MACINTYRE-Against The Self-Images of The Age

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 295

Against the self-images of the age

ESSAYS ON IDEOLOGY AND PHILOSOPHY


Alasdair MacIntyre

AGAINST THE SELF-IMAGES


OF THE AGE

Essays on ideologyand philosophy

UNIVERSITY OF NOTRE DAME PRESS

Notre Dame, Indiana


University of Notre Dame Press Edition 1978
undpress.nd.edu
Reprinted in 1984, 1989, 2001

First published in 1971 by Gerald Duckworth & Company Limited


Copyright© 1971 by Alasdair MacIntyre
Chapter 4 copyright©1964 by The New York Review
Chapter 19 copyright© 1967 by The Aristotelian Society
Published by arrangement with Gerald Duckworth & Company Limited

Published in the United States of America

This ebook has been made possible in part by a major grant from the
National Endowment for the Humanities: Exploring the human
endeavor. Any views, findings, conclusions, or recommendations
expressed in this book do not necessarily represent those of the National
Endowment for the Humanities.

Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data


MacIntyre, Alasdair C.
Against the self-images of the age.

Reprint of the ed. published by Duckworth, London.


Includes bibliographical references.
I. Philosophy-Addresses, essays, lectures.
2. Ideology-Addresses, essays, lectures. I. Title.
[B2 .M34 1978] 108 78-1571
ISBN 0-268-00586-9
ISBN 0-268-00587-7 (pbk. : alk. paper)
Contents

Introduction vii
PART ONE

1 The end of ideology and the end of the end of 3


ideology
2 God and the theologians 12
3 Psychoanalysis : the future of an illusion? 27
4 The socialism of R. H. Tawney 38
5 How not to write about Lenin 43
6 How not to write about Stalin 48
7 Trotsky in exile 52
8 Marxist mask and romantic face: Lukacs on Thomas 60
Mann
9 Marxism of the will 70
10 Pascal and Marx: On Lucien Goldmann'sHidden God 76

PART TWO

I I Philosophy and ideology: Introduction to Part Two 91


12 What morality is not 96
13 Hume on "is" and "ought" 109
14 Imperatives, reasons for action, and morals 125
15 "Ought" 136
16 Some more about "ought" 157
17 Pleasure as a reason for action 173
18 The antecedents of action 191
19 The idea of a social science 211
20 Emotion, behavior and belief 230
21 Rationality and the explanation of action 244
V
vi Contents
22 Is a science of comparative politics possible? 260
23 Political and philosophical epilogue: a view of The
Pover.tyof Liberalismby Robert Paul Wolff 280
Introduction

These essays would normally not be expected to appear within the


same covers; for the intellectual habits of the age would construe
them as belonging to two different and not very closely related
genres. I make no apology for this, since one aim of the book is
precisely to break with some of these habits. It is true, of course,
that those essays which have been published previously appeared
in two very different kinds of periodical-professional philo-
sophical journals, such as the Philosophical Review, on the one
hand, and journals of general intellectual culture, such as Encounter,
on the other. For the institutions and the organization of our
culture runs pari passu with its habits of mind, and therefore
either one does not publish at all or one accepts being miscon-
strued in terms of dichotomies to which one may be resolutely
opposed.
The particular dichotomy which I am identifying here, for the
purpose of opposing it, is that between the detailed, analytical,
conceptual inquiries of contemporary philosophy and those
inquiries into the truth of weltanschauungen which laymen some-
times suppose to be the province of philosophy, but which are so
seldom carried on within its bounds. However I should immediately
distinguish between a legitimate version of this dichotomy and an
illegitimate one. It is extremely important that rigorous attention
to analytical detail should not be vitiated by premature attempts to
assess the significance of that detail in terms of some larger issue ;
and it is inevitable that ideological stances should be adopted and
ideological criticism should be carried forward-since in neither
politics nor religion is the urgency of crises delayed by the exigencies
of the calendars of academic inquiry-when crucial detailed
work still remains to be done. None the less, on the one hand it is
essential to underline that, of the multiplying of distinctions,
there may turn out to be no end; and that which distinctions are
important can only be assessed in terms of some criteria of larger
vii
viii Introduction
significance. On the other hand, every doctrine which is not to be
corroded by intellectual complacency has to expose its vulnerable
commitments in all their piecemeal detail. When J. L. Austin
declared that truth is important but that importance is not, he
perhaps made himself the unwitting ally of those dogmatists
whose doctrines were thereby placed low on the list of priorities
for intellectual examination.
The unity of this book resides therefore in the aspiration to link
philosophical criticism and ideological commitment, and, doubt-
less, with the project thus generally defined very few will be found
to quarrel. But doubtless also almost everybody-whether those
who believe themselves committed to one of the ideologies dis-
cussed in these essays or those who confidently believe themselves
exempt from ideological adherence-will find grounds for
quarreling with the way in which I have tried to carry out this
project. Against those who believe that some particular ideology is
still able to provide the light that our individual and social lives
need, I shall assert that-in the case of psychoanalysis, of
Christianity, and above all of Marxism-either intellectual
failure, or failure to express the forms of thought and action
which constitute our contemporary social life, or both, have led to
their necessary and in the long run not to be regretted decay.
Against those who believe that in our type of society ideology as
such can no longer find living roots or expression, I shall assert
that it is the specific traits of these particular ideologies that we
have inherited which make them no longer viable, and not any
characteristics of ideology as such; and moreover that the belief in
the end of ideology itself masks an ideology which is no less an
ideology for being so often unacknowledged and which is perhaps
less reputable than it might be insofar as it goes unrecognized.
In particular I believe that the nature of contemporary academic
philosophy in the Anglo-Saxon world has contributed in a marked
way to the persistence among us of certain uncriticized ideological
concepts and values. The activity of the philosopher in the Anglo-
Saxon world has been variously defined in the last seventy years in
ways which, although inadequate, point to a truth about the
nature of that activity: "analysis," "linguistic analysis," "con-
ceptual analysis," "inquiries into meaning." Such characterizations
are bound to be inadequate, not only because of their brevity, but
also because the question of the nature of analysis and the question
of the relationship of linguistic expressions to concepts have of
course themselves been central matters for philosophical argument
during this whole period. But it is clear that the procedure of
Introduction ix
philosophers has been usually and characteristically to select
some set of linguistic expressions or of concepts and to then
inquire into their meaning, use, and logical liaisons; the categoriza-
tion of types of meaning, of use, and of logical relationship being
an activity that has proceeded side by side with these more
particular inquiries. What has not been sufficiently remarked is
the lack of attention consequently paid to the historical and social
sources of the expressions or the concepts which are to be the
focus of attention ; and this has led to distortion in at least two
ways. There is, first, the possibility of making judgments about
the meaning, use, or logical relationships of some particular type
of expression on the basis of an inadequate sample. We may take an
impoverished view of the range of types of moral concepts or of
moral statements, or we may distort our views of particular
concepts by being parsimonious with our examples. When pro-
fessing to study moral concepts as such or "the" language of
morals, we may be merely studying one particular variation on
possible moral themes, perhaps that which is dominant on our own
social milieu. A second possible source of error is in the loss of
insight into changes of meaning and transformations of concepts
which can only be studied if we are prepared to give historical
depth to philosophical inquiry. These two sources of error may
result in our conferring necessity, inevitability, and universality
on some conceptual scheme, some way of looking at the world,
which is in fact local in both time and place and to which there
are alternatives. In doing this, philosophy may thus appear to
guarantee one way of looking at the world by seeming to demon-
strate its necessity; and this is the key role of inadequate philosophy
in underpinning ideology.
I shall therefore move in the argument of the succeeding
essays from trying to show that Christianity, psychoanalysis, and
especially Marxism fail as ideologies for reasons quite other than
those propounded in the end-of-ideology thesis and that the
end-of-ideology thesis itself masks an ideology, to arguing that a
true perception of the latter fact and an ability to understand the
world in more adequate and less impoverished ways depends
upon the outcome of inquiry in moral philosophy and the philo-
sophy of the social sciences. This is my task; how inadequately
I have carried it out and how urgently it is necessary to improve
the argument and to perform the task more adequately nobody is
more aware than I am.
I have left those essays, which have already appeared elsewhere,
substantially in the form in which they were originally presented
,.
X Introduction
This is not because of laziness, but because to rescue them from
their form as reviews or essays written at a particular time or
place would require that I should know how to tie these arguments
together into a substantive whole. This I do not yet know how to
do, but I regard learning how to do it as a prerequisite for further
advancing inquiry into these questions.

It remains for me to thank the editors and publishers of the


following periodicals or books for permission to reprint: Encounter
for 2, 3, 5, 7, 8, 10; New York Review of Books for 4; The Yale
Law Journal for 6; Partisan Review for 9 ; Philosophy for 12;
The Philosophical Review for 13 ; The Journal of Philosophy for 14;
The Monist and The Open Court Publishing Company, La
Salle, Illinois for 17; Messrs. Routledge and Kegan Paul and
Humanities Press for 18 (from British Analytical Philosophy,
edited by B. Williams and A. Montefiore); The Aristotelian
Society for 19.

Finally there is another kind of gratitude: to Miss Barbara


Warner and to Mrs. Betty Griffin who typed and retyped; to the
Librarian of the London Library and his colleagues for their
patient and scholarly help; and to my colleagues at the University
of Essex and at Brandeis University for so much illuminating
argument and criticism. I owe a particular debt to the members
of the Study Group on the Unity of Knowledge for discussion of
several themes in this book, especially of essays 20 and 21, and to
the Ford Foundation for making such discussion possible.
.ALASDAIR MAclNTYRE
Waltham, Massachusetts
January 1971
PART ONE
I

The end of ideology and the end of


the end of ideology

The 1950s were a decade of immoderate claims made on behalf


of what its defenders took to be moderation. Apocalyptic saluta-
tions hailed the arrival of the mixed economy guided by what
was alleged-quite falsely-to be Keynesian economic theory;
messianic value was attached to the politics of social democracy.
As in earlier apocalyptic and messianic moments, it was proclaimed
intemperately that nothing but the sober truth was at last being
told. The core of this prophesying was the "end-of-ideology"
thesis, first advanced by Edward Shils at a Congress of Cultural
Freedom meeting in 1954 and later endorsed and developed by
Daniel Bell and Seymour Martin Lipset. The central message of
this thesis was that in the advanced industrial societies of the West,
ideology was at an end because fundamental social conflict was at
an end.
In the view maintained by advocates of this thesis, there were
no longer any social roots for a politics which proposed a revolu-
tionary transformation of the social order. There might still
be Utopian visions of a social order in which the ills of the existing
order had been done away-and Daniel Bell at least was anxious
to stress the continuing relevance of Utopian vision, provided that
it was treated as vision and not as something else; but practical
politics must now be a matter of pragmatic compromise with an
agreed framework of basic and even not so basic values. This
agreed framework depended upon a consensus which had been
arrived at by means of the institutions of the welfare state and of the
economic and political domestication of the working class. Those
rival and competing interests which had been allowed expression
within the official political order would therefore no longer breed
disruptive conflict; and the presentation of ideological world
views which might guide and inform a politics of passionate
3
4 Against the Self-Images of the Age
conflict would henceforth be out of place in the advanced industrial
societies.
That the end-of-ideology thesis was a diagnosis which expressed
something real and important about those societies in the 1950s is
undeniable. The political apathy, for instance, to which its
protagonists pointed (and which Lipset, for example, took to be a
precondition of the stability of democratic political orders) was not
an illusion. Moreover, the proliferation of similar theses among
political philosophers and political scien(ists is itself to some
degree evidence of a general frame of mind. Shils in Chicago,
Lipset in California, Bell in New York found allies in J. L. Talmon
in Jerusalem, who proclaimed that the ideological theorists of the
eighteenth and nineteenth centuries-and especially Rousseau
and Marx-were the progenitors of the totalitarian politics of the
twentieth century (the equation of ideological theorizing with
totalitarian politics is a central theme in most of these writers); in
Sir Isaiah Berlin at Oxford, who identified a belief in "positive
liberty" (to be found in Rousseau and Hegel) as a prime source of
totalitarian evils; and in Norman Cohn, who saw in the millenarians
of the Middle Ages and the sixteenth century the predecessors
of modern Utopians, identifying the source of both movements in
the psychological disorders-and probably the paranoia-of the
individuals concerned. The end-of-ideology thesis, therefore,
was part of a general intellectual landscape. Moreover, it found a
counterpart in the avowed beliefs of those engaged in politics.
The writings of Anthony Crosland and John Strachey espouse
what is plainly the same basic standpoint.
If therefore the sheer weight of this agreement is evidence that
the end-of-ideology thesis expressed something implicitly or
explicitly recognized by many perceptive observers of the 1950s,
it still remains to ask whether the end-of-ideology thesis diagnosed
correctly the nature of that to which it was sensitive. On this
point three initial observations are in order. The first is that when
such writers spoke of the end of ideology in the advanced societies
of the West, what they plainly had primarily in mind was the final
demise of the influence of Marxism in these societies. Even if those
writers were themselves Marxists, or post-Marxists, none were
unwilling to declare their allegiance in Cold War terms, and it is
therefore pertinent to ask whether they may not have confused
the local demise of Marxist ideology with the local demise of
ideology. To ask this question suggests that we ought to inquire
whether these authors had freed themselves from the influence of
Marxism to quite the extent which they believed they had. For
The end of ideologyand the end of the end of ideology 5
their thesis appears to be that it is because what they take to be
profound social changes have occurred that ideology is no longer
possible. In their view of the causal sequence-for which none
of these writers seems to argue explicitly-it is possible to perceive
the ghosts of the Marxist concepts of basis and superstructure. For
otherwise, surely they might have taken more seriously the
possibility that it was because ideology was not what it was, that
social and political conflict was not what it was, rather than
vice versa.
I deliberately used in the last sentence the neutral expression
"because ideology was not what it was," in order to lead on to the
suggestion that, in fact, the end-of-ideology theorists had mis-
construed their situation in two related ways. They were right
to see that in the 1950s ideology was not what it was; and they were
right also to relate this fact to the lessening of social conflict. But
not only did they confuse the exhaustion of Marxism with the
exhaustion of ideology, they failed to entertain one crucial
alternative possibility: namely, that the end-of-ideology thesis,
far from marking the end of ideology, was itself a key expression of
the ideology of the time and place where it arose. Here again
there is a strong reminiscence of classical Marxism. For Marx saw
Marxism as having an independence of existing social structures
and hence an objectivity which rescued it from the relativity of
ideological thought which he diagnosed in his opponents. It was,
of course, only in the Communist future, when the social roots of
ideological thinking had been finally destroyed, that ideology
would finally wither away. But Marxism offers an anticipation of
this apocalyptic culmination. This surely is the ancestor of that
muted apocalypticism in Bell and Lipset which surrounds the
announcement of the end of ideology.
To make good the thesis that the end-of-ideology thesis was
itself part of an ideology, and was thus also self-refuting, it is
necessary to be clear about what we ought to understand by the
expression "ideology." Shils, Bell, and Lipset are all astonishingly
brief in their exposition; since I wish to make use of this notion
not merely to criticize the end-of-ideology thesis, but for other
independent purposes, I shall have to discuss this point at some-
what greater length.
I take any ideology to have three key features. The first is that it
attempts to delineate certain general characteristics of nature or
society or both, characteristics which do not belong only to
particular features of the changing world which can be investigated
only by empirical inquiry. So for Christianity the God-created and
6 Against the Self-Images of the Age
God-maintained character of the world is just such a characteristic;
so for Marxism the laws of dialectical change are such a character-
istic.Two closely related queries can always be raised about this
feature of an ideology: What is the status of statements about these
general characteristics and how do we show such statements to be
true or false? And what is the relationship between the truth or
falsity of such statements and the truth or falsity of scientific or
historical claims about the character of empirically investigable
processes and events? How for Christianity are claims about
divine providence related to claims about historical events in
first-century Palestine? How for Marxism are claims about the
dialectic related to claims about the wage levels of the working
class under industrial capitalism?
The second central feature of any ideology is an account of the
relationship between what is the case and how we ought to act,
between the nature of the world and that of morals, politics, and
other guides to conduct. That is to say, I am making it a defining
property of an ideology that it does not merely tell us how the world
is and how we ought to act, but is concerned with the bearing of the
one upon the other. This involves a concern, explicit or implicit,
with the status of statements of moral rules and of statements
expressing evaluations.
This latter concern, like the concern with the status of statements
about the nature of things, shows that a good deal of what I have
characterized as ideology not only overlaps with the proper
concerns of philosophy, it is philosophy. So that philosophical
inquiry is always liable to be a solvent of ideological conviction and
commitment by arriving at conclusions incompatible with the
positions of a particular ideology. Likewise, the dominance of a
particular ideology may limit or inhibit philosophical inquiry.
I do not refer only or most importantly to the use of policemen by
those who are not only ideologically committed but also politically
powerful to threaten or abolish free inquiry. For what I shall treat
as the third defining property of an ideology is that it is not merely
believed by the members of a given social group, but believed in
such a way that it at least partially defines for them their social
existence. By this I mean that its concepts are embodied in, and
its beliefs presupposed by, some of these actions and transactions,
the performance of which is characteristic of the social life of that
group. The relatively noncommital word "group" is used advisedly,
for it is itself a matter for ideological debate how ideologies come to
exercise such hold as they do upon social life. There is a Christian
account of why Christians are Christians and the heathens are not;
The end of ideology and the end of the end of ideology 7
and there is a Marxist account of why Marxists are Marxists and
the heathens are not. It is for this reason that a good deal of
ideology not only overlaps with the proper concerns of sociology,
but is sociology; and hence, sociological inquiry, like philo-
sophical inquiry, is liable to be a solvent of ideological conviction
and also to be limited or inhibited by the dominance of particular
ideologies.
This potentiality of conflict between any dominating or even
aspiring ideology, and both philosophy and sociology, is not
merely a source of tension. Rather, it is one of the signs, although
only one of the signs, that an ideology is living and not dead, that it
should actually breed conflict both with the philosophy and with
the empirical science of its day. Conversely, any situation in which
an ideology has no problems of conflict with philosophy or human
or natural science is characteristically a sign, not that the ideology
in question has triumphantly solved the intellectual problems of
the age, but rather that the ideology has become empirically
vacuous and has won its freedom from conflict at the cost of
becoming empirically and perhaps practically empty.
That this is true of Christianity as it now exists I have argued in
two essays in The Religious Significance of Contemporary Atheism, 1
and I shall not repeat the argument here, especially as the germ of
that argument is to be found in "God and the Theologians." 2
But it is important to stress that it is not just the character of
Christianity or just the character of contemporary society, but
rather the coincidence of certain features of these two changing
characters that has rendered Christianity ideologically vacuous.
The attempt to maintain the values and the credibility of
Christianity in the intellectual and moral climate of, for example,
contemporary Britain has led to a vacuity that was not present
when Christians such as Karl Barth or Dietrich Bonhoeffer or
Franz Jaegstaetter defined their faith in words and action by
contrast with and against Nazi mythology.
An ideology may of course be empirically vacuous, because it is
held in such a way that it is unfalsifiable, and yet not be practically
vacuous. So it is with psychoanalytic doctrine in a certain social
milieu at the present time. In the cultural desert created by the
prejudices of the liberal intelligentsia of New York or of the
Californian cities, the questioning of the scientific pretensions of
psychoanalysis is restricted almost entirely to those concerned
with the philosophy of science. The therapeutic needs of such aids
1 With Paul Ricoeur (New York: Columbia University Press, 1967).
2 See pp. 12-26.
8 Against the Self-Images of the Age
perhaps make intelligible the extraordinary situations whereby a
theory that is certainly no better confirmed-and perhaps not as
well confirmed-as witchcraft or astrology should have gained the
credence that it has.
Finally, at this point we ought to note that the same doctrine can,
during its history, experience vicissitudes as a result of which it
alters its ideological character, both in respect to its relevance and
vacuity and in respect to the liberating or oppressive character of
its social effects. This is peculiarly true of both Christianity and
Marxism. But in the advanced industrial societies of the West at
least, although it may be dangerous to misunderstand why
Christianity and Marxism are for the most part impotent, it is far
more dangerous to rest this misunderstanding on the kind of
endorsement of the status quo involved in the end-of-ideology
thesis.
The ideological character of that thesis is most clearly apparent
in Lipset's version of it in Political Man. The key notions which
carry ideological weight are those of the conflicting interests
which have been domesticated within the welfare state and that of
the political consensus which provides the framework for that
domestication. The key empirical contention is that a large measure
of nonparticipation in active political decision-making promotes
democratic and peaceful political and social processes, while
widespread participation tends to go hand in hand with totali-
tarianism and authoritarianism. About these notions and this
contention the following needs to be said : first, that the crucial
question is how an interest is defined and how it is identified.
Lipset and Bell, when they speak of the welfare state, clearly have
in mind the recognition of trade unions either in their own right
or through social-democratic parties as an interest which the
political decision-makers must consult. But what about the
recipients of welfare? Do they or ought they to constitute an
interest with a distinctive political voice? What is quite clear is
that the processes of formal democracy can coexist with the
recognition of certain institutionalized interests, while the dis-
tribution of power and of the goods of which power determines the
recipients remains radically unequal and radically unjust. The
continuous rediscovery of and indeed the continuous re-creation
of poverty in advanced societies ought to make this fact central to
any political analysis.
Consensus is a concept correlative to that of interest. The
question of which interests are recognized and acknowledged and
the question of whose voice is heard in the consensus are the same
The end of ideologyand the end of the end of ideology 9
question. It is not, of course, the case that those whose wants are
not recognized and acknowledged as an interest by the established
political consensus do not have their needs considered in the
course of political decision-making; they may constitute an object
of acute concern, especially when they create problems for their
decision-makers. If the problems they create are sufficiently
intractable, then the attempt will be made to give the problem-
makers an institutionalized voice within the consensus. So at any
given time there will be two types of politics possible: one, the
politics of those within; the other, the politics of those excluded.
The end-of-ideology thesis is one ideology of those concerned
with legitimating only the former.
This exercise is underpinned by the selection of facts and by
lack of conceptual awareness. The selection of facts is a matter
of the type and the range of variables studied. Lipset never con-
siders the type of nonparticipation in decision-making-which in
fact prevails in totalitarian and authoritarian states and organiza-
tions as a counterexample to his thesis-with the consequence,
that either his thesis must be construed as false or his use of
"participation" so loose and undefined as to be useless for his own
express purposes. But above all, Lipset never considers how the
evaluation and selection of the facts not only results in a political
commitment (as Charles Taylor has argued in his paper on
'Neutrality and Political Science' 1 and as Lipset himself acknow-
ledges when he writes that "democracy [he means the parliamen-
tary democracy of the West] is not only or even primarily a means
through which different groups can attain their ends or seek the
good society; it is the good society itself in operation" Political
Man, p. 403), but arises from a critical standpoint which is not
only methodological but also ideological. The Lipset-Bell vision
of the world is informed by a view of rationality which makes
liberal, pragmatic man the paradigm of rationality. Hence, the
antithesis is framed between the reasonable, empirical approach
of the proponents of the end-of-ideology thesis and the partisan
passions of les ideologues(this deprecating sense of ideology was
first used by Napoleon). Now rationality may be and, as I shall
argue in a later essay, is one. But what are rational goals for those
within the consensus to lay down, explicitly or implicitly, for
those outside the consensus are not rational goals for those outside
the consensus to lay down for themselves, if only because of the
1 In Philosophy, Politics, and Society, Third Series, edited by P. Laslett
and W. G. Runciman (Oxford: Blackwell; New York: Barnes & Noble,
1967).
IO Against the Self-Imagesof the Age
force of that always to be remembered truism that not only in the
end, but even in the relatively short run, nobody can know what
an agent wants better than-the man himself. Every restriction
upon the right of men to speak for themselves in this respect
involves either some unjustified claim that others can know better
than they what they want, or some claim that their wants are
irrelevant, perhaps because what they want is not what is good for
them. Hence, the democratic claim of Jefferson or of Robespierre
is the necessary political counterpart of any moral regard for
human wants.
The ideological antithesis of Jefferson or Robespierre is Burke,
and it is no accident that the antithesis between a politics of
interests and a politics of ideology is as at home in Burke's writ-
ings as it is in those of Bell or Lipset. What Burke failed to see is
what Bell and Lipset fail to see: that the costs of consensus are
paid by those excluded from it. It is noteworthy that neither Bell
in The End of Ideology,nor Lipset in PoliticalMan or even in his
much later article on "Anglo-American Society", in the Inter-
national Encyclopaediaof the Social Sciencessees the place of the
blacks in advanced societies as posing a radical question mark.
Of them we may say what Michelet said of the Irish when he
reproved the English: "Sitting at your ease on the corpse of
Ireland . . . be good enough to tell us: did your revolution of
interests not cost more blood than our revolution of ideas?"
(The Irish were for a long time the blacks of the British Isles.)
The central polarity of advanced industrial societies is that be-
tween minorities who cannot solve their problems and majorities
who cannot even face them. One instrument which is of impor-
tance in their avoidance-behavior (the behavior which elected
Mr. Nixon to the Presidency) is the largely implicit belief that all
problems are piecemeal and detailed, to be confronted by an
empirical and pragmatic approach and that the transformation of
society as a whole is an ideological will o' the wisp. But just this is
the belief explicitly articulated and defended by the end-of-
ideology thesis. It is thus not merely an ideology, but one that
lacks any liberating power.
When I speak of the end of the end of ideology I do not mean
of course to dwell merely on the fact that the end-of-ideology
thesis is itself ideological. For while the end-of-ideology thesis was
sensitive to a widespread mood in the 1950s among not only
intellectuals, but also students, it proved to be highly discordant
with the mood of intelligentsia of the 1960s when social conflict
was at its most intense in the advanced societies in the institutions
The end of ideologyand the end of the end of ideology 11
of higher education. What was notable was, of course, not the
birth of new ideologies, but a romanticism which sometimes dis-
claimed any coherent ideology and sometimes constructed an
amalgam of ideological fragments to use for its own purposes.
This confrontation of middle-aged pragmatism and youthful
romanticism, of a pragmatic insistence on the detailed and the
empirical and a passionate attachment to vague and large ideolo-
gical critiques, is misleadingly characterized as a generational
conflict, even if it was in fact accompanied by such conflict. For
such a characterization misses the symbiotic character of the
phenomenon; the pragmatism of the attitude involved in the
end-of-ideology thesis leaves precisely those whom it seeks to
educate vulnerable to almost any ideological appeal by its failure
to criticize social wholes. Each party to this dispute provides the
other with an opponent made in precisely the required image.
The children of those who define social reality in technocratic,
bureaucratic, and academic terms aspire to a definition of human
reality which will escape all institutional constraints. The implicit
nihilism of so much student attack on institutions is the natural
outcome of the defense of the institutions of the status quo as the
only possible ones.
It is partly because of this connection that the end-of-ideology
thesis still deserves attention. Those who wish to remake society
are under an obligation to learn to frame alternative institutions
that will escape the crushing polarities of the present. This is a
political task. To perform it in a minimally adequate way it will be
a necessary preliminary to understand how we can escape ideolo-
gical deformation by the social order in which we live. One version
of that deformation is to allow the fear of 1984 to revive the politics
which glorified 1688.
2

