Eric Moses Gurevitch - The Epistemology of Difference
Eric Moses Gurevitch - The Epistemology of Difference
Eric Moses Gurevitch - The Epistemology of Difference
Abstract
Keywords
…
Published with license by Koninklijke Brill NV | doi:10.1163/25425552-12340042
© Eric Moses Gurevitch, 2023 | ISSN: 2542-5544 (print) 2542-5552from
Downloaded (online)
Brill.com 10/10/2023 06:11:09PM
via Open Access. This is an open access article distributed under the terms
This is an open access article distributed under the terms of the CC BY 4.0 license. of the CC BY 4.0 license.
https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/
2 10.1163/25425552-12340042 | Gurevitch
⸪
The Question of Caste
In May 1068, a reservoir in the Cāḷukya domains needed mending. This particu-
lar reservoir had proven to be a continual source of trouble for the agricultural
community at Bāḷguḷi that depended on the water collected and distributed
from it.2 Like many similar waterworks, the “great reservoir” at Bāḷguḷi was at
risk of silting and breaches. Periodic dredging and repairs were necessary, and
these were largely funded through local revenue sources approved by the cen-
tral Cāḷukya bureaucracy. At times these funds were sourced from local tolls.
At times they were redirected from local taxes demanded by the Cāḷukya court.
And in 1068, the funds were secured through a complex transaction initiated
by one Mahādevayya, a transaction that turned caste differences into a mon-
etary vehicle. Mahādevayya purchased the rights to revenue from the leases
of sharecropping, oppressed-caste Śūdras—this is the term the inscription
uses—from local, land-owning Brahmins. He then donated this revenue to the
upkeep of the reservoir. In exchange, the town elders granted Mahādevayya a
gift of the taxes placed on the oppressed-caste barber community. The steady
stream of revenue extracted by Brahmin landowners from Śūdra sharecrop-
pers was redirected by state apparatuses and kept the water flowing in the
inland Deccan plateau. Disputes over water could quickly turn violent.3 And
caste was one of the many ways in which resources and rights were allocated
and contested in medieval India.4 Caste—to borrow a phrase—mattered.5
Philosophy also mattered in western India. Starting in the 11th century,
philosophers came to serve important roles—both administrative and
intellectual—in the chancelleries supported by the Western Cāḷukya and
Paramāra courts. (fig. 1) Their names were inscribed in stone, and they became
the topic of donative inscriptions attached to public-works projects. And caste
mattered for these philosophers. They used their privileged court positions to
author long philosophical texts, and they invariably took up the topic of the
epistemology of caste.
This article follows the careers and arguments of three Jain philosophers:
Vādirāja, who was employed in the Western Cāḷukya court of King Jayasiṃha II
(r. 1015–1042); Prabhācandra, who was employed in the Paramāra courts of
King Bhoja (r. 1010–1055) and Jayasiṃhadeva (r. 1055–1070); and Anantavīrya,
a philosopher from a generation earlier, whom Vādirāja and Prabhācandra
followed. All three expanded on the interventions of Akalaṅka (c.770), a
scholar who rewrote Jain philosophy by putting it into conversation with other
schools of thought.6 These philosophers brought technical epistemology into
new contexts. “In the royal court,” a Kannada inscription from 1147 explains,
“Vādirāja’s pastime was achieving victory over the throngs of haughty people,
and Emperor Jayasiṃha’s pastime was composing records of victory to give to
3 See for instance Epigraphia Carnatica, vol. 5, pt. 1, Hassan Taluq, no. 34, which records a mur-
der over water-rights and subsequent arbitration also during the reign of Jayasiṃha II.
4 The complex way caste fit into other regional divisions of power is detailed in Cynthia Talbot,
“A Revised View of ‘Traditional’ India: Caste, Status, and Social Mobility in Medieval Andhra,”
South Asia 15, no. 1 (1992): 17–52. For a discussion of caste-disputes in inscriptions from this
period, see J. Dunncan M. Derrett, “Two Inscriptions Concerning the Status of Kammalas and
the Application of Dharmasastra,” in Professor K.A. Nilakanta Sastri Felicitation Volume, ed.
Saw Ganesan et al. (Madras: Prof. K.A. Nilakanta Sastri Felicitation Committee, 1971), 32–55
and more broadly Burton Stein, Peasant, State, and Society in Medieval South India (Delhi:
Oxford University Press, 1980).
5 See Surinder S. Jodhka, “The Problem: Introduction to Caste Matters, A Symposium on
Inequalities, Identities and Disintegrating Hierarchies in India,” Seminar, no. 633 (2012) and
now Suraj Yengde, Caste Matters (Gurgaon: India Viking, 2019).
6 On Akalaṅka, see Piotr Balcerowicz, “Siddhasena Mahāmati and Akalaṅka Bhaṭṭa: A Revo‑
lution in Jaina Epistemology,” Journal of Indian Philosophy 44 (2016): 993–1039 and Nagin
J. Shah, Akalaṅka’s Criticism of Dharmakīrti’s Philosophy (Ahmedabad: L.D. Institute of
Indology, 1967).
him.”7 King Bhoja, an inscription from 1115 says, bowed down to Prabhācandra,
thus anointing his feet with the red rays of light that shown from the gems
embedded in his crown.8 As these philosophers brought Jain epistemology to
the courtly stage, references to Akalaṅka and quotations from his work began
to be used in inscriptions appended to monuments, grants and charters across
the Deccan.9
That these philosophers chose to write about the epistemology of caste was
no accident. They wrote at a time when Jains claiming to be Brahmins were on
the rise.10 And there were intellectual precedents for the turn to caste in these
11 Vincent Eltschinger, Caste and Buddhist Philosophy, trans. Raynald Prévéreau (Delhi:
Motilal Banarsidass Publishers, 2012), 127. Also see Prabal Kumar Sen, “Caste in Classical
Indian Philosophy: Some Ontological Problems,” in Classical Buddhism, Neo-Buddhism
and the Question of Caste, ed. Pradeep P. Gokhale (London: Routledge, 2020), 40–64.
