, bank
creditors whose claims are implicitly guaranteed by the government, e.g. creditors in “too-big-to-
fail” institutions, also have reduced incentives to monitor.
The literature on corporate finance and corporate governance and the literature on banking
have extensively studied the impact of different means of financing on these governance
problems. These literatures have identified potential governance benefits associated with debt
financing, and some people cite these benefits when arguing against significant increases in
equity requirements.
In this section, we discuss the main arguments regarding the disciplining role of debt in the
context of banking. We distinguish two main lines of arguments:
(i) that the hardness of the claim held by debtors imposes discipline on management and
prevents waste;
30
On excessive risk taking, see Jensen and Meckling (1976), Stiglitz and Weiss (1981); in the context of banking,
disastrous examples are provided by the German banking crisis of 1931 (Born 1967, Schnabel 2004, 2009) and the
American Savings and Loans Crisis of the eighties (Dewatripont and Tirole 1994, Kane 1989, and White 1991). In
the latter crisis, the deregulation of the early eighties permitted gambling for resurrection by institutions that would
have been declared insolvent if fair value accounting had been properly applied. Haldane, Brennan, and Madouros
(2010) argue that observed increases in ROE are not necessarily a measure of increased value brought about by
banks, but are more likely the result of risk taking strategies by banks. This is consistent with the suggestion that
“risk shifting” is a significant problem in highly leveraged financial institutions.
24
(ii) that, with debt finance, the threat of non-renewal of funds eliminates moral hazard,
including management taking excessive risks.
In each case, we find the argument that debt is capable of providing governance benefits, let
alone uniquely capable of doing so, suspect. Too little attention is paid to the fact that debt
finance generates substantial governance problems of its own and that the problem of excessive
risk taking or “risk-shifting” is more serious the more highly leveraged the institution is. Too
little attention is also paid to the fact that the presumed benefits can also be provided by other
devices when equity capital levels are increased. Finally, we note that the experience of the
recent financial crisis does not support the case that debt provides effective discipline for banks.
“Capital requirements are not free. The disciplining effect of short-term debt, for
example, makes management more productive. Capital requirements that lean
against short-term debt push banks toward other forms of financing that may
allow managers to be more lax.” (Squam Lake Report (French et al. 2010, p. 44).)
From a corporate governance perspective, debt holders have the advantage that their claims
are fully specified in advance. Thus, as long as the bank is able to satisfy these claims, what debt
holders are paid is independent of how the bank is doing in its business, so that debt is
informationally undemanding. When the bank is doing well, debt holders need not worry much
how the bank’s management behaves or whether the management’s business reports are to be
trusted. By contrast, outside shareholders have many reasons to worry. For example, they must
worry whether management might be diverting funds to its own personal benefits, e.g., by
spending excessive amounts on golf tournaments and corporate jets as occurred at RJR Nabisco.
This so-called “free cash flow” problem can be particularly severe in mature companies whose
managers may find too few profitable investment opportunities in their own area of expertise and
therefore look to diversify into other areas.31
31
On debt as a device to mitigate diversion of company resources for the private benefits of management, see Jensen
and Meckling (1976) and Hellwig (2009a). The notion that debt is informationally undemanding is discussed by
Townsend (1979), Diamond (1984), Gale and Hellwig (1985), Gorton and Pennacchi (1990), and Dang, Gorton, and
Holmström (2010). Debt as a solution to the free-cash-flow problem is discussed by Jensen (1986, 1989, and 1993).
25
These considerations seem to support the notion that, because debt is a hard claim, the
governance problems associated with debt finance might be less serious and less costly than the
governance problems associated with equity in reducing monitoring costs and making sure
managers operate the firm as efficiently as possible. However, the conditioning statement “as
long as the bank is able to satisfy these claims” in the preceding paragraph hides the fact that
debt finance in fact generates and exacerbates frictions and governance problems that are
potentially even more serious and harder to alleviate than the governance problems that might be
associated with equity finance. Because of the limited liability of equity, debt gives rise to
potential default and insolvency. If default is likely or, worse, if default has already occurred, the
suggestion that debt is informationally not very demanding is clearly false. In such an event,
sorting out the borrower’s assets and determining what the lenders get is quite costly and may
require very large amounts of resources.32 Also, and most importantly, as already mentioned in
Section 4.2 and in the introduction to this section, the presence of debt creates incentives for
excessive risk-taking. The problem of excessive risk-taking is the more pronounced the more
highly leveraged the firm is. It is particularly serious for banks with their extraordinarily high
leverage.
The assessment that debt is valuable because it imposes discipline must therefore be viewed
in proper context. Whereas the Squam Lake Report points to potential positive incentive effects
of debt finance, it ignores the potential negative incentive effects. A proper analysis must
consider the tradeoff between them. Along these lines we observe that non-financial firms, faced
with the same tradeoff, routinely choose substantially lower levels of leverage than financial
firms, yet we know of no evidence that they are more poorly governed.33
We also question whether the so-called “free cash flow” problem, which focuses on
management’s ability to withhold cash from shareholders and engage in wasteful investment, is
the primary governance problem to which banks are exposed. In fact, the governance problem
that is often alluded to when discussing financial firms in the popular press is not one that debt
may solve. Rather, it is the problem of excessive risk taking, which is exacerbated with leverage.
Finally, it is not clear why debt is or should be uniquely capable of providing managerial
oversight for financial institutions. Fundamentally, managerial incentives are driven by
compensation and retention schemes. Capital structure appears to be a rather crude instrument to
provide such incentives, and one fraught with socially costly indirect consequences. If
managerial oversight is the main motive for high bank leverage, then we would argue that policy
makers should focus attention on supporting improved or alternative governance mechanisms,
rather than continue to rely on the use of socially-costly high levels of leverage.
32
Beyond direct costs, there are generally significant indirect costs of financial distress and bankruptcy due to
operational disruptions, as well as significant social costs imposed upon outside parties.
33
On average, U.S. non-financial firms have maintained more than 50% equity historically.
26
As an example of one possible mechanism, consider the proposal of an Equity Liability
Carrier (ELC) for financial institutions, introduced by Admati and Pfleiderer (2010). The
structure is illustrated in Figure 3.
Equity
FI Equity
Risky Liabilities ELC
Assets Other Equity Investors
(with
Assets
recourse to
ELC)
ELC
Under the ELC, existing bank equity, along with additional equity capital associated with
increased requirements, are held in a separate holding company with governance that is
independent of the bank itself. While the bank’s creditors have recourse to the ELC assets, bank
managers do not.34 In this way, bank managers continue to operate under the “discipline” of high
leverage, but the ultimate costs of a default are largely absorbed by the ELC. As owners of the
bank’s equity, the ELC board and its shareholders have a vested interest monitoring and ensuring
the bank is efficiently managed (and given their exposure to the bank’s liabilities, they will guard
against risk-shifting as well). As explained in Section 6 below, there is no reason that such a
structure, or for that matter additional equity held directly by banks, would have a meaningful
impact on the portfolio holdings of final investors.
Other mechanisms are surely possible. Rather than rely on mandatory interest and principal
payments to provide discipline, well-capitalized banks could, for example, commit to a level of
equity payouts, which, if not maintained, would trigger a shareholder vote to replace incumbent
management. Such a mechanism would seem to provide virtually equivalent discipline without
the costs of leverage, unless the commitment mechanism could be easily undermined by
management.35 In that case, government policy could and should be directed toward
34
Note that the equity of the financial institution is not held publically. Instead it is held by the ELC. The ELC is
100% financed by equity that is publically held by investors.
35
It is important to recognize that none of the existing literature considers such mechanisms. Indeed, any effective
governance by equity holders is generally ruled out ex ante, with the objective of establishing the potential role of
27
strengthening corporate governance practices to allow for such commitment, rather than continue
to allow high leverage.
“The key to the market-discipline approach is placing private parties at risk with
respect to undesirable behavior by banks. The mechanism for doing so is
subordinated debt… Requiring banks to maintain minimum ratios of subordinated
debt relative to insured debt … imposes market discipline on banks, and thus
limits banks’ incentives to take on risk. Bankers that take on excessive risk, or
who manage assets poorly, will find it difficult to sell their subordinated debts,
and will be forced to shrink their risky assets or to issue new capital to satisfy the
discipline of private uninsured debt holders.” (Calomiris (1999).)
Beyond being a hard claim, the potential disciplining effect of debt is claimed to be enhanced
whenever debt contracts, even long-term debt, must be repeatedly renewed. The presumption is
that, in fear for their money, creditors will monitor the activities of their bank and, if they see
something that they don’t like, they will refuse to renew their loans. It is further assumed that
management will refrain from doing anything that might annoy the creditors in order to avoid the
difficulties created by a failure to have the bank’s loans rolled over. Calomiris and Kahn (1991),
for example, have argued that the “on demand” clause in certain deposit contracts serves to
impose such discipline on bank management.36 Because depositors whose deposits are insured,
have no incentives to engage in the requisite monitoring, Calomiris (1999) has suggested that
banks should issue additional debt – subordinate to any deposits and crucially, uninsured– to
fulfill the disciplining role that depositors fail to supply (see Calomiris (1999)). Similarly, Poole
(2010) suggests that discipline can be delivered by staggered tranches of junior, long-term debt
that must be renewed, e.g. ten-year debt with 10% coming due each year.
debt in providing discipline. That debt uniquely satisfies this role is a much stronger statement, and one that to our
knowledge is completely unsupported.
36
See also Diamond and Rajan (2001), where demandable debt, with the threat of a run, serves to make the banker
tougher in his negotiations with the bank’s own borrowers.
28
Whereas our preceding discussion has pointed to the fact that high leverage itself provides
incentives for excessive risk taking, Calomiris (in the quote given above) suggests that even this
moral hazard is eliminated by debt holders engaging in monitoring so as to penalize the bank if it
takes on too many risks. Calomiris and Poole both suggest that the shrinkage of the balance sheet
that would result from long term debt refusing to renew the debt is a better disciplinary device
than regulators can otherwise achieve.37 Note that even if one concludes that subordinated debt
has some useful role to play, additional equity can still be added to the balance sheet, essentially
placing it on top of the “useful” subordinated debt and other liabilities. This will reduce risk and
the incentives for risk-shifting, all without reducing the disciplining function the subordinated
debt might play.
At this point, however, any theory of the disciplining role of short-term (or renewable) debt
must come to terms with the observation that, in the years leading up to the financial crisis of
2007-2008, there was a large expansion of short-term debt of banks. This debt finance, much of
it in the form of repo contracts, was provided and repeatedly rolled over without any indication
of debt holders exerting discipline. As documented by Adrian and Shin (2010), leverage at
leading investment banks reached a peak towards the end of 2007, long after the crisis had
broken into the open. By this time asset holdings from subprime mortgage securitization were
firmly in place (i.e., the proverbial skeletons were already in the closets).