God and the theologians1

Bishops provide news items under three kinds of headlines:


they comment on our Morals, they forward schemes of Church
Reunion, and-much less often-they discuss Christianity in
public. The reported comments of the Bishop of Peterborough
as well as the Archbishop of Canterbury on the book Honest to
God2 make it clear that the charge against the Bishop of Woolwich
is largely that his utterances were public and that the first of them
was an article in the Sunday Observer. To the discussion of
speculative theological issues between consenting adults in private
the Archbishop obviously would have less objection.
The reactions of his episcopal colleagues however provide
only one indication of the importance of what Dr. Robinson said
in Honest to God. The real interest among large numbers of people
usually deeply inarticulate about religion is even more significant.
More than one kind of raw nerve was touched by Dr. Robinson's
theme. For he drew our attention to the fact that although the
death of God has been announced over and over again in our
culture, it remains true that God is an unconscionable time a-
dying. I do not refer by this to the staying power of ecclesiastical
institutions; they probably contribute to the strengthening of
atheism as much as they ever did. But the survival of religious
modes of feeling and questioning at widely different levels in our
culture points clearly to something that Nietzsche and Feuerbach
missed.
To put what Dr. Robinson wrote into perspective it is worth
recalling that atheism is not all of one kind. Like Christianity it
has its rival traditions. There is the speculative atheism which
is concerned to deny that over and above the universe there is
something else, an invisible intelligent being who exists apart
1Reprinted from Encounter, September 1963.
1Dr. John A Robinson, the Bishop of Woolwich. Honest to God
(London: SCM Press; Philadelphia: The Westminster Press, 1963).
12
God and the theologians 13
from the world and rules over it. Such an atheism is concerned to
point out fallacies in the arguments for the existence of such a
being, to stress the fact that we have no need of this hypothesis;
and in general to expose religion as a series of intellectual mistakes.
Its patron saints are David Hume and Bertrand Russell. Insofar
as it seeks to explain religion it tends to lay stress on the general
folly and weakness of human beings; its panacea is usually educa-
tion, and its grief is that increased education by no means always
produces increased skepticism about Christianity.
It is at just this point that a quite different kind of atheism
intervenes to inquire why we should ever have expected otherwise.
Since argument is not what fathers religious beliefs in the first
place, why should learning the difference between good and bad
arguments produce skepticism? Religion is misunderstood if it is
construed simply as a set of intellectual errors; it is rather the case
that in a profoundly misleading form deep insights, hopes, and
fears are being expressed. We have to remove the mask of super-
naturalist error-to this extent this second tradition presupposes
the first. But to do so will be to expose a set of misunderstood
truths. Religion needs to be translated into nonreligious terms and
not simply rejected. This is the atheism of Feuerbach, of David
Friedrich Strauss, and of the young Karl Marx. Its task is not a
purely intellectual one; it is rather to transform society so that men
will no longer need to resort to religious forms of expression. When
the hopes which men have are embodied in secular social forms
they will no longer need to appear in disguise as portraits of another
and supernatural realm.

What is striking about Dr. Robinson's book is first and foremost


that he is an atheist in both senses. He devotes a good deal of his
space to attacking the notion of a being "out there." He quotes
Bonhoeffer as saying that "Man has learned to cope with all
questions of importance without recourse to_ God as a working
hypothesis. . .. " But not only this: he is prepared to translate
theological statements into nontheological. He says that what we
mean when we speak of God is "that which concerns us ultimately";
that to speak of God is to speak of the deepest things we experience.
"Belief in God is a matter of 'what you take seriously without any
reservation' ", and to assert that God is love is to assert the supre-
macy of personal relationships. All theological statements can
consequently be translated into statements about human concern.
Dr. Robinson explicitly contrasts his view with what he calls
"supernaturalism" and with what he calls "religion." Yet,
Against the Self-Images of the Age
although he is prepared to assert with Feuerbach that "the true
atheist is not the man who denies God, the subject; it is the man
for whom the attributes of divinity, such as love, wisdom, and
justice are nothing," he is unwilling to abandon the word "God"
and a great many kindred theological words. Yet I think that we
might well be puzzled by this strong desire for a theological
vocabulary; for the only reason given for preserving the name
"God" is that "our being has depths which naturalism, whether
evolutionary, mechanistic, dialectical, or humanistic, cannot or
will not recognize." But this is to say that all atheists to date have
described "our being" inadequately. And that our accounts of
human nature are all inadequate, most atheists would concede.
But what, according to the Bishop, is at issue is how to describe
our nature and not anything else. So the Bishop is fundamentally
at one with Hume and Feuerbach, and at odds with Aquinas,
Luther, and Billy Graham.
The second half of Honest to God reveals that the Bishop is a
very conservative atheist. He wants an atheist Christology, he
wishes to retain and to revise the notion of worship, and his moral
attitudes are in fact intensely conservative. Sex outside marriage
turns out to be just as wrong in the eyes of the Bishop, who says
we must ask what the demands of love are, as it ever was for any
Bishop who asked what ecclesiastical authority said. Indeed, the
combination of radical intellectual doubt with conservative
moralism is intensely reminiscent of Robert Elsmere and of the
agonies of Victorian clergymen. Only Dr. Robinson scarcely
appears in agony; he has a cheerful, even brisk style. And he
recognizes much less clearly than some of his episcopal critics the
implications for traditional Christianity of what he is saying.
But Dr. Robinson is not alone here. The response to his book
might suggest that the combination of a religious vocabulary with
substantial atheism has a wide appeal. And this is a second reason
why Honest to God may be important. For the quality of this
response may reveal .something of the situation of theology in
general in our sort of society. Dr. Robinson after all does more
than merely quote Karl Barth, Rudolf Bultmann, Dietrich
Bonhoeffer, and Paul Tillich; he presents his views as the out-
come of a revolution in Protestant theology defined by those
names.
So that two questions press on us: is Protestant theology, and
not merely Dr. Robinson, essentially atheistic now? And what light
does such theology throw upon our social life?
Modem Protestant theology is rooted in catastrophe. The liberal
God and the theologians 15
idealism which easily confused a secular faith in uninterrupted
progress with belief in the actions of a divine providence could
not survive the trenches of World War I. Tillich was an army
chaplain, as Bultmann was to be later on. Bonhoeffer was to be
executed by the Nazis. The problem of evil had to be more than
an academic exercise. Moreover the matter of traditional Pro-
testant preaching with its moralizing and its promise of pietistic
consolations could scarcely survive. Two questions pressed in:
how can we think of God after the Somme, after Auschwitz?
And how can we preach to contemporary man ?1
The first answer to these questions was Barth's commentary on
Romans, where St. Paul's Greek is conjured into a blend of
Luther, Calvin, Dostoevski, and Kierkegaard. (Not so misleading
either, for each of them had digested large quantities of St. Paul.)
Barth's message is that any attempt to justify belief in God or any
attempt to comprehend God's ways by translating revelation into
terms other than its own is bound to fail. God is infinitely distant
from man and totally other. In revelation he condescends to us:
we can only accept or reject, we cannot argue. Evil cannot be
explained; but we can be redeemed and saved from its power.
At first sight Barth's starting-point in theology is at the opposite
pole from that of Dr. Robinson. And certainly as Barthian
theology has developed systematically, it has remained a keystone
of orthodoxy, by now a major influence among Roman Catholics
as well as among Protestants. But Barthian theology none the less
contains the materials for its own self-transformation. For if the
Word of God cannot be identified with any frail human attempt
to comprehend it, the way is open for sympathy with those who
reject human theologies which have attempted to substitute for
the Divine Word (and perhaps Barthian theology among them).
So Barth has always had an interest in Ludwig Feuerbach. If it is
any human work or word which we have to carefully avoid identi-
fying or confusing with the divine, then we are in a very different
1 It is the recurrence of these two questions together which leads Dr.
Robinson to write sometimes as if he is concerned with whether and what
God is and sometimes as if it is merely a matter of finding conveniently
different images to suit different audiences. So he can say that he does
not wish to disturb those who find it possible still to think of God in
traditional ways. This makes it possible for the Archbishop to present
Dr. Robinson as a mildly erroneous and overenthusiastic champion of some
aspects of orthodoxy at the expense of others. But in fact if Dr. Robinson's
argument is right, the traditional views of God are not merely outmoded;
they are simply false. And in other passages Dr. Robinson recognizes this.
16 Against the Self-Images of the Age
position from that of traditional Protestant pietistic orthodoxy.
For none but God can be infallible; and hence no church authority,
and not even the scriptures, can be treated as infallible without
impiety. This was the basis upon which Barth welcomed radical,
scholarly criticism of the New Testament while fundamentalist
orthodoxy always rejected it. "We have this treasure in earthen
vessels."
At this point, therefore, Protestant theology has had to face up
to its own inadequacies. Dr. Robinson is misleading here, for his
mosaic of quotations from Bultmann, Tillich, and Bonhoeffer
might suggest too great a likeness between these theologians :
whereas what is in fact striking is that from quite different stand-
points all these theologians converge upon unbelief. Consider
them in turn.
Bultmann's theology 1 has three quite separate elements to it.
There is first of all his historical skepticism about the New Testa-
ment events. Closely connected with this is his belief that the New
Testament message is presented in terms of a prescientific cos-
mology and that consequently the gospel must be "demytholo-
gized" before it can be preached to scientific man. And there is,
thirdly, his view of what the demythologized message in fact is.
The prescientific cosmology is one of a three-tiered universe to
which belong notions of a descent into hell, an ascent into heaven,
a coming again from the heavens, of angelic and demonic hier-
archies, and indeed of miraculous powers. This mythology conceals
rather than conveys the message that man is a prey to an inauthen-
tic existence, that Jesus summons him to a decision, by which he
can face up to his being as that of one who is going to die and so
begin to live authentically. What Jesus really meant turns out to
have been an anticipation of Martin Heidegger, and when the
gospel is demythologized a theistic existentialism is what remains.
But is this existentialism more than nominally theistic? Bult-
mann's pupil Kamlah took the final step of pointing out that what
Bultmann takes the life of faith to be makes its possibility logically
independent of the occurrence of any event in Palestine in the first
century and, indeed, of the existence of a supernatural being.
Christianity is secularized by stages into an atheistic philosophy.
Bultmann's own retention of some elements of traditional Christian
1 See Rudolf Bultmann, Existence and Faith: Shorter Writings (New

York: Meridian Books; London: Hodder & Stoughton, 1960); This


World and the Beyond (London: Lutterworth Press; New York: Scribner,
1960); The History of the Synoptic Tradition (New York: Harper & Row;
Oxford: Blackwell, 1963).
God and the theologians
theism appears to have no rational justification within the frame-
work of his own thought.
Tillich's 1 contrast with Bultmann is at first sight sharp. Tillich
sees himself as the heir of "the Protestant principle" that no
finite being must be confused with the divine. Insofar as seculariza-
tion has been an insistence that nothing in nature must be identified
with God, secularization is a genuine ally of Protestant Chris-
tianity. God is not a being, who just happens to exist, an additional
individual: in denying the existence of God the atheists are in the
right. It is true that in his Systematic Theology Tillich slips into
ascribing to God predicates which we would normally take to imply
that God was a being. God creates and God reveals himself, for
example. But he believes that in doing this he is able to rely on his
own doctrine of God. This is two-sided. In the first volume of
the Systematic Theology there is a good deal of traditional meta-
physical play with being and not-being. But the rules of play are
all governed by an initial criterion whose implications are far
more drastic than Tillich realizes : theological statements are
statements about what ultimately concerns us, and we learn the
nature of what ultimately concerns us by "an analysis of the
concept 'ultimate concern.' ... " If the object of theological
discourse is our own ultimate concern, what of God? It turns out
that "God" just is the name for that concern. We get the transition
from ontological assertion to ultimate human concern very clearly
stated in a sermon:
The name of this infinite and inexhaustible depth and ground
of all being is God. That depth is what the word God means.
And if that word has not much meaning for you, translate it
and speak of the depths of your life, of the source of your being,
of your ultimate concern, of what you take seriously without
any reservation. Perhaps in order to do so you must forget
everything traditional that you have learnt about God, perhaps
even that word itself. For if you know that God means depth,
you know much about him. You cannot then call yourself
an atheist or unbeliever. For you cannot think or say: Life has
no depth I Life is shallow I
Clearly, however, the conversion of the unbeliever is only so
1 See Paul Tillich, The Courage to Be (New Haven, Conn.: Yale
University Press; London: Collins, 1950); Theology of Culture (London
and New York: Oxford University Press, 1964); Dynamics of Faith-
WorldPerspectives (New York: Harper & Row; London: Allen & Unwin,
1958).
18 Against the Self-Images of the Age
easy for Tillich because belief in God has been evacuated of all its
traditional content. It consists now in moral seriousness and
nothing more. Even if we were to concede Tillich a verbal triumph
over the atheist, the substance of atheism has been conceded.
Just as Bultmann's view of the New Testament points toward
skepticism, so does Tillich's analysis of the doctrine of God. It
seems that Dr. Robinson is not alone as a theological atheist.
But what of Dietrich Bonhoeffer? Those who have written of
him have usually dwelt on the posthumously collected Letters and
Papers from Prison1 at the expense of his earlier books, and more
expressly at the expense of Sanctorum Communio and Akt und Sein.
What Bonhoeffer tried to explain was the specific character of a
Christian way of life in a Christian community. In Akt und Sein
he even tries to solve theological problems by showing the role
of the concepts in question in the life of the church. And the life
of the Christian community in Sanctorum Communio is specified
in terms of sociological categories borrowed from Ferdinand
Tonnies, the familiar categories of Gemeinschaft and Gesellschaft.
But Bonhoeffer wishes to show not what Christian societies share
with other societies, but precisely what distinguishes Christian
from other shared ways of life. He rejects the answer which both
some religious apologists and secular sociologists would give:
that the specific differentia lies in the performance of certain
religious practices or in the status accorded to certain special
theistic types of explanation. God is not a hypothesis, or if he is
treated as one, then it is a hypothesis which has already been
discredited. The Christian way of life consists not in any reliance
either on ecclesiastical forms or on divine power but in a life of
worldly powerlessness, lived totally for others. So we get the
final conclusion in his notes in prison that
The transcendence consists not in tasks beyond our scope and
power, but in the nearest Thou at hand. God in human form,
not, as in other religions, in animal form-the monstrous,
chaotic, remote and terrifying-nor yet in abstract form-
the absolute, metaphysical infinite, etc.-nor yet in the Greek
divine-human of autonomous man, but man existing for others,
and hence the Crucified....
So the distinction between secular atheistic man and Christian
man is that the latter acknowledges his powerlessness in his con-
cern for others. But what would it be like to do this in the world of
1 Dietrich Bonhoeffer, Letters and Papers from Prison (New York:
Macmillan; London: SCM Press, 1956).
God and the theologians
today, of the welfare state and of the underdeveloped countries,
facing the patterns of world revolution? One gets from Bonhoeffer's
writings no clear picture of what type of action he would actually
be recommending now, but one gets the clearest picture of what
Bonhoeffer means if one sees it in the context out of which he
wrote. For in Nazi Germany, and in the Europe of the 1930s, the
Christian role was at best one of suffering witness. The Nazi
regress to gods of race made relevant a Christian regress to a witness
of the catacombs and of the martyrs. There was available then a
simple form in which to relive Christ's passion. Bonhoeffer lived
it. And in all situations where nothing else remains for Christians
this remains.
But what has this Christianity to say not of powerlessness, but
of the handling of power? Nothing; and hence the oddity of trying
to reissue Bonhoeffer's message in our world. Consider Bon-
hoeffer's cry from prison:
Man's religiosity makes him look in his distress to the power of
God in the world; he uses God as a deus ex machina.The Bible
however directs him to the powerlessness and suffering of
God; only a suffering God can help.
Imagine it directed to a church which is providing chaplains
for the West German armed forces, as Bonhoeffer's church is,
or to a church which chose the right moment to get out of gilt-
edged securities and into equities, as Dr. Robinson's did. Only a
suffering God can help?
Bonhoeffer's Christianity is then intelligible only in one sort of
context. Outside that context it lacks precisely any specific
differentia from the way of life of sensitive generous liberals. It
does not issue in atheism as the conclusion of an argument (as
Bultmann's theology does), and it does not present atheism in
theological language (as Tillich's theology does), but it fails in
the task for which it was designed and in our sort of society it
becomes a form of practical atheism, for it clothes ordinary liberal
forms of life with the romantic unreality of a catacombic voca-
bulary.
We can see the harsh dilemma of a would-be contemporary
theology. The theologians begin from orthodoxy, but the ortho-
doxy which has learnt from Kierkegaard and Barth becomes too
easily a closed circle, in which believer speaks only to believer, in
which all human content is concealed. Turning aside from this
arid in-group theology, the most perceptive theologians wish to
translate what they have to say to an atheistic world. But they are
20 Against the Self-Images of the Age
doomed to one of two failures. Either they succeed in their trans-
lation: in which case what they find themselves saying has been
transformed into the atheism of their hearers. Or they fail in their
translation: in which case no one hears what they have to say but
themselves.
It is this last alternative which leads to the hothouse atmosphere
of so much theological discussion; it is the former which leads to
Dr. Robinson's conclusions. We can see now that Dr. Robinson's
voice is not just that of an individual, that his book testifies to the
existence of a whole group of theologies which have retained a
theistic vocabulary but acquired an atheistic substance. Yet how
can these continue to coexist? To answer this question we must
look at the social context of this type of theology.
Dr. Robinson writes as if the secularization of the modern
world were an accomplished and a recognized fact. If he were
correct we should expect a corresponding sense of triumph in
secularist writers. In fact we find too often the same uneasiness
that we discover in the theologians.
Dr. Gerhard Sczsczesny's The Future of Unbelief1 caused a
minor sensation when it appeared in Germany. It had its place
in the whole history of the rise of a dissenting intelligentsia in
postwar Germany (a piece of cultural history almost unknown in
England). But Sczsczesny's argument is doubly paradoxical. For
he argues first that we ought to recognize that we are now living
in "a post-Christian era," and the paradox is that if this were
clearly true there would be no need to call upon people to recog-
nize it. Sczsczesny would not have to fight against the cultural
orthodoxy of the cou/csu. And when Sczsczesny goes on to
construct his humanist alternative to Christianity the criteria
to which he appeals are ordinary humanist ones. So that unless
people are already convinced secularists they are unlikely to listen
to him. Moreover, he formulates his alternative in terms of fairly
abstract and hence unobjectionable principle. Justice, equality,
and honesty are all commended. Yet anyone who lived through
the German catastrophe must know that the problem is not
whether justice, equality, and honesty are admirable; the problem
is how to embody them in social institutions. And to solve this
problem we have to recognize clearly what our existing social
order is. If we do so we shall see that it is very far from being
completely secularized.
England is perhaps an untypical country. The English have
neither the ecclesiastical political parties of Europe, nor the
1 Gerhard Sczsczesny, The Future of Unbelief (London: Heinemann).
God and the theologians 2I