12 I take this formulation from Ian Hacking, Representing and Intervening (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1983), 22–38.
13 The literature comprising these 20th-century disputes is massive. See especially, Arjun
Appadurai, “Is Homo Hierarchicus?,” American Ethnologist 13, no. 4 (1986): 745–61;
Bernard S. Cohn, “The Census, Social Structure and Objectification in South Asia,” in An
Anthropologist among the Historians and Other Essays (Delhi: Oxford University Press,
1990), 233–38; Ronald Inden, Imagining India (Bloomington: Indiana University Press,
1990); Nicholas B. Dirks, Castes of Mind: Colonialism and the Making of Modern India
(Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2001); Thomas R. Metcalf, Ideologies of the Raj
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994); Susan Bayly, Caste, Society and Politics in
India from the Eighteenth Century to the Modern Age (Cambridge, England: Cambridge
University Press, 1999). Scholarly debates about the colonial construction of caste have
been put to both emancipatory as well as revanchist uses, being used to critique the colo-
nial order as well as to deny its continued reality into the post-colonial period. See Mosse,
David. “Outside Caste? The Enclosure of Caste and Claims to Castelessness in India and
the United Kingdom.” Comparative Studies in Society and History 62, no. 1 (2020): 4–34.
14 Anand Teltumbde, The Persistence of Caste (London: Zed Books, 2010).
traded on the argument that his opponents held patently absurd positions that
led to nonsense. He was impossible for later philosophers to ignore, in part
because of his reformulation of the fundamental building-blocks of epistemol-
ogy, and in part because he was able to get under the skin of those he disagreed
with. And Dharmakīrti’s jokes provide a useful entry point to understanding
how critiques of caste were connected with arguments about the Vedas and
the Sanskrit language.
These jokes would sometimes come at the expense of Jains. The Jain doc-
trine of ontological perspectivism provided Dharmakīrti with an opportunity
to demonstrate the ethical implications of his epistemological arguments. In
one of his most heated exchanges, Dharmakīrti mocked the “shameless” Jains
for espousing a perspectival theory of reality in which things can be under-
stood in multiple manners.15 This perspectival view of reality argues that we
can ascribe seemingly contradictory characteristics to the same phenom-
enon based on the circumstances and our point of view. But if things are as
the Jains say and—in some sense—both different from as well as identical
to each other, Dharmakīrti quipped, then what would stop someone who
is told to “eat yoghurt” from chasing after a camel?16 Akalaṅka and the Jain
epistemologists who followed him took umbrage at Dharmakīrti’s character-
ization of Jain perspectival ontology, arguing that the doctrine of ontological
perspectivism does not mean that anything goes. Commenting on Akalaṅka’s
rebuttal of Dharmakīrti, Vādirāja could hardly contain his disdain, writing that
“Dharmakīrti is here speaking about Jain philosophy without understanding
it, and so he is known as a clown. Because it is established that someone who
criticizes an opponent’s position without understanding it is a clown.”17
But the post-Akalaṅka Jain epistemologists would not shy away from using
Dharmakīrti’s jokes for themselves when it came to critiquing other schools
of thought. In particular, Anantavīrya, Vādirāja and Prabhācandra would all
appropriate a joke regarding dog-flesh that Dharmakīrti made at the expense
of Brahmins who venerated the Vedas. This critique of the Veda—together
It is not the case that the Veda, which is liable to be changed by other
people, loudly proclaims—slapping its knee—“This is my form! This is
my meaning!” If both the Veda and its meaning were determined in and
Vādirāja’s goal was to trap the Mīmāṃsā philosopher into admitting that
either the Veda is not eternal—since, if it were, it would be impossible for
a human being to distort it—or admitting that the entire Mīmāṃsā herme-
neutic project is pointless. The Mīmāṃsā philosopher Kumārila (c.660) was
wrong, Vādirāja argued, to say that “if there were any distortion of the Veda, it
would be removed by many people.”22 Such a statement failed on two counts.
First, it was flawed from an ontological viewpoint, since it implies that the
Veda could possibly be changed, since humans are only capable of changing
things that are impermanent. But Kumārila’s statement was also flawed from
an epistemological viewpoint. There is no way of assessing different claims to
unbroken traditions. After all, even the traditions of barbarians (mlecchādi)
could be considered authoritative on such lines, since they are accepted by
many people as being eternal.23
Vādirāja proceeded to bring the attack to the heart of the Mīmāṃsā proj-
ect by arguing that the Mīmāṃsā claim to an eternal meaning of the Veda is
disproven by the fact that different Mīmāṃsā philosophers disagree on the
meanings of Vedic passages. “Śabara considers the black magic of the Hawk
Sacrifice to be harmful, while Umbeka considers to be otherwise,” Vādirāja
argued, “How could that not be a contradiction in the meaning of the Veda?”24
Listing several disagreements among Mīmāṃsā philosophers, Vādirāja wrote
that “There are yet many other examples of differences in commentarial tradi-
tions. So how is it that one could know that a particular Vedic commentary
refers to true things, and not another?”25 The point was to bring into question
Author: In that case, even someone who has become a Buddhist is actu-
ally still a Brahmin.