In the crisis, this short-term debt finance broke down. Short-term funding was withdrawn
from conduits and structured investment vehicles in August 2007, from Bear Stearns in March
2008, and from Lehman Brothers in September 2008. These reactions did have serious
consequences for the affected banks. However, given the unchecked buildup of positions prior to
July 2007, it is difficult to think of these events as an instance of effective discipline of short-
term lenders over bank managers. Indeed, the breakdowns of short-term funding appeared to be
driven by public information rather than information acquired by the monitoring carried out by
short term lenders. The August 2007 breakdown of conduit refinancing through asset-backed
commercial paper was triggered by the substantial downgrades of Mortgage Backed Securities
(MBS) and Collateralized Debt Obligations (CDOs) by the rating agencies, and by the
insolvencies of two Bear Stearns Hedge Funds. The breakdowns of repo refinancing for Bear
Stearns and Lehman Brothers were triggered by asset price declines, in particular, in these
institutions’ share prices. None of these instances suggests that debt holder monitoring played an
effective disciplining role of its own.
In addition to recent history, there are conceptual reasons to doubt the effectiveness of “debt
renewal” as an optimal disciplining mechanism. Absent insolvency or market failure, debt can
37
For a recent model that attempts to model the tradeoffs associated with the disciplinary role of rolling over debt,
see Cheng and Milbradt (2010). In this model equity and the manager are not distinguished, and only the maturity
structure of the debt is considered; the more fundamental question of optimal leverage is not addressed.
29
always be renewed at a sufficient yield. In that case, the only potential disciplining effect can
come from the information that is provided when the debt is repriced. Any actual discipline for
managers must still come through shareholders. And while there is potentially valuable
information to be learned from the occasional repricing of the firm’s debt, it is important to recall
that the firm’s equity is repriced on a daily or hourly basis, and generally provides even more
information regarding the performance of the firm.38 Because debt is informationally less
demanding than equity, as long as debt holders believe that the bank is going to fulfill its
obligations, they don’t care how the bank is doing; in contrast, shareholders always care about
the extra million dollars that the bank may be earning or losing. For this reason, monitoring
incentives for shareholders with respect to the problem of waste and “free cash flows” are much
stronger than for debt holders.39 Moreover, debt holders may forego their own monitoring if they
believe that they are protected by marketable collateral or government guarantees, or if they
believe that stock prices provide enough of a clue as to where the bank is going.
Thus, debt only directly provides true discipline in the extreme scenario in which refinancing
the debt is infeasible due to clear insolvency, or sufficient uncertainty regarding insolvency to
induce market failure – a run on the bank. In this regard short-term debt finance also has a
significant cost. The presumed disciplinary mechanism relies on uncoordinated behaviors,
introducing an element of fragility into the system so that there is a positive probability of
distress and inefficient destruction of asset values. Each lender’s interest to be first in line if
things go wrong may lead to a run taking place simply because each participant fears that the
other participants are running. If the bank’s assets are illiquid, such a run may result in an
inefficient liquidation. The intervention of the short-term debt holders may thus impose large
costs on the bank. As recent experience has shown, especially that related to the Lehman
bankruptcy, there may be even larger costs for the rest of the financial system and the overall
economy.
In the literature on the disciplinary role of short-term debt finance, the problem of fragility
has been downplayed, even as the suggested mechanisms rely on fragility to deliver the
discipline. The suggestion that short-term lenders may start a run merely because they expect
others to do so, as in Diamond and Dybvig (1983), has been countered with the observation that,
empirically, runs and other breakdowns of short-term refinancing are triggered by adverse
information and should therefore be interpreted as a way of processing that information, possibly
even one that is efficient.40 In this view, fragility may be an unavoidable consequence of the fact
38
It might be objected that share price levels do not provide direct information about the riskiness of the bank’s
assets, an item of concern for regulators and creditors, especially uninsured creditors. It should be noted, however,
that the volatility of stock prices gives information about the riskiness of the assets. In addition, option markets exist
for the publically traded equity of most large banks and option pricing reveals the market assessment of risk levels.
39
Indeed, discipline from shareholders plays a potentially strong role when management incentives are linked to
shareholder value; see Holmström and Tirole (1993).
40
For theoretical analyses, see Chari and Jagannathan (1987) and Jacklin and Bhattacharya (1988). For an empirical
assessment, see Calomiris and Gorton (1991).
30
that the debt holders’ information is noisy. In other words, the possibility that a breakdown of
short-term refinancing of a bank may be the result of self-fulfilling prophesies in the strategic
interaction between different debt holders is not eliminated when the debt holders’ behaviors are
driven by their information.41 Thus, we cannot accept the view that the mechanism of market
discipline by short-term debt holders is at all efficient. 42
It is important to observe that fragility is essential for the disciplining mechanism that short-
term debt is presumed to provide.43 However, because of the potential inefficiencies involved in
fragility, regulators often seek to avoid the socially costly consequences of fragility through
bailouts or other subsidies. But while bailouts may be justified ex post, knowing that they are
probable ex ante works to undermine any discipline the leverage was intended to provide.
Finally, it should be observed that virtually all proposals in the capital regulation share the
objective of reducing fragility, thereby in fact undermining any capability, should it exist, for
fragility to impose discipline.
In sum, we do not find any strong theoretical or empirical justification for the proposition
that high leverage plays a necessary, significant positive role in the governance of large financial
institutions. Given that the disciplinary benefits are not apparent, are likely to be small, and
potentially can be achieved in other ways, and given the large social costs of highly leveraged
and fragile banks, the disciplining argument is in our view not a reason for regulators to avoid
imposing high equity capital requirements. Indeed, as we noted in Section 3.1 (and as will be
discussed in further detail in Section 7), additional equity can be added to banks’ capital structure
on top of existing deposits and any “useful” subordinated debt. Doing so will further reduce
incentives for risk-shifting without sacrificing any disciplining function of such debt.
“[F]ully two thirds of the CFOs (Chief Financial Officers) said that they were
reluctant to issue common equity when they thought that it was undervalued….
Taken together, these findings suggest that a large percentage of companies are
41
For example, the model with multiple debt holders in Calomiris and Kahn (1991) exhibits multiple equilibria, an
equilibrium with all depositors running even though information is good, as well as an equilibrium with no
depositors running. In some models in which monitoring provides debt holders with private information, the
equilibrium is unique, but may be excessively sensitive to the information that is available. However, in the presence
of a public signal, such as the bank’s stock price, equilibrium in these models may not even be unique, i.e., fragility
due to multiple self-fulfilling prophesies may be an issue. See Morris and Shin (1998), Rochet and Vives (2004),
Goldstein and Pauzner (2004), C. Hellwig (2002) and Angeletos and Werning (2006).
42
In Rochet and Vives (2004), individual information is noisy and aggregate information is not, but the withdrawal
mechanism is ill suited to provide for an efficient use of the aggregate information.
43
Fragility is essential to solve the information acquisition free-rider problem among debt holders, because it
provides an incentive to collect information so that they can be first in line when things go wrong, benefitting at the
expense of debt holders who are later in line. The lack of co-ordination among creditors that raises the possibility of
a run is thus an integral part of the mechanism.
31
hesitant to issue equity because they feel their stock is undervalued.” (Graham
and Harvey (2002, p.16-17).)
Assessment: This is not a valid reason to allow banks to have high leverage; better capitalized
banks would suffer less from this problem, and there are ways to mitigate costs of issuing equity
by reducing the banks’ discretion.
Bankers are reluctant to issue equity when they believe it is undervalued in the market. They
are also averse to selling shares when they believe equity issuance would be met with a negative
stock price reaction. Such a reaction will occur if investors fear that equity is relatively likely to
be issued when managers believe the bank is weak.44 Because of the negative “signaling” effect
associated with issuing new shares, bank management may avoid issuing equity to meet
increased capital requirements, and instead cut lending as a way to build up capital.
Note first that the negative signaling effect of equity issuance on stock prices can be
neutralized by eliminating managers’ discretion regarding the issuance decision. Recall that in
the original implementation of the Troubled Asset Relief Program (TARP) in 2009, the
government did not give large banks the choice of whether to accept government investment or
not, so as to mute any information that might be gleaned from the choices made by the banks. In
a similar fashion, corporate insiders eliminate negative inferences that might be drawn from their
stock sales by committing in advance to selling pre-specified amounts at pre-specified times. If
increased equity capital requirements are accompanied by regulation mandating that all banks
issue new equity at a pre-specified schedule, the “stigma” associated with equity issuance would
be removed, and banks would not have a reason to reduce lending in order to satisfy capital
requirements.
It is also very important to observe that if banks were better capitalized, they generally would
have more retained earnings available to fund new investments, since they would have less to
pay out in required interest payments. With higher retained earnings, banks could expand lending
activity more rapidly without the need to raise external capital, which might involve issuing
undervalued securities. Not only will better capitalized banks have less to pay out in required
interest payments, they will also have reduced incentives to pay large dividends. This is because
the more highly leveraged a bank is, the more the equity holders gain (at the expense of debt
44
This observation was first made in Myers and Majluf (1984) in the general context of firms raising outside capital.
For a model where this effect is present in the context of banking, see Bolton and Freixas (2006).
32
holders or those guaranteeing the debt) from a given cash payout to equity.45 The lowered
incentive to pay dividends in better capitalized banks will lead to more retained earnings.
Note also that if a bank does issue equity, the cost associated with any under-pricing of
equity is likely to be lower when a bank has higher capital. As we have shown in Section 3,
higher capital lowers sensitivity of the value of equity to the value of the bank’s underlying
assets. Thus, if investors undervalue a bank’s assets, the underpricing of its equity will be lower
in percentage terms when the bank has more existing equity than in the case where it is highly
leveraged. In that sense, managers and equity holders of better capitalized banks would find that
the cost of raising external funds are not as significant as they would be if the bank were highly
leveraged.46
Finally, we observe that, while issuing equity might be costly for the bank’s existing
shareholders, buying underpriced equity benefits new investors. Thus, the costs for the bank’s
existing investors can be mitigated simply by giving them the option to participate in the new
issue through a rights offering. In this case any costs shareholders incur due to under-pricing will
be offset by gains on their new holdings.