majority churchgoing of the United States. But they experience


many of the same pressures, and they therefore find analogous
religious phenomena. The number of Easter communicants in
the Church of England has risen very slowly but fairly steadily
for a decade and a half. Over half the marriages in England take
place in Anglican churches. Over half the children eligible for
Anglican baptism are so baptized. Between the 10 per cent or so
of clear and convinced Christians at one end of the scale and the
xo per cent or so of convinced skeptics at the other, there is the
vast mass of the population, mostly superstitious to some degree,
using the churches and especially the Church of England to cele-
brate birth, marriage, and death, and to a lesser degree Christmas.
This use or misuse of the churches is rooted in a set of vague,
half formulated and inconsistent beliefs.
In 1944-45 Mass-Observation carried out a survey in a London
borough on the topic of religious belief which was published
under the title of Puzzled People. In 1960 they quota-sampled the
same borough. The inconsistency of both self-styled believers and
self-styled unbelievers is perhaps the most striking single fact.
In both 1945 and 1960 over 40 per cent of those attending Anglican
services said that they did not beli~ve in a life after death, while at
least a quarter of those classed as doubters, agnostics, and atheists
said that they prayed, and over 20 per cent of them said that Christ
was more than a man. Tom Harrisson's account of these people's
beliefs in Britain Revisited is consistent with the answers that
industrial workers gave to Dr. Ferdynand Zweig on religious
questions, and in The British Worker Dr. Zweig concludes that
80 per cent of workers have some sort of "vague belief." But it
would be sadly mistaken to suppose that this state of affairs is
confined to working-class adults and children. The survey of
contemporary attitudes among the readers of New Society (May
1963) showed a majority both for the-belief that Christian morality
is moribund and for the belief that this is a sad thing. But the
majority also believe-what the authoritative exponents of
Christianity deny-that divorce should be made easier. So we
find among some of the best-educated by our conventional
standards a paradoxical wish to hold on to a morality which
conflicts with their own morality on matters of central importance.
Behind this paradox one senses a belief that Christian theology
is false and a wish that it were not, which at other social levels
appears as the kind of half-belief which I have described.
The sources of this lack of consistency are several. The folk-
beliefs of the English cannot be understood without under-
22 Against the Self-Images of the Age
standing the whole history of Christianity's rearguard actions,
including the highly dubious use of religion in wartime. But
we can discover one clue to the immediate causes of the confusion if
we notice that 67 per cent of children who are subjected to
Anglican baptism decline to 24 per cent who find their way to
confirmation; and there is another steep decline to the figures for
adult church-going.
It is just not true that children in this country are indoctrinated
in Christianity as a result of the 1944 Education Act. What they
are indoctrinated in is confusion. This confusion is rooted in the
fact that on the one hand religious instruction is compulsory,
and yet on the other it is clear that schools do not take it seriously
in the way that they do basic literacy or subjects such as history or
chemistry. Since teachers usually do not even attempt to give any
criteria for accepting or rejecting belief, many children naturally
remain in a half-light between acceptance and rejection.
Secularized? Not at all. The secondary modern school children of
whom Dr. Harold Loukes wrote in Teenage Religion would
suggest, for example, that the question of whether God did or did
not make the world could not be answered because nobody else can
have been there to see. If they do believe in God, it is often the
God "up there" (literally, physically "up") who Dr. Robinson
thinks has been incredible for a long time.
Christianity provided pre-industrial England with a common
frame of reference, with a sense of over-all meaning and with a
pattern which gave form to life. Revolutionary protest from the
Levellers to the Chartists could express itself within this pattern
just as much as the conservatism of the squirearchy. But industrial
society has never been able to accommodate a religious interpreta-
tion of its own activities. The founders of atheist humanism
hoped for and predicted secularization not merely in the sense of
abandonment of religious belief and practice, but in the sense of a
transformation of human goals and hopes from other-worldly
into this-worldly. The present was to be judged and transcended,
not by looking to the justice of heaven but by looking to that of the
future. The hope of glory was to be, and in some important
measure was, replaced by the hope of Utopia.
But we have neither glory nor Utopia to hope for. The hope
that a secular Utopian tradition, whether Liberal or Marxist,
sought to provide was never realized. The routines of working-
class life, the competitive ladders of the middle classes, absorb us
into immediacy. We are dominated by a present to which the idea
of a radically different future is alien. What conventional politics
God and the theologians 23
promises us is always a brighter version of what we have now.
This is why political talk about ends and aims is always doomed to
become rhetoric. In this situation the substance of religious
belief is no longer with us, but in our ordinary secular vocabulary
we have no language to express common needs, hopes, and fears
that go beyond the immediacies of technique and social structure.
What we do have is a religious language, which survives even
though we do not know what to say in it. Since it is the only
language we have for certain purposes it is not surprising that it
cannot be finally discarded. But since we have no answers to give
to the questions we ask in it, it remains continually in need of
reinterpretation, reinterpretation that is always bound to fail. We
should therefore expect to find continual attempts to use religious
language to mask an atheistic vacuum, and sooner or later someone
was bound to try to preserve the religious language and the
atheistic content together by suggesting, although not of course
explicitly, that the latter simply is the meaning of the former.
Not that this suggestion could possibly work a cure for any of our
ills. The only cure lies in the transformation of our social structures;
within theological discourse, as Feuerbach and Marx saw, we are
bound to remain blind to the human significance of theological
discourse. Hence Dr. Robinson's book needs not only to be
understood as a symptom of our condition, but to be sympathized
with as a desperate attempt that cannot succeed.
If the core of my argument is correct, then we should be able to
construct a hypothesis about contemporary moral theology.
Either it will remain within the theological closed circle : in which
case it will have no access to the public and shared moral criteria
of our society. Or it will accept those criteria: in which case it
may well have important things to say, but these will not be
distinctively Christian. I take it as partial confirmation of my
argument, therefore, that when we encounter Cambridge theolo-
gians grappling with real moral problems 1 it turns out that their
Christianity is residual. This is not to say that they have not
learnt from Jesus and from Christian traditions; but rather, that
they have learnt in ways that are accessible to the atheist too.
When Professor D. M. MacKinnon writes about extramarital
intercourse he judges alternatives in terms of human concepts of
integrity and stability. He criticizes some uses of the notion of
sacrifice in Christian morality. He argues that Christianity is a
1 Objections to Christian Belief, Four Lectures by D. M. MacKinnon,

H. A. Williams, A. R. Vidler and J, S. Bezzant (London: Constable;


Philadelphia: Lippincott, 1964).
2
24 Against the Self-Images of the Age
unique source of moral inspiration, because it tries to hold together
the truth about what men are and the need for them to be merciful
to one another. But he presents these as truths for anyone to
grasp, whether Christian or not. And this is true also of the
outstanding contribution to the debate from among the Cambridge
theologians, which is made by Mr. H. A. Williams in his essay on
"Psychological Objections to Christianity."
Williams' attack is directed against the moral forms of con-
temporary Christianity. He exposes the fake character of a great
deal of remorse and searching of conscience by describing its role
in providing a welcome barrier to genuine self-knowledge. He
brings out excellently the way in which condemnation of overt
breaches of the sexual code, whether in ourselves or in others, can
be a symptom of a more than ambiguous attitude to sexuality, and
how the price of self-knowledge and truthfulness may be a life
which conventional Christianity condemns. Williams finds a clue
to Christianity in Christ's obvious preference for publicans and
sinners over the clergy. Williams could scarcely be more severe
in his treatment of his own religion, and if it is necessary to ask
whether he goes far enough, it is not because one could go any
farther in that direction. It is rather that he never asks what makes
traits like conscientiousness and a sense of duty so important to
contemporary Christianity. The answer is that these traits belong
to the manner in which we act; they do not define the contents of
our actions. Injunctions to repent, to be responsible, even to be
generous, do not actually tell us what to do. And about the content
of the moral life Christians in fact have no more to say than anyone
else. Christians behave like everyone else but use a different
vocabulary in characterizing their behavior, and so conceal their lack
of distinctiveness. Thus true self-knowledge for Christians would
involve the uncovering of much more than a retreat by individuals
into neurotic self-concealment. But even in this Christians only
reflect a general predicament.
All those in our society who self-consciously embrace beliefs
which appear to confer importance and righteousness upon the
holder become involved in the same strategies. The fact that their
beliefs make so little difference either to them or to others leads
to the same concern with being right-minded rather than effective.
Hygienic, liberal, periodical-reading progressives who are against
capital punishment and blood sports tend to be quite as nasty as
Christians are, in this respect.
And there are many other varieties of the neurotic self-deceiver.
When Williams tries to accuse his fellow-Christians of believing
God and the theologians 25
not in God, but Nobodaddy, I hope that he makes them wince. But
I hope he also makes all those of us wince who have turned
conscientious atheism into a substitute Nobodaddy of our own.
The one person in the discussion clearly determined not to
wince is the Archbishop of Canterbury. His pamphlet Image Old
and New misses almost all the points. Dr. Robinson is treated as an
unbalanced reformer who has stressed some aspects of the
Christian faith at the expense of others. Ascetic retreat from the
world and unbreakable rules still have their place. (Why do
unbreakable rules always turn out to be about sex and not about
war?) But the worst feature of his pamphlet is the paternalistic
tone. He calls Bonhoeffer's views "thoughts mature in depth but
often incomplete, alas, in their working out" and wonders whether,
had he lived, he would not have changed his views. He seeks to
spread reassurance.
But reassurance is just what Christians should not be looking for
at this point in their history. It is not Dr. Robinson who will be
disturbing them, if they are disturbed. The fragility of their
religion is due not to the theologians but to its role in our social
life. This the theologians only reflect. But it is not surprising that
when they reflect it as faithfully as Dr. Robinson has done, all the
vices of self-deception which Mr. Williams castigates are brought
into play, as they have notably been brought into play in so much
of the response to Honest to God.
Because all this is so, it is highly important that the theologians
should not be left alone with their discussions, to carry them on as
they please. For the significance of their discussions extends far
beyond theology. The public response to Honest to God helped to
make this clear. But in the next phase when the issues are less
immediately newsworthy, the danger is that God will once more
be treated as an in-group totem. Once there were organized
secularist groups (the Rationalist Press Association, the Ethical
Union, and the like) which could have assisted in ensuring that the
discussion continued in the public forum. But all these groups
essentially became nonconformist churches and share in the
general decline of nonconformity. So one gets the pathos of
humanist groups in universities which are imitations of the
Student Christian Movement. At the moment one cannot dispense
with this kind of group, if only because it provides a counter-
weight to the Christians. But the danger is that atheism is then
treated as if it too is the private creed of yet another minority
religious group, whereas atheism is in fact expressed in most of our
social life.
26 Against the Self-Images of the Age
The difficulty lies in the combination of atheism in the practice
of the life of the vast majority, with the profession of either
superstition or theism by that same majority. The creed of the
English is that there is no God and that it is wise to pray to him
from time to time.
3
Psychoanalysis: the future
of an illusion?1

The more that is written about psychoanalysis the more puzzled


one can become. On the one hand there are the ever new but
all too familiar expositions of the system. Dr. J. A. C. Brown's2
and Dr. Reuben Fine's 3 are among the most recent to hand.
Excellent as expositions, the time has come when defensive
exposition is not enough. Taken as we are again and again on the
same conducted tour of Freud's views, the intellectual boredom is
intensified. Yet there is a whole series of books which excite and
illuminate, and could not have been written but for Freud. I do
not mean by this simply to assert the truism that there are dull
authors and that there are exciting authors. The contrasts between
psychoanalysts are far more extreme than that. It is rather that
what is at first sight the same Freudian methodology appears
capable both of crippling the intellect and of liberating it. How so ?
Psychoanalysts, like priests, suffer from an initial disadvantage :
they have to take care to keep separate the situations in which they
must assume the pose of authority from those in which they
themselves must accept the authority of rational argument. The
pulpit is no place to debate the existence of God and the couch is
for free association, not for theoretical objections. And yet-
unless the theoretical objections can be answered, the clinical
authority of the analyst is faked. It was Karl Kraus who remarked
that psychoanalysis is in fact the disease for which it purports to be
the cure. One gets a hint that, as so often with Kraus, what looks
like an easy witticism will bear closer scrutiny from the curious
1 Reprinted from Encounter, May 1968.
1 J. A. C. Brown, Freud and the Post-Freudians (London and Baltimore:
Penguin Books, Pelican ed., 1961).
8 Reuben Fine, Freud: A Critical Evaluation of His Theories (New York:

David McKay; London: Allen & Unwin, 1962).


27
Against the Self-Images of the Age
tone which infects the answers that some psychoanalysts make to
their critics. There is an important difference between their attitude
and that of Freud who wrote:
Looking back, then, over the patchwork of my life's labors, I
can say that I have made many beginnings and thrown out
many suggestions. Something will come of them in the future,
though I cannot myself tell whether it will be much or little ....
This underlying caution was always there to temper Freud's
flights of speculative enthusiasm. Unfortunately it appears to be
mainly the speculative enthusiasm which his heirs have inherited
-at least on the occasions when they respond to criticism.
In order to evaluate this response, we must first understand the
critics, and in order to understand them we must set out the
features of psychoanalytic theory which invite criticism. We can
illuminate the logical structure of psychoanalytic theory by
remembering that Freud's contentions were made at three different
levels. First of all, Freud drew our attention to hitherto unnoticed
types of episodes. He reclassified and redescribed our behavior. He
made us aware of what needed to be explained. Secondly, he
suggested a correlation between adult episodes and traits and the
passions and actions of the world of early childhood. Thirdly, he
produced a theory to explain that correlation; or rather he pro-
duced a range of theoretical notions, of which the earlier account
of the distribution and transformations of libido and the later
trinity of id, superego, and ego are the most important. It is often
difficult in exposition to keep the distinction between these
three levels clear, partly because kindred notions appear at all three
and more especially when this is so because the explanatory
theory helps to provide a vocabulary for the description of the very
facts which the theory is designed to explain. One example of this
is the way in which the notion of unconscious motivation is often
used both descriptively to bring out features of goal-directed
behavior in which the agent himself remains unaware of his
goals and resists (again without recognizing what he is doing)
any correct identification of them-and also as part of the
account of the formation of character which is invoked to explain
such behavior. Another is the way in which adult behavior may be
characterized as Oedipal, an instructive resemblance with child-
hood behavior being brought out by a term the use of which
already half-commits us to a particular explanation of this
resemblance.
This transition from level to level is itself important for at least
Psychoanalysis:the future of an illusion? 29
two reasons. There is perhaps no discipline to compare with
psychoanalysis for the way in which the very use of the vocabulary
commits the novice-quite unconsciously-to acceptance of a
complex theoretical framework. And moreover this is common to
all the rival analytic schools, or to all at least which share some sort
of Freudian commitment. Melanie Klein differed from Freud
about many things, and especially the characterization of early
childhood; Freud himself was always prepared to revise his own
theoretical apparatus; but what cannot be revised without loss
of the theory altogether is the notion of a set of childhood traits, a
corresponding set of adult traits, and a theoretical bridge between
them. It is upon the concepts out of which this bridge is to be built
that attention can therefore be focused.
Central among them is that of repression.Freud's own view both
of the cause and of the consequences of repression gradually
changed. He came in his later period to see repression as a response
above all to anxiety, when he had earlier seen anxiety as an effect of
repression. And he came to envisage it as only one of the defensive
strategems to which the threatened ego might resort. But it
retains a central and characteristic place. In a paper of 1908,
Characterand Anal Erotism, Freud wrote that:
We can at any rate lay down a formula for the way in which
character in its final shape is formed out of the constituent
instincts: the permanent character traits are either unchanged
prolongations of the original instincts, or the sublimations
of those instincts, or reaction-formations against them.
To this thought Freud remained faithful; and this required that he
remained faithful also to the notion of repression. Dr. Brown has
summarized his unchanging view in writing:
that the unconscious plays a predominant part in mental
life, since it takes its energy from the instinctual drives, and its
contents are kept out of awareness not because they lack
significance but because they may be so significant as to con-
stitute what is felt as a threat to the ego. When this occurs they
are actively repressed and can find expression only by devious
methods, as in symptoms, certain character traits, and the other
phenomena which represent compromise solutions to a conflict
between primitive drives seeking an outlet and learned ego and
superego behavior patterns which must inhibit them ....
Repression is itself an unconscious process ....
The difficulties which critics have alleged against this position are
30 Against the Self-Images of the Age
of at least three kinds. There is the too open texture of the con-
cepts ; the apparent falsity and the untested character of certain
of the factual claims ; and the unfalsifiability of parts of the
theoretical apparatus. A concept like "repression," for instance, can
only be safely used if we are given criteria for its application, such
that we can identify at least central cases of repression taking
place. For its full use in psychoanalytic theory we should also need
criteria to determine when behavior evidences the effect of re-
pression and when memories that have been recalled have been
recalled as a result of a cessation of repression rather than from
some other possible cause.
But we are supplied with no adequate criteria. We are not told
how to recognize the response of repression when it is first made;
and when later on the analyst interprets his patient's behavior as
manifesting effects of repression, what he will treat as confirmatory
of his interpretation is probably a set of further reactions by the
patient-dreams, newly recalled memories, changes in attitude to
the analyst, and the like. Analysts have discussed with a great deal
of care what the criteria of a correct interpretation ought to be. 1
But while they have produced some interesting generalizations
about the kind of result that may follow from one sort of interpre-
tation rather than another, what they have not done is to explain
how these responses help to confirm the truth of the interpretation,
as distinct from the effectiveness of it in producing further
reactions. To do this successfully we should need the concept of
repression and kindred concepts of defense to be defined more
sharply in operational terms. More than this we must take care to
see that the concepts are not defined in terms of the theory. For if
repression is defined or explained in terms of unconscious instinc-
tual drives, as it is in the quotation from Dr. Brown, then the use
of the term is already part of our theoretical explanation of what
occurs, and we shall still lack an adequate way of characterizing
and identifying the occurrences which the theory is designed to
explain.
At the level of the empirically observable there are much
simpler questions to be put to the analyst. What are the alleged
facts which the theory explains? What factual generalizations are
entailed by the theory and must be true if the theory is true?
Experimental psychologists have expended effort and ingenuity in
1 See especially Susan Isaacs. "Criteria for Interpretation," Inter-
national Journal of Psychoanalysis (1939); and P. M. Turquet, "The
Criteria For A Psychoanalytic Interpretation," Aristotelian Society
Supplementary Volume (1962).
Psychoanalysis: the future of an illusion? 31
trying to specify the necessary generalizations and confirm or
falsify them. The result of this effort is a sifting out from the
Freudian amalgam of particular hypotheses concerning the
effects of maternal deprivation at different ages, the preferences of
children for one parent rather than the other, the formation of
character traits, and so on. When these hypotheses are tested, we
find that the Freudian doctrine seems to be a mixture of true and
false statements. In so appearing it loses its unity of structure. This
loss is further intensified by the separating out in the process of the
testable elements in the theory from the untestable.
I am not now referring to the kind of untestability which
derives from the too open texture of the key concepts, but to the
tendency to specify too many ways in which the theory may be
confirmed and not enough ways in which it might be falsified.
Consider the already quoted statement from Character and Anal
Erotism. The instinctual drives may be transformed so that they
manifest themselves in one way; or it may be the processes of
reaction formation result in their being manifested in a precisely
opposite way. The same type of background may result in sadistic,
aggressive behavior or in gentle, nonviolent behavior. The
hypothesis has become a bet that cannot lose; but by the same
token, as Karl Popper has shown, it cannot win. Whatever the
behavior, the hypothesis is not falsified, and its unfalsifiability is
fatal to its status as a hypothesis.
All this is preliminary to a central argument. The criticisms
I have summarized are almost overfamiliar to analysts.1 But what
has been inadequately commented upon is the type of answer
which is being made by the analysts and their supporters to the
critics. I ought in fairness to the reader to stress that I am going
to try to set out the analytic case against the critics at its strongest.
That is why I want to attend especially to arguments used by Dr.
Brown and Dr. Edward Glover.
Begin with Brown's reply to the charge that experimental
evidence does not bear out Freud s hypotheses:
That two American psychologists should ask college students to
recall at random pleasant and unpleasant experiences on the
assumption that, if repression were a fact, more of the former
than the latter would be recalled is bad enough; that, as Professor
1 See especially H.J. Eysenck, "What is Wrong with Psychoanalysis?"
in Uses and Abuses of Psychology (London and Baltimore: Penguin
Books, Pelican) and B. A. Farrell, "Psychoanalytic Theory?" in New
Society, June 20 and 27, 1963.
32 Against the Self-Images of the Age
Eysenck assures us, a group of strong and presumably normal
individuals were persuaded to starve themselves for an appre-
ciable period in order to prove that Freud's theory of dreams
as wish-fulfillments was false because they did not dream of
food, strains one's credibility; but that an eminent educational
psychologist should solemnly "prove" the Oedipus complex
to be a myth by the simple expedient of asking a number of
other professional psychologists about the preferences of their
own children towards one parent or the other baffies com-
prehension. Freud at no time said that unpleasant experiences
as such were likely to be forgotten; he said that experiences
which might conflict with other dominant tendencies of the
personality were likely to be repressed, whether as experiences
they were pleasant or not; he did not say that for any appreciable
period a child showed overt preference for the parent of the
opposite sex, because the very word "complex" refers to
unconsdous attitudes which are unconscious precisely because
they are forbidden; he did not assert that hunger made one
dream of food, although explorers and others subjected in-
voluntarily to hunger have said that it did, and he would
certainly have seen through the fallacy of supposing that
voluntary and experimental subjection to starvation bears any
resemblance in its emotional significance to the involuntary
situation in which the basic issue is not primarily lack of food but
imminent proximity of death. 1
Let us concede at once the crudity of the experiments referred to;
but even that crudity is a testimony to the difficulty of translating
Freudian concepts into terms that will yield testable hypotheses. If
the experimentalists have, as Brown accuses, mistranslated the
concepts, the only adequate rejoinder would be to produce a
correct translation and then await the verdict of experiment.
But not only does Brown not do this, he does not even seem to
admit the suggestion that there is a need for experiment. Yet until
and unless such translations and experiments are provided the best
available verdict on psychoanalytic theory would be that of "Not
Proven." None the less Brown claims that
Freud alone amongst the founders of analytic schools under-
stood and made thorough use of the scientific method in his
investigations. Freud's approach was as logical and his findings
as carefully tested as Pavlov's, but he was able to deal success-
fully with phenomena inaccessible to Pavlov....
1 J. A. C. Brown, op. cit., pp. 192-3.
Psychoanalysis:the future of an illusion? 33
Yet throughout Brown's book what we are offered are confirmatory
observations, not crucial tests of Freudian theory.
It is of course not only the opponents of analysis who have
recognized the need for more inquiry at this point. Dr. Edward
Glover has subjected both the lack of adequate definition of
concepts and the absence of prediction and testing from psycho-
analytic work to a critique as fierce as that of any experimentalist.
But, so he has argued in two recent papers, 1 we should not there-
fore arrive at negative conclusions about psychoanalysis. For the
carefully devised experiments of the ordinary descriptive psycho-
logist are themselves suspect, since in the experimental study of
variations in the behavior of a particular group compared with a
control group, we may ignore the possibility of unconscious
factors affecting the behavior of the chosen control, in such a way
that the matching and comparison are unreliable.
From all this follows the somewhat disconcerting conclusion
that under present systems of control we have no sound
justification for abandoning a causal theory simply because the
application of statistical controls appears to show that it is
non-specific. When allegedly scientific procedures appear to
point conclusively in one direction, the investigator of deep
and unconscious factors should not be too perturbed if these
conclusions run counter to his own interpretations. Although
apparently wrong by the standards of natural science he may
yet be right by the standards of depth psychology.
The difficulty with this argument lies in its covert circularity.
We cannot trust present experimental techniques because their
use neglects the operation of unconscious factors; the only
techniques which would be reliable would therefore be those
which took account of the operation of such factors. But to admit
the existence of the kind of unconscious factors of which Dr.
Glover speaks is already to concede substantial truth to the very
body of theory which we require to be tested. Dr. Glover's
criticism of the experimentalists presupposes that the issue
which divides him from them has already been fundamentally
settled in his favor. Appearing to concede the need for neutral
experiment, he in fact lays down preconditions for the construction
of such experiments which ensure that his own positions will
1 Edward Glover, "Psychoanalysis and 'Controlled' Research in
Delinquency," British Journal of Cn'minology (1962), and "Research
Techniques in Psychoanalysis and in General Psychology," in Readings
in Psychology, edited by John Cohen (New York: Hillary House, 1964).
34 Against the Self-Images of the Age
remain basically unscathed. It is this that makes the onus of
disproof which he lays upon the experimental critics so unreal.
The inescapable conclusion of this part of the argument is that
psychoanalytic theory is in no sense well founded and that it is not
science in any recognizable sense. But this is not just because it is
inadequately vindicated by experiment. It is much more because,
although it clearly is in fact not vindicated, it is presented by its
adherents as though its truth were well established. Dr. Brown
compares Freud to Newton; Dr. Glover says that "Freud was able
to establish some of the most important laws regarding human
behavior"; Dr. Fine asserts that general psychology now accepts
the core of Freud's work. Brown and Fine give the impression
that the rejection of psychoanalysis is eccentric and restricted to
an imperceptive minority. But Professor 0. H. Mowrer, by any
standards a central figure in the development of contemporary
psychology, decided in the end for "the basic unsoundness of
Freud's major premises." This kind of conclusion the layman all
too seldom has brought to his attention.
But it works, so it will be said, Surely, it will be added, it is
unforgivable to have treated psychoanalysis primarily as a body of
explanations rather than as a method of therapy. Yet the whole
argument so far is intended, above all, to raise a question about
the therapy. It has often been asserted that the therapy is in-
effective; roughly speaking, such evidence as there is points to an
insufficiently dissimilar rate of cure for patients who are not
treated at all as for those who are treated by analysis. But the
evidence is not very good and about it, once again, the important
point is not that the claims of psychoanalysishave been overthrown,
but that they have never been vindicated. Yet even this is not
what is crucial. What matters is that the practice of the therapy
presupposes the truth of the theory. The claim that what the
patient acquires is genuine self-knowledge of a past still alive in his
present can only be made good if the theoretical bridge between
childhood and adult life does not break down. The authority of
the analyst in his therapeutic role rests on his supposed theoretical
equipment and backing as well as his clinical skills. Yet the theory
which the therapy embodies is a theory in which neither analyst nor
patient have a right to be confident. But without confidence the
therapy could not even begin. So how is the confidence to be
engendered? Only in unjustifiable ways. .
The larger problem is the sociological one. False or unjustified
assertions have been propagated in our time with the power of
almost omnipotent states to back them up; beliefs now usually
Psychoanalysis: the future of an illusion? 35
discredited but once plausible have often survived into our own
age. But I know of no other example of a system of beliefs,
unjustified on the basis of the criteria to which it itself appeals, and
unbacked by political power or past tradition, which has propa-
gated itself so successfully as Freudian orthodoxy. How did it do
it?
Consider the following vocabulary: adjustment, conflict,
integrate, relate, relationship .... It is the vocabulary of Jules
Feiffer's characters. It is also the vocabulary of Feiffer's readers:
the vocabulary of a segment of urban, middle-class intelligentsia
whose cultural situation deprived them of large-scale theory at the
same time as it made large-scale theory an intense necessity for
them. The skepticism of an earlier generation had deprived them
of religion. The history of their own time deprived them of
Marxism and in so doing of their hold upon the public world of
political ends. The intellectual may be socially valued for his
functional utility; but otherwise, his arena is increasingly that of
private life. He needs to make his own experience intelligible:
an image of the public world as a mere projection upon a larger
screen of the private rages and longings, hopes and fears which
circumscribe him. The intolerable character of his condemnation
to private life is relieved by an overpersonalization of that life.
The ideology of personal relationships invokes a public sanction
in the closed system of psychoanalytic theory. And a whole
vocabulary of personal relationships enables psychoanalysis to
appear, not as one more questionable theory, but as the un-
questionable framework which gives life meaning.
Yet if this suggestion-which amounts to saying that psycho-
analysis is the folk religion of one section of the intelligentsia-
were not only true, but the whole truth, we should scarcely
expect the series of encounters between psychoanalysis and the
larger world of society, politics and history to be as fruitful as
they have been. Two books published since 1958 furnish a record
of such encounters. They are Bruno Bettelheim's The Informed
Heart 1 and Erik H. Erikson's Young Man Luther: A Study in
Psychoanalysis and History. 2 Both exhibit a certain ambivalence
toward the orthodox psychoanalytic tradition. Both return us to
Freud himself, but to a different Freud both from the Freud of
orthodoxy and from the Freud of each other.
Bettelheim is at once the most striking and the most intelligently
radical of Freudian revisionists. He is the most striking because his
1 New York: Free Press; London: Thames and Hudson, 1961.
2 New York: W.W. Norton; London: Faber and Faber, 1959.
Against the Self-Images of the Age
revisions began in Dachau and Buchenwald. He is intelligently
radical in his clear statement of what must be rejected in Freud.
What struck me first was ... that those persons who according
to psychoanalytic theory as I understood it then, should have
stood up best under the rigor of the camp experience, were
often very poor examples of human behavior under extreme
stress.
So he began to reflect on the nature of environment and on the
apparent irrelevance of the explanation of types of behavior in
terms of their origin.
It just would not do under conditions prevailing in the camps
to view courageous, life-endangering actions as an outgrowth
of the death instinct, aggression turned against the self, testing
the indestructibility of the body, megalomaniac denial of
danger, histrionic feeding of one's narcissism or whatever other
category the action would have to be viewed from in psycho-
analysis.
Not only the predictions, but also the values of psychoanalysis
were put in question, and a common root was discerned for both
errors. This root lay in the attention paid to the pathological, the
lack of attention to the normal. Bettelheim stresses how psycho-
analytic explanations of genius explain everything but the genius.
Work, art, social life: all the normal ends of man evade being
treated as the outcrops of infantile patterns.
When Bettelheim discusses his own experience in the camps in
detail what is striking is the way in which psychoanalysts' concepts
become less and less theoretical, more and more descriptive. The
same is true of Erikson's work. Erikson-both in his earlier work
Childhood and Society and in his study of Luther-uses not the
Freudian system, but rather Freud's techniques of observation.
He pays attention to the facts which Freud discovered rather than
to the theoretical entities alleged to be lurking behind these facts.
And he works empirically, generalizing from instance to instance,
and making modest predictions based on such generalizations. So
he detects a pattern of crises in the development of the child. He
makes use of Freud's descriptions to illuminate these crises;
but his theory of stages is derived not from the theory so much
as from generalizations about the empirical material of a much
more modest kind than are some of Freud's own larger statements.
The historical material is in his hands not something to which a
ready-made psychoanalytic theory is applied. The vindication of
Psychoanalysis:the future of an illusion? 37
Erikson's statements about Luther lies in the evidenceabout Luther,
not in the congruence with established psychoanalytic doctrine.
In other words, psychoanalysis need not become the self-enclosed
system which it so often is. But how do we avoid this? What is
the difference between Brown and Fine on the one hand and
Bettelheim and Erikson on the other?
Part of the answer is surely obtained by considering the strain
within Freud's own writings between observation and explanation,
between the material he amasses and the theoretical forms into
which he cast his presentation of that material. The comparison
with Newton misled not only his expositors but Freud himself.
What Freud showed us were hitherto unnoticed facts, hitherto
unrevealed motives, hitherto unrelated facets of our life. And in
doing so his achievement broke all preconceived conceptual
schemes-including his own. As a discoverer he perhaps resembles
a Proust or a Tolstoy rather than a Dalton or a Pasteur. We could
have learnt this from reading Freud himself; but the division
among his heirs also reveals the fact clearly.
Yet both sets of heirs are legitimate. The sterility and the
perversity are as Freudian as the perceptive fertility of a Bettelheim
or an Erikson. Freud, too, was a victim of the need to explain, of
the need to be Newton. The paradox of the history of psycho-
analysis is that it is those analysts most intent on presenting their
subject as a theoretical science who have transformed it into a
religion, those most concerned with actual religious phenomena,
such as !Bettelheim (who has written a monograph on initiation
rites) and Erikson, who have preserved it as science. The achieve-
ment of Bettelheim and Erikson has been to extend our subjection
to the phenomena themselves. But in so doing they have not
diminished but increased its complexity.
The outcome of Freud's discoveries is to leave us not with a
solution but with more problems, among them the problem of how
to understand the analysts themselves, and the differences be-
tween them.
4