Author: That is not the case. Because devotion to the Vedas exists even
in Śūdras.32
32 tadāpy asau brāhmaṇaḥ tadanupraveśe tu viparītaḥ iti cet | nanu kiṃ brāhmaṇatvaṃ
naṣṭam? tathā cet; na nityaṃ sāmānyam iti karkamadhyam adhyāsīno muṇḍo na gauḥ
syāt | atha na naṣṭam; tadanupraveśe ’pi brāhmaṇa eva | vede bhaktyabhāvān neti cet | kiṃ
tadbhaktir eva brāhmaṇyam, anyad vā? prathamapakṣe na tat sāmānyam jñānaviśeṣatvāt
tasyāḥ | tathā ca suptādyavasthasya vyāpādane ’pi na brahmahatyādidoṣaḥ | dvitīyapakṣe
tadabhāve ’pi tadavasthaṃ tad iti sa eva doṣaḥ | atha tadbhaktyā sa eva jñāpyate | na; śudre
’pi tadbhāvāt | Anantavīrya, Siddhiviniścayaṭīkā, 515.
for the epistemology of caste. This terrain had earlier been delimited by the
Mīmāṃsā philosopher Kumārila.33 Kumārila rejected definitions of caste based
on physical appearance or behavior, but still argued that caste is cognizable
as a class category that is inherent in individuals. A class category—Kumārila
argued—can be recognized on account of a person’s lineage. He wrote:
33 See the discussion on genealogy being the sole criterion of cognizing caste in Wilhelm.
Halbfass, Tradition and Reflection: Explorations in Indian Thought (Albany, NY: State
University of New York Press, 1991), 368–71.
34 yathaiva tulyaśiraḥpāṇyādyākāreṣv api saṃkīrṇalokadṛṣṭigrāhyeṣu brāhmaṇādiṣu mātā‑
pitṛsambandhasmaraṇād eva varṇavivekāvadhāraṇaṃ bhavati, tathā sādhuśabdāvadh‑
āraṇam apīti lokavirodhābhaḥ | Kumārila, Tantravārttikam on Mīmāṃsāsūtram 1.3.25, on
p. 229.
35 Kumārila, Ślokavārttika, (Ākṛtivāda) 13.18.
Akalaṅka cut a path between the Scylla that is the Mīmāṃsā and Nyāya
notion of a class as a universal that pervades particular instances and the
Charybdis that is the Buddhist position that a class is a mental construct estab-
lished through the process of exclusion.36 For Akalaṅka and his followers, a
class category is not something that can be known through sampling individ-
ual manifestations, nor is it something that can be known through exclusion
of everything that is not included in the category. They denied the universal
nature of purported universals, arguing that a class category is not a singular,
pervasive and unchanging entity. And yet, they argued, the position developed
by the Buddhist philosophers Dignāga, Dharmakīrti and their followers over-
stated the case when they argued that a class category is nothing more than a
mental construction founded on exclusion.
In his summary of Akalaṅka’s philosophy, the Jain philosopher Māṇikya‑
nandin (c.950) built on Akalaṅka’s definition of class categories as similar
permutations and further divided them into “vertical” and “horizontal”—or
“diachronic” and “synchronic”—classes. Māṇikyanandin wrote that synchronic
classes are defined by being similar permutations, while diachronic classes are
a way of describing the substance that remains pervasive when something
undergoes successive changes.37 These distinctions would be utilized by both
Prabhācandra and Vādirāja in the eleventh century, and would also be repur-
posed to explicate the theory of exclusion by the Buddhist scholar Ratnakīrti
(c.1070), who was working at the Buddhist center of learning Vikramaśīla in
Bihar.38 These new tools for analyzing general classes provided epistemologists
with ways out of some of the problems that had plagued earlier theorists of
caste. But they would also present their own difficulties.
Prabhācandra’s critique of caste comes in both his Sun for the Blossoming
of the Lotuses of Realia (Prameyakamalamārtaṇḍa) and in his Moon for the
Blossoming of the Lily of Logic (Nyāyakumudacandra). Much of the argument
from the earlier Sun was repurposed in the Moon. And the argument—often
word-for-word—was quickly picked up by Vādideva, who wrote his Ocean
The point here is that direct perception prevents the foundation of the inference
of social class based on particular modes of conduct. The fallacy is twofold: On
the one hand, we can find people who would normally be defined as Brahmins
who do not engage in the particular modes of behavior supposedly associated
with them. On the other hand, we also can find people who would normally
be defined as non-Brahmins who engage in the modes of conduct supposedly
associated with Brahmins.42 And hence, any inference that would be founded
on such criteria would be both under-determined as well as over-extended.
“Indeed,” Prabhācandra wrote, “even a Śūdra can travel to a foreign-land and
either study or teach the Veda.”43 But such a person would not be accepted by
the Mīmāṃsaka interlocutor as a Brahmin. Modes of conduct turn out to be
poor criteria for establishing a social class, since everyday life is much more
complicated than such a schema would allow.
Prabhācandra argued that the broad use of the term “Brahmin” in every-
day language should be taken as a warning about the nature—or rather, the
non-existence—of abstracted social class categories. Once he had shown
that direct perception and inference cannot be used to cognize a social class,
Prabhācandra considered the argument that “there is a teaching regarding
the three dominant castes that is not disputed by scripture, and when that
is cognized, it is a means of valid knowledge for really existent things.”44
Prabhācandra did not argue against the possibility of learning from teachers.
But a teaching should correspond to natural kinds, and as such cannot be con-
tradicted by direct perception. And the sorts of teachings that dominant-caste
scholars invoked in defining Brahmin-ness cannot be shown to cover all cat-
egories. We cannot rely on such people to serve as authorities, since, “we can
observe many people who are conventionally designated by those who talk of
the three dominant castes with the term ‘Brahmin’ without any dispute, and
yet who live in a contrary manner.”45
Prabhācandra argued that the conventional use of language can lead people
astray by introducing categories that do not exist as natural kinds. But phi-
losophy must also be able to account for ordinary language. Prabhācandra
concluded his discussions of social class in both the Sun and the Moon with
reflections on the everyday usage of terms such as “Brahmin.” Philosophy
cannot deny the fact that everyday language is used by people to talk about
Brahmins as people who act in certain ways. But Brahmin-ness is not a philo-
sophically rigorous category, and we should not depend on it to extrapolate a
42 Six modes of conduct (ṣaṭkarman) were associated with being a Brahmin in the classic
Sanskrit legal texts. The locus classicus is Manusmṛti 10.75.