To summarize, concerns about the costs associated with issuing equity due to the possibility
that it is undervalued are not legitimate reasons to avoid imposing higher equity capital
requirements on banks. Since information-related costs can be mitigated if bank managers have
less discretion with respect to payout policies and the issuance of new equity, increased equity
capital requirements can be implemented with new equity issuance in a relatively short period of
time and without significant cost to existing shareholders.
5.3 Is Observed High Leverage Evidence that Equity Requirements are Socially Costly?
“The tendency for banks to finance themselves largely with short term debt may
reflect a privately optimal response to governance problems.” (Kashyap, Rajan
and Stein (2008).)
Statement: “The fact that banks voluntarily choose high leverage is evidence that such leverage
must be optimal from a contracting perspective. Attempts to limit bank leverage will therefore be
privately and socially costly.”
45
In our view (and in the view of many others), the U.S. government should not have allowed large banks to
continue paying dividends while at the same time providing TARP funds to recapitalize these institutions and
encourage lending. Banks in England, by contrast, were forbidden from paying dividends during this period.
46
More precisely, for a given dollar amount of equity raised, the cost from underpricing will be lower with higher
capital. If the bank raises both equity and debt in the same proportion as its original capital structure, then the cost
from underpricing will be independent of capital structure.
33
Assessment: This statement is false. First, systemic risks, as well as tax subsidies and implicit
guarantees may make high leverage privately optimal to bank shareholders and managers even
when it is in fact socially suboptimal. Second, managerial compensation that is linked to ROE
exacerbates the incentives to undertake high leverage. Third, because of ongoing incentives to
increase leverage at the expense of earlier creditors, it is likely that observed bank capital
structure itself is at least partly due to the banks’ imperfect ability to precommit their own future
financing choices. Such constrained “optimality,” which takes as given the bank’s inability to
commit, does not preclude the possibility that capital regulation might lead to better outcomes
even from a private ex ante perspective.
There is the view that, even if we do not have a theoretical justification for it, high leverage
must be efficient for banks simply because that is the capital structure that banks have chosen.
While this “revealed-preference” of banks for high leverage is clear, the fact that banks are
highly leveraged does not mean that regulation cannot improve over this outcome from a social,
or even a private, perspective. As we show below, the mere existence of high leverage in
financial institutions cannot be regarded as evidence that this outcome is privately or socially
desirable.
As we observed in Section 4, there are reasons, such as taxes and implicit guarantees, that
banks find debt an attractive form of financing. High levels of leverage could simply be the
optimal response to these subsidies.47 More generally, if default on debt involves external costs
that are not borne by the contracting parties – i.e. the bank, its managers, or its outside financiers
– then private contracting will lead to an excess of debt finance relative to what is desirable from
a social point of view. Because banks have a private incentive to increase leverage in order to
take advantage of subsidies, and because banks do not account for the negative externalities their
own leverage creates, we cannot use their choice as a measure of the socially optimal level of
bank leverage.48
While it is clear why observed bank leverage is not socially optimal, it is tempting to
presume that it is at least privately optimal from the perspective of bank managers and investors.
This presumption, however, is unproblematic only if these financing patterns are committed to ex
ante, before the bank is set up. If, at that time, all the prospective participants, present and future
financiers, agree on a complete contract and can foresee all contingencies, the result can be
47
Hanson, Kashyap and Stein (2010) argue that competition among banks pushes them to reduce funding cost as
much as possible, and this drives them to be highly leveraged. In our view the main reason that leverage reduces
banks’ funding costs is because it allows them to take greater advantage of government subsidies associated with
debt. In a model with competition, most of these advantages would be passed on to borrowers, but this does not
justify high leverage, which is socially costly. As noted in Section 4.1, if the government wishes to subsidize the
banks’ borrowers, it should do so directly, and not indirectly through subsidies to bank leverage.
48
In this regard a better benchmark for optimal leverage in the absence of subsidies may be real-estate investment
trusts (REITs), which do not enjoy tax benefits from leverage nor are candidates for bailouts in the event of default.
Historically, REITs have typically maintained equity capital in excess of 30%. (See Ooi, Ong and Li, 2008.)
34
presumed to be privately optimal. In practice, however, financing is determined by an ongoing
process, with new contracts being concluded all the time. In this setting, there are reasons to
believe that observed financing structures are not privately optimal, and that the extent of debt
finance can be excessive even from the perspective of the participants themselves.
The basic problem is that new financing decisions affect the return prospects of incumbent
debt holders and shareholders, i.e., they have an “external effect” on existing claim holders.
These effects may be positive or negative in principle, but since managers who have incentive
contracts that are based on equity performance typically make the decisions, decisions that
cannot be committed to in advance would typically benefit equity and dilute the value of existing
debt.49 For example, if incumbent debt holders do not have strong defenses against a dilution of
their claims by new borrowing, the bank’s management may have excessive incentives to engage
in such borrowing.50 We may presume that incumbent debt holders do as much as they can to
protect themselves against such dilution by introducing appropriate covenants when they provide
their funds to the bank. However, to the extent that such covenants are not complete, there is
always a risk that the covenant has a loophole that provides room to engineer such a dilution
anyway. Given these risks, observed market outcomes may involve too much use of contracts
that dilute previous financiers’ claims relative to what would be privately optimal under perfect
commitment.
49
Positive external effects are to be expected if the inflow of new money enhances the bank’s prospects and saves
the bank from an imminent default, and negative external effects are to be expected if the claims of the new
financiers dilute the positions of the incumbents.
50
This agency problem associated with debt, that equity holders have an incentive to take advantage of existing debt
holders by diluting the value of their claim, is discussed in most corporate finance textbooks; see e.g. Berk and
DeMarzo (2010). For a specific model, Bizer and DeMarzo (1992) demonstrate that even if existing debt holders
have seniority, borrowers have an incentive to issue junior debt that reduces the value of senior debt by lowering its
credit quality. The equilibrium level of leverage can then be well in excess of the ex ante optimum. A manifestation
of the same problem, due to lack of commitment about the maturity structure of debt, is key to results in
Brunnermeier and Oehmke (2010), who show that banks have an incentive to shorten the maturity of claims to
“preempt” existing creditors. Thus, banks may have too much short-term debt relative to the ex ante optimum.
51
For the “debt overhang” problem of shareholders fearing that returns to new investments will be captured by debt
holders, see Myers (1977).
35
The problem of moral hazard in ongoing financing relations also concerns dividend policies.
If a bank is highly leveraged, the bank’s shareholders — and the bank’s managers as well —
have strong incentives to have earnings paid out, rather than retained, since if earnings are
retained there is the possibility that they will be used to satisfy the claims of the debt holders in
financial distress. As a further manifestation of the debt overhang problem, the bank, by
maintaining high payouts, effectively under-invests relative to the policy that would be chosen
by a less highly leveraged bank.
Another reason it may be difficult for banks to reduce leverage arises if prospective new
shareholders are worried that they don’t know enough about the skeletons that the bank may still
have in its closets. In that case, as discussed in Section 5.2, a new equity issue is likely to be
perceived as an indication that the value of the assets of the bank is known by managers to be
low. In this case they may insist on a low share price, too low perhaps to meet the incumbent
shareholders’ demand that their positions not be diluted. Absent a mandatory requirement to
recapitalize the firm, bank managers are likely to be reluctant to do so for fear of such
underpricing.
Thus, for the reasons we have outlined, high leverage is unlikely to be an optimal solution to
a contracting problem, from either a social or private perspective. Banks have strong incentives
to maintain high leverage to exploit both tax and distress-related subsidies, and ignore any
systemic risk this leverage creates. Moreover, absent the ability to commit, heavily indebted
banks have incentives to maintain or increase leverage and equity payouts in order to exploit
existing debt holders. As a result, we should not use observed levels of leverage as an indication
that increasing equity capital is socially undesirable. 52
Statement: “Increased equity requirements would have an adverse effect on the lending
decisions of banks and will inhibit economic growth.”
52
This is consistent with the finding in Mehran and Thakor (2010) that bank valuation measures seem to be
positively correlated with higher levels of equity capital in the cross section.
36
Assessment: This statement is false. High leverage distorts lending decisions and because of
this, better capitalized banks generally make better lending decisions. In particular less leveraged
banks are less inclined to make excessively risky investments or to pass up worthwhile loans due
to frictions associated with high leverage.
We now turn to what seems to be the biggest concern many have expressed about increased
capital requirements, namely the notion that increased requirements will cause banks to cut back
on lending and to charge more on the loans they make. Based on the discussion in Sections 3-5
we are now in a position to offer a detailed analysis of this issue.
Before attempting to analyze the claims that increased equity requirements would lead to a
“credit crunch,” we must remember that the biggest “credit crunch” in recent memory, the total
freezing of credit markets during the recent financial crisis, was not due to too much equity but
in fact to the extremely high levels of leverage in the financial system. In other words, credit
crunches arise when banks are undercapitalized. If all banks have sufficient equity capital, they
will have no reason to pass up economically valuable lending opportunities, and the risk of future
credit crunches is reduced.
Arguments that increased equity capital requirements will adversely affect banks’ lending
seem to fall into two categories. In the first category are arguments to the effect that, when banks
have less equity than required, they will cut back on lending. In the second category are
arguments to the effect that banks’ lending criteria are tied to the way they are funded and that,
with a greater share of equity finance, lending criteria will be more restrictive. We examine
these two types of arguments separately.
Arguments to the effect that banks cut back on lending because they have too little equity
often are rooted in the belief that, with a “fixed amount” of bank capital, higher equity capital
requirements can only be met by scaling back on loans and other investments. For some
institutions, e.g., public banks in Germany, which have only limited access to the market, this
belief may be justified. However, in the absence of such institutional constraints and other
frictions, it is unjustified. As noted in Section 3, higher equity capital requirements do not need
to be met by scaling back on loans and other investments. Banks can in fact continue their
lending without scaling back and at the same time meet higher requirements, either by
substituting equity for some liabilities (as suggested in Figure 1, Balance Sheet B) or by
expanding the balance sheet (as suggested by Figure 1, Balance Sheet C).
Thus, the imposition of higher capital requirements does not force banks to restrict lending.
However, as discussed in Section 5, undercapitalized banks might choose not to issue new equity
-- and thereby pass up valuable lending opportunities -- because doing so would (i) help creditors
37
at the expense of shareholders (the “debt overhang” problem) and (ii) potentially send a negative
signal to the bank’s investors regarding its future prospects. The problem of debt overhang is
particularly relevant in the transition when higher capital requirements are imposed. It is also
relevant in a crisis, when losses have eaten into bank equity. There is evidence that both of these
concerns played a significant role in the recent crisis, and it is the reason that governments
(through programs such as TARP in the U.S.) attempted to reduce bank leverage using capital
injections and asset purchases.53
To overcome this private disincentive to issue equity and recapitalize, the imposition of
higher capital requirements should be accompanied by requirements for banks to quickly meet
them by restricting payouts and issuing new equity.54 Furthermore, if a bank fails to maintain
sufficient equity capital, similar mandates should be triggered. Once appropriately recapitalized,
banks are positioned to invest in any new profitable lending activities that arise.