The socialism of R. H. Tawney 1

The deaths of R. H. Tawney and Hugh Gaitskell occurred so close


together that they provide an apt symbol for the end of a period
in the history of the British Labour Movement. It was a period in
which the Right wing of the Labour Party was hard put to it to
provide a rationale for its policies, which would both justify its
opposition to Marxism and yet enable it to escape from the plati-
tudes of merely liberal good will. The number of those who
might have provided such a rationale were surprisingly few. The
Webbs defected to Stalinism from the Fabian Society (consistent
elitists who believed throughout their career in socialism imposed
from above, they merely changed in their choice of elite) ; John
Strachey only defected to the Fabian Society from Stalinism at
the end of the 1930s; and G. D. H. Cole was always too much of a
Marxist to work within the limitations that the Labour Right
imposed upon itself. Tawney therefore stood almost alone.
The present collection of essays,2 written at various dates be-
tween 1914 and 1953, reiterates themes from all Tawney's major
work. In The Acquisitive Society he criticized capitalism because
it encouraged economic power without social responsibility. The
right to property had become separated from any obligation to
discharge a useful social function. In Equality he attacked the view
that the natural inequality of man in respect of ability justified
inequalities of wealth and status; rather, so he argued, it would be
in an egalitarian society that diversity of abilities would flourish
most for the common good. In Religion and the Rise of Capitalism
he studied the origins of acquisitive individualism. The present
collection of occasional pieces on social history, on education, and
in defense of the programs and performances of British social
1 Reprinted with permission from The New York Review of Books.
Copyright© 1964 The New York Review.
2 A review of R. H. Tawney, The Radical Tradition, edited by Rita

Hinden (London: Allen & Unwin; New York: Pantheon Books, 1964).
38
The socialism of R. H. Tawney 39
democracy, accompanied by a preface by Rita Hinden and by
Gaitskell's address at the 1962 Memorial Service for Tawney,
makes an illuminating book.
The heart of the matter for Tawney is the moral deficiency of
capitalism.
The revolt of ordinary men against Capitalism has had its
source neither in its obvious deficiencies as an economic engine,
nor in the conviction that it represents a stage in social evolu-
tion now outgrown, but in the straightforward hatred of a
system which stunts personality and corrupts human relations
by permitting the use of man by man as an instrument of
pecuniary gain. . .. "
It is this demon-the idolatry of money and success-with
whom, not in one sphere alone but in all, including our own
hearts and minds, Socialists have to grapple.
Sentences like these are scattered throughout Tawney's writings.
One need not be a cynic nor an immoralist to find so much cliche-
ridden high-mindedness suspect. The answer of his admirers
may be to stress, as Gaitskell does in his address, Tawney's
personal goodness-"! think he was the best man I have ever
known." The difficulty is that what both the reminiscences and
Tawney's own writings communicate is a banal earnestness rather
than the manifold virtues ascribed and praised. It is fairly clear
what is missing. The moral denunciation of British capitalism
took its content and its interest not from the morality of socialists
but from the immorality and evil of capitalism. What we miss in
these essays is the social context of the 1920s, of poverty, of un-
employment, of suffering.
Moreover the immediacy of these evils was linked with a hard-
headed, common-sense practicality about their cure. Public
ownership of the coal mines or the railways in Britain was not a
radical solution; that it was the only solution, was implicitly
acknowledged by the lack of Conservative opposition when the
measures were finally put through Parliament in the late 1940s.
But why did it take so long to achieve this solution? A govern-
ment commission headed by Mr. Justice Sankey and including,
along with Tawney, men of widely different views had recom-
mended the nationalization of the mines in 1919. The reason for
the delay lies in the failure of nerve in Britain's ruling class be-
tween the two wars. The politicians of the age-MacDonald,
Snowden, Bonar Law, Baldwin, and Chamberlain-are in per-
spective tiny and impotent figures. No wonder that in comparison
Agat'nst the Self-Images of the Age
with them Tawney assumed the appearance of great moral stature.
Yet if he appears impressive by contrast, we must also ask whether
in many ways he did not share many of the attitudes and indeed
illusions of his contemporaries.
Tawney equated capitalism with private capitalism, and private
capitalism with the effective sovereignty of the functionless share-
holder. He defined socialism on at least two levels, both of which
were inadequate. At one level he meant the moral values of
fraternity and equality, which are, unhappily, terms too vague
and general for political guidance until they are embodied in
specific social practices and institutions. At another level he
defined socialism by his concept of capitalism: the replacement
of private ownership by public ownership or control and the
state's acceptance of responsibility for social welfare. Thus he
never took stock of the capitalism of the big corporation-the
capitalism which may for its own purposes accept trade unionism,
the welfare state, and even measures of state intervention and
public ownership. He is in fact oblivious not merely of Keynes,
but of the kind of capitalist ethos in which neo-Keynsian politics
could be made effective.
Yet is it not perhaps absurd to criticize Tawney for being
limited by the horizon of his period? Not if what we are criticizing
is above all lack of political intelligence and imagination. The
lack of political imagination is notably present in his estimate
(reprinted in The Radical Tradition) of the role and achievement of
the postwar Labour government. He profoundly underestimates
the continuity of that government with the wartime coalition
government. He writes of the Labour ministers as if they were by
deliberate choice implementing socialist policies, when in fact
they were providing the necessary and inevitable solutions to the
problem of laying a new basis for British capitalism. He never
mentions the frustration and disillusionment that that govern-
ment engendered, especially among its working-class supporters.
To say this is not to underrate the achievements involved in im-
plementing the 1944 Education Act (passing it was the work of
the wartime coalition government), or of the handing over of
power in India, or of the creation of the National Health Service.
It is to say that any intelligent pragmatist, thoroughly but far-
sightedly imbued with capitalist values, could not and would not
have done otherwise. And it is not only that Tawney underrated
the resources of an intelligent conservative defense of capitalism.
In his statement of socialist objectives he is curiously blind to
how greatly his declared ends and his chosen means were at odds
The socialism of R.H. Tawney 41
with one another. He cared passionately that workers should
extend their control over the work process; and he wanted,
probably more than anything else, to democratize the British
educational system. Yet the kind of orthodox Labour Party politics
in which he put his hope has always been managerial and merito-
cratic. The Labour Party has shown immense hostility to those
rank-and-file trade unionists who have been concerned with
issues of workers' control; and it has shown a simple lack of
interest in many less radical measures concerned with democracy
in industry. In education the Labour Party's support for compre-
hensive schools and for equality of opportunity did not, when it
was in office, prevent it from helping to create through the 1944
Education Act a class system in education which not only favors
the middle-class child, but has helped to create new class barriers.
Labour is increasingly the political expression not of workers, but
of managers and technocrats. It is the party of the other half of
our ruling class.
Why did Tawney succeed in concealing from himself as well as
from others the extent to which the British Labour Party is
merely an alternative Conservative Party? One answer can be found
in The Radical Tradition. Tawney did not lack that essentially
English quality, insularity. It is no accident that there is little in
his book about peace or international socialism. In his essay on
"Social Democracy in Britain" he asserts that "it is not for a
foreigner to discuss" the standing of capitalism in the United
States. And he appears to restrict himself not only geographically
but theoretically. We have jibes-not arguments-against Marxism,
and economic expertise is treated as a topic for a joke. The limits
of theoretical inquiry appear to be those which actually exist in
the House of Commons, a not very theoretical body.
Tawney thus appears to define politics itself as what might go
on in a British Parliament. Since the role of Parliament, and con-
sequently of electoral politics, in the decision-making processes of
British life has steadily declined, it is not surprising that already
his writings have a curiously antique air. He never even asks
whether Parliament may not be among the institutions which
need democratizing. And however radical he may be about the
economic activities of private capitalism, he is a true member of
the Labour Party in being completley complacent about British
political institutions.
So a book of essays designed to celebrate "the Democratic
Socialist philosopher par excellence" is in fact a monument to the
impotence of ideals. It is not that Tawney failed to live up to his
42 Against the Self-Images of the Age
ideals or to propagate them. He succeeded admirably. Nor is it
that his ideals were insufficientlyhigh. It is simply that the Socratic
question of whether one would rather have one's shoes mended
by a good cobbler or a good man has relevance in politics too.
Goodness is not enough.
5
How not to write about Lenin 1