43 śūdro ’pi hi kaścid deśāntaraṃ gatvā vedaṃ paṭhati pāṭhayati vā | na tāvatāsya brāhma‑
ṇatvaṃ bhavadbhir abhyupagamyata iti | Prabhācandra, Prameyakamalamārtaṇḍa, 487.
44 etenāvigānatas traivarṇikopadeśo ’tra vastuni pramāṇam | Prabhācandra, Prameyakama‑
lamārtaṇḍa, 486.
45 dṛśyante hi bahavas traivarṇikair avigānena brāhmaṇatvena vyavahriyamāṇā viparyaya‑
bhājaḥ | Prabhācandra, Prameyakamalamārtaṇḍa, 486.
coherent class category. Philosophy can be used to probe the positive and neg-
ative concomitance of certain predicates. And through such means, it can be
used to show that everyday appeals to caste are ultimately unreliable. So, while
everyday language allows for people to talk of “Brahmins,” rigorous analysis
should prevent people from talking of “Brahmin-ness” as a natural kind. This
conclusion came in a complex exchange with the hostile interlocutor:
Author: That too is not a proper objection. Because the social order of
the castes and life-stages as well as the everyday practice of performing
austerities and giving gifts is established with regards to a particular indi-
vidual who is characterized by marks such as particular actions and being
endowed with the sacred thread. But Brahmin-ness, which has been con-
structed by you—my interlocutor—as an essence that is eternal, etc. is
not established from any means of valid knowledge. And so, the every-
day talk about Brahmins, etc., which is exclusively founded on particular
activities, is proper.46
After arguing that the social class of Brahmin-ness cannot be founded on a par-
ticular mode of conduct, Prabhācandra was forced to clarify his position. His
denial of the reality of Brahmin-ness as a class category should not be taken
as a denial of social distinctions. Brahmins exist. Caste can have real effects in
the world even if its ontological status is unreal. Prabhācandra did not deny
that people in the world go around talking about Brahmins, and when pressed,
define them through a set of activities. To deny these realties is not something
that philosophy can do. But philosophy can show that such usage is not rig-
orous, and that it does not refer to some eternal nature found in Brahmins.
Philosophy can show that doubts will inevitably arise with the everyday talk
about social class. And philosophy can be used to reassess prevalent regimes
of evidence.
Brahmin-ness was used in this argument to solve a problem that arose in the
wake of Akalaṅka. If a class cannot be known through sampling—that is, if
the repeated observation “this is a Brahmin, and this is a Brahmin” is insuf-
ficient to establish a class—it becomes difficult to determine what actually
that holds a class together. And if they rejected the Buddhist notion of exclu-
sion and the Mīmāṃsā notion of pervasion as definitional of a class category,
it remained a problem for Prabhācandra and other post-Akalaṅka thinkers
to demonstrate how similarity can be determined. Their definition of class
categories hinged on the notion of “similar permutations.” Similarity is not
quite identity, and it cannot be expressed as a shared quality that is found in
each individual. As such, it risks becoming a sort of black-box, something that
cannot be investigated any further. And there is the possibility of an infinite
regress, because one might be compelled to ask whether there is a similarity for
all similarities and how that could possibly be cognized. Prabhācandra denied
the basis of this question and argued that not all similarities are alike. It was at
this moment that the question of caste became epistemologically important,
and Prabhācandra used it to distance himself from the earlier Buddhist phi-
losophers he followed for much of his arguments.
If the Buddhist in Prabhācandra’s account opened by saying that all class
categories are unreal—like sky-lotuses or the horn of a donkey—Prabhācandra
went on to argue that class categories are really-existing things, albeit not eter-
nal essences distinct from particular instances. And yet some class categories
that are commonly taken to be real are not. The Buddhist argument that any-
thing expressible in language is a conceptual construction is too broad, and it
fails to distinguish between different sorts of classes for things in the world.
Brahmin-ness is one of those class categories that is as unreal as sky-lotuses.
But not all class categories are unreal. When asking questions about concep-
tual construction, it is most important to ask the question of what exactly is
being described as constructed. Asking “the construction of what?” will make
all the difference.47 Not all conceptual constructions are alike. Caste, follow-
ing Prabhācandra’s general discussion of classes, came to serve as a test-case
47 I take this phrasing from Ian Hacking, The Social Construction of What? (Cambridge, Mass:
Harvard University Press, 1999).
to probe the limits of the notion of similarity. The question of caste became a
question of identity in the literal sense—it became a question of what counts
as “the same” across a set of individuals who are irreducibly diverse.
In his discussion of the question of caste, the Buddhist philosopher
Dharmakīrti made a provisional distinction between natural and linguistic
differences that he later would nuance in making his larger arguments about
conventional and ultimate reality.48 In posing the question of the efficacy of
mantras, Dharmakīrti argued that “there is not a natural difference between
people, who may be given the titles ‘Śūdra’ or ‘Brahmin.’ Indeed, real objects,
which adhere to natural distinctions, do not become different because of
a nominal distinction of ordinary language, which depends on people’s
intentions.”49 On the other hand, a natural distinction, Dharmakīrti would go
on to argue, “can be observed when there is a difference in terms of form, quali-
ties, or capacity, as in the case of the difference between cows and horses. And
ordinary people cognize it without the assistance of a teaching.”50
It would seem here—and Dharmakīrti would elsewhere problematize this
distinction—that there are some sorts of class categories that are founded
on linguistic conventions and some that arise naturally in human cognition.
The necessity of instruction to convey a class category would, in this view,
serve as a criterion by which to distinguish linguistic from natural divisions.
Ultimately, for Dharmakīrti, all such class distinctions should be consid-
ered unreal, and the question of how to distinguish between different sorts
of non-existing entities would become a heated topic of debate among later
Buddhist philosophers—most prominently Prajñākaragupta.51 This discus-
sion was picked up by epistemologists with Jain commitments, who built
upon Buddhist arguments to deny many sorts of classes without accepting the
Buddhist conclusion that all classes are ultimately unreal.