Another type of argument that increased capital requirement will lead to a contraction of
lending is based on the notion that changes in capital requirements will make some loans
unprofitable that were previously profitable to make. This change in profitability will, it is
argued, be due to the fact that these loans must be “funded” in a different way. The change in
profitability will then lead to changes in banks’ lending decisions. In this context the appropriate
question is not only whether better capitalized banks make different loan decisions than more
highly leveraged banks, but also whether their lending decisions will be better or worse, from a
social perspective. In fact, we will argue at the end of this section that if banks have significantly
more equity, they are likely to make more appropriate lending decisions and we can expect the
cost of credit to be as low as is economically justifiable.
More appropriate lending decisions may involve reductions in some kinds of lending. Such
reductions, however, while annoying to the potential borrowers, may well be beneficial to the
economy as a whole. For the economy as a whole, the objective is not to have as much lending
as possible, but to have as much lending as is appropriate in view of investors’ willingness and
ability bear risks. Excessive risk taking, as discussed in Section 5, may well take the form of
excessive lending. This should be avoided.
53
There is also a concern that, with capital requirements framed in terms of risk-weighted assets, bank loans would
be most strongly affected by this scaling back. By cutting back on conventional banks loans, which carry a risk
weight of 100%, banks can reduce capital needs much more than by reducing their holdings of bonds or asset-
backed securities that have lower risk weights. Thus, as argued by Brealey (1996) and Hellwig (2010), the current
system of risk-weights used in capital regulation might itself contribute to a credit crunch. Given the experience with
asset-backed securities in the crisis, the risk weights driving this diversion of funds out of lending and into
marketable securities seems inappropriate and distortionary.
54
Hanson, Kashyap and Stein (2010) discuss the importance of debt overhang in potentially leading to lending
contraction when banks are under-capitalized and make similar recommendations.
38
How does the way loans are “funded” affect their profitability? Some of the discussion of
this issue and the effects that capital requirements will have on banks’ lending decisions appears
to involve the fundamental fallacies about capital structure and banks’ cost of capital that were
discussed in Section 3.3. In order to avoid these fallacies one must be very careful to properly
account for changes in risk when considering how loans are made and funded. As an example,
consider the following assessment by Acharya, Schnabl, and Suarez (2010, p. 33) of banks using
conduits and structured investment vehicles in order to invest in mortgage-backed securities
without backing them by equity capital.
“We can assess the benefits to banks by quantifying how much profit conduits
yielded to banks from an ex-ante perspective using a simple back-of-the-envelope
calculation. Assuming a risk weight of 100% for underlying assets, banks could
avoid capital requirements of roughly 8% by setting up conduits relative to on-
balance sheet financing. … Further assuming an equity beta of one and a market
risk premium of 5%, banks could reduce the cost of capital by 8% × 5% = 0.004 or
40 basis points by setting up conduits relative to on-balance sheet financing.
… banks earned about 10 basis points on conduit assets. … it seems clear that
conduits would not have been profitable if banks had been required to hold equity
against their assets in conduits. In fact, banks would have made a loss of 30 basis
points on each dollar invested. However, given that banks were not required to hold
equity, they could earn a “profit” of 10 basis points.”
To make the fallacy involved in ignoring risk in the profit calculation completely obvious,
consider the implications of this argument taken to the extreme. If one simply compares
investment return with apparent financing costs to compute profitability as is done in the
55
Boot (1996) and Boot and Schmeits (1998) argue that in making investment decisions bankers use a type of
“mental accounting” where they match the loans they make with particular sources of funding, and compare returns
on that basis.
39
example above, then it follows that almost any bank and any firm can significantly increase its
“profitability” by issuing debt and using the proceeds to buy the debt issued by firms with lower
credit ratings. A firm with a rating of A might be able to issue debt at 6% and use the proceeds to
finance investment in B-rated debt with an expected return of 7.5%, producing 150 basis points
of “pure profit.” Of course, it is easily seen that this increases risk and the shareholders must be
compensated for this. The true question is whether the extra 150 basis points in return
compensates for the increased risk.
From a normative perspective, in a world without frictions and distortions, the decision on
whether to make a particular loan or not should be independent of the bank’s capital structure,
i.e., on how the bank is funded. The decision should depend only on whether the excess of the
loan rate over the market rate of interest for risk free securities provides the bank with a
sufficient premium to make the risks associated with the loan acceptable. This latter question in
turn should depend only on the risk characteristics of the loan and on the assessment of these risk
characteristics by investors in the market.56 Neither the bank’s other assets, nor the bank’s capital
structure should play a role.57
The key ingredient of the analysis is the overall required return that is appropriate for the
investment. The required return for the loan is determined by its riskiness as it is measured and
priced in the market place of risky investments. From this perspective, the assessment cited by
Acharya et al. (2010), which may well be a realistic description of how bankers would make this
particular decision, appears as an instance of managers attempting to take on excessive risk at the
expense of incumbent financiers, or of the taxpayers, and hoping they can enjoy the upside
without needing to worry about the downside.58 A bank that invests billions of dollars in
mortgage-backed securities to earn 10 basis points above commercial-paper rates is raising
expected returns to shareholders. However, to do so, it must bear the associated risks – risks
from borrowing short to buy long-lived securities as well as the credit risks of mortgage-backed
securities. These risks burden incumbent debt holders (and the government to the extent that it
implicitly guarantees the bank’s debt) as well as shareholders. If markets are informed about
these risks, the required rates of return on the bank’s securities must adjust. Unless the premium
of 10 basis points is deemed to be sufficiently high, this adjustment makes incumbent debt
holders and shareholders take a loss. If markets are not informed about these risks, which may
56
In the simplest mean-variance model of risk pricing, the loan’s risk would be assessed in terms of its covariance
with the market, and the requisite risk premium would be derived by weighting this covariance with the market price
of risk.
57
One may object that in practice bank loans tend to be opaque and market investors are unable to completely assess
their risks and price them. This objection does not have any bearing on what should occur from a normative
perspective. Indeed, it highlights the importance of understanding the criteria that the bank should be using. In the
end, even if the bank does know more about the loan at the time it is originated, market investors will generally
develop some understanding of the risk characteristics of the bank’s loan portfolio, and will use this understanding
to price the bank’s securities in the market.
58
This is an instance of the problem, discussed in Section 5.3, that issuing additional debt to fund new investments
may be the result of a conflict of interest between equity holders (or managers) and previous financiers.
40
well have been the case in the situation that is described here, incumbent debt holders and
shareholders will still be damaged when the risks come home, as they in fact did in August 2007.
As discussed in Section 4, it is true that increased equity capital requirements will remove
some of the subsidies banks capture through high leverage, namely tax and implicit guarantees.
If taking away these subsidies causes banks to lend less or to charge higher rates than is
considered desirable, it may be desirable from a public-policy perspective to subsidize bank
lending. If lending needs to be subsidized because it is important for the economy then, as we
argued in Section 4, more targeted and less costly ways must be found to provide such subsidies
than encouraging banks to be highly leveraged.
We now turn to the question of whether better capitalized banks will make better or worse
lending decisions. The discussion in Section 5 suggests that, because of frictions associated with
governance and information, highly leveraged banks are generally subject to distortions in their
lending decisions. These distortions may lead them to make worse lending decisions than they
would have made if they were better capitalized, involving either too much or too little lending
relative to some social optimum. First, equity holders in a leveraged bank, and managers
working on their behalf or compensated on the basis of ROE, have incentives to make
excessively risky investments, and this problem is exacerbated when the debt has government
guarantees.59 Second, when banks are distressed, credit markets can freeze and certain loans will
not be made due to a “debt overhang” problem. Valuable loans that are not made as a result of
debt overhang would be undertaken if the bank were better capitalized, since in that case the
value created by the loans would be captured by those who would fund it.
We have also argued that better capitalized banks, which have more internally generated
funds with which to make new loans, would have less need to issue new claims and thus are less
likely to have to issue undervalued equity. And it is possible for regulators to reduce the
resistance of banks to issue equity or to withhold dividend payments that is due to negative
market reaction to such actions. Thus, while banks might find it difficult to raise new equity if
investors are suspicious that they have “skeletons in the closet,” it might be possible for
regulators to alleviate some of this problem by mandating new equity issuance and limiting
payouts so as to enhance banks’ ability to retain earnings until they build adequate cushions. In
any case, this issue will not affect lending adversely once banks are better capitalized.
59
It has been argued (perhaps with some hindsight bias) that a significant number of the loans that were made prior
to the 2007-2009 financial crisis, such as some sub-prime mortgage loans, were ones that should not have been
made and could not be justified by conventional lending standards.
41
perspective. To the extent that banks can quickly get to the point of being better capitalized (by
adding equity without suffering negative consequences, as discussed in Section 5.2), there should
be no concern with any negative impact on the economy of increased equity capital
requirements.
We have argued in Section 3.1 that there is no need for banks to change their deposit base or
even to reduce the amount of debt they have in response to an increase in equity requirements.
Recall Balance Sheet C in Figure 1: A transition from the original balance sheet to Balance Sheet
C would involve issuing new equity and using the proceeds to purchase additional assets such as
marketable securities. We now address some concerns that might be raised regarding this way of
creating a larger equity cushion.
One concern might be that it is costly or inefficient for banks to hold large positions of
marketable securities that are unrelated to their core business. Among non-financial firms,
however, it is common to hold cash and marketable securities. For a set of large technology
firms, the size of these holdings is shown in Table 1.
42
simply for the purpose of backing up their substantial debt obligations? Surely the concern that
holding such securities is unrelated to core business of a bank is much less compelling than it is
for non-financial firms.
From the perspective of the overall economy, one might ask whether, economically, it makes
sense for banks to issue equity in order to hold marketable securities and thus to “intermediate”
the holdings of securities in the economy. Doesn’t this reallocation distort the structure of the
overall financial system? Figure 4 illustrates the implications of expanding the bank’s balance
sheet using newly issued equity to acquire marketable securities.