Discussions of historical method rarely illuminate one crucial


point: what kind of rapport must the historian have with his
subject if he is to write about it successfully? Clearly it is not just
a matter of a certain sympathy to be felt by the historian for his
subject. A certain lack of sympathy may indeed be necessary. But
it must be a lack of sympathy of the right kind. For those who intend
to write about Lenin there are at least two prerequisites. The first
is a sense of scale. One dare not approach greatness of a certain
dimension (and what holds of Lenin would hold equally of
Robespierre or of Napoleon) without a sense of one's own limita-
tions. A Lilliputian who sets out to write Gulliver's biography
had best take care. Above all he dare not be patronizing. This
danger is not entirely avoided by all the contributors to a new set
of essays about Lenin. 2
The second prerequisite is a sense of tragedy which will enable
the historian to feel both the greatness and the failure of the
October Revolution. Those for whom the whole project of the
revolutionary liberation of mankind from exploitation and aliena-
tion is an absurd fantasy disqualify themselves from writing about
Communism in the same way that those who find the notion of the
supernatural redemption of the world from sin an outmoded
superstition disqualify themselves from writing ecclesiastical
history. How much can be achieved none the less is witnessed to
by Gibbon and by Hume, as well as by their successors; and how
much is necessarily missed out is witnessed to at the same time.
So far as the October Revolution is concerned, a sense of tragedy
is as likely to be obliterated as effectivelyby the spirit of orthodox
hagiography as it is by the philistinism so characteristic of much
anti-Communism. Indeed orthodox hagiography has had to ignore
entirely the truth about Lenin's last days.
1Reprinted from Encounter, May 1968.
2Leonard Schapiro and Peter Reddaway, eds., Lenin: The Man, the
Theorist, the Leader (New York: Praeger; London: Pall Mall, 1967).
43
44 Against the Self-Images of the Age
Among Lenin's likes were cats, hunting, tidiness, and Pushkin;
among his dislikes bohemianism, religion, and Mayakovsky. He
once found himself unable to shoot a fox because "really she was
so beautiful." He feared the power of great music to distract his
energies and emotions from revolutionary ends. These and other
opaque facts about his complex and subtle character are brought
out in an excellent essay by Peter Reddaway entitled "Literature,
the Arts and the Personality of Lenin." Reddaway also notes the
traits singled out by commentators as different as Trotsky,
Lunacharsky, and Berdyaev, an overriding simplicity and cer-
tainty of revolutionary purpose. "Purity of heart," wrote Kierke-
gaard, "is to will one thing." It was Lenin's purity of heart that
his opponents could not and his critics cannot bear. This trait
has been subject of much misunderstanding. It is often treated as a
personal characteristic which Lenin simply happened to have,
and so it will appear if it is detached from the theoretical judg-
ments which informed it.
Professor Leonard Schapiro, Mr. Reddaway's co-editor,
stresses Lenin's "fear that the revolution might be 'missed'. As he
saw it, compromises, reforms, concessions by the government, a
rise in living standards, could all easily operate to postpone or
even render impossible or very difficult" the revolution predicted
by Marx. What Schapiro does not discuss is the question of the
source of this fear. To this question there may be a surprising
answer. Lenin shared the views of those Marxists whom he was
shortly to denounce as "economists" apparently up to his receiv-
ing in his Siberian exile in 1899 Eduard Bernstein's Die Voraussetz-
ungen des Sozialismus und die Aufgabe der Sozialdemokratie. That
he then proceeded to refute and denounce Bernstein is well
known; in this he was at one with every orthodox Marxist, includ-
ing his future bitter enemy Kautsky. But in this denunciation he
did not continue to believe, as Kautsky believed, that the history
of capitalism was moving forward in a law-governed way so that
even if the transformation of the labor movement into a revolu-
tionary socialist movement and the subsequent victory of socialism
was not quite an automatic process, it was in some sense inevitable.
It is difficult to see that Lenin took anywhere but from Bernstein
his new belief that in the course of capitalism's development the
working class might be domesticated and the trade unions become
the instrument of that domestication. Certainly even on this point
Lenin did not agree with Bernstein. What Bernstein thought was
in fact going to happen, Lenin took to represent only one possi-
bility, but it was the possibility which would be realized unless
How not to write about Lenin 45
pos1t1ve countervailing action were taken. In the very act of
attempting to refute revisionism Lenin seems to have learnt from
it.
The socialist revolution is then from 1899 onward an urgent
matter of will, organization, and an eye for opportunity. Any road
is permissible which runs more nearly toward the goal than any
other road perceived at the same moment. This single criterion
allows for a combination of undeviating purpose and flexibility
of both tactics and doctrine. The flexibility of Lenin's doctrine
has also another source. Lenin saw threats to the revolution from
a number of directions quite as, if not more, clearly than he en-
visaged the road forward. Consequently he rarely devoted himself
to expounding doctrine except in the context of polemic. Since
he polemicized from time to time on several fronts and tended to
allow his project of the moment to be aimed at defeating one
particular enemy once and for all, it is not surprising that the
key texts are not merely not entirely consistent with each other,
but form, in some way, a collection of fragments. Out of these
fragments a monument has been built-and admiration and en-
mity have both contributed to it-called "Leninism." But "Lenin-
ism" has a purely factitious unity. The doctrines of State and
Revolution (1917), for example, contain elements which are found
nowhere else in Lenin. Among these is a strongly stated belief in
the possibility of the radical democratization of society immediately
after the socialist revolution. This belief is not only at odds with
Lenin's general attitude to the working class; it is one that he
never seems to have taken seriously when within a year the
revolution had occurred and he was proceeding to construct the
socialist order. Again if we compare his attitude to the working
class under capitalism in What Is To Be Done? ( 1902) with that in
Imperialism: The Highest Stage of Capitalism (1916) there is at
least a crucial difference of emphasis. In the former he sees the
natural trend in the development of the working class as being
nonrevolutionary; in the latter he sees the nonrevolutionary
character of the working class as having to be explained by the use
of the superprofits of imperialism to buy off the aristocracy of
labor. It is not that these two theses could not under certain con-
ditions be reconciled. It is rather that Lenin tends to confront
problems in isolation from each other.
Nor is this surprising. Lenin poses the problem of the transition
tst>socialism. About this Marx said very little, Engels only slightly
more, and Engels' remarks on victory through parliamentary
elections and the outdatedness of military insurrections were
Against the Self-Images of the Age
scarcely likely to be appreciated by Lenin. Classical Marxism is a
doctrine in which insight into the bourgeois societies of the mid-
and late-nineteenth century was bought at the price of all too
close a reflection of the categories of that society in its own theories.
In consequence when Marxism came to be applied to new situa-
tions at the end of the nineteenth century and the beginning of the
twentieth century would-be Marxists were left with a good deal
of freedom, both theoretical and practical. The phenomena of
imperialism, for example, evoked quite different responses from
Rosa Luxemburg, from Lenin in 1899, and from Lenin in 1916.
In The Development of Capitalism in Russia (1899), as Professor
Alec Nove points out in his outstanding essay, "Lenin as Econo-
mist," Lenin argued against Struve's view that foreign trade can
be a means by which capitalism can rid itself of surpluses which it
cannot sell on the home market. According to Imperialism-and
Lenin makes no reference to his own past views-such surpluses
can at least for a time be exported. But this very inconsistency is a
sign of the degree of freedom which Marxist theorists possessed
at this period.
This freedom to theorize within a framework which was a good
deal less constraining than even the Marxist theorists themselves
believed and liked to believe makes the old question of whether
Lenin was or was not a genuine and orthodox Marxist one to which
rival answers can with equal plausibility be given. Some of these
rival answers are discussed by Professor J. C. Rees, who points
out acutely how one can frame an impressive case--as Sukhanov
and other Mensheviks did-for saying that on Marxist grounds
Russia was in 1917 far from ready for a proletarian revolution;
but that one could also in 1917 have framed an impressive case
for saying that Marxist theory supplied no ready-made recipes
for application to Russia and that what was required was a creative
remaking of the Marxist categories.
Not all the contributors to this volume are as clear as Professor
Rees is about the kind of advantage that we have over Lenin in
being able to view his actions as he could not, just because we
know what happened next. The shadow of what happened next
can far too easily be allowed to obscure what in fact happened.
It ought also to be remarked that Mensheviks have been better
at writing memoirs since 1917 than they were at making political
decisions at the time. For when the worst has been said about
Lenin it is clear that there was no possibility of Marxist revolution
except for that which Lenin seized upon and indeed partly created.
We ought not to confuse a proper grasp of the tragic dimensions
How not to write about Lenin 47
of the October Revolution with the sentimentality that actually
prefers tragic failures of integrity to any substantial achievement
and so idolizes Martov and even finds it far easier to come to terms
with Trotsky or Rosa Luxemburg than with Lenin, just because
in the end they were losers. But of course none the less Lenin lost
too. His late protests against bureaucracy, against the low level of
Soviet culture and more specifically against Stalin-those protests
which the hagiographers cannot take seriously-in no way amount
to any kind of renunciation of the revolution, but Lenin did none
the less acknowledge some of his responsibility for some of the
negative sides of the Soviet Revolution. Yet Stalinism was not in
any sense the legitimate successor even of the negative sides of
Lenin's work. The claim that Stalin's work continued Lenin's is
familiar not only from Stalinist pens, but also in the writings of
those critics of Lenin who wish to fasten on him responsibility
for a variety of policies which he never envisaged.
To those critics one must concede at least two points. The first
is that Lenin of course was always prepared for tactical retreats
from socialist principles and was prepared to be almost indefinitely
flexible and adaptive; but where Lenin recognized such retreats
for what they were, Stalin presented them as advances toward
socialism and in the course of doing so redefined socialism away
into tyranny. The second is that it is certainly true that under-
lying such Leninist retreats was a crude utilitarianism: the end of
socialism justifies any necessary means. But the key word here is
"necessary." The memoirs of Victor Serge, for example, witness
to Lenin's personal humanity in 1917-18. There was never in
Lenin the sense of pleasure in terror or the sense of gratuitous
personal hostility so evident in Stalin. It remains true that such
utilitarianism corrupts and corrupted, that it formed the moral
link between Lenin and Stalin.
Lenin's was a heroic attempt to force a social situation unfore-
seen by Marx into the categories of Marxist theory, and to do this
not merely in theory but in deed. The future as Lenin envisaged
it was the same future which Marx had envisaged. The past
which Lenin viewed was the past which Marx had depicted.
Lenin's task was to remake the present so that it might be a bridge
between that past and that future. The intractability of that
present, its refusal to be molded in Leninist ways, teaches the
moral that Leninism provides us with few, if any, specific political
recipes; what Lenin achieved in spite of that intractability carries
the moral that this may not be as important as Lenin's detractors
have thought.
6

How not to write about Stalin 1

Miss Stalin 2 both demonstrates and helps to perpetuate one of the


myths of the modern world: the belief that the explanation of
what is puzzling on the public stage lies in the realm of private life.
There is a small grain of truth here. Sometimes a man's relations
with his wife or friends may suggest a new light in which to see
his actions as a revolutionary or a statesman. But in general what
is crucial in the relationship of private to public life is the irrele-
vance of the one to the other. That Himmler detested cruelty to
animals does nothing to explain the politics of the Final Solution.
Miss Stalin's revelation that her father was exceptionally good at
handling domestic servants is quite as uninteresting, and obviously
so. Less obvious and therefore more dangerous is the suggestion
that two of Stalin's personal relationships may explain at least in
part the development and character of his tyranny.
The first of Miss Stalin's suggestions is that her mother's
suicide may have played a decisive role in Stalin's development.
"What was the effect of my mother's death? Did it simply leave
my father free to do what he would have done in any case? Or was
it that her suicide broke his spirit and made him lose his faith in
all his old friends?" The second suggestion is that the author of the
essential evil in Stalin's career was Beria. Kirov's murder, for
example, so Miss Stalin says, was far more probably the work of
Beria than of Stalin. The two suggestions are linked, for Beria's
ascendancy followed, on Miss Stalin's interpretation, the death of
her mother. It is true that she claims that she is not trying to shift
blame from Stalin to Beria: none the less she writes that "the spell
cast on my father by this terrifying evil genius was extremely
powerful, and it never failed to work."
1 Reprinted from The Yale Law Journal.
2 Svetlana Alliluyeva, Twenty Letters to a Friend. Translated by
Priscilla Johnson McMillan (New York: Harper & Row; London:
Hutchinson, 1967).
HO'IJJnot to write about Stalin 49
Her metaphor is at once revealing and inapposite. Everything
we know about Stalin makes the notion of him as somehow spell-
bound extremely unconvincing. But Miss Stalin has no other
terms in which to think of her father. In particular she seems
incapable of thinking in political terms. Hence those of Stalin's
political actions which impinged upon her-the imprisonment of
Alexander Svanidze or that of Polina Molotov-appear in her
narrative as arbitrary and unrelated actions. This appearance of
arbitrariness infects even her account of her mother's suicide.
She says of her mother's suicide note that she has been told by
those who saw it that "it was a terrible letter, full of reproaches
and accusations. It wasn't purely personal; it was partly political
as well." But either she does not know or she is unwilling to say
what the political content of the note was. Her comments are as
follows:
People shot themselves fairly often in those days. Trotskyism
had been defeated. Collectivization of the farms had just gotten
under way. The Party was torn by opposition and factional
strife. One leading Party member after another did away with
himself. Mayakovsky had shot himself only a short time before.
People couldn't make sense of this, and the memory was still
very fresh. I think all this couldn't fail to have had its effect on
my mother, impulsive and susceptible as she was. The Allilu-
yevas were all sensitive and high-strung ... (p. 114).
In other words, suicide was breaking out all over and her mother
was peculiarly liable to contagion. But there is in fact no reason for
believing that N adezhda Alliluyeva was peculiarly vulnerable to
suicide, except that she did in fact kill herself; and suicide was
relatively frequent at that period for highly specific reasons, on
which her remarks about Party strife throw no light. Party strife
had been bitter for many years without bringing comrades to self-
destruction.
The hypothesis I would advance about Nadezhda Alliluyeva's
suicide is suggested partly by its date, November 1932. It occurred,
that is, when the consequences of Stalin's politics of forced collec-
tivization and speeded-up industrialization had already become
clear, but when the repression and the purges in the Party had yet
to begin. Terror in the countryside and increased exploitation of
the working class had become central facts of Soviet social life,
but the mass killing of Communists would still have seemed novel
and horrific even to those who were about to carry it out. Stalinism
had laid its economic foundation, to use a different idiom, but it
50 Against the Self-Images of the Age
had not yet erected its political superstructure. What was the
relationship between these two periods?
The key lies in the nexus between Stalin's economic policies-
which were directed toward problems for which, as Trotsky never
fully understood, there were no soci.alistsolutions-and the politi-
cal need for purges created by the failure to acknowledge that
socialist theory had perforce been left behind when these policies
were adopted. In the final analysis Stalin succeeded, not so much
because of the ruthlessness of his tactical maneuvers, as because
there was no alternative to the substance of the economic policies
he pursued during both periods. Certainly there was a gratuitous
inhumanity in the implementation of those policies. But the
capitulation of so many principled and tough Old Bolsheviks
cannot be explained in terms only of weakness, torture, or bribery.
It is explicable in terms of the incoherence of Stalin's adversaries
who could not by applying their socialist and democratic principles
frame any more adequate solution. Moreover, many of Stalin's
supporters were sufficiently principled to discover in time the gap
between their socialist desires and ideals and the form of state
which Stalin was actually bringing to birth. Indeed, when the
purges came, Stalin's own earlier supporters were decimated as
much as were the ranks of the old Trotskyists and Bukharinists.
But though there may have been no alternative of substance to
the economic policy which Stalin had pursued since before 1932,
what could have been admitted was that what was being built
was not socialism. One can imagine that if Lenin had survived to
1930 he would have pursued in a more radical way the approach
he followed when he defended the NEP not as socialist, but as
necessary. What led to the corruption of socialism was Stalin's
insistence that what he was doing was socialist. A whole redefini-
tion of Marxism thereby became necessary. To secure that re-
definition a whole generation of Marxists was to be obliterated.
Briefly and perhaps cryptically, it is often supposed that Bolshevik
history has had to be rewritten in Russia because the purges and
the trials made unpersons of so many Old Bolsheviks. The truth
is, I suggest, that the purges and the trials were necessary because
the history of the Bolsheviks, including the history of their theoreti-
cal positions, had to be rewritten so that the true nature of socialism
could be forgotten and the Stalinist redefinition could reign
unchallenged in a society where not the working class but the
bureaucracy ruled.
In 1932 the task of ideological redefinition was only beginning,
and the gap between Stalinist deeds and Marxist words was at its
How not to write about Stalin 51
most obvious. It was at this point that Syrtsov, Lominadze and
Riutin, all of them Stalinists, hoped to depose Stalin; all were
imprisoned. In this year Skrypnik., also a Stalinist, committed
suicide when Stalin discovered the opposition to him in the
Ukranian government, in which Skrypnik. was Commissar for
Education. Suicide is indeed a much more intelligible reaction
among the disillusioned Stalinists than it would have been then
among the adherents of Trotsky or those of Bukharin, who must
for some years have lost most, if not all, of their illusions. Thus
Nadezhda Alliluyeva's suicide falls into its ttagic place in the
historical sequence. Miss Stalin, who sees only the sequences of
personal biography, thus deprives her mother's action of one
possible meaning it may have held. Equally she sees Beria as a
private author of evil; she does not see that the unfolding of
Stalinism created a role for Beria and those like him. The role and
not the man determined the scale of the evil.
None the less, to treat the weaknesses of Miss Stalin's memoirs
as simply symptoms of a defective point of view, without inquiring
about the social roots of that point of view, would merely duplicate
her error. Miss Stalin has a religious perspective upon the world,
albeit a rather indefinite one, and her devotion to Russia has
religious overtones. Indeed, when she wrote her memoir she
believed that she would never be capable of \eaving Russia. One
can understand why the Russia Miss Stalin confronts, the Russia
which she claims that her father always loved, was an abstract
mystical entity; privilege and wealth have always separated her
from social reality. The most characteristic Soviet experience is
to stand in a queue for bread; this does not seem to be a thought
that Miss Stalin has ever had. It would be too prosaic for her.
There remains one aspect of her book which is of real value.
She does reveal in how impossible a position we put the children
of major figures. They lead private and not public lives, but their
private lives are distorted by the way in which they are exposed to
the public gaze. Of Stalin's children one became a drunkard and
one has now written memoirs; but one became a hero. Yakov, the
son of Stalin's first marriage, who was largely disowned by his
father, seems to have been, and not only from this account, a
straightforwardly moral and finally heroic figure who defied the
Germans in his prison camp and was murdered by them. Miss
Stalin when speaking on the power of Truth and Goodness to
survive falls victim to her own rhetoric; on her half-brother's
simple nobility of character she sounds more truthful than at any
other point in her unattractive book.
7
Trotsky in exile1

Trotsky learning to fish in the Sea of Marmora from an illiterate


Greek boy; Trotsky on a ski trip in the Norwegian Arctic;
Trotsky feeding the rabbits among the cacti at Coyoacan: images
such as these all contribute to the violent sense of dislocation
which is produced by turning from the first two volumes of Isaac
Deutscher's biography to the third. 2 But this dislocation is not of
course merely a matter of place. Trotsky's physical remoteness
from events in the years 1929-40 is only matched by his apparent
political isolation. The creator of the Red Army is reduced to the
leader of a scattered following of a few hundred militants; the
inspirer of the Soviets is a stateless exile. Exile, of course, is not
necessarily impotence. But the question must be faced. Is Trotsky
in exile, like Marx in the British Museum, a commentator who is
also an actor, or is he, like Napoleon on St. Helena, an outcast from
the world of action ?
What kind of answer one gives to this question will determine
the whole perspective in which one sees Trotsky's last decade. To
understand Deutscher's answer fully we shall have to look back
to his Stalin. Deutscher's own statement in the preface to the 1961
edition of Stalin of the unity of his work on Stalin and Trotsky
justifies us in so doing.
"In attempting to find an historical parallel to Stalin," wrote
Trotsky in 1940, "we have to reject not only Cromwell, Robes-
pierre, Napoleon, and Lenin, but even Mussolini and Hitler."
"What appears to be established," wrote Deutscher in his Stalin
(1949), "is that Stalin belongs to the breed of the great revolu-
tionary despots, to which Cromwell, Robespierre, and Napoleon
belonged."
The gap between Deutscher's judgment and Trotsky's is a first
1Reprinted from Encounter, December 1963.
2Isaac Deutscher, The Prophet Outcast (London and New York:
Oxford University Press, 1963).
52
Trotsky in exile 53
clue to Deutscher's standpoint. For Deutscher believes that there
is a "broad scheme of revolutionary development" which is
"common to all great revolutionaries so far." The first stage is one
in which "popular energy, impatience, anger and hope" burst out,
and "the party that gives the fullest expression to the popular
mood outdoes its rivals, gains the confidence of the masses and
rises to power." There follows a second heroic stage of civil war
in which revolutionary party and people are so well attuned that
the leaders "are willing and even eager to submit their policies
to open debate and to accept the popular verdict." This stage is
short. Weariness and ruthlessness combine to open a gap between
party and people. The party cannot abdicate without sacrificing
the basis the revolution has created for social advance and pros-
perity; but it can no longer listen to-it must indeed in time
suppress-the voice of the people. At this point the revolutionary
party is split between those who see government by the people as
the heart of the revolution and therefore cry that the revolution is
betrayed and those who justify the new antidemocratic use of
power as the only way to serve the ultimate interests of the people
by preserving the gains of the revolution. This story is one that
Deutscher supposes can be told of any "party of the revolution,
whether it be called Independent, Jacobin or Bolshevik," whether
it is English, French or Russian. It is within the framework of this
story that Stalin and Trotsky are made to appear as playing out
necessary roles. Trotsky, the caretaker of revolutionary purity, is
necessarily doomed to political isolation in the period of the anti-
democratic conservation of revolutionary gains. The significance
of the quotation from Machiavelli which stands at the head of
Deutscher's first volume is now clear: the prophet must be armed
precisely so that he can, when the people no longer believe in the
revolution, "make them believe by force."
This is the setting for the message that is spelled out in the
concluding volume. Trotsky's ideas and methods, so Deutscher
argues, belonged to classical Marxism; but the 1930s were an
epoch hostile both to revolution and to Marxism. After the
Second World War revolution resumed its course-but not as
Marxism had predicted. It was revolution from above, brought to
Eastern Europe by a foreign army, to China by a peasantjacquerie,
which none the less inaugurated a socialist revolution. The Soviet
bureaucracy-so Deutscher continues-is gradually reforming
itself and at some point in this process will be forced to acknow-
ledge Trotsky's greatness. Classical Marxism will then have come
into its own. Trotsky is thus honored by Deutscher on two counts:
54 Against the Self-Images of the Age
as the great dissenter whose protest was both necessary and neces-
sarily ineffective; and as the future patron saint of post-Khrush-
chevite Russia. That this is the frame within which the portrait
of Trotsky in his last years is painted entails that Deutscher has
written both a biography and a political tract. The weakness of his
book arises from the conflict between these two tasks.
The strength of the book lies in the meticulous scholarship :
names, dates, places, at this level of fact Deutscher, as always, is a
model of industry. Moreover his style is as magisterial as ever.
He writes with the restrained passion of the deeply committed
writer, whose deepest commitment of all is to objectivity. And yet,
although objectivity can rescue one from many errors, it cannot
either obliterate or conceal the effects of the basic incoherence of
Deutscher's perspective. To exhibit this incoherence it is enough
to look at how Trotsky himself developed his own positions in the
years of exile.
Trotsky between 1928 and 1940 held at least four positions on
the nature of the Russian state. In 1928 he held that political
power, though effectively controlled by the bureaucrats, was still
in some sense in the hands of the workers, because it was still
possible for them to use constitutional means to "regain full
power, renovate the bureaucracy and put it under its control by
the road of reform of the party and the Soviets" (letter to Borodai).
He could write that "the socialist character of industry is deter-
mined and secured in a decisive measure by the role of the party,
the voluntary internal cohesion of the proletarian vanguard, and
conscious discipline of the administrators, trade union func-
tionaries, members of the shop nuclei, etc." (letter to the Sixth
Comintern Congress). What matters is the access to political
institutions still available to workers.
By 1933 Trotsky believed that this access was no longer available,
but that Russia was still a workers' state. The cruel repression
exercised by the bureaucracy is not incompatible with their
maintaining the core of revolutionary gains so long as the means of
production remain nationalized; but they have been able by reason
of the backwardness of Russia to produce a tyranny which en-
dangers the revolution. Trotsky by now believed that inside and
outside Russia the Left Opposition had to constitute new political
parties, genuinely revolutionary in the rest of the world, genuinely
reformist in Russia. Reformist, because the bureaucracy was not
as yet a new ruling class in the classical Marxist sense, and the
prospect of a political strategy in which the bureacrats could be
expropriated without force in the long run was not as yet unrealistic.
Trotsky in exile ss
By the time The Revolution Betrayed was written in 1935 the
perspective had changed yet again. Certainly Russia is still a
workers' state, even though so gravely degenerated. But the bureau-
cracy can only be overthrown by a political revolution. The
portrait of deadening, tyrannical oppression which is painted in
The Revolution Betrayed could not be bettered. Why then did
Trotsky continue to insist that bureaucracy was only a caste, not a
class, and why did he make the preservation of nationalized
property the criterion of socialism? The answer is that up to this
point he always envisaged the bureaucracy's final goal as being the
restoration of private capitalism. He supposed that socialism and
private capitalism exhausted the political alternatives-wrongly.
For in the period immediately before his death Trotsky did come
around to envisage, even if only as a theoretical possibility, a new
kind of exploitation-the collective class rule of the bureaucracy.
This he did not believe to have yet occurred. But his analysis of
Soviet totalitarianism became even more radical.
L' etat c'est moi is almost a liberal formula by comparison with
the actualities of Stalin's totalitarian regime. Louis XIV
identified himself with both the state and the Church-but
only during the epoch of temporal power. The totalitarian state
goes far beyond Caesaro-Papism. . . . Stalin can justly say,
unlike le Roi Soleil, "la societe c'est moi."
Although Trotsky continued to defend the view that in some sense
the Soviet Union was a workers' state, he had committed himself
to predictions about the results of the Second World War, the
outcome of which would for him settle the matter. If his view
were correct, the Soviet bureaucracy after a victorious war would
be overthrown as a result of proletarian revolution in the advanced
countries of the West. If the view of those Trotskyists who held
that a kind of bureaucratic state capitalism existed in Russia were
correct, they would be vindicated by the failure to occur of such a
revolution and such an overthrow. It was with this question still
before him that Trotsky died.
To read Trotsky's successive evaluations of the Russian state
against the background of what was done to his followers, his
family, and himself is to understand that theory too can have a
dramatic role. For it was not merely Trotsky's person but his
theoretical powers that Stalin wished to condemn to death.
Stalinism required the pulverization of every independent political
voice in Russia and in the international Communist movement;
hence not only the Moscow trials, but the extended passion of the
3
Against the Self-Images of the Age
Trotskyists in the Siberian camps, where those who had never
surrendered, but who had continued to organize strikes, protests,
and political propaganda among their fellow prisoners, were in
1938 marched out in groups and shot. Leon Sedov, Trotsky's
elder son, died mysteriously in Paris with the GPU not far from
his bedside; Sergei, who had reacted against both his father and
his father's politics, and who worked quietly as a private citizen in
Moscow, died at the hands of the GPU; Zina, one of his daughters
-the other was already dead-had committed suicide under
intense nervous strain in Berlin some years before. Rudolf
Klement, the Secretary of the Fourth International, was in 1938
murdered, mutilated, and dropped in the Seine. If Trotsky was
not utterly crushed, it was only because he was upheld by his wife
Natalya and by the conviction that no one but he could carry
through his task and that the importance of his work was only to
be measured by the venom he aroused in Stalin.
Among the many characters with walk-on parts in this drama
some are familiar. Those who in 1962 protested at the Home
Secretary's inhumanity to that "persecuted progressive," Dr.
Soblen, will meet him again in Deutscher's pages as the GPU
agent Roman Well. Mr. Kingsley Martin turns up at Coyoacan,
but the meeting is not altogether pleasant, because Mr. Martin
wishes to defend the honor of his friend Mr. D. N. Pritt over his
defense of the Moscow trials. M. Leon Blum appears suppressing
protests against the trials and purges. Theodore Dreiser, Romain
Rolland, and Louis Fischer play familiar roles as Stalinist apolo-
gists. If anyone says that at that time any of them could not have
known better, that the threat of fascism and the effectiveness of
Stalin's propaganda exculpate these men, the answer is that many
who were far from Trotsky's Marxism did know better. The aged
John Dewey, chairman of the committee that vindicated Trotsky
against Stalin's accusations, comes out of the whole affair with
immense honor. So does Charles Beard, the veteran American
historian. And they were not alone.
But the dimensions of Trotsky's tragedy and the way in which
reactions to it became a touchstone of honor and dishonor only
make the re-evaluation of his views the more crucial. An essential
piece of evidence is Trotsky's single most brilliant piece of political
comment, the pamphleteering on Germany from 1930 to 1933.
The diagnosis of Nazism as "the extremism of the center" which
Professor S. M. Lipset advanced in Political Man is already made
by Trotsky. His castigations of the Comintern over its attitude to
the social democrats, to the government of Bruning, and to Hitler
Trotsky in exile 57
himself all bore fruit in verified predictions. At the center of his
analysis the stress is on the importance of the presence or absence
of a politically awakened working class. (Trotsky's advice about the
mobilization of the workers was never taken by the Comintern;
but a parody of his point was taken, perhaps unwittingly, by
Debre and de Gaulle when the paras threatened. Was there by the
remotest of chances and historical ironies a link in Malraux?)
This remains at the core of all Trotsky's analyses. For the Trotsky
of the 1930s, as for Marx, socialism can be made only by the
workers and not for them.
It is in part because of this that Trotsky, had he lived, would
have had to treat his predictions about the aftermath of the
Second World War as falsified. He could not but have concluded
from his own premises that Russia was in no sense a workers'
state, but rather a grave of socialism. The liberalization of Khrush-
chev would have appeared to him as parallel to the liberalization
which has developed in other capitalisms once primitive accumula-
tion has been accomplished. He could never have accepted
Deutscher's analysis, which has only one thing in common with
his own: the use of nationalized property as a criterion for
socialism. Trotsky never believed in the possibility of the bureau-
cracy's self-reformation. In The Revolution Betrayed Trotsky
wrote of the bureaucracy that
To the extent that, for the benefit of an upper stratum, it
carries to more and more extreme expression bourgeois norms
of distribution, it is preparing a capitalist restoration. This
contrast between forms of property and norms of distribution
cannot grow indefinitely. Either the bourgeois norms must
in one form or another spread to the means of production,
or the norms of distribution must be brought into corres-
pondence with the socialist property system.
According to Deutscher it is this latter course that Stalin's
successors have adopted. In what way the norms of distribution
differ from bourgeois norms he never explains (in Deutscher's
view Britain also has surely abandoned bourgeois norms of
distribution). But what is most interesting is that both Alfred
Rosmer, Trotsky's most able and trusted companion, and Natalya
Trotsky herself drew the opposite conclusion. It was for this
reason that Natalya Trotsky explained her break with the stunted
and ingrown politics of the self-styled Trotskyists by writing: "If
this trend continues, he (Trotsky) said, the revolution will be at
an end and the restoration of capitalism will be achieved. That,
58 Against the Self-Images of the A.ge
unfortunately, is what has happened even if in new and unexpected
forms" (letter to the Political Committee of the Socialist Workers'
Party, 1951). Almost her last political act was a letter in Azione
Communista in November 1961 denouncing the idea that Mao
Tse-tung was in any sense Trotsky's heir, and asserting that
Russia and China were as far from socialism as Franco's Spain.
One has, therefore, to choose. Either one can see Leon Trotsky
in Natalya's perspective or in Deutscher's, but not in both. There
seems little doubt which Trotsky would have chosen. The
distressing thing to him about Deutscher's biography would have
been that it makes him so acceptable to those against whom he
struggled for his entire life. What is more, Deutscher's adroitness
will make his conclusions equally palatable on both sides of the
Iron Curtain. The news that socialism is Khrushchevite liberaliza-
tion plus nationalized property will not come amiss in Moscow.
Both Trotsky and classical Marxism, it turns out, have to be
amended to fit in with Russian reality. Trotsky's Marxist pre-
dictions were wrong, but Marxism is somehow vindicated none
the less and so is Trotsky. I do not understand how. In the West
too the news that the Khrushchevite regime is the necessary
outcome of the Russian revolution will be welcome. For this can
be thrown back at all believers in the possibility of socialism in the
West. It is admirably suited for apologists of the status quo.
Trotsky, the inevitable protester against the inevitable course of
socialist history, can be safely received by both sides as a dead
martyr, with a sigh of relief that they have not the living revolu-
tionary to deal with.
What is most curious about Deutscher's anxiety to approve of
the present developments in Russia and of Trotsky and of the
letter of classical Marxism, is that Trotsky's own attitude to
Marxism was far less hagiographical. Throughout his life Trotsky
was prepared to reformulate Marxism. The theory of permanent
revolution bears striking witness to this. In the 1930s we see him
trying to use the Marxist theory of classical capitalism to under-
stand entirely new situations. In this situation it may have been
that Marxism proved a totally inadequate scheme (the orthodox
sociological response) or it may have been that it provided a
necessary starting-point for a new, more complex, but still
Marxist, schematism. The attempts to characterize the Russian
bureaucracy pose just this question; the attempt to characterize
postwar Western capitalism would have posed it even more
harshly. But whatever answers Trotsky might have given, he
could never have been an accomplice to Deutscher's worship of the
Trotsky in exile 59
accomplished fact. Deutscher himself sees clearly in his discussion
of Trotsky's History of the Russian Revolution that Trotsky was no
believer in Deutscherian necessity.
The Shakespearean richness of character which is among the
chief glories of the History brings out the important difference
between those actors who are essentially representatives of a
social group or class, and who are therefore replaceable, and those
actors who are more than this, who cannot be so replaced. Miliukov,
the Russian liberal, is essentially a mirror for the Russian bourge-
oisie-- "grey, self-interested, cowardly." Lenin, by contrast, was
both an expression of his party and more than this. Had he been
absent, the revolution's chances, so Trotsky argued, would have
been very different. Deutscher devotes several pages to trying to
refute Trotsky's conclusion on this point and we can see why this is
necessary for his whole argument. If from time to time history
presents us with real alternatives where my actions can make all
the difference, then I am not just part of an inevitable historical
progress. Deutscher invokes Plekhanov's determinism on his side
and the reminiscence of Plekhanov is suggestive. Deutscher's life
of Trotsky, with all its scholarship, its brilliance of style, its
perversity about socialism, its service of the established fact, and
its determinism, is just the biography that we can imagine a
Plekhanov of the 196qs writing. But Trotsky himself evades all
the categories of a Plekhanovite Marxism; his image refuses to
be accommodated.
The truth of this is reflected in the way that his name continues
to haunt all established powers. So-called Trotskyism has been
among the most trivial of movements. It transformed into abstract
dogma what Trotsky thought in concrete terms at one moment in
his life and canonized this. It is inexplicable in purely political
dimensions, but the history of the more eccentric religious sects
provides revealing parallels. The genuine Trotskyism of Rosmer
and Natalya must have at most a few hundred adherents in the
entire world. Yet Trotsky's is the name which is continually
invoked, at one level by employers who fear rank-and-file industrial
agitation, and at another by those super-employers, the Russian
and Chinese states, in their polemics against each other. If they
were to read Deutscher and to accept his conclusions, they would
wonder what the specter could have been which haunted them.
But I doubt if it is possible to lay Trotsky's ghost so easily.
8
Marxist mask and romantic face:
Lukacs on Thomas Mann 1