48 See the recent debate over the “hierarchy of discourses” found in Dharmakīrti’s writing in
Dan Arnold, “Buddhist Idealism, Epistemic and Otherwise: Thoughts on the Alternating
Perspectives of Dharmakīrti,” Sophia 47, no. 1 (2008): 3–28.
49 śūdraviprābhidhānayoḥ puruṣayoḥ svabhāvābhedāt | na hi puruṣecchānuvidhāyino nāmav‑
yavahārabhedāt svabhāvabhedānubandhinām arthānām anyathātvam asti | Dharmakīrti,
Auto-commentary on Pramāṇavārttikam 1.295. See the summary of the full argument in
Eltschinger, Caste and Buddhist Philosophy, 103–107.
50 sa khalv ākṛtiguṇaśaktibhede dṛṣṭo gāvāśvavat | anupadeśaṃ cainaṃ lokaḥ pratipadyate |
Dharmakīrti, Auto-commentary on Pramāṇavārttikam 1.295.
51 On this, see Eli Franco, “How to Distinguish between Non-Existing Entities? Dharmakīrti
and Prajñākaragupta on Universals as Objects of Knowledge,” Rocznik Orientalistyczny 65,
no. 1 (2012): 51–62 and Lawrence McCrea, “Prajñākaragupta on the Pramāṇas and Their
Objects,” in Religion and Logic in Buddhist Philosophical Analysis, ed. Helmut. Krasser
et al. (Wien: Verlag der Österreichischen Akademie der Wissenschaften, 2011), 319–28.
It is certainly not the case that the social class of Brahmin-ness can be
perceived through direct perception in an ordinary person—call him
“Devadatta”—in the manner in which cow-ness is defined by a similar-
ity in things such as cows-with-broken-horns and cows-without-horns.
Otherwise, there would be no such doubt as “is this person a Brahmin,
or are they something different?” And so, the teaching of things such as
family lineage is useless for the removal of that doubt. Indeed, the deter-
mination as to whether “is this a cow or is this a person?” is not dependent
on the teaching of things such as family lineages.52
Unlike a class category such as humanness or a quality like whiteness, the cat-
egory of Brahmin-ness is not perceptible without an additional teaching, and
so it cannot be counted as a natural kind. The class category of humanness is
manifested by the form of the hands, feet and other factors that people pos-
sess, a form that is distinct from the particular forms possessed by cows and
horses.55 But no such criterion can be conceived for Brahmins. Prabhācandra
here argued that it is linguistic convention that produces conceptions of social
class categories that are additional to the natural class category of being a
human. Following this appeal to conceptions, Prabhācandra’s hostile interloc-
utor asked, “How is it that there is such a recurring cognition that is attached
to the social class that is Brahmin-ness anywhere?”56 To which Prabhācandra
replied:
class category on its own, what would be the use of its being dependent on an
additional assisting factor?”60
Anantavīrya, Prabhācandra and Vādirāja—following Akalaṅka—all argued
that some class categories are real things that people can directly perceive. This
is because a component of any cognition is the cognition of similarity. And to
perceive similarity is to cognize a class category. This entails a class category
that is strikingly different from the universal of Mīmāṃsā or Nyāya. A class is
not an eternal essence that is separate from each particular and yet pervades
it. Rather, a class category is an aspect of any particular that is perceived. We
can know the reality of a class category through cognitions of similarity. But
this does not mean that a class is necessarily a mental projection. Some classes
are very real, for instance species and sex. Yet, some class categories are men-
tal projections. That is, some classes can only be cognized with the assistance
of an instruction. These classes are ultimately unreal. To distinguish between
these different types of conceptions is of utmost importance to a philosopher.
And the question of caste was the central site for Anantavīrya, Prabhācan‑
dra and Vādirāja to distinguish these different sorts of conceptions.
It is not, in the first instance, that that fact of one’s parents being
non-promiscuous is cognizable from direct perception, because it is
impossible for a normal person with limited vision to directly witness
an object of the form “this person was born from this mother and this
very father.” Nor is it cognizable from an inference. Because you—my
interlocutor—do not accept the possibility of an inference for something
that is not an object of direct perception. And an inference proceeds
from an inferential mark. And there isn’t any inferential mark for indicat-
ing the fact that one’s parents are non-promiscuous.63
This article opened by arguing that caste mattered and that caste was a
problem.65 Caste was made into a problem in different ways in the medi-
eval India, and as such it became a matter of concern for different sorts of
individuals. In one sense, caste was a material problem, a problem about the
64 sadaiva avalānāṃ kāmāturatayā iha janmany api vyabhicāropalambhāt anādau kāle tāḥ
kadā kiṃ kurvantīti brahmaṇāpi jñātum aśakyam | Prabhācandra, Nyāyakumudacandra,
773. Compare Prabhācandra, Prameyakamalamārtaṇḍa, 482.
65 In thinking about the historical coming into being of caste as epistemological and socio-
logical problems, I follow Viswanath, Rupa. The Pariah Problem: Caste, Religion, and the
Social in Modern India. Cultures of History. New York: Columbia University Press, 2014.