A A
C C
B B
D D
E E
Investors Investors
F
F
Bank Bank
Equity Equity
The figure shows that if the bank issues more equity to buy marketable securities, there is not
necessarily any effect on the aggregate assets – or the aggregate production activities – in the
economy. On the left-hand side of the figure, investors hold securities A through F directly, as
well as bank equity. On the right-hand side of the figure, investors hold securities A through E
and a larger position of bank equity than before. Security F is now being held by the bank.
Indirectly, however, investors are also “holding” this security as shareholders of the bank.
Ultimately, directly or indirectly, all securities, representing claims against all assets in the
economy, are held by final investors. All that is done by moving from the left-hand side to the
right-hand side of Figure 4 is to arrange the claims in a different way. Aggregate asset
allocations in the economy are not affected.
Thus, in the context of the entire economic system, expanding banks’ balance sheets does not
change, and in particular does not prevent, the undertaking of any and all productive activities,
and it also does not need to affect the risk-return profile of the holdings of individual and
43
institutional investors.60 Those who hold diversified portfolios of assets still have access to the
same combinations of risk and return, and the riskiness of bank equity, as modified by additional
holdings, can be taken into account.61,
This is not to say that there are no real effects of replacing the arrangement on the left-hand
side by that on the right-hand side of Figure 4. First, on the right-hand side of Figure 4, the chain
of transactions linking final investors to the issuer of security F is potentially longer; this longer
chain might involve higher transactions costs.62 Second, the greater the equity that the bank has
on the right-hand side of Figure 4, the more robust the bank is in “crisis” situations, when bank
assets fall significantly in value. In such a situation, some of the value of security F is received
not by the bank’s shareholders but by its creditors. The loss is borne by shareholders. From a
social perspective, such an outcome is much better than a default that would have severe
repercussions for the rest of the financial system. In addition, the fact that the loss is borne by the
shareholders and not by creditors and the government reduces ex ante risk shifting incentives.
In terms of what types of securities banks would purchase if they need to add cushions but do
not have valuable loans to make note that between January 2008 and August 2010, the
outstanding U.S. treasury debt held by the public increased by $2.4 trillion. This increase alone
represents almost 20% of the total value of assets held by U.S. commercial banks, which is
approximately $12 trillion. These new assets, among others, could be used to increase banks’
equity by as much as 16.6%. The use of marketable securities to increase the equity cushion of
banks, however, does not require that all or even most of these securities be completely liquid or
“safe.” The addition of any security to the bank’s balance sheet acquired using the proceeds of an
equity issuance decreases systemic risk.
Our discussion up to this point has been exclusively focused on the costs and benefits of
increasing the equity capital requirements of banks. Another important regulatory issue concerns
liquidity requirements for banks. A full discussion of liquidity requirements is beyond the scope
of this paper, but it is useful to make a few observations about liquidity in the context of our
analysis of increased equity requirements. Much of the focus on liquidity needs of banks is
related to the fragility associated with highly leveraged banks that rely on short-term funding.
Liquidity problems arise when short term funding is not renewed and banks may be forced to sell
assets on short notice. Liquidity is important because a liquidity crisis can lead to distress for
banks that are technically solvent. For such banks a significant “reserve” of liquid assets may be
prudent. Liquidity reserves become less important when banks are much better capitalized. First,
even if a bank uses short-term funding, the scenarios that require liquidity (e.g. a run on the
60
The one exception to this is the redistribution of liability in a crisis away from the government and its taxpayers
and toward bank equity holders.
61
To the extent that bank equity becomes less risky, those who would like to take on additional risk can create
leverage by buying on margin, trading options in an exchange, etc.
62
However, if these securities were already held by other intermediaries, the effect may not be there at all.
44
bank) become less likely when the bank is better capitalized. Second, if the bank is better
capitalized, the central bank or “lender of last resort” has less reason to worry that a liquidity
crisis is actually a solvency crisis. Increased equity capital thus ultimately lowers the cost of
central banks providing liquidity backstops.
We have argued that the social costs of banks holding thicker capital cushions are very small.
We are not necessarily saying that the social costs of increased liquidity requirements are small.
Cash is obviously the most liquid of assets, and it pays no (nominal) return. The cost of the
liquidity provided by cash is the opportunity cost of not receiving a higher return from a less
liquid security. Holding excessive amounts of cash (or other liquid assets whose return is low
because of a liquidity premium) relative to the bank’s liquidity needs is costly because the bank
pays an unnecessary liquidity premium. This inefficiency can be interpreted as a social cost.63
As discussed above, however, additional equity does not necessarily have to be invested in cash,
and it can either be put into profitable lending or invested in marketable securities that earn risk-
adjusted, market-determined returns. Because increased equity requirements can reduce the need
for liquidity as discussed above, they provide an additional benefit of reducing the total cost of
liquidity that banks must bear.
Finally, banks play an important role in helping to satisfy demand for liquidity by issuing
“money-like” securities. These are safe, liquid, and “informationally insensitive” securities in the
sense that those who buy and sell them do not need to invest resources to figure out how to value
them, and those trading them are less worried about trading with better informed counter
parties.64 In expanding the balance sheet we have not reduced the dollar amount of the banks
liabilities and so we have not reduced the amount of money-like securities it issues. The
increased capital cushion further reduces the probability of default of the bank, making the
money-like securities even less risky and more informationally insensitive, and thus more liquid.
Increased bank capital thus allows banks to reduce their demand for and increase their supply of
liquid assets in the economy.
Contingent capital, i.e., debt that converts to equity in some scenarios, has recently been
proposed, e.g., by Flannery (2002) and Squam Lake Group (French et al., 2010), as a security
that regulators should encourage or perhaps require financial institutions to issue. This notion is
being examined by the Basel committee as an alternative to at least some Tier 2 capital that
63
For a formal treatment of the costs of inefficient holdings of liquid assets and the role of public liquidity
provision, see Bolton, Santos and Scheinkman (2010)
64
See, for example, Gorton and Pennacchi (1990), and Dang, Gorton and Holmström (2010).
45
could absorb some losses in a crisis. Related proposals involving mandatory conversion of debt
to equity to help simplify bankruptcy procedures have been termed “bail-in.”65
Clearly, once a bank is in difficulties, it is important to have mechanisms that provide for
“expedited resolution” without having to go through all the potential inefficiencies of an
insolvency proceeding. However, while such remedies are clearly valuable from an ex post
perspective, contingent capital, as a security on the bank’s balance sheet, must be assessed from
an ex ante perspective, and thus in the context of capital requirements for banks.66 Indeed, any
regulation regarding the types of securities that are issued by financial institutions must be
assessed in this more general context and assessed within all possible strategies, including
increasing equity requirements.
From this perspective, contingent capital appears as a form of hybrid capital, subordinated
debt that is transformed into equity when the stipulated conversion conditions are realized. As
such, it has both debt-like and equity-like features. From a public-policy perspective, the
question must be why the particular combination of debt-like and equity-like features in
contingent debt should be preferable to the combination that is obtained by issuing a combination
of debt and equity in the first place. If we want to enhance the bank’s capital cushion, why not
just require the cushion to come in the form of simple equity?
In many discussions it appears that one of the main motivations for having “debt-like”
contingent capital is to preserve for the banks the tax subsidy associated with debt financing. As
discussed in Section 4.1, however, preserving this subsidy is not justified from a public-policy
perspective.67 There are many other complications that arise with contingent capital, particularly
how triggers and conversion rules should be designed so as to make it an effective cushion and
also prevent potential for manipulation by investors or managers, especially close to such times
when the triggers are potentially reached.68 Given these and other complications, and the fact that
65
On the bail-in concept see, for example, “From Bail-Out to Bail-In,” The Economist, January 30, 2010.
66
Contingent capital is often discussed in the narrow context of how regulators would handle distressed financial
institutions at the time of systemic crisis. For example, in French et al. (2010), contingent capital is discussed in a
chapter that is distinct from the discussion of capital regulation (and in fact these two chapters are separated by a
chapter on compensation).
67
In fact, since contingent debt holders do not have “creditor’s rights,” it is not even clear whether interest paid on
contingent debt is tax deductible according to current U.S. law. This indeed illustrates the fact that contingent capital
has equity-like feature and its issuance shifts some downside risk to contingent capital holders. In a well-functioning
markets, these investors will have to be compensated for bearing this risk.
68
For discussions of various issues related to how triggers should be set and the potential for a “death spiral” if the
conversion decision can be manipulated through short-term trading see Duffie (2010), Sundaresan and Wang (2010),
and McDonald (2010). Pennacchi, Vermaelen and Wolff (2010) propose a version of contingent capital that they
call COERCs (Call Option Enhanced Reverse Convertibles”), which are designed to avoid many of the potential
complications and the potential for manipulation that might arise with other versions of contingent capital. COERCs
have the feature that equity has the option to repay the debt to avoid dilutive conversion.
46
it has not been established that contingent capital alleviates any inherent frictions, we are
skeptical that going down this route is a worthwhile approach69.
Figure 5 compares creating cushions using contingent capital to doing so using simple equity
instead of contingent capital.
Equity
Contingent
Capital Equity
Structure with Assets
Contingent Capital Before
“Straight” Assets “Straight”
Debt After Debt
Equity
Equity
Structure with Assets
Equity Before
“Straight” Assets “Straight”
Debt After Debt
The top panel illustrates how contingent capital is meant to provide a cushion in the event of
a crisis. An event that causes asset values to decline leads to the conversion of contingent capital
to equity. The balance sheet before the crisis (the top left hand side) is transformed into the
balance sheet on the top right hand side. In the bottom panel we trace the same development, but
in this case we assume that additional equity was used to provide the additional cushion instead
of contingent capital. The outcome is of course the same. The major difference is that with equity
there is no need to go through the process of mandatory conversion, and the potentially
problematic process and uncertainties leading up to the actual conversion are avoided.70
69
A similar conclusion is reached in Goodhart (2010).
70
In this figure we are implicitly assuming that the “straight debt” is safe or insured, so its value does not change
from “before” to “after.” If the bank had some straight debt that is not insured, then its value might decline in this
47
The proponents of contingent capital seem to regard it as a device to resolve some of the
difficulties that stand in the way of a recapitalization through the market once the bank is in
difficulties. By having an automatic conversion of debt into equity, the bank may avoid the debt
overhang problem described earlier, which prevents certain valuable loans from being made. If
investors anticipate such a possibility, however, they would require high rates of interest on these
securities as compensation for the risk to which they are exposed. (This conclusion follows from
the same basic insights discussed in Section 3.3.) From this perspective, it is not clear why, apart
from the banks’ private tax considerations, provision of an additional cushion by contingent
capital should be preferable to provision of such a cushion by additional equity. One can in fact
think of equity as contingent capital that is converted ab initio.