The dictatorship of the proletariat, the politico-economic means of


salvation demanded by our age, does not mean domination for its
own sake and in perpetuity; but rather in the sense of a temporary
abrogation, in the Sign of the Cross, of the contradiction between
spirit and force; in the sense of overcoming the world by mastering
it; in a transcendental, transitional sense, in the sense of the King-
dom. The proletariat has taken up the task of Gregory the Great,
his religious zeal bums within it, and, as little as he, may it withhold
its hand from the shedding of blood. Its task is to strike terror into
the world for the healing of the world, that man may finally achieve
salvation and deliverance, and win back at length to freedom from
law and from distinction of class, to his original status as child of
God.
NAPHTA in The Magic Mountain

In The Magic Mounta£n the spokesman of the reactionary Fascist,


anti-democratic Weltanschauung, the Jesuit Naphta ....
LuKi\cs in Essays on Thomas Mann 2
"Lukacs, who is anyhow well-disposed towards me (and who
plainly has not recognized himself in Naphta) ... " wrote Thomas
Mann in a letter in 1949.3 That Georg Lukacs' essays upon
Thomas Mann form part of the elaborate defenses with which

1 Reprinted from Encounter, April 1965.


2 Georg Lukacs, Essays on Thomas Mann. Translated by Stanley
Mitchell (New York: Grosset and Dunlap; London: Merlin Press,
1964).
3 For the facts about the Mann-Lukacs relationship, see the essay
"Zauberberg-Figuren" in Tessiner Schreibtisch by Karl Kerenyi (Stutt-
gart, 1963). For a suggestive, but speculative interpretation see Victor
Zitta, Georg Lukacs' Marxism, Alienation, Dialectics, Revolution (New
York: Humanities Press).
6o
Marxist mask o:ndroma.nticface: Lukacs on Thomas Mann 61
Lukacs buttresses his inability to recognize himself as he was in
his brilliant and many-sided youth lends to these essays a poignancy
and a fascination which they certainly do not provide in their role
as literary criticism. The pompous, ponderous style in which
they are written all too easily conveys the impression of one
Grand Old Man saluting another, the Gamaliel of Central
European Communism (as a [London] Times leader writer once
called Lukacs) applauding the Nobel Prize winner. Nor is the
translation to blame for this impression; the translator has
rendered Lukacs' professorial prose excellently. And the conse-
quence might well be that the brief, uncomplicated, facile judg-
ments on Lukacs, which it has become fashionable to pass in the
West, will not be shaken at all by these essays. Yet they are in
fact further evidence of the enigmatic and complex quality of
Lukacs' achievement.
It is common knowledge that Lukacs has publicly disavowed his
youth. In Hungary in 1948 he was accused by Gyorgy Somly6 of
staging an auto-da-fe with his own early writings. Lukacs replied
vehemently that those works "which I have transcended with my
own development and which were moving in an improper
direction" should not receive attention either from himself or from
others. He raged when Merleau-Ponty in 1955 discussed his
History and Class-Consciousnessof 1923 and spoke of "treachery"
and of the "falsification of a book forgotten for good reasons."
This un-Marxist attempt to separate his present from his past, the
self from its deeds, has so strong an emotional charge behind it
that one cannot but ask, "Why?" Unless one can answer this
question posed in a very general way one is unlikely to answer
satisfactorily the particular question of why Lukacs, consciously
or unconsciously, has refused to recognize his own features in
those of Naphta. There is, of course, a strong presumption that
the refusal is at least semiconscious, even though Mann himself
exhibited strong anxiety that Lucacs should not recognize himself
in Naphta and was completely certain that he had not done so.
The reason for doubting whether Mann's assurance was justified
is simply that, in his references to Naphta, Lukacs seems to rely
upon his readers not actually having the text of The Magic
Mountain available. How otherwise could he so confidently and
without explanation characterize as fascist a character who pro-
pounds belief in Communism, the abolition of classes, the
dictatorship of the proletariat, and a version of the labor theory of
value? Of course, Naphta (as Thomas Mann himself insisted)
differs from the young Lukacs in a large number of ways. Naphta
Against the Self-Images of the Age
is a Jesuit; Lukacs is not. But the young Lukacs was deeply
involved with Christianity and often writes of God with immense
seriousness. The influence of Dostoevski is strong in the years
before 1914; so more surprisingly is that of Plotinus and of the
German mystics Eck.hart and Tauler.
The commonest explanation of Lukacs' rupture with his youth
assimilates it to the recantations of intellectuals in the Stalinist
period in Russia. There would be some room for doubt about the
explanatory value of this parallel just because it is still unclear how
far we understand the psychology of these recantations. But in any
case Lukacs' behavior since 1924 bears all the marks of being not
so much a response to pressures from without as a continuous
self-inspired attempt to destroy what survives in him of his youth.
He has, of course, not been able to avoid a continuous return to the
subject matter of his early writings. But he voluntarily and long
before he went to live in the Soviet Union abjured their standpoint,
as a result of the condemnation of History and Class-Consciousnes.
Ernst Bloch predicted in his original review of it that the Russians
would dislike it: "Some of them will say that Marx had not
placed Hegel on his feet so that Lukacs can put Marx back on his
head." None of the Russians was in fact as witty as this. Zinoviev
nagged shrilly at the Fifth Congress of the Comintern in 1924 that
"we must not let this extreme left tendency grow up into a
theoretical revisionism" and picked out Lukacs' work in philosophy
and sociology for special mention. Lukacs was at once confronted
with a dilemma whose roots were already obvious in the text of
History and Class-Consciousness. For there he explains Marxism as
the class-consciousness of the proletariat whose articulate repre-
sentative is the Communist Party. Thus it is entailed by Lukacs'
own argument that if the Comintern holds that Marxism is not
what Lukacs says it is, then Lukacs must be wrong. Or, rather,
either Lukacs is wrong or the Comintern is not the true Communist
Party. But if it is not, then Marxism is only a theory, only an idea;
it lacks any material incarnation. To have grasped this horn of the
dilemma would have thrown Lukacs back to his starting-point in
an unbearable way. And his tragedy resides in his never having
been able to return to it. But what was his starting-point and why
would return to it have been unbearable?
In answering this question we can also try to answer another. It
is a commonplace that in History and Class-Consciousness Lukacs
produced a Hegelian interpretation of Marx that set Marx's
own writings in a systematic framework quite different from and
incompatible with that in which Engels had set them in Anti-
Marxist mask and romantic face: Lukacs on Thomas Mann 63
Duhring. When in 1931-32 Marx's so-called Economic-Philosophical
Manuscripts of 1844 became known, it was clear that Marx himself
had defined his own thought near its outset in precisely the terms
of that same Hegelian framework which Lukacs had once more
spelled out. This confirmation of Lukacs' interpretation-Lukacs
could not possibly have known of the contents of the manuscripts in
1923-was a brilliant literary reconstruction for which his dis-
owning of History and Class-Consciousness has never allowed him
to claim the credit. What, in fact, enabled Lukacs to do this was
the degree to which he had in his own experience recapitulated
Marx's intellectual development. In order to understand this,
both Marx and Lukacs have to be placed-if in the briefest, most
inadequate way-in relation to their own culture.
The seminal period of German culture is essentially philosophical
in a way that English culture never is. It is therefore much easier to
interpret it in terms of a unity of ideas and imagination, to narrate
its history as a series of attempts to frame answers to pervasive
questions that were at once Kantian and Faustian. The literary
critic of this culture cannot evade, any more than the philosopher
can, the relationships and the antagonisms between value and
fact, law and inclination, reason and the passions, society and the
individual. But the literary critic has to deal with these not just
as conceptual oppositions, but rather with embodied, imaginative
resolutions of these antagonisms in the Greece of Holderlin's poems
or in Goethe's later writings. One way of recounting Lukacs'
career would be to set out the history of his continuous reinterpre-
tation of the central features of German culture between 1780
and 1850. If one did this, one would discover a recurrent instability
in which the would-be settled views of any one period in his life
are undermined by his insights at other periods.
At his worst in his self-willed Stalinist period before the war he
writes in terms of the crude dichotomy between idealism and
materialism fathered by Engels and by Lenin's Materialism
and Empirico- Criticism. But these concepts, as Lenin himself
understood later, are chameleons of the mind, taking color only
from the examples which they are ostensibly used to explain. So
in the Destruction of Reason Lukacs turned instead to the conflict
between reason and unreason and tried to use this as an analytical
tool. In so doing he continued his campaign against the interpre-
tation of German Romanticism as essentially irrationalist, an
interpretation which he stigmatized as anticipating Nazi in-
terpretations of German cultural history. (This did not save him
from being himself stigmatized as a revisionist for abandoning the
Against the Self-Images of the Age
cant about materialism and idealism.) The most important
justification that Lukacs has ever given for this view has, however,
implications which he himself has never understood (or at least
admitted). Discussing the Romantic opposition of reason to the
passions in Goethe and His Age, Lukacs argued that this opposition
depends upon a falsely partial view of both reason and passions,
an opposition which had been created by the rationalists of the
eighteenth century. It follows that it is not reason itself, but a dis-
torted view of reason against which the Romantic rebels. Yet if
this is so, doubt is then thrown on Lukacs' own categories. For
in a culture where concepts of reason and the passions are thrown
up by the very nature of its social life and its definitive ideas, the
man who claims to be able to detect the distortion must warrant
his claims by showing how it is possible for him to escape the
distorting influences which imprison everyone else.
Neither the young Marx in the 1840s nor the young Lukacs in
1918 was able to take Hegel's way out, that of claiming that in him
the Absolute has finally broken through the relativities of history
so that the thoughts expressed in the Logic are the thoughts of God
himself, thinking them through Hegel's pen. But both have to try
and find a vantage point outside their own society and culture. In
order to explain Lukacs' attempt to do this one cannot avoid
attempting to explain Marx's; and this is not quite the boring
rehearsal of stock platitudes about The Young Marx that it might
seem to be, since The Young Marx is a plaster figure in whose
lineaments it is fairly difficult to pick out the face of the young
Marx.
The myth of the plaster figure runs: once upon a time there was
a young humanistic Marx who inherited from Hegel and from the
Left Hegelians the notion of alienation. This Marx was not yet
preoccupied with socio-economics. But as he be~ame so pre-
occupied, he discarded the notion of alienation. Indeed his
break with the Left Hegelians and his discarding of the notion
of alienation are sometimes seen as two aspects of the same
process. The locusclassicusfor this myth is Lewis Feuer's "What Is
Alienation? The Career of a Concept, " 1 and in order to destroy
the myth one has only to set two of Feuer's key theses beside
what Marx actually says.
So Feuer writes: "In these early writings, Marx and Engels,
as Freudian forerunners, regarded love, not work, as the source of
man's sense of reality," and he quotes from The Holy Family
(published in 1845 but written in the autumn of 1844). But
1 In New Politics, Spring 1962.
Marxist mask and romantic face: Lukdcs on Thomas Mann 65
already in the Economic-Philosophical Ms. (written in April to
August 1844) Marx had clearly argued the central relationship
between work and the sense of reality. And indeed the quotation
from The Holy Family does not bear an entirely clear sense when
placed in its context.
Secondly, Feuer claims that "the word 'alienation' was absent
from Marx's mature analysis." But in the Grundrisse in 1857-58
(unpublished until 1939-41) Marx is still writing:
The ancient conception in which man always appears (in
however narrowly rational, religious, or political a definition)
as the aim of production, seems very much more exalted than
the modern world, in which production is the aim of man and
wealth the aim of production. In fact, however, when the narrow
bourgeois form has been peeled· away what is wealth, if not the
universality of needs, capacities, enjoyments, productive
powers, etc., of individuals produced in universal exchange?
What, if not the full development of human control over the
forces of nature--those of his own nature as well as those
of so-called "nature." . . . In bourgeois political economy-
and in the epoch to which it corresponds-this complete
elaboration of what lies within man appears as total alienation.2
This survival of the concept of alienation into Marx's mature
writings is important for my immediate purposes; for had the
concept not, as Feuer claimed, survived in them-although the
word is admittedly not used in Capital-how could Lukacs have
correctly deduced the core of Marx's thought from the later
writings which he knew? The survival of the concept is important
for other reasons. The concepts of work and freedom in the mature
Marx are in fact unintelligible unless related to the notion of
alienation, and to precisely that notion of alienation set out by
Lukacs.
Alienation has at least four defining features. First of all men are
divided within themselves and from each other, by not being able
in their work to pursue ends that are their own, by having external
ends imposed upon them. Secondly, means and ends are inverted.
Where men should eat and drink in order to act, they have to work
in order to eat and drink. Thirdly, men reify their social relation-
ships into alien powers which dominate them. In virtue of this
reification they become involved in conceptual puzzles and
1 Karl Marx, Pre-Capitalist Economic Formations (London: Lawrence

& Wishart, 1964), pp. 84-5.