Downloaded from Brill.com 10/10/2023 06:11:09PM
via Open Access. This is an open access article distributed under the terms
JOURNAL OF SOUTH ASIAN INTELLECTUAL HISTORY ( 2023) 1–35 of the CC BY 4.0 license.
https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/
26 10.1163/25425552-12340042 | Gurevitch
regime to a biometric one.69 This was a moment in which caste was turned
into a statistical object, wherein standard deviation could be understood, to
use P.C. Mahalanobis’s evocative phrase, to describe “caste distances.” Initially
using specialized anthropometric tools and later using techniques conceived
to be less prone to observer intervention, such as blood sera and genomic
markers, this biometric regime—never hegemonic—was constructed on the
analogy of race and caste and used multiple practices in an attempt to stabilize
caste as an epistemic object.70
This biometric regime built on top of—but did not replace—early-modern
evidentiary regimes, the practices and values of which have been exten-
sively mapped by recent scholarship. This was a regime in which written
documents mattered and were used to assess the validity of claims to caste.71
Understanding how these evidentiary regimes operated has helped to show
the effects of colonial and post-colonial state interventions into the question
of caste.72 Collectively, these studies have shown how, as Rosalind O’Hanlon,
Gergely Hidas and Csaba Kiss have put it,
Caste was not a changeless system until the colonial ‘reinvention’ about
which so many scholars have written. Rather, the colonial state inherited
an order of varṇa and jāti marked by acute and still developing tensions,
69 Projit Bihari Mukharji, “Profiling the Profiloscope: Facialization of Race Technologies and
the Rise of Biometric Nationalism in Inter-War British India,” History and Technology 31,
no. 4 (2015): 376–96.
70 Projit Bihari Mukharji, “From Serosocial to Sanguinary Identities: Caste, Transnational
Race Science and the Shifting Metonymies of Blood Group B, India c. 1918–1960,” The
Indian Economic & Social History Review 51, no. 2 (2014): 143–76.
71 See especially Dayal, Subah, “Making the ‘Mughal’ Soldier: Ethnicity, Identification,
and Documentary Culture in Southern India, c. 1600–1700,” Journal of the Economic and
Social History of the Orient 62, no. 5–6 (2019): 856–924; O’Hanlon, Rosalind, “Letters
Home: Banaras Pandits and the Maratha Regions in Early Modern India,” Modern Asian
Studies 44, no. 2 (March 2010): 201–40; Peabody, Norbert, “Cents, Sense, Census: Human
Inventories in Late Precolonial and Early Colonial India,” Comparative Studies in Society
and History 43, no. 4 (October 2001): 819–50; and Cherian, Divya. Merchants of Virtue:
Hindus, Muslims, and Untouchables in Eighteenth-Century South Asia, 2022.
72 See Rosalind O’Hanlon, “Contested Conjunctures: Brahman Communities and ‘Early
Modernity’ in India,” The American Historical Review 118, no. 3 (2013): 765–87 and
Rosalind O’Hanlon, “Caste and Its Histories in Colonial India: A Reappraisal,” Modern
Asian Studies 51, no. 2 (2017): 432–61.
A spate of recent studies has shown exactly what this early-modern order was,
what types of evidence counted, and how disputes about caste were adjudi-
cated and enforced.74
The quarry I am after is slightly different and is one degree removed from
this important scholarship. What I have tried to emphasize in this article is
that this fact—the fact that there were different regimes by which to know
caste—was itself an object of scholarly inquiry in medieval South Asia. The
fact that there were different regimes by which to know caste was turned
into an object of scholarship by philosophers who sought to investigate the
conditions of possibility for making claims about caste. And, in the eleventh
century, the epistemological problem of caste was interrogated alongside the
socio-legal problem of caste.
In their discussions of what constitutes a means of valid knowledge, Vādirāja
and Prabhācandra rejected what they called the everyday conception of evi-
dence. They both cited a commonly accepted statement of legal procedure
that say that “evidence is said to be of three types: documents, witnesses, and
usufruct.”75 The locus classicus for this juridical understanding of evidence was
given in the Brahmanical Law Code of Yājñavalkya (Yājñavalkyasmṛti).76 By the
medieval period, variations on this statement were included in general guides
to politics produced in the Deccan such as Somadeva’s Ambrosia of Political
Discourse (Nītivākyāmṛtam).77 Both Vādirāja and Prabhācandra refuted this
juridical notion of evidence, arguing that it did not capture with precision
73 Rosalind O’Hanlon, Gergely Hidas, and Csaba Kiss, “Discourses of Caste over the Longue
Durée: Gopīnātha and Social Classification in India, ca. 1400–1900,” South Asian History
and Culture 6, no. 1 (January 2, 2015): 102–29, on p. 118.
74 In addition to the scholarship cited above, see Ananya Vajpeyi, “Śūdra Dharma and Legal
Treatments of Caste,” in Hinduism and Law: An Introduction, ed. Donald Davis, Timothy
Lubin, and Jayanth Krishnan (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2010), 154–66;
Samuel Wright, “History in the Abstract: ‘Brahman-Ness’ and the Discipline of Nyāya in
Seventeenth-Century Vārāṇasī,” Journal of Indian Philosophy 44, no. 5 (2016): 1041–69;
Sumit Guha, Beyond Caste (Leiden: Brill, 2013); and Christian Lee Novetzke, “The Brahmin
Double: The Brahminical Construction of Anti-Brahminism and Anti-Caste Sentiment
in the Religious Cultures of Precolonial Maharashtra,” South Asian History and Culture 2,
no. 2 (2011): 232–52.
75 likhitaṃ sākṣino bhuktiḥ pramāṇaṃ trividhaṃ smṛtam | Quoted in Vādirāja, Nyāyaviniś‑
cayavivaraṇam, vol. 1, p. 57; and Prabhācandra, Prameyakamalamārtaṇḍa, 8.
76 pramāṇaṃ likhitaṃ bhuktiḥ sākṣiṇaś ceti kīrtitam | Yājñavalkyasmṛti 2.22ab.
77 bhuktiḥ sākṣī śāsanaṃ pramāṇam | Somadeva, Nītivākyāmṛtam 28.9.
the definition of evidence. Documents are not enough. They cannot speak for
themselves. The philosopher and the jurist have different criteria for assessing
evidence, and philosophers can demonstrate the limits of juridical reasoning.