In this context, it is also useful to go back to the experience of the crisis. According to the
Basel Committee on Banking Supervision (2009), one flaw in pre-crisis arrangements had been
the poor quality of capital, different regulators in different countries having different standards as
to which securities they treated as capital and which ones they did not. In many cases, various
hybrid securities were included in Tier 1 capital, certain forms of subordinated debt in Tier 2
capital. When the crisis came, these securities did not always provide the cushion they should
have provided. Indeed, some governments were afraid of domino effects of defaults and
extended their bailouts to even these securities.
Relative to the various forms of hybrid securities and subordinated debt securities, contingent
capital would seem to have the advantage that conversion would be automatic, without
insolvency proceedings. While we share the view that insolvency proceedings are too
complicated, lengthy, and costly, we are not convinced that automatic conversion would solve
the problem. First, if the holders of these securities are sufficiently important, government
temptation to bail them out will be no less than it was for subordinated and hybrid securities in
the current crisis. Second, while the conversion itself may be automatic, when the bank is in
difficulties, holders of these securities may want to sell them before the conditions for
conversion arise. In other words, the attempt to smooth matters in a later stage may just pull
some of the frictions forward in time.
We have seen no compelling argument that contingent capital that has a debt-like structure
prior to conversion has a positive impact on governance problems sufficient to justify including
it in capital regulation. The skepticism that we expressed in Section 5.1 concerning the potential
role of debt in resolving governance problems extends to the “debt-like” features of contingent
capital. In sum, in our view the case for including contingent capital as part of capital regulation
has not been established against simpler approaches based on equity.
transition, because the lower asset value might expose it to an actual default risk. This does not change the
conclusion that the structure with equity leads to the same results as the one with contingent capital.
48
9. Conclusions and Policy Recommendations
In this paper we have examined various claims and arguments that assert that increasing
equity requirements for large banks entails significant costs. We find that these claims and
arguments, when analyzed from first principles, are very weak and not compelling. Why do we
hear these arguments? One possible answer is given in the table on the last page, which
summarizes our analysis of the various claims. We see that managers and bank shareholders
have some strong incentives to maintain high leverage for banks and to resist increased equity
capital requirements. In particular government subsidies that reward debt financing (and penalize
equity financing) benefit managers and shareholders. These subsidies would be reduced if equity
capital requirements were increased. Of course, arguments made by bankers against increased
capital requirements are not automatically invalid just because it might be in their interest to
oppose this stricter regulation. Rather, political and regulatory authorities should be especially
skeptical when evaluating claims that are not supported by strong arguments. As we have shown
above, the most important claims that are advanced in this context are based on fallacies,
irrelevant facts, or insufficiently rich theories.
The debate over capital regulation is a bit reminiscent of the battle over expensing stock
options some years ago. The issue in that debate concerned inconsistencies in the treatment of
employee compensation on the income statement. Whereas compensation in cash and restricted
stock was recognized as an immediate expense for the calculation of earnings, employee stock
options were not recognized as an expense as long as the options were not “in the money” when
they were issued. When the Financial Accounting Standards Board (FASB) attempted to change
this accounting treatment in 1994 by requiring that options be expensed in a way that reflected
their true cost, a fierce political battle ensued.
Opponents of option expensing made three types of arguments. The first was that a company
incurs no cost in granting executive stock options when they are issued, since the options are not
in the money. Of course, this statement is simply fallacious. The second statement that was often
made was that executive options are difficult to value with precision. But while this statement is
true, because the value of these options depends, for example, on the difficult to model exercise
decisions of employees, it is basically irrelevant. Just because the options are difficult to value
does not mean that valuing them at zero is appropriate.71 The third argument made against
expensing options asserted that expensing options would have a real and negative impact on the
economy, by somehow preventing entrepreneurial firms from obtaining financing, which would
impede growth and reduce the competitiveness of the U.S. economy. These assertions were
ultimately based on some form of investor irrationality, since they implied that investors would
71
In fact, companies often value complex liabilities, such as health care costs of retirees, in preparing accounting
statements.
49
be misled by changes in accounting rules even though these changes had no effect on the
underlying economics of the firm.
All of the above arguments were made at various times, but of course it was the claims about
the “real” effects of expensing options that were most effective with politicians. In fact, in 1994
the U.S. Congress threatened to dismantle FASB unless it backed off from the plan to expense
options. A decade later, after World Com, Enron, and other corporate scandals, it suddenly
became politically palatable to expense options, and FASB went ahead to change the rules with
minimal objections from Congress. And the result? There has been no evidence that this change
in accounting rules had any negative economic impact whatsoever.
Quite similarly, as we have discussed, the arguments against high equity capital requirements
fall under the same three categories: those that are fallacious, those that are true but irrelevant,
and those that are unpersuasive. Because the social benefits of significantly reducing bank
leverage are significant, and because there are no significant social costs of increasing equity
requirements for banks, politicians and regulators should not be overly concerned with threats
that credit markets will be adversely affected by increasing equity requirements. High equity
requirements need not interfere with any of the valuable intermediation activities undertaken by
banks. Regulators should therefore take steps to impose significantly higher equity requirements
as quickly as possible.
Given the above assessment, what is the appropriate equity capital requirement? Various
empirical studies, e.g., BIS (2010), Bank of Canada (2010), and IIF (2010), have attempted to
answer this question using a variety of models to estimate the costs and benefits of increased
equity requirements. Going through the different empirical models that are used in these
documents is beyond our scope here. However, it appears that the methods of analysis used in
most of these studies fall prey to many of the concerns we have identified in this paper. For
example, in BIS (2010) the analysis uses a fixed estimate for the cost of equity that is based on
historical averages, ignoring the fact that decreased leverage would necessarily lower the risk
premium on equity. Moreover, the approach in most of these studies assumes that if bank
margins or ROE decline, or bank taxes increase, these effects translate to social costs, which is
incorrect. Calculations of the benefits of increased equity requirements in these analyses also do
not take into account potential improvements in the quality of lending decisions that better
capitalized banks are likely to make. While some of these might be hard to measure, we suspect
that upon closer examination the net social benefits of increased equity requirements have been
under-estimated in these studies. This under-estimation might be quite substantial if, as we have
argued, the social costs are significantly over-estimated.72
72
Kashyap, Stein and Hanson (2010), who also point out fallacies associated with not adjusting required returns to
the reduced riskiness of equity that results from higher equity requirements, focus on the legitimate concerns related
to regulatory arbitrage and shadow banking, which we mention below. However, in their estimate of the impact of
increased equity requirements on lending costs, they still take the tax code as given, neglecting the fact that such
50
To attempt to give even a rough, order-of-magnitude answer to the question of what
appropriate equity requirements should be, one must in principle refer to how capital ratios are
calculated, something that we have not addressed in this paper. While important institutions have
vaunted themselves as having 10% core capital relative to risk-weighted assets under Basel rules,
this measure has often meant only 1% to 3% capital relative to the overall balance sheet (i.e.,
unweighted assets). The notion of using risk-weighted assets for capital regulation is based on
the fact that the riskiness of the assets should in principle guide how much of an equity cushion
is prudent for regulators to require. In the recent financial crisis, however, we have seen that
assets that had zero risk weights in the banks’ models could suddenly experience severe
problems.73 Any system of capital regulation must come to terms with these issues.
Leaving aside the issue of how one accounts for the riskiness of banks’ assets, and taking as a
benchmark current levels of risk, one can discuss capital requirements in terms of unweighted
equity ratios, i.e., equity capital relative to total assets (off-balance sheet as well as on-balance
sheet) held by the bank. Historical comparisons (e.g., evidence provided in Haldane (2009))
suggest that equity capital ratios as high as 20% or 30% on an unweighted basis should not be
unthinkable. Another benchmark can be gleaned by considering Real Estate Investment Trusts
(REITs), which do not enjoy tax benefits from leverage nor are they candidates for bailouts in
the event of default. According to Ooi, Ong and Li (2008), REITs typically maintain equity
capital in excess of 30% of assets. Based on all of these observations, we believe equity capital
ratios equivalent to 10% of unweighted assets, and possibly higher, should be seriously
considered and thought of as feasible.
The above is not to suggest that setting “a number” for the unweighted or weighted equity
ratio is all there is to capital regulation. An ever-present and important challenge in capital
regulation is achieving international harmonization and determining on an ongoing basis the
appropriate set of institutions that should be regulated. Issues related to the cyclical dynamics
implied by rigid equity requirements must also be considered carefully by regulators.74 It is also
critical that regulators be able to assess the true leverage of banks and prevent them from using
various tricks to hide their actual exposure, as we now discover has been the case for a number
of financial institutions. The shadow banking system, as explored by Poszar et al. (2010), must
be understood by regulators and steps must be taken to ensure that the financial reporting of
transfers are not themselves a social cost. As discussed in Section 5.2, we also take issue with their recommendation
that regulators give banks significant time to adjust to higher equity requirements due to information asymmetries
and the “stigma” associated with equity issuance. Instead, we recommend payout restrictions and possibly
mandatory equity issuance that in fact alleviate these problems and accelerate the capitalization process.
73
Given this experience, Hellwig (2010) has suggested that the notion of measuring risks is itself quite an illusion
and that in practice the risk-calibration approach provides banks with too much scope for manipulating their models
so as to “economize” on equity capital by not recognizing risks.
74
See Goodhart (2010) and Hanson, Kashyap and Stein (2010) for a discussion of this issue, and some specific
proposals.
51
banks provides useful and accurate information about their actual leverage and financial health in
order to prevent the phenomenon of “regulatory arbitrage.”
How would banks get to the point of having much larger equity cushions? Should they be
given many years to build up their equity capital? It is widely argued, and recent policy
proposals recommend, that banks be given a very long time to adjust to new capital
requirements. Kashyap, Stein and Hanson (2010) based their recommendation on the claim that,
as suggested in Myers and Majluf (1984), equity issuance might be costly if investors fear that
managers issue equity only when it is overpriced, which may make banks reluctant to issue new
equity to satisfy capital requirements. We have suggested, however, that this problem can be
alleviated if regulators actually remove some of the discretion that banks might otherwise have
with respect to equity issuance, thereby eliminating the stigma associated with it. By setting
schedules for banks so that they must issue equity at specific times, investors will no longer be
justified in making negative inferences about any particular bank based on the fact that it is
issuing equity. As we noted, this approach is similar to what the U.S. Treasury did when forcing
all large banks to accept Troubled Asset Relief Program (TARP) funds so as to remove any
stigma associated with taking the funds.