66 Against the Self-Images of the Age
confusions. And finally, men find life irremediably split up into
rival and competing spheres, each with its own set of norms, and
each sphere claiming its own narrow and therefore deforming
sovereignty. But all this makes it clear that alienation is essentially a
contrast concept. We can understand what it is to be alienated
only if we can also understand what it is or would be not to be
alienated. Whence did Marx, whence did Lukacs derive the notion
of a form of human life in which man would create his own ends,
in which conceptual confusion and contradiction would be
resolved into a clarity about means and ends, so creating a human
nature in which the ideal and the actual would at last coin-
cide? The surprising answer may be that the unalienated men
of the Marxist feature are the artists of the German Romantic
ideal.
"Thus man also creates according to the laws of beauty."
So Marx. Marx's description of the senses of reintegrated man
finding their own proper aesthetic objects, his attempt to establish
a connection between freedom and aesthetic activity, and his
belief that in free, aesthetic activity the contradictions of unfree
existence are resolved, is a reissue of a theme in Schiller's break
with Kant in the "Kallias" letters. 1 Even more, Schiller's concept
of Selbstbestimmung is an important anticipation of Marx's
"self-activity." The Hegelian concept of self-activity is not its
only ancestor. It is hardly surprising that Lukacs, coming across
Schiller's declaration that it is man who plays (and play includes
the whole realm of aesthetic activity) who is most truly man, should
use this saying to interpret Marx in a sense relevant to his own
problems. These were complex.
Both the energy and the "intellectual poetry" (his own phrase)
of the young Lukacs arise out of the tension between the conceptual
and theoretical resources available to him to interpret reality and
the impact of the reality itself. In the view of the young Lukacs,
the poet faced with the inadequacy of the first to the second creates
his own reality. But the critic cannot rest content except with a
grasp of both poetry and social reality which can only come from
a philosophy in which reality is disclosed. Lukacs reads the history
of past literature and criticism in terms of the attempted resolution
of the tension between the realm of intelligibility and that of
brute reality. Belief in God plays a key role here, especially in the
definition of the tragic vision in which the hero who is confronted
by the demands of a transcendence which he cannot discover
1 Karl Marx, Early Writings. Translated and edited by T. B. Bottomore
(London: Watts; New York: McGraw Hill, 1963), p. 16o-62.
Marxist mask and romantic face: Lukacs on Thomas Mann 67
anywhere in the empirical world must live out his tasks in conflict
with a reality that never discloses the divinity he seeks.1 The
tragic vision in which meaning can only be conferred on the world
from outside it, and yet the world is silent as to its own meaning,
recurs in a conceptualized form in classicalGerman philosophy. The
tragic hero is transformed in turn into the epistemological subject
of Kantianism whose categories can never reveal theDing-an-sich, the
Fichtean Ego, and the Hegelian Self. But each of these philosophies
finds itself still external to the reality it seeks to comprehend,
reduced to spawning metaphysical fictions on a grand scale. It was
the insight of Hegel, rendered into realistic social terms by Marx
(and Marx's "materialism" consists in really no more than this
rendering) that the escape from the contradictions and mystifica-
tions thrown up by this philosophy did not lie simply in intellect-
ually dissipating them by greater clarity in conceptual analysis.
In the Hegelian-Marxist view such conceptual contradictions
and mystifications express the incoherences of a whole form of
life. To overcome them one does not have merely to philosophize
more clearly, but to learn to act in a new way: revolutionary
praxis, as characterized by Marx in the Theses on Feuerbach. Here
Lukacs sees the resolution of his new problems. The praxis in
which contradiction disappears is that of the proletarian, not just
that of the actual workingman but that of the essential proletarian
for whom the Hungarian Soviets of 1919 provided a spokesman.
So the contradictions of tragedy are overcome; transcendence
re-enters the world; the immediate ends of man become meaning-
ful. The Kingdom of God will have been taken by storm. To
read History and Class-Consciousnessas a solution to the problems
of The Soul and the Forms is to read it as the work of Lukacs-
Naphta.
Thus Lukacs staked his existence on the possibility of integrating
art with social life in a praxis in which life should itself have the
coherence and meaning of art. He analyses bourgeois social reality
with the tools derived from Georg Simmel and Max Weber; he
understands art and literature in terms of the Romantic ideal.
And he invokes Marxism to link the two analyses so that the
aesthetic may be at home in the world. But in so doing he creates
insoluble problems for his own future activities as a critic, prob-
lems that are nowhere more apparent than in his writings on
Thomas Mann.
1 For the best account of this phase of Lukacs' thought, see Lucien
Goldmann, The Hidden God (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul; New
York: Humanities Press, 1964).
68 Against the Self-Images of the Age
Lukacs' immense sympathy for Mann derives from the fact that
the externality of art to bourgeois society is itself a central imagina-
tive theme for Mann; Lukacs' difficulty in writing about Mann is
that Mann was always ambivalent in his attitudes both to art and to
bourgeois society. This Lukacs concealed from himself by
simply not seeing in Mann's work every tendency which might
underline the necessarygap between art and social life to the possible
nonexistence of which Lukacs' whole critical career is pledged.
Thus Lukacs cannot acknowledge himself in Naphta because the
manifestly desperate character of Naphta's enterprise corresponds
to the latently desperate character of Lukacs' own enterprise.
What is desperate and neurotic, of course, is not Lukacs' Com-
munism or his wish to resolve the contradictions of theory with
the conceptual scheme of a new form of social life; it is his
impatience with history, with the slow pace of social development.
This he himself was to recognize, but his recognition of this
impatience was turned into an acceptance of the subintellectual
world of Stalinist materialism and thereby into a disowning of
both the origin and the meaning of his own enterprise.
Lukacs' arbitrary excision from Mann's work of all that does
not fit into the role which he imposes on Mann-that of the
bourgeois realist who disowns the decadence of modernism-
is most obvious when Lukacs simply writes off the opinions Mann
professed in his essays. So Mann's expressed admiration for
Freud is dismissed and The Holy Sinner read as a refutation of
Freud. Equally Mann's expressed attitude to Nietzsche has to be
discounted. For Lukacs wants to see Adrian Leverki.ihn in Dr.
Faustus as a contemporary Nietzsche. But of course there is a
strong element of Lukacs' antimodernism in Mann; neither
Mann nor Lukacs really understands Schiller's notion of art as
play, which underlies so much modern art. Both are therefore
least at home with music. And Lukacs' attack on Schonberg (like
his distaste for Joyce) is rooted not in social perceptiveness,
but in a clinging to the values of the bourgeois nineteenth century.
This clinging is truer of Lukacs than it is of Mann. There is in
Leverki.ihn more of Mann than Lukacs could allow and Mann's
attitude to the narrator, the old-fashioned classical humanist
Serenus Zeitblom, contains far more irony than Lukacs can detect.
This is because there is in Lukacs more of Zeitblom than he
re.alizes. In an age when the formality of art and its autonomy
have been among its chief safeguards from degeneration (this is
what the Nazi attacks on Schonberg and Joyce signify) the
attitudes of the older Lukacs smack more than a little of the
Marxist mask and romantic face: Lukacs on Thomas Mann 69
"power-protected inwardness" which he condemns in Bismarckian
Germany.
Yet in the latest of these essays, on The Confessionsof Felix Krull,
Confidence Man, that Lukacs is a genius still appears. The
comparison of the Joseph saga with Felix Krull is full of insight
into Mann's handling of character. But it is by now genius
that has paid a high price for survival. Lukacs most resembles one
of Stendhal's characters. Like them, he has lived in a post-
revolutionary age in which the price of survival is to pay more than
lip service to the values of petty, bourgeoisified despotisms.
And the romantic aspiration to embody art in life itself could not
have continued to inspire as it has done, if Lukacs had not rein-
carnated it so often in the Protean doctrines with which he
disguises the unchanging inheritance from The Soul and the Forms
and History and Class-Consciousness.
Like Julien Sorel or Fabrice, Lukacs has involved himself in
countless strategems; like Sorel he has faced the death penalty,
like Fabrice he has avoided it. But the declining quality of his
writing suggests that time has done its work, that the face behind
the mask has taken on the aspect of the mask. Naphta's suicide
was one way of paying the debts of romanticism to reality; the
long, tortuous, intertwining of enlightenment and deception that
Lukacs has practiced is another.
9

Marxism of the wilI'

Of the books below2 the two most important are Gerassi's collection
of Che Guevara's writings and Rojo's brilliant biography. Guevara's
own reminiscences of the Cuban revolutionary war are interesting,
but the reader needs to be well informed already to make much
use of them. Debray's theorizing is perhaps only interesting for the
contrast between the Debray version of Che and Che as he was,
and the Sartre is worth noticing in this context because it helps us
to judge how much of Debray is Paris academicism. Finally I
notice the American version of Che's diaries merely to note that
it differs in important ways from the Cuban version. The publishers
on their dust jacket say their edition "was authenticated not by
Cubans or Bolivians but by Americans"; here's news for you,
Stein and Day-I still do not trust it. James accuses Che of
"personal pique" ; his publishers join with him in entertaining
the suggestion that Castro was jealous of Che, deliberately denied
the help he could have given, and so betrayed him. This obscene
suggestion does not come well from Americans, who ought at
least to realize that the death of Guevara may well cost them as
much as his life did.
The death of Che had-and it is difficult to use the word after it
has been so cheaply misused-tragic quality. To use a dramatic
metaphor is not to suggest anything histrionic about Che's actions
1 Reprinted from Partisan Review, 1969.
2 A review of John Gerassi, ed., V enceremos! The Speeches and Writings
of Che Guevara (New York: Macmillan; London: Weidenfeld & Nicolson,
1969; Che Guevara, Reminiscences of the Cuban Revolutionary War (New
York: Grove Press; London: Allen & Unwin, 1968); Daniel James, ed.,
The Complete Bolivian Diaries of Che Guevara (New York: Stein & Day;
London: Allen & Unwin, 1969); Ricardo Rojo, My Friend Che (New
York: Dial Press, 1969); Regis Debray, Revolution in the Revolution?
(New York and London: Monthly Review Press, 1967); Jean-Paul
Sartre, The Communists and Peace (New York: Braziller, 1968).
70
Marxism of the will 71
or passions; it is to indicate that those actions and passions are an
appropriate subject for poetry as well as for history, because, as
Aristotle said, poetry is "more universal" than history. Che was
not just an individual, but a representative figure, who lived out
a tragic action. A tragic action is one in which a hero encounters a
catastrophe as a result of a flaw in his character. By character I
do not mean a mere assemblage of psychological traits, I mean
rather the incarnation of a role. (What poetry was for Aristotle,
sociology is for us.) What was Che's flaw?
To ask this question, I have suggested, is to ask about a role
and not about an assemblage of personal traits. That personal
traits can explain little in political or social action is made clear
once again in reading reminiscences of Che by those who knew him
well. He was an asthmatic who developed a will strong enough to
take him onto the athletic field and through medical school. He
was an ascetic who did not undervalue sex or alcohol. He was an
altruist, but without any signs of that self-contempt which so
often underpins altruism. I shall suggest later that these traits
were not entirely unimportant in relation to some key positions
that Che took up; but there are no splendid psychological generali-
zations to be constructed which will demonstrate that asthmatic,
ascetic altruism is the seedbed of revolution. As so often, what is
impressive is not the connection, but the relative lack of connec-
tion between individual personality and social role. The need to
reminisce about Che has in any case obviously little to do with any
task of explanation; it is much more as though his friends still
have to reassure themselves that it all really did happen, that this
living out of one of our political dreams was not in fact only a
dream.
The search for such reassurance is perhaps connected with the
extent to which the Cuban Revolution was an accidental happen-
ing. By this I mean much more than that it did not follow out the
patterns of previous revolutions. Regis Debray is able to emphasize
that and yet to insist that the Cuban Revolution embodied an
experience from which more generally applicable laws and maxims
can be extracted. In this he follows Che faithfully and yet there
is an important difference in tone between what Huberman and
Sweezy call Debray's "comprehensive and authoritative presenta-
tion of the revolutionary thought of Fidel Castro and Che Gue-
vara" and what we actually encounter in Che's writings. This
difference arises from the stale, academic atmosphere of Debray's
arguments. For however authentically Debray may reproduce
what is new and Cuban, he does so in a setting and a style which
Against the Selj-11llllgesof the Age
is old and French. So that while in Guevara's own narratives the
Marxism-Leninism somehow coexists with a sense of the Cuban
Revolution as a chain of improvisations and coincidences, in
Debray's writing revolutionary action becomes nothing but matter
for theoretical formulas counterposed to other theoretical formulas.
Accident has disappeared and with it truth.
We find in Debray a constant reiteration of Sartrian themes.
There are the same strange attempts to unite historical necessity
and absolute freedom, to dissent from Stalinism and yet to count
Stalin among the revolutionary ancestors, and to portray Trot-
skyism as the villain of the piece; indeed Debray explicitly refers
back to Sartre's fifteen-year-old anti-Trotskyist polemic in
The Communistsand Peace.One can well understand why Trotsky's
ghost haunts Sartre and Debray. For both Sartre and Debray
have a peculiar conception-far more elitist than that of Leninism
--of an inert mass of be it workers, be it peasants, who need a
leadership of particular gifts to rouse them to revolutionary
activity. Sartre in 1952 and 1954 was equally contemptuous of
those sociologists who declared that the French working classes
were not revolutionary and those Trotskyists who declared that
they were revolutionary-but that their revolutionary tendencies
were suppressed or inhibited by their reaction to the Stalinist
leadership of the Communist Party of France. In Sartre's view
the working masses are not, but will become, a revolutionary
class precisely because the Communist Party presents them with
goals which transcend their immediate needs; so for Debray the
guerrilla army is to present the peasants with goals which trans-
cend their immediate needs. It is a doctrine which enables Sartre
and Debray to set on one side in the most arbitrary way the
question of what workers or peasants do in fact want now. It also
enables Sartre to disregard the theoretical positions of St~linist
bureaucrats; his understanding of the falsity of Stalinism seems
in his writings of the early 1950s only marginal to his evaluation
of Stalinism's political function. So Debray too exalts questions of
organization over questions of political goals and programs and
sneers at the Trotskyists for their emphasis upon fundamental
theory.
In his intellectual style then Debray is unlike Che; but Che
himself could not avoid facing dilemmas which in other contexts
were responsible for creating Trotskyism, and he could not avoid
making choices which were incompatible with Trotskyism. This is
because Trotsky himself had had to face at successive points in his
career all the dilemmas of those who wish to make a Marxist
Marxism of the will 73
revolution in an underdeveloped country and because too the
failure of Trotskyism to provide a recipe for successful revolu-
tionary practice in the face of those dilemmas is an inescapable
fact. What is the part of the peasantry in the making of a Soci.alist
revolution? Marx could see no part for them, Mao invented one
ex nihilo and called it Marxist, and every position intermediate
between Marx's and Mao's has been taken up by some Marxist
theorist at some time. Trotskyism at the very least represents the
thesis of the ineliminable necessity of the participation of an
industrial working class in revolution-making. Can there be
soci.alismin one country? One paradox of post-Stalin Stalinism is
that it may be those who are most repelled by the surviving
Stalinist features of the Soviet Union who therefore try to build a
socialist revolution in isolation from the Soviet camp or at least in
the minimum of contact with it. But in so doing they revive the
very thesis of "socialism in one country" on which Stalinism was
founded and in this way reject Trotskyism. What is the place of
the revolutionary party? The orthodox Communist Parties in
Latin America are obviously not revolutionary parties; their weak-
ness and their reformism are notorious. But in the struggle waged
by peasant guerrillas there is little room for a party at all. Hence
Trotskyism once more appears as the ghost of orthodox Bolshev-
ism, repudiating militantly the only militant strategies apparently
open in Latin America.
Guevara's position is thus easily defined by contrast with that
of Trotskyism, and in this at least Debray is perceptive. But if
Guevara offered us a revolution made by peasants, a revolution
which creates socialism in one country, and a revolution with a
revolutionary army rather than a revolutionary party, he aspired
to do so as a Marxist-Leninist, and here is the crux. For if Bol-
shevism can only appear in the modern world in ghostly form,
Trotskyism is indeed its authentic ghost. How then can an anti-
Trotskyist position be grafted on to Marxism-Leninism? To answer
this question will return us to my initial inquiry as to the tragic
flaw in the role acted out by Che. For what Che uses to close the
gap between what the Marxist-Leninist must hold on an objective
analysis to be a situation in which the socialist revolution cannot
yet be made and the revolutionary aspirations of the selfsame
Marxist-Leninist who confronts himself with this, as it must
seem, defeatist analysis, is an appeal to pure will. Lenin too was
confronted with this gap and at every stage wrestled to link the
present and the future by means of a consciousness nurtured by
the organizational forms of the party. In Guevara, although
74 Against the Self-Images of the Age
questions of organization are treated with intellectual respect, it
is the voluntarist component of Leninism which is appealed to as
never before.
Consider for example the question of planning. Guevara con-
ducted a polemic against the French Communist expert on
planification, Charles Bettelheim, in which he argued that because
of the level that consciousness (in the Marxist sense) had reached
in the world at large, the social and political consciousness of
Marxists in a country where the objective conditions for a socialist
revolution had not yet been reached could none the less enable
them to transcend those limitations and to do what seemed
objectively impossible. From this premise Che argued further
in more general terms for a relative independence of cultural
superstructure from economic basis. This led him to quarrel
with Bettelheim and other Marxists on economic policy. Material
incentives, such as may be provided by a wages structure may be
appropriate as the mainspring of a market economy, but are
inappropriate to socialism. Centralized planning demands the
centralization of major economic decision-making, but it does not
require centralized management.
What is to take the place of material incentives and of the
dictates of centralized management? A new motivation springing
from the new nature of socialist man. Moral incentives must be
the mainspring; material incentives must be subordinate. The
word "moral" recurs throughout Che's writings. He was the
minister who awarded the title "Hero of Labor" to workers who
excelled. In his speeches to workers he constantly urged sacrifice
and hard work. His personal asceticism put his right to make such
calls beyond question. But their theoretical justification is quite
another matter.
Behind the Leninist voluntarism we see in Che the revival of an
older answer to the Marxist dilemma about morality. Marx him-
self never raises explicitly the question of the motives of those who
seek to achieve socialism. At the turn of the century when Bern-
stein raised the question of the moral foundations of socialism
and turned back to Kant's invocation of duty in order to answer it.
Kautsky replied to him with a crude invocation of utilitarianism
which relied on an underlying appeal to material self-interest;
and Rosa Luxemburg in her polemics against Bernstein avoided
coming to grips with this question at all. Bernstein's Kantian
answer was in fact more influential than we sometimes realize;
and to be Kantian was not necessarily to be a right-wing social
democrat. After 1914 Kautsky the orthodox Marxist was far to the
Marxism of the will 75
right of Karl Liebknecht, the Kantian and Spartacist. Guevara
was Karl Liebknecht's spiritual heir; like Liebknecht he in the end
bore witness to the fact that moral heroism is not enough. In the
improbable environment of Cuba, Kantian moral theory was
reborn as revolutionary.
Che's moral heroism, his attempt to transcend the material
environment, was the tragic flaw which finally destroyed him in
Bolivia. When he left Cuba he wrote to his children: "Above all,
always be able to feel deeply any injustice committed against
anyone in any part of the world. It's a revolutionary's most
beautiful quality"; and to his parents: "Essentially, nothing has
changed, except that I am much more conscientious, my Marxism
has struck deep roots and is purified." Again the Kantian note is
struck. Conscientiousness took him to his death, because it led
him to ignore political and military facts, and especially Barrientos'
ability to mobilize peasant support.
When I stress Che's moralism, I do not want to underestimate
his intellectual qualities. Americans in particular should read the
speech rejecting the Alliance for Progress made at the Punta del
Este Conference of the OAS in 1961; about that particular
Kennedy cloud-cuckoo project Guevara has proved alarmingly
right. But when Guevara is not being critical of imperialism, he is
all too apt to substitute invocations of honor or of the spirit of
sacrifice for intellectual analysis. Guevara's student admirers are
indeed moved precisely by this and so is John Gerassi who has
done scholarship a service by his collection of Guevara's speeches
and writings. Yet what they admire is just that abstract moralism
which Marx himself ought to have taught us to suspect. Che's
last letter to his parents begins with an allusion to Cervantes:
"Once more I feel Rocinante's ribs under my heels; I'm taking to
the road again with my shield on my arm." Perhaps as he wrote
this he should have remembered that other reminiscence of
Cervantes in a footnote in Capital which ends by Marx remarking
that "Don Quixote long ago paid the penalty for wrongly imagin-
ing that knight errantry was compatible with all economic forms
of society."
IO

Pascal and Marx:


On Lucien Goldmann's Hidden God 1

The irregular verb which many Anglo-Saxon philosophers


conjugate on their way to international ·conferences runs, "I am
sober; you are intoxicated; he is a French philosopher." A tradi-
tion of rhetoric and a belief that for Frenchmen clarity is not an
achievement but a birthright have admittedly often worked havoc
with analytical sobriety across the Channel. But the unfamiliar
atmosphere of French philosophy has other more admirable
causes. It is in particular more conscious of its background in
intellectual and social history, and not just in the history of philo-
sophy. It is therefore often at its best when it is self-consciously
historical in its approach. And this, too, is often the best way for
us to approach it. History may provide an initial common ground
where philosophy itself would fail us. Metaphysical excitement
may appear the more justified at the close, if the starting-point
was dull and factual. What facts more dull than names and dates?
Every one of Macaulay's Utopian schoolboys knows the name of
Rene Descartes; not even they know that of Antoine Le Maitre.
But it was in successive years (in 1636 and in 1637) that Descartes
published the account of that winter morning nearly twenty
years before when he stayed in by the stove and so founded
modern philosophy, and that Le Maitre withdrew from the world
to live in solitary penance at Port-Royal. Both Descartes and Le
Maitre are significant because of what the future was to make
out of them, and the more significant because they came to
symbolize two incompatible alternatives for the modern world.
It turned out that Descartes had woven into a single rational
system some o_fthe dominant themes of the next age, in its life as
well as in its thought: the isolated individual as self-sufficient in
knowledge and action; the ideal of mechanical explanation; the
1 Reprinted from Encounter,October 1964.
76
Pascaland Marx: on Luci,enGoldmann'sHidden God 77
reduction of God to the status of a guarantee that the gaps in
rational argument can be filled, and the actions of individuals
harmonized; the dualisms of reason and the passions, and of mind
and matter. Cartesianism is the new consciousness expressed as a
doctrine. From the world to which Descartes gave expression
Le Maitre withdrew, abandoning his already successful career as a
lawyer. His spiritual director was the Abbe de Saint-Cyran,
friend of Cornelius Jansen, the Bishop of Ypres, and director of
the nuns of Port-Royal, then :n Paris. On May 2, 1638, Saint-
Cyran was arrested on Richelieu's orders, accused of depriving
the state of its ablest subjects, and never left prison.
From the very first, therefore, the devotional and doctrinal
movement of J ansenism was recognized by the powers that be as
their enemy. Withdrawal from the modern world was a challenge
to it. In its withdrawal Jansenism asserts its own counter-thesis:
"It is from our separation and absence from the world that is
born the presence and feeling for God" (Saint-Cyran). Or again:
We must have a low opinion not only of the truths which we
discover through our own minds, but also of those which God
gives us by his divine light. For this light is not the perfect gift
of which the Scriptures speak ... (Barcos).
Most radically of all J ansenism declared that there are divine
commandments which the just man who lacks the requisite Grace
-and the just man may well lack the requisite Grace-cannot
by his own efforts obey. So we get the paradox of the just man who
is yet condemned by God, who is yet a sinner. Or at least these
positions seemed to the critics of J ansenism to follow from its
central thesis-the J ansenists themselves oscillated between deny-
ing that this was a correct characterization of Jansen's theology
and asserting that it was a correct characterization not only of
Jansen's views, but also of St. Augustine's, and therefore orthodox.
What matters is the Jansenist assertion of an unbridgable gap
between the concepts by means of which the world understands
justice and those in which God reveals his will.
God or the World? As always the choice was between a highly
specific God and a highly specific world: an Augustinian God and
a Cartesian world. How was one to choose? Within the Jansenist
movement there were different answers. One, that of Martin de
Barcos, was a total refusal of the world. Another, that of Antoine
Arnauld, involved the drawing of an almost Thomistic line between
the realm in which natural reason is competent and the realm in
which only faith in supernatural revelation can guide. Character-
Against the Self-Images of the Age
istically Barcos wrote to advise other adherents of J ansenism on
matters of faith; Arnauld equally characteristically was the author
both of De La Frequente Communion (paradoxically named, since
the standards of spiritual achievement demanded prior to com-
munion are so high that infrequent communion would have to be
the rule) and of the Logique de Port-Royal. Arnauld tries to give
unto Descartes the things that are Descartes', and unto God the
things that are God's. Unfortunately, as Barcos correctly saw, one
cannot serve both God and Descartes, at least in any easy syn-
thesizing way. This becomes plainest when one considers the role
of God in Cartesianism: the God whom Descartes uses to guarantee
the existence of the external world and to give the first push to the
mechanisms of the physical universe is precisely that God of the
philosophers whom the J ansenists contrast with the God of
Abraham and Augustine.
The question of compromise with the world arose, too, at the
political level. Barcos, the consistent extremist, severed his
connection with Port-Royal finally when the compromise embodied
in the Peace of Clement IX in 1669 was accepted. That Barcos was
in some sense right is shown by the fact that neither the Roman
church nor the French state was able to compromise with Jan-
senism from their own point of view and pressed forward to its
total destruction. What was it that they could not accept? The
J ansenists, especially Barcos, recognized a duty of obedience to
their God-given superiors. They asked only to be left alone. But
in providing a withdrawal from the world of church, state, and
Cartesianism they affronted it. To understand in what the affront
consisted we must consider further who the J ansenists were. Yet
before asking that question it is even more important to note that
the possibilities of Jansenism are not exhausted by the alterna-
tives of Barcos and Arnauld.
Suppose that, unlike Arnauld, one recognized the impossibility
of a compromise between God and the contemporary world; yet,
unlike Barcos, one could not deny the achievement of Descartes
and wished to go beyond it by criticizing it. Suppose that none
the less one could not but live in the sight of the God of Abraham
and Augustine. One would then have to affirm two apparently
incompatible truths:
If ever there is a time when one should make profession of
opposites, it is when one is accused of omitting one of them ...
(fragment 865). 1
1 I have numbered the fragments as in the Brunschvicg edition.
Pascal and Marx: on Lucien Goldmann's Hidden God 79
It is for failing to do this that Pascal reproves the Jansenists.
Pascal aspires both to reject and to accept the world. He could
thus in one and the same period of his life write of the vanity of
scientific pursuits and set himself successfully to solve the problem
of the cycloid. When Gilberte Pascal wrote her brother's biography,
she explained his application to mathematics at that period as an
attempt to take his mind off his toothache. Leon Brunschvicg
explained Pascal's denigration of science by referring to his failure
to convince the Jesuit Noel and Descartes of the significance of
his experiments with the vacuum. Both explanations obscure the
complexity of Pascal's position:
One does not show one's greatness by being at one extreme,
but by touching both at the same time, and by filling all the
space between.
This is not the position of Pascal in the Lettres Provinciales in
which the Jesuit opponents of Jansenism are met on their own
ground. But, on this interpretation, from March 1657 onward
Pascal elaborated a new and paradoxical attitude of which the
Pensees are the expression.
This interpretation of Pascal is the work of Lucien Goldmann, 1
the Marxist editor of Barcos' correspondence, himself an original
philosopher of great powers. In Goldmann's view Pascal's final
position is an extreme rendering of a coherence implicit in the rest
of J ansenism, but only expressed in other writers in one-sided and
incomplete forms. He lays great stress on the change in Pascal in
1657; the earlier crisis of 1654 when Pascal had the religious
conversion, whose record was the Memorial, had led Pascal into a
life which only found its intellectual expression after 1657. Until
then he stood with Arnauld in dividing the provinces of faith and
reason.
But after 1657 he affirms both a philosophical view of the world
which transcends Cartesianism and a view of God which makes all
worldly activity worthless. Sometimes these attitudes are com-
bined in the same fragment:
Descartes-We must say, approximately, "This occurs by
figure and motion," for that is true. But it is ridiculous to say
which figures and motions; and try to reconstruct the machine.
For it is unnecessary, uncertain, and difficult. And even if it
were possible, I do not consider the whole of philosophy to be
worth an hour of trouble (fragment 79 ).
1 The Hidden God, trs. P. Thody (1964). Lucien Goldmann's untimely