Despite this critique, in the subsequent century, Yājñavalkya’s Law Code
would find a place at the heart of the Western Cāḷukya court, through Vijñāneś‑
vara’s Concise Commentary (Mitākṣara), which served to retrench caste
orthodoxy and a documentary order of evidence.78 Vijñāneśvara’s Concise
Commentary went on to be used as the basis for much colonial property law,
serving as a foundation for assessing inheritance and familial lineages outside
of Bengal.79 And in discussing mixed-castes, the Brahmin jurist Vijñāneśvara
invoked the argument about natural kinds that we have seen in a manner at
odds with that of Anantavīrya, Vādirāja and Prabhācandra. He wrote that “just
as a cow is produced in a female cow because of a male cow, a horse is pro-
duced in a mare on account of a stallion, in the same manner, a Brahmin child
is produced in a Brahmin woman because of a Brahmin man.”80 Vijñāneśvara
admitted a distinction between cows and Brahmins, but for him the differ-
ence between these two sorts of classes was insignificant. He wrote that “while
species is understood by means of direct perception, the social classes such
as Brahmins are defined by scriptures, in accordance with what has been
recollected.”81 Vijñāneśvara and the Brahmin legal theorists like him drew a
divide between epistemology and ontology: Even though it takes different
ways of knowing to distinguish Brahmins and cows, they are coherent catego-
ries of the same sort. And texts point to the reality of Brahmin-ness.
It was precisely this regime of evidence that Vādirāja and Prabhācandra
refused. They denied that documentary evidence could ever provide socially
constructed categories such as caste the kind of validity their sectarian and
intellectual opponents required. But they did not deny that such claims
78 Whitney Cox, “Law, Literature, and the Problem of Politics in Medieval India,” in
Hinduism and Law, ed. Donald Davis, Timothy Lubin, and Jayanth Krishnan (New York:
Cambridge University Press, 2010), 167–82. For an opposing interpretation of this text,
see Jason Schwartz, “The King Must Protect the Difference: The Juridical Foundations of
Tantric Knowledge,” Religions 9, no. 4 (2018). Donald Davis has shown how Vijñāneśvara
follows the 9th-century jurist Medhātithi in his arguments. See, Davis, Donald R. “Seeing
through the Law: A Debate on Caste in Medieval Dharmaśāstra.” Contributions to Indian
Sociology 56, no. 1 (February 1, 2022): 17–40, on. p. 31.
79 Nandini Bhattacharya-Panda, Appropriation and Invention of Tradition (New Delhi: OUP
India, 2007).
80 yathā gor gavi gauḥ, aśvād vaḍavāyām aśvaḥ tasmād brāhmaṇād brāhmaṇyām utpanno
brāhmaṇa iti na viruddham | Vijñāneśvara, Mitakṣara, 65.
81 yatra pratyakṣagamyā jātir bhavati tatra tathā | brāhmaṇādijātis tu smṛtilakṣaṇā
yathāsmaraṇaṃ bhavati | Vijñāneśvara, Mitakṣara, 65.
were made and that they had very real effects in the world. Philosophy can-
not change how people normally talk. But it can change how people assess
evidence. Vādirāja and Prabhācandra—following Anantavīrya—used their
writing to bring different regimes of evidence into conflict with each other. In
so doing, they showed that there can never be a definitive way of fixing caste.
Acknowledgements
This paper would not have been possible without encouragement from
Pradeep Gokhale in philosophic matters. I thank Seema Chauhan, Whitney
Cox, Lorraine Daston, Pranathi Diwakar, Shireen Hamza, Anil Mundra,
Rosalind O’Hanlon, Andrew Ollett, Surabhi Pudasaini, Itamar Ramot, Samira
Sheikh, and Sarah Taylor for substantive discussions on the paper. Lawrence
McCrea provided corrections and suggestions on the final draft.
Bibliography
Primary Sources
Akalaṅka. Nyāyaviniścaya. In Akalaṅka, and Vādirājasūri. Nyāya Viniścaya Vivaraṇa of
Śrī Vādirāja Sūri the commentary on Bhaṭṭākalaṅkadeva’s Nyāya Viniścaya. Edited by
Mahendrakumāra Jaina. 2 vols. Benares: Bhāratīya Jñānpītha Kāshi, 1949.
Akalaṅka. Siddhiviniścaya. In Akalaṅka, and Anantavīrya. Siddhiviniścayaṭīkā. Edited
by Mahendrakumāra Jaina. 2 vols. Benares: Bhāratīya Jñānpītha Kāshi, 1959.
Anantavīrya. Siddhiviniścayaṭīkā. In Akalaṅka, and Anantavīrya. Siddhiviniścayaṭīkā.
Bhoja. Samarāṅgaṇasūtradhāra. Edited by T. Gaṇapati Śāstrī and Vasudeva Saran
Agrawala. Revised. Baroda: Oriental Institute of Baroda, 1966.
Dharmakīrti. The Pramāṇavārttikam of Dharmakīrti; the First Chapter with the Auto‑
commentary. Edited by Raniero Gnoli. Roma: Instituto italiano per il medio ed
estremo oriente, 1960.
Jayanta Bhaṭṭa. Āgamaḍambara otherwise called Ṣaṇmatanāṭaka. Edited by V. Ragha‑
van and Anantalal Thakur. Darbhanga: Mithila Institute, 1964.
Kumārila. Ślokavārttika. Edited by Dvārikādāsa Śāstri. Prāchyabhārati Series 10. Vara‑
nasi: Tara Publications, 1978.
Kumārila. Tantravārttika. Edited by Gaṅgādhara Śāstri. Benares Sanskrit Series.
Benares: The Benares Printing Press & the Vidya Vilas Press, 1903.
Māṇikyanandin. Parīkṣāmukha. In Prabhācandra. Prameyakamalamārtaṇḍa. Edited
by Mahendra Kumar Shastri. 2nd ed. Bombay: Satyabhamabai Pandurang, Nirnaya
Sagar Press, 1941.