Banks clearly serve an important function in the economy by providing credit and creating
liquid deposits. As we have argued, high leverage is not required for them to be able to perform
75
Banyi, Porter and Williams (2010) document an increase in stock repurchases by U.S. financial institutions prior to
2007, including specifically those who later received TARP funds. According to Acharya, Gujral, and Shin (2009),
large U.S. banks paid $130 billion in dividends during 2007-2008, years in which they were in distress and where
most were also being provided with additional funding from the government Acharya, Gujral, and Shin (2009),
Acharya, Mehran and Thakor (2010) and Goodhart et al (2010), suggest that regulators use restrictions on dividends
as part of prudential capital regulation.
76
Note that banks’ stock prices will likely fall as a result of implementing such policies because current prices
reflect the value of government subsidies as well as shareholders’ ability, absent such dividend prohibition, to
generate cash payout on a regular basis without too much concern about the solvency of the bank. Forcing banks to
retain earnings and to build up their equity capital reduces the value of these subsidies (a benefit to taxpayers), and
in addition would provide significant social benefits.
52
these socially valuable functions. If one believes that certain activities performed by banks and
financial institutions need to be subsidized because the free market does not lead to the best
outcome, then subsidies should be given directly to those activities rather than through a system
that encourages dangerous levels of leverage and excessive risk taking and effectively penalizes
equity finance.
The main message we would like to deliver to regulators is that they should not be overly
concerned with threats that a substantial increase in equity requirements will have significant
negative effects on the economy and growth. Once regulators accept our assessment that, at least
starting from the current situation, bank equity is not expensive, capital regulation can become an
effective, powerful and flexible tool with which the health and stability of the financial system
can be maintained. Given appropriate systems for tracking the systemic risks of important
financial institutions, regulators can use their judgment to adjust the equity requirements of all
banks according to economic conditions, possibly using tools such as payout restrictions and
mandatory equity issuance, in a manner analogous to the use of margin requirements by financial
exchanges to maintain the safety of transactions.77 We are confident that financial markets will
adjust quickly to such a system with no substantial adverse effects, and that the overall impact
will be to enhance the role of the financial sector in the broader economy.
We have based our analysis of the costs and benefits of increasing equity requirements for
banks on what we assess to be the fundamental economic issues involved. We expect that some
will disagree with our conclusions. Any discussion of this important topic in public policy should
be fully focused on social costs and benefits. Moreover, any assertions that are made should be
based on sound arguments and persuasive evidence. Unfortunately, the level of policy debate on
this subject that we have seen is not always consistent with these standards.
77
For example, Hart and Zingales (2010) propose that regulators use market information to determine when to force
banks to recapitalize. As mentioned in Duffie (2010), regulators might be able to force banks to increase equity
capital through mandatory rights offerings.
53
Would this “reason” Would this “reason”
From a public policy perspective, is
“Reasons” given for why increased give incentives to give incentives to bank
this a legitimate reason for not
equity capital requirements would bank managers to shareholders to object
Is the statement true? significantly increasing capital
be costly object to increased to increased capital
requirements?
capital requirements? requirements?
No. Equity can be added
Increased equity requirements would
to the balance sheet It should not, because It should not, because it
prevent banks from operating at the No! It is false.
without changing the it is false. is false.
optimal scale.
bank’s core business.
It should not, because
Increased equity requirements reduce
Yes if compensation risk is reduced and the
the average ROE (Return on Equity) Generally Yes. No! This is irrelevant to value creation.
depends on ROE. value of equity would
for banks.
not change.
Increased equity requirements would No. Changing the
increase banks’ total funding costs, capital structure changes
It should not, because It should not, because it
because banks would be forced to use how risk is distributed No! It is false!
it is false. is false.
more equity, which has a higher but not the overall cost
required rate of return. of funding.
Increased equity requirements would Perhaps, but this No! Tax shields subsidize the use of
Yes, because
decrease the size of the interest tax depends on their debt, but it makes no sense to
Yes. shareholders benefit
shields banks can obtain through debt compensation and encourage leverage since it generates
from subsidies.
financing. preferences. negative externalities and distortions.
Increased equity requirements reduce No! Guarantees subsidize the use of
Yes, because
banks’ ability to use cheap debt Yes if compensation is debt, but it makes no sense to encourage
Yes. shareholders benefit
financing that is subsidized by implicit related to equity value. leverage since it generates negative
from subsidies.
government guarantees. externalities and distortions.
It should not, because
Increased equity requirements would No! Claims that debt disciplines
there are alternative
reduce managerial discipline and thus Very unlikely to be true. No. managers are not supported by adequate
ways to create effective
interfere with effective governance. theories or by empirical evidence.
governance.
No! Better capitalized banks have more
Increased equity requirements would
retained earnings for lending; any
lead banks to restrict lending if they
Possibly true. Perhaps. Perhaps. negative impact of equity issuance or
perceive their equity to be under-
payout restrictions can be mitigated by
valued.
reducing banks’ discretion.
54
References
1) Acharya, Viral V., Irvind Gujral, and Hyun Song Shin (2009) “Dividends and Bank Capital
in the Financial Crisis of 2007-2009,” Working paper.
2) Acharya, Viral V., Philipp Schnabl, and Gustavo Suarez (2010) “Securitization without
Risk Transfer,” Working paper.
3) Acharya, Viral V., Hamid Mehran, and Anjan Thakor (2010) “Caught between Scylla and
Charybdis? Regulating Bank Leverage when there is Rent Seeking and Risk Shifting,”
Working paper.
4) Admati, Anat R. and Paul Pfleiderer (2010), “Increased Liability Equity: A Proposal to
Improve Capital Regulation of Large Financial Institutions,” working paper.
5) Adrian, Tobias and Hyun Song Shin (2010), “Liquidity and Leverage,” Journal of
Financial Intermediation, 19, 418-437.
6) Adrian, Tobias and Markus K. Brunnermeier (2009), “CoVaR.” Federal Reserve Bank of
New York Staff Report 348.
7) Angeletos, George-Marios, and Iván Werning (2006), “Crises and Prices: Information
Aggregation, Multiplicity, and Volatility,” American Economic Review 96, 1720-1736.
8) Bank of Canada (2010), “Strengthening International Capital and Liquidity Standards: A
Macroeconomic Impact Assessment for Canada.”
9) Banyi, Monica, Susan Porter, and Susan Williams (2010), “Stock Repurchases and TARP
in the Banking Industry,” Working paper.
10) Basel Committee on Banking Supervision (BIS, 2009), “Strengthening the Resilience of
the Banking Sector.”
11) Basel Committee on Banking Supervision (BIS, 2010), “An Assessment of the Long-Term
Economic Impact of Stronger Capital and Liquidity Requirements.”
12) Bebchuk, Lucian A., Alma Cohen, and Holger Spamann (2010), “The Wages of Failure:
Executive Compensation at Bear Stearns and Lehman 2000-2008,” Yale Journal of
Regulation, 27, 257-282.
13) Bebchuk, Lucian A. and Holger Spamann (2010), “The Wages of Failure: Executive
Compensation at Bear Stearns and Lehman 2000-2008,” Yale Journal of Regulation, 27,
257-282.
14) Berger, Allen N., Richard J. Herring, and Giorgio P. Szego (1995), “The Role of Capital in
Financial Institution,” Journal of Banking and Finance, 19, 393-430.
15) Berger, Allen N., and Christa H.S. Bouwman (2010), “Bank Capital, Survival, and
Performance around Financial Crises,” working paper.
16) Berk, Jonathan and Peter M. DeMarzo (2008), “Corporate Finance,” Prentice Hall.
17) Bhagat, Sanjai and Brian Bolton (2010), “Investment Bankers’ Culture of Wonership?”
Working paper.
55
18) Bizer, David and Peter M. DeMarzo (1992), “Sequential Banking,” Journal of Political
Economy 100, 41-61.
19) Bolton, Patrick and Xavier Freixas (2006), “Corporate Finance and the Monetary
Transmission Mechanism,” Review of Financial Studies, 19, 829-870.
20) Bolton, Patrick, Tano Santos and Jose Scheinkman (2010), “Outside and Inside Liquidity,”
Quarterly Journal of Economics, forthcoming.
21) Bolton, Patrick, Hamid Mehran and Joel Shapiro (2010), “Executive Compensation and
Risk Taking,” working paper.
22) Boot, Arnoud W.A. (1996), “Comments on “Market Structure, Monitoring and Capital
Adequacy Regulation” by Thomas Gehrig”, Swiss Journal of Economics and Statistics,
132, 703-706
23) Boot, Arnoud W.A. and Anjolein Schmeits (1998), “Challenges to competitive banking: a
theoretical perspective,” Research in Economics (1998) 52, 255–270.
24) Boskin, Michael J. (2010), “Time to Junk the Corporate Tax,” The Wall Street Journal,
May 6, 2010.
25) Brealey, Richard A., Stewart C. Myers, and Franklin Allen (2007), “Principles of
Corporate Finance,” 9th Edition, McGraw-Hill Irwin.
26) Brealey, Richard A. (2006), “Basel II: The Route Ahead or Col-de-sac?,” Journal of
Applied Corporate Finance, 4, 34-43.
27) Brunnermeier, Markus and Martin Ohemke, (2010), “The Maturity Rat Race,” Working
paper.
28) Calomiris, Charles W. (1999), “Building an Incentive Compatible Safety Net,” Journal of
Banking & Finance, 23, 1499-1519.
29) Calomiris, Charles W. and Gary Gorton (1991), “The Origins of Banking Panics,” in: G.
Hubbard (ed.), Financial Markets and Financial Crises, University of Chicago Press,
Chicago, 109-173
30) Calomiris, Charles W. and Charles M. Kahn (1991), “The Role of Demandable Debt in
Structuring Optimal Banking Arrangements,” American Economic Review, 81, 497-513.
31) Chari, Varadarajan V., and Ravi Jagannathan (1988), “Banking Panics, Information, and
Rational Expectations Equilibrium,” Journal of Finance 43, 749-760.
32) Cheng, Ing-Haw and Konstantin Milbradt (2010), “The Hazards of Debt: Rollover Freezes,
Incentives, and Bailouts,” Working paper
33) Dewatripont M, and Jean Tirole (1994), "A Theory of Debt and Equity: Diversity of
Securities and Manager-Share-holder Congruence,” Quarterly Journal of Economics, 109,
1027-1054.
34) Diamond, Douglas W., and Phillip H. Dybvig (1983), “Bank Runs, Deposit Insurance, and
Liquidity,” Journal of Political Economy 91, 401-419.
