Brock, Informed-Consent Textbook
Brock, Informed-Consent Textbook
Brock, Informed-Consent Textbook
Informed consent
21
24
Patient well-being
Clearly, the fundamental goal of the physician-patient rela-
tionship is to protect and promote the patient's health. Med-
ical care treats disease and thereby prevents, eliminates, or
ameliorates pain and suffering, disability and premature loss
of life. But given the great complexities and sophisticated
knowledge involved in such treatment, it is not immediately
clear why the patient's health is not best served by vesting
ultimate decision-making authority with the physician.
Whether a person is healthy or diseased, and what will most
effectively treat his or her disease, would seem to be "ob-
jective" matters about which well-trained experts such as
physicians can best decide. Patients, however, are often con-
fused, anxious, and fearful and as a result sometimes make
decisions not in their best interests. They sometimes refuse
clearly beneficial treatment, select treatment less efficacious
than others available, and fail to complete beneficial treat-
ments. Why then is the patient's well-being best promoted
by leaving ultimate decision-making authority with him or
her?
The answer lies in three key points: first, and least im-
portant, "health" is not a fully "objective" matter, invariant
between persons; second, medical criteria alone often do not
fully settle which treatment is correct or best for a given
medical condition, and third, the relative importance or value
of health as compared with other aspects of individual well-
being differs for different people.
In perhaps the great majority of cases what constitutes an
impairment to health is not controversial - major diseases
like cancer or diabetes, fractured limbs, serious infections,
and so forth. Because these diseases can have serious adverse
effects on an individual's normal functioning and even lead
to untimely death, it is largely uncontroversial that they are
25
27
Patient self-determination
The nature of self-determination. The other principal value
promoted by the informed-consent doctrine is patient self-
determination. A person's interest in self-determination re-
flects the common desire to make important decisions about
one's life oneself and according to one's own aims and val-
ues. Self-determination involves the capacities of individuals
to form, revise over time, and pursue a plan of life or con-
ception of their good. It is a broad concept applicable at both
the levels of decision and of action. Patients' exercise of self-
determination in the context of health care involves their
deciding which alternative treatment will best promote their
own particular goals and values. As I will discuss later, this
requires that they become informed about the nature and
28
29
31
32
33
34
35
Competence
The requirement that a patient be competent in order to give
binding consent is more complex than first appearances
might suggest. In some cases it is clear whether the patient
is competent. Some people are unable to participate in de-
cision making about their health care to any significant extent
36
37
38
39
41
42
Voluntariness
For the consent of a competent decision maker to be binding,
it must be voluntary or freely given. Consent that is obtained
as a result of coercion or duress, manipulation or undue
influence, is invalid and does not authorize treatment. An
43
44
45
affect their choice. For example, they are not told of alter-
native treatments to the one the physician prefers, or of sig-
nificant risks or side effects of a recommended treatment.
This clearly limits a patient's capacity to make an informed
choice that best fits his or her particular needs and values.
Manipulation can, however, be far more subtle than out-
right deception. For example, a physician's manner and tone
of voice can indicate whether a risk is one to worry about,
or whether a concern is justified. The way information is
presented can affect how the patient responds to it - for
example, "This treatment succeeds in two out of every five
cases" or "This treatment fails most of the time." In some
cases, there may be no fully "objective" or "neutral" form
in which necessary information can be conveyed. Neverthe-
less, it generally is possible to avoid putting information in
a form designed to change the patient's decision from what
it would have been with a sound understanding of the in-
formation. Such manipulation may be conceived as being
"for the patient's own good" and producing the "best" de-
cision. Or it may be used merely to avoid the more difficult
and time-consuming process of helping the patient clearly
understand the situation and how alternative courses of ac-
tion may or may not serve his aims and needs. But in the
former case it both infringes self-determination by denying
patients a sound understanding on which to base their choice
and fails to respect the extent to which people's own aims
and values determine what will best promote their own well-
being. In the latter case, although the outcome of patients'
decisions may not be different as a result of the manipulation,
the manipulation bypasses patients' own deliberative pro-
cesses and their self-determination is compromised, making
the decision not fully theirs.
None of this is to say that physicians should not make
treatment recommendations to patients who want those rec-
ommendations, or that such recommendations are inherently
manipulative. On the contrary, it is part of physicians' profes-
sional responsibility to make such recommendations avail-
able, and these recommendations naturally and reasonably
46
Informed understanding
The goal of the requirement that consent be informed is for
patients to achieve a sufficient understanding of their con-
dition and possible treatments so that they can make a sound
assessment of which treatment, if any, will best serve their
goals and values. It thereby permits an informed exercise of
self-determination and promotes a decision most in accord
with the patient's well-being. It is worth adding as an im-
portant practical matter that therapeutic benefits can accrue
from the patient's being well-informed (for example, in-
creased conformity to a treatment regimen), that the great
majority of patients want vital information about their treat-
ment,3 and that the lack of an adequate explanation of the
nature and purpose of a procedure is a major cause of refusals
of treatment by patients.4 Physicians sometimes conceive of
informed consent as principally requiring a disclosure of the
risks of treatment in order to protect themselves from legal
47
48
49
Legal policy
Here, as elsewhere in this essay, the focus is on the ethically
sound basis and nature of informed consent. There may be
good reason not to fully individualize the legal requirement
for disclosure because of the difficulty of establishing in lit-
igation, often taking place long after the event in question,
what the particular patient wanted to know. Doing so would
create an invitation for self-serving testimony by patients,
for whom a remote risk has eventuated in actual harm, that
50
52
NOTES
53
54