Secondary Sources
Appadurai, Arjun. “Is Homo Hierarchicus?” American Ethnologist 13, no. 4 (1986):
745–61.
Arnold, Dan. “Buddhist Idealism, Epistemic and Otherwise: Thoughts on the Alterna‑
ting Perspectives of Dharmakīrti.” Sophia 47, no. 1 (2008): 3–28.
Arnold, Dan. “On Semantics and Saṃketa: Thoughts on a Neglected Problem with
Buddhist Apoha Doctrine.” Journal of Indian Philosophy 34, no. 5 (2006): 415–78.
Arnold, Daniel. “Of Intrinsic Validity: A Study on the Relevance of Pūrva Mīmāṃsā.”
Philosophy East and West 51, no. 1 (2001): 26–53.
Balcerowicz, Piotr. “How Could a Cow Be Both Synchronically and Diachronically
Homogenous, or On the Jaina Notions of Tiryak-Sāmānya and Ūrdhvatā-Sāmānya.”
In Approaches to Jaina Studies: Philosophy, Logic, Rituals and Symbols, edited by
N.K. Wagle and Olle Qvarnström, 211–37. Toronto: University of Toronto: Center for
South Asian Studies, 1999.
Balcerowicz, Piotr. “Is ‘Inexplicability Otherwise’ (Anyathânupapatti) Otherwise Inex-
plicable?” Journal of Indian Philosophy 31, no. 1/3 (2003): 343–80.
Metcalf, Thomas R. Ideologies of the Raj. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994.
Mosse, David. “Outside Caste? The Enclosure of Caste and Claims to Castelessness in
India and the United Kingdom.” Comparative Studies in Society and History 62, no. 1
(2020): 4–34.
Mukharji, Projit Bihari. “From Serosocial to Sanguinary Identities: Caste, Transnational
Race Science and the Shifting Metonymies of Blood Group B, India c. 1918–1960.”
The Indian Economic & Social History Review 51, no. 2 (2014): 143–76.
Mukharji, Projit Bihari. “Profiling the Profiloscope: Facialization of Race Technologies
and the Rise of Biometric Nationalism in Inter-War British India.” History and
Technology 31, no. 4 (2015): 376–96.
Novetzke, Christian Lee. “The Brahmin Double: The Brahminical Construction of
Anti-Brahminism and Anti-Caste Sentiment in the Religious Cultures of Precolonial
Maharashtra.” South Asian History and Culture 2, no. 2 (2011): 232–52.
O’Hanlon, Rosalind. “Caste and Its Histories in Colonial India: A Reappraisal.” Modern
Asian Studies 51, no. 2 (2017): 432–61.
O’Hanlon, Rosalind. “Contested Conjunctures: Brahman Communities and ‘Early
Modernity’ in India.” The American Historical Review 118, no. 3 (2013): 765–87.
O’Hanlon, Rosalind. “Letters Home: Banaras Pandits and the Maratha Regions in Early
Modern India.” Modern Asian Studies 44, no. 2 (2010): 201–40.
O’Hanlon, Rosalind, Gergely Hidas, and Csaba Kiss. “Discourses of Caste over the
Longue Durée: Gopīnātha and Social Classification in India, ca. 1400–1900.” South
Asian History and Culture 6, no. 1 (2015): 102–29.
O’Hanlon, Rosalind, and Christopher Minkowski. “What Makes People Who They Are?
Pandit Networks and the Problem of Livelihoods in Early Modern Western India.”
The Indian Economic & Social History Review 45, no. 3 (2008): 381–416.
Patil, Parimal G. “On What It Is That Buddhists Think About: Apoha in the Ratnakīrti-
Nibandhâvali.” Journal of Indian Philosophy 31, no. 1 (2003): 229–56.
Peabody, Norbert. “Cents, Sense, Census: Human Inventories in Late Precolonial and
Early Colonial India.” Comparative Studies in Society and History 43, no. 4 (2001):
819–50.
Schwartz, Jason. “The King Must Protect the Difference: The Juridical Foundations of
Tantric Knowledge.” Religions 9, no. 4 (2018).
Sen, Prabal Kumar. “Caste in Classical Indian Philosophy: Some Ontological Prob‑
lems.” In Classical Buddhism, Neo-Buddhism and the Question of Caste, edited by
Pradeep P. Gokhale, 40–64. London: Routledge, 2020.
Shah, Nagin J. Akalaṅka’s Criticism of Dharmakīrti’s Philosophy. Ahmedabad: L.D.
Institute of Indology, 1967.
Taber, John. “Dharmakīrti, Svataḥ Prāmāṇyam, and Awakening.” Wiener Zeitschrift Für
Die Kunde Südasiens 56/57 (2015): 77–98.
Taber, John. “What Did Kumārila Bhaṭṭa Mean by Svataḥ Prāmāṇya?” Journal of the
American Oriental Society 112, no. 2 (1992): 204–21.
Talbot, Cynthia. “A Revised View of ‘Traditional’ India: Caste, Status, and Social Mobility
in Medieval Andhra.” South Asia: Journal of South Asian Studies 15, no. 1 (1992): 17–52.
Teltumbde, Anand. The Persistence of Caste: The Khairlanji Murders and India’s Hidden
Apartheid. London: Zed Books, 2010.
Vajpeyi, Ananya. “Śūdra Dharma and Legal Treatments of Caste.” In Hinduism and Law:
An Introduction, edited by Donald Davis, Timothy Lubin, and Jayanth Krishnan,
154–66. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2010.
Viswanath, Rupa. The Pariah Problem: Caste, Religion, and the Social in Modern India.
New York: Columbia University Press, 2014.
Wright, Samuel. “History in the Abstract: ‘Brahman-Ness’ and the Discipline of Nyāya
in Seventeenth-Century Vārāṇasī.” Journal of Indian Philosophy 44, no. 5 (2016):
1041–69.
Yengde, Suraj. Caste Matters. Gurgaon: India Viking, 2019.