56
35) Diamond, Douglas W., (1984) “Financial Intermediation and Delegated Monitoring,”
Review of Economic Studies 51, 193-414.
36) Diamond, Douglas W., and Raghuram G. Rajan (2000), “A Theory of Bank Capital,”
Journal of Finance, 55, 2431-2465.
37) Diamond, Douglas W., and Raghuram G. Rajan (2001), “Liquidity Risk, Liquidity Creation
and Financial Fragility,” Journal of Political Economy 109, 287-327.
38) Duffie, Darrell (2010), “How Big Banks Fail and What to Do About It,” Princeton
University Press, forthcoming.
39) Elliott, Douglas J. (2009), “Bank Capital and the Stress Tests,” Working paper.
40) Flannery, Mark J. (2005), “No Pain, No Gain? Effecting Market Discipline via Reverse
Convertible Debentures,” Chapter 5 of Hall S. Scott, ed. Capital Adequacy Beyond Basel:
Banking Securities and Insurance, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
41) French, Kenneth R., et al. (2010), “The Squam Lake Report: Fixing the Financial System,”
Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ.
42) Gale, Douglas M. and Martin F. Hellwig (1985), “Incentive-Compatible Debt Contracts:
The One-Period Problem,” Review of Economic Studies 52, 647-663.
43) Goldstein, Itay, and Ady Pauzner (2005), “Demand-Deposit Contracts and the Probability
of Bank Runs,” Journal of Finance 60, 1293-1327.
44) Gorton, Gary B (2010), Slapped by the Invisible Hand: The Panic of 2007, Oxford
University Press.
45) Gorton, Gary B. and George Pennacchi (1990), “Financial Intermediation and Liquidity
Creating,” Journal of Finance, 49-71.
46) Gorton, Gary B. and Andrew Metrick (2009), “Securitized banking and the run on repo,”
NBER Working Paper No. 15223.
47) Goodhart, Charles (2010), “How Should We Regulate the Financial Sector?” Chapter 5 of
The Future of Finance, LSE.
48) Goodhart, Charles, M. U. Peiris, D.P. Tsomocos, and A. P. Vardoulakis (2010), “On
Dividend Restrictions and the Collapse of the Interbank Market,” Annals of Finance,
February.
49) Graham, John R., and Campbell Harvey (2002), “How do CFOs Make Capital Budgeting
and Capital Structure Decisions,” Journal of Applied Corporate Finance, Spring, pp. 8-23.
50) Grossman, Sanford J., and Oliver D. Hart (1980), “Takeover Bids, the Free-Rider Problem,
and the Theory of the Corporation,” Bell Journal of Economics 11, 42-64.
51) Haldane, Andrew G. (2009), “Banking on the State,” Presented at the Federal Reserve
Bank of Chicago 12th Annual International Banking Conference, September 25, 2009.
52) Haldane, Andrew, Simon Brennan and Vasileios Madouros (2010), “What is the
Contribution of the Financial Sector: Miracle or Mirage?” Chapter 2 of The Future of
Finance, LSE.
57
53) Hanson, Samuel, Anil K. Kashyap, and Jeremy C. Stein (2010), “A Macroprudential
Approach to Financial Regulation,” Journal of Economic Perspectives, Forthcoming.
54) Harrison, Ian (2004), “Banks, Capital and Regulation: Towards an Optimal Capital Regime
for a Small Open Economy,” Working paper, Reserve Bank of New Zealand.
55) Hart, Oliver and Luigi Zingales (2010), “A New Capital Regulation for Large Financial
Institutions,” Working paper.
56) He, Zhiguo and Wei Xiong (2009), “Dynamic Debt Runs,” Working paper.
57) Hellwig, Christian (2002), “Public Information, Private Information, and the Multiplicity of
Equilibria in Coordination Games,” Journal of Economic Theory 107, 191-222
58) Hellwig, Martin F. (2009a), “A Reconsideration of the Jensen-Meckling Model of Outside
Finance,” Journal of Financial Intermediation 18, 495-525.
59) Hellwig, Martin F. (2009b), “Systemic Risk in the Financial Sector: An Analysis of the
Subprime-Mortgage Financial Crisis,” De Economist, 157, pp 129-207
60) Hellwig, Martin F. (2010), “Capital Regulation: Business as Usual?” Working paper.
61) Holmström, Bengt, and Jean Tirole (1993), “Market Liquidity and Performance
Monitoring,” Journal of Political Economy 101, 678-709.
62) Holtfrerich, Carl-Ludwig (1981): “Die Eigenkapitalausstattung deutscher Kreditinstitute
1871-1945,” Bankhistorisches Archiv, Beiheft 5, 15-29.
63) Institute of International Finance (IIF, 2010) “Interim Report on the Cumulative Impact on
the Global Economy of Proposed Changes in the Banking Regulatory Framework.”
64) Jacklin, Charles J., and Sudipto Bhattacharya (1988), “Distinguishing Panics and
Information-Based Bank Runs: Welfare and Policy Implications,” Journal of Political
Economy 96, 568-592.
65) Jensen, Michael C. (1986), “Agency Costs of Free Cash Flow, Corporate Finance and
Takeovers,” American Economic Review, Papers and Proceedings 76, 323-329.
66) Jensen, Michael C. (1989), “Eclipse of the Public Corporation,” Harvard Business Review,
September-October 1989, 61-74.
67) Jensen, Michael C. (1993), “The Modern Industrial Revolution, Exit, and the Failure of
Internal Control Systems,” Journal of Finance 48, 831-880.
68) Jensen, Michael C. and William H. Meckling (1976), “Theory of the Firm: Managerial
Behavior, Agency Costs and Capital Structure,” Journal of Financial Economics 3, 305-
360.
69) Kane, Edward J. (1989), “The S & L Insurance Mass, How Did It Happen?” Urban
Institute Press, Washington.
70) Kashyap, Anil K., Raghuram G. Rajan, and Jeremy C. Stein (2008), “Rethinking Capital
Regulation,” September 2008, Federal Reserve Bank of Kansas City Symposium.
58
71) Kashyap, Anil K., Jeremy C. Stein, and Samuel Hanson (2010), “An Analysis of the
Impact of “Substantially Heightened” Capital Requirements on Large Financial
Institutions,” Working Paper.
72) King, Mervyn (1990),”International Harmonisation of the Regulation of Capital Markets:
An Introduction,” European Economic Review, 34, 569-577.
73) Mankiw, Gregory N., Matthew C. Weinzierl, and Danny Yagan (2009), “Optimal Taxation
in Theory and Practice,” Harvard Business School Working paper.
74) Mehran, Hamid and Anjan Thakor (2010, “Bank Capital and Value in the Cross Section,”
Review of Financial Studies, forthcoming.
75) Kotlikoff, Laurence J. (2010), “Jimmy Stuart is Dead: Ending the World’s Financial
Plague Before it Strikes Again,” John Wiley & Sons, Inc.
76) McDonald, Robert L. (2010), “Contingent Capital with a Dual Price Trigger,” Working
paper.
77) Miller, Merton H. (1995), “Does the M&M Proposition Apply to Banks?” Journal of
Banking and Finance, 19, 483-489.
78) Modigliani, Franco and Merton H. Miller, (1958), “The Cost of Capital, Corporation
Finance, and the Theory of Investment” American Economic Review, 48, 261-297.
79) Morris, Stephen, and Hyun Song Shin (1998), “Unique Equilibrium in a Model of Self-
Fulfilling Currency Attacks,” American Economic Review 88, 587-597.
80) Myers, Stewart C. (1977), “Determinants of Corporate Borrowing,” Journal of Financial
Economics 5, 147-175.
81) Myers, Stewart C. and Nicholas S. Majluf (1984), “Corporate Finance and Investment
Decisions When Firms Have Information that Investors Do Not Have,” Journal of
Financial Economics 13, 187-222.
82) Myers, Stewart C. and Raghuram G. Rajan (1998), “The Paradox of Liquidity,” Quarterly
Journal of Economics 113, 733-771.
83) Ooi, Joseph T. L., Seow-Eng Ong, and Lin Li (2008), “An Analysis of the Financing
Decisions of REITs: The Role of Market Timing and Target Leverage,” Journal of Real
Estate Finance and Economics, 40, 130-160.
84) Poole, William, (2009), “Moral Hazard: The Long-Lasting Legacy of Bailouts,” Financial
Analysts Journal, Nov/Dec, 1-7.
85) Pennacchi, George, Theo Vermaelen and Christian C.P. Wolff (2010), “Contingent Capital:
The case for COERCs,” Working paper.
86) Poole, William, (2010), “Ending Moral Hazard,” Financial Analysts Journal, Nov/Dec, 17-
24
87) Pozsar, Zoltan, Tobias Adrian, Adam B. Ashcraft, and Haley Boeskey (2010), “Shadow
Banking,” Federal Reserve Bank of New York Staff Report 458.
59
88) Rochet, J-C., and Xavier Vives (2004), “Coordination Failure and the Lender of the Last
Resort: Was Bagehot Right After All?” Journal of the European Economic Association 2,
1116-1147.
89) Ross, Stephen A., Randolph W. Westerfield, and Jeffrey Jaffe (2008), “Corporate
Finance,” 8th Edition, McGraw-Hill Irwin.
90) Schaefer, Stephen M. (1990), “The Regulation of Bank and Securities Firms,” European
Economic Review, 34, 587-597.
91) Schnabel, Isabel (2004), “The German Twin Crisis of 1931,” Journal of Economic History,
64, 822-871.
92) Schnabel, Isabel (2009), “The Role of Liquidity and Implicit Guarantees in the German
Twin Crisis of 1931,” Journal of International Money and Finance, 28, 1-25.
93) Stein, Jeremy C. (2010), “Monetary policy as financial-stability regulation,” Working
Paper, Harvard University.
94) Stiglitz, J. E. and A. W. Weiss (1981), “Credit Rationing in Markets with Imperfect
Information,” American Economic Review 71, 393-410.
95) Sundaresan, Suresh and Zhenyu Wang (2010), “Design of Contingent Capital with Stock
Price Trigger for Conversion,” Working paper.
96) Townsend, Robert M. (1979), “Optimal Contracts and Competitive Markets with Costly
State Verification,” Journal of Economic Theory 21, 265-293.
97) Turner, Adair (2010), “What do Banks do? Why do Credit Booms and Busts Occur and
What can Public Policy Do about it?” Chapter 1 of The Future of Finance, LSE.
98) White, Lawrence J. (1991), “The S&L Debacle: Public Policy Lessons for Bank and Thrift
Regulation,” Oxford University Press, New York.
60