death in 1970 robbed us of the finest and most intelligent Marxist of the age.
80 Against the Self-Images of the Age
Sometimes we get an acute criticism of Cartesianism of purely
philosophical interest:
If man were to begin by studying himself, he would see how
incapable he is of going beyond himself. How could it be
possible for a part to know the whole? But he may perhaps aspire
to a knowledge of at least those parts which are on the same
scale as himself. But the different parts of the world are all so
closely linked and related together that I hold it to be impossible
to know one without knowing the other and without knowing
the whole (fragment 72).
At other times we find the whole of human knowledge brought
under condemnation:
Everything here on earth is partly true and partly false. But
essential truth is not like this, for it is wholly pure and wholly
true. The mixture that we find here on earth both dishonours
and destroys this truth ... (fragment 385).
Is Pascal simply inconsistent? Should his solution have been in a
tough-minded way to grasp one of the horns of his dilemma and
abandon the other? This would have been the Cartesian solution
as it would also have been the Augustinian. But Pascal inhabits
two conceptual universes the claims of which he can neither
reconcile nor abandon. Torn as he is between two realms, he can
see each from the point of view of the other and his own predica-
ment from both. Thus from within Christianity he sees his dilemma
as itself prefigured by Christian theology. For does not Christian
theology assert that we inhabit two realms, that man belongs both
with the angels and the beasts, that if human nature ignores its
limitations and seeks to be angelic it becomes bestial, that a hidden
God has revealed himself incarnate and so on? The paradoxes of
Christianity show it to be divine.
Yet from within the world he can see Christianity in the per-
spective of his own critique of Cartesianism. His skepticism about
clear and distinct ideas ("Too much clarity darkens") and about
any allegedly indubitable first principles, even those of skepticism,
extends to any alleged arguments for Christianity, even his own.
The theory of chances, which he had elaborated to assist his friend
Mere at the gambling tables, encounters its limit at the point at
which there are no more probabilities, but the stakes are infinite.
Yet at this very point a wager cannot be avoided. It is only
through a wager that God exists that meaning is conferred on an
otherwise meaningless world. Yet it is from the standpoint of that
Pascaland Marx: on Lucien Goldmann'sHidden God 81
world that we have to learn that belief in God has to accept the
status of a wager.
Let Pascal abandon the world and he becomes the ancestor of
Kierkegaard, of a self-contained fideism. Let him abandon
Christianity and he becomes the ancestor of Hume, avoiding
skepticism only by calling nature and custom to his aid. His
greatness is in abandoning neither. Why? To understand Gold-
mann's answer to this question we must turn to his use of Marx
and Lukacs.
The danger is that we read what Goldmann has to say through
our own preconceptions; and where Marxism is concerned no one
is without preconceptions. Goldmann's thesis is that Pascal ex-
pressed in one particular form a coherent world vision which
Lukacs was to characterize. That world vision, the vision of
tragedy, is rooted in the social history of Jansenism, expressing
the attitudes implicit in the predicament of the noblessede robe.
Our preconceptions and prejudices might lead us to treat Gold-
mann's views as just one more explanation of the history of thought
in terms of an economic and social basis. But if we did we should
miss the concreteness of Goldmann's concerns. He is very far
from forcing the interpretation of J ansenism and Pascal into an
already existing theoretical structure. Rather it is at least partly
through his studies of J ansenism and Pascal that he gives meaning
to his theoretical terms. So one cannot fully understand the early
theoretical chapters of his book until one has read the later his-
torical and literary studies. Pascal and J ansenism are made to
illuminate Marxism quite as much as Marxism is made to illu-
minate Pascal and J ansenism. Pascal himself would have under-
stood this: "The last thing one discovers when writing a book is
what ought to have come first."
The tragic vision, which Lukacs described, 1 is the vision of a
world where God is no longer present, and yet even in his absence
life has to be lived out by the tragic hero with the eye of God upon
him. Because God is absent, the hero cannot succeed in the world.
Because God, though absent, still regards him, he cannot abandon
his task. He is the just man under condemnation, whom the critics
of J ansenism saw at the heart of Jansenist doctrine. So long as he
responds by refusing the world, he is Barcos. So long as he tries
to live in the world and yet also to refuse it, he is Pascal himself.
"In Die Seele und die Formen (Berlin: Essays Fleischel, 1911). The
Lukacs whom Goldmann follows is the since self-condemned Lukacs of
this book and of Geschichte und Klassenbewusstsein. Lukacs has now (1971)
altered his attitude to his work of this period yet once more.
82 Against the Self-Images of the Age
The Lukacs of 1911 saw the tragic vision as one form of aesthetic
insight; Goldmann sees it as.capable of embodiment only when it
expresses a form of social life which can recognize its own crisis
in this vision.
The noblessede robe (as contrasted with the noblessede cour) was
composed of those lawyers and administrators whom the French
monarchy used in achieving hegemony over the rest of the nobility,
strengthening itself by this alliance with the Third Estate and the
townsmen. During the seventeenth century the monarchy breaks
this alliance and becomes an independent power, balancing class
against class and governing through its own corpsde commissaires.
The noblessede robe thus find themselves on the defensive; their
allegiance to the crown and to the established order is the condition
of their flourishing and yet now the crown has less and less use for
them. They can less and less live out the only role they know, and
yet they must recognize the legitimate authority of the power that
is abolishing that role. The congruence of this social experience
with the tragic vision is clear. (One is reminded of Milton who does
not just have to justify the ways of God to man in general, but has
to reconcile the hidden fact that God rules with the manifest fact
that Charles II rules and the saints do not.) Thus the parlement's
manifest sympathy for J ansenism is for Goldmann a sign of
recognition by a segment of the middle class that in J ansenism
their own fragmentary attitudes receive completer expression and
endorsement than elsewhere.
Goldmann is at the opposite extreme from those self-styled
Marxists who have tried to reduce the artist or the philosopher
to a mere product of his social background. He sees that such a
reduction fails to account precisely for what interests us in a
writer's achievement, his distinctiveness. Goldmann's injunction
is rather that we should understand the background through the
writer, seeing in the coherence of great art or great philosophy
something that is only implicit in the thought and action of
ordinary men. So he invites us to understand J ansenism through
Pascal, and the noblessede robe through Jansenism. Moreover,
the greatest writers both express and transcend their age. They
show us the possibilities in the age of going beyond it, whereas
lesser writers exhibit the limitations imposed upon them by the
age.
It is not only Pascal whom Goldmann views in this light. He
analyses Racine's tragedies in terms of the concept of the tragic
vision, seeing a parallelism between the J ansenism of refusal of the
world and the tragedies of refusal, Andromaque and Britannicus,
Pascal and Marx: on Lucien Goldmann's Hidden God 83
while Pascal's attitude is paralleled in Phedre. These parallelisms
are brought out within a much more detailed classification of
tragedy. The justification of this classification and the use of
Lukacs' artificial construct of the tragic vision can lie solely in
whether it enables us to understand better not only the plays
themselves, but also the author's relationship to them. And
Goldmann follows Racine himself in seeing the heart of Jansenism
in Phedre. For it was in the preface to Phedre that Racine hoped
that his method in this play "would perhaps be a way of reconcil-
ing with tragedy a number of persons famous for both their piety
and doctrine"-although he does so ostensibly for the platitudi-
nous reason that in his play virtue and vice receive their deserts.
Whereas in fact if Goldmann is right the greatness of Phedre
herself is that she cannot refuse the claims of the world as em-
bodied in her own passion and her conception of Hippolytus but
nor can she refuse to live with the eye of God upon her. Of Phedre
what Lukacs wrote of the tragic hero holds:
He hopes that a judgment by God will illuminate the different
struggles which he sees in the world before him, and will reveal
the ultimate truth. But the world around him still follows the
same path, indifferent to both questions and answers. No word
comes from either created or natural things, and the race is not
to the swift nor battle to the strong. The clear voice of the
judgment of God no longer sounds out above the march of
human destiny, for the voice which once gave life to all has now
fallen silent. Man must live alone and by himself. The voice of
the judge has fallen silent forever, and this is why men will
always be vanquished, doomed to destruction in victory even
more than in defeat.
Tragic thought is not simply an episode in the past. Pascal, in
Goldmann's view, is not only illuminated by Marx and Lukacs, he
is their ancestor. He anticpates their epistemology in two crucial
respects. First of all, he understands that the knowledge of man
himself depends on grasping the individual as part of a totality.
Yet we cannot grasp the totality except insofar as we understand
the individuals who comprise it. Marx wrote:
A loom is a machine used for weaving. It is only under certain
conditions that it becomes capital; isolated from these condi-
tions it is as far from being capital as gold, in its natural state,
is from being coin of the realm.
What are these conditions? They include both the existence of a
Against the Self-Images of the Age
whole system of economic activity and the informing of human
activities and intentions by concepts which express the relation-
ships characteristic of the system. We identify a loom as capital or
gold as coin only when we have grasped a whole system of activities
as a capitalist or monetary system. The individual object or action
is identifiable only in the context of the totality; the totality is only
identifiable as a set of relationships between individuals. Hence
we must move from parts to whole and back from whole to parts.
Goethe, Hegel, and Marx all grasped versions of this truth about
the human sciences. Pascal, as Goldmann interprets!him, uses it
against Descartes in the fragments about the whole and the parts
and about figure and motion, which I quoted earlier. We can put
the essence of his criticism by saying that, just as no amount of
mechanical explanation of the working of a loom will tell us what
weaving is, or how a loom becomes capital, so no amount of
mechanical explanation of reflexes will tell us what human action
is or how a man becomes in his actions like an angel or a beast.
For that we need to understand human action as part of a total
system in which certain norms are established. The difficulty is
that men have false as well as true consciousness of the systems
of which they form a part. They need a criterion for discriminat-
ing true from false, and they exhibit this need especially in trying
to understand the over-all context of their actions. For Pascal this
context is provided by God and his will; for Hegel and Marx by
the history of society. For Pascal the contradictions involved in
the task are ultimate and irresoluble; for Hegel and Marx they
can be transcended in a future form of human community. But
if tragic thought and dialectical thought differ in these crucial
respects, they also resemble each other at key points. Both know
that one cannot first understand the world and only then act in it.
How one understands the world will depend in part on the deci-
sion implicit in one's already taken actions. The wager of action is
unavoidable. Goldmann is willing even to use the word "faith" of
the Marxist attitude, and he sees a real continuity between Augusti-
nian theology and Marxism, despite their differences on such
issues as the actual existence of God:

Subsequently Hegel, and especially Marx and Lukacs, have


been able to substitute for the wager on the paradoxical and
mediatory God of Christianity the wager on a historical future
and the human community. In doing so, however, they have
not given up the main demands of tragic thought, that is to say a
doctrine which explains the paradoxical nature of human
Pascal and Marx: on Lucien Goldmann's Hidden God 85
reality, and hope in the eventual creation of values which
endows this contradiction with meaning and which transforms
ambiguity into a necessary element in a significant whole.
Not eternity but the future provides a context which gives mean-
ing to individual parts in the present. The future which does this
is as yet unmade; we wager on it not as spectators, but as actors
pledged to bring it into being.
Thus if Goldmann presents us with a Marxist Pascal he also
offers us a Pascalian Marx. In so doing he breaks, as the young
Lukacs broke before him, with the view of Marxism as a closed,
mechanistic and deterministic system of thought, and he illumi-
nates a variety of Marxist texts which both Marx's critics and his
defenders too often neglect. He makes it possible to understand
the horror with which the Stalinist Lukacs must have come to
regard his own youth.
Is what Goldmann says true? Partly this is an empirical ques-
tion, to be answered by close historians of Jansenism and careful
students of Pascal and Racine. Partly it is a question of how far the
notion of "the tragic vision" is a useful construct. What does it
help us to see to which we should otherwise be blind? But the
implications of Goldmann's work extend far more widely than
do these questions.
For by placing tragic thought, Cartesian rationalism, and
Marxism in the way that he does he commits himself to schematic
interpretation of the history of modern philosophy. This schema-
tism is made explicit at a number of points in the book, but more
especially in a brilliant excursus on the Faust legend and in several
discussions of Kant, to whom Goldmann devoted an earlier book.1
To put it very crudely, Goldmann sees Kant as standing at an
extreme point in the development of the related rifts between
fact and value and between virtue and happiness. For Kant the
highest good is still virtue crowned with happiness; but virtue and
happiness cannot be brought together within the world. It is only
beyond the present world by a power outside it that they can be
reconciled. Practical life is intolerable unless there is such a divine
power, but theoretical inquiry cannot show either that there is or
is not such a being. So for Kant moral rules are independent of
how the world goes, to be obeyed whatever the consequences of
obeying them; and yet there would be no point in obeying the
rules unless the universe were of a certain kind. Thus Goldmann
1 La communaute humaine et l'univers chez Kant (Paris: Presses Univer-
sitaires de France, 1948).
86 Against the Self-Images of the Age
sees Kant, too, as holding together a tragic contradiction, and in
so doing acting as Pascal's successor.
It is in his treatment of Kant that the striking differences
between Goldmann and his Anglo-Saxon counterparts emerge.
Moral philosophy in England is notably unhistorical. Books are
too often written about "the" moral vocabulary apparently on the
assumption that there is an unchanging structure of concepts.
It is too often assumed, when moral philosophers apparently
disagree about "good" and "ought," that they are holding rival
and competing views of the same concepts, rather than elucidating
very different concepts from very different historical periods.
Goldmann's book is in this respect a model of how to write moral
philosophy.
Moreover, in bringing out the links between Augustinianism
and Marxism, for example-and they go far further than I have
suggested in this review-Goldmann contributes to an urgent con-
temporary task, that of redrawing the lines of intellectual contro-
versy. It has been becoming increasingly plain that whether a man
calls himself a Christian, a Marxist, or a liberal, may be less im-
portant than what kind of Christian, Marxist, or liberal he is. I
remarked earlier that Augustinians and Marxists do differ after
all about the existence of God; but they agree that whether God
exists or not is a crucial question. In so doing they unite against
both Christians of the Tillich-Robinson kind and liberals of a
certain kind who think religion a matter of "private" life. Equally
that both Goldmann and Sartre call themselves Marxists does not
obliterate the gulf that separates their views, let alone that which
separates both from M. Garaudy 1 and the French Communist
Party's intellectual enclave.
Finally, it is not of course true that the tragic is a category
which can finally be transcended and left behind. It remains a
possibility wherever the attempt is made to live within and to
transcend a society. This attempt need not be tragic in its dimen-
sions. Stendhal's heroes make it in quite a different way. But it
remains a possibility:

There are only three kinds of person: those who, having found
God, seek Him; those who, not having found Him, spend their
time seeking Him; and those who live without having found
Him and without seeking for Him either. The first are both

1 In spite of Roger Garaudy's later reversal of his Stalinist positions,

I see no need to change what I wrote earlier.


Pascal and Marx: on Luci.enGoldmann'sHidden God 87
blessed and reasonable, the last both mad and unhappy, and
the second unhappy but reasonable (fragment 257).
This is an age when no one is blessed and reasonable and most are
mad and unhappy. The task is to be unhappy but reasonable.
PART TWO
II

Philosophy and ideology:


Introduction to Part Two

The aspiration of Marxism was to provide a perspective in which


the present might be understood as a transition from the enslave-
ment of the past to the liberation of the future. This view of the
present does of course appear in vulgarized form as a common-
place of the nineteenth century, not specific to Marxism. It
reappears in psychoanalysis as a doctrine about individuals:
"Where id was, there ego shall be." And it plainly has a Christian
ancestry. But where Christianity saw this liberation as at the end of
and transcending the history of this world, Marxism placed it
within history and indeed within the foreseeable future. All three
doctrines therefore characterize the present in terms of its relation-
ship to past and future: as a time of redemption from sin, as a point
where neurotic entanglements with the past give way before the
constructive aspirations of the ego ideal, and as the period of the
revolutionary passage from exploitation and unfreedom to
socialism and then to Communism.
To characterize the present in these ways, to insist indeed that
the present is only adequately described when it is characterized
in these ways, is to use descriptions the application of which
commits the user to certain evaluations. To say of a man that he is
deeply neurotic, a sinner, or either exploited or an exploiter is not
only to say what he is, but also to say what he ought to be. Just
what is the relationship of this "is" to this "ought" ? From Kant
onward at least, there have been philosophers who have insisted
that judgments of fact were one thing, judgments about what is
right or good quite another thing, and that the latter could never be
logically derived from the former. This view of morality as an
autonomous sphere was certainly a faithful rendering of a view
highly influential in the society which these philosophers belonged
to. For, according to a view that was often tacitly presupposed by
91
92 Against the Self-Images of the Age
liberal individualism, questions of fact are settled independently
of what anyone wants or chooses, but questions of value are
settled only by the individual's choosing and standing by some
particular set of principles. The individual confronts the objective
facts with a freedom to make such evaluations as he will.
But is this view of man true? Or is it a view-true to some
extent at least of liberal, individualist men-made true indeed by
their believing it to be true? And does the corresponding philo-
sophical view of the autonomy of morality and of the logical
gulf between "is,, and "ought" express what is true only of the
scheme of ideas and beliefs which informed and informs liberal
individualism, or does it rather express a truth about the nature of
morality as such? It was against Kant's treatment of "is,, and
"ought'' that the young Marx reacted as early as 1837; and
certainly the truth of Kant's thesis is incompatible with the truth
of Marx's mature doctrine. For according to Marxism, there are
not neutral, objective facts on the one hand and individuals
freely choosing their values on the other. It is rather the case that
an individual with a given role has norms and ends such that
when he accepts a given characterization of the facts, he also
evaluates them in accordance with his class role. (Class role is of
course never simply a matter of having a particular kind of occupa-
tion.) Hence, for Marxism the key descriptive expressions in our
vocabulary are also evaluative. Nor is this merely a matter of such
expressions being composites in which a descriptive component is
joined to the expression of an evaluative choice. For in a Marxist
view, values are not chosen, they are given; indeed, the view that
values are not given but chosen is, in a Marxist view, one of the
given evaluations of a liberal, individualist society. For it itself
embodies an evaluative attitude.
By contrast, the view of social science implicit or explicit in
the attitudes expressed by the end-of-ideology thesis is one that
accepts the separation of fact and value, usually in a version
derived from Max Weber. It follows that, underlying the con-
frontation of these two ideologies-Marxism and that which,
as I argued earlier, is embodied in the end-of-ideology thesis-
there is a crucial philosophical disagreement. Moreover, this
same issue, and a number of other closely related philosophical
issues, are raised by another problem that is central to the ideo-
logical themes discussed in the first part of this book. Marx
originally indicted capitalist values as well as capitalist methods.
His belief that any appeal to the exploiters on a moral basis was
bound to embody the illusion of common standards of justice
Philosophyand ideology:Introductionto Part Two 93
governing human behavior made him suspicious of all moralizing.
But when Eduard Bernstein attempted to find a Kantian basis for
socialism, the defenders of Marxist orthodoxy Karl Kautsky
and Rosa Luxemburg were forced to reopen the question of the
nature of the moral authority of the Marxist appeal to the working
class. This question, as the experience of Luxemburg and of
Lukacs, of Trotsky and of Guevara shows, was never satisfactorily
answered. Equally, those who broke with Marxism because of its
moral failures, both under Stalin and in the post-Stalinist age,
have been extremely unclear as to the kind of authority that their
moral condemnation has possessed. To what were they appealing?
Silone, for example, turned to so highly personal a Christian
vision that it would be difficult to understand how this could
provide a general and impersonal basis for the kind of moral
dissidence that so many have underwritten. It does in fact seem
to be the case that from the moral collapse of Marxism men can
only turn back to clutch at fragments of that pre-Marxist moralizing
which Marx criticized so radically and so effectively.
We therefore cannot escape asking the question: what is
morality? and what is its power in the world? And this not only
for the reasons I have already given. If we are to escape that
"worship of the established fact" which is embodied in the
end-of-ideology view of the world, if we are to criticize effectively
the uncontrolled, destructive progress of advanced societies in the
name of an alternative vision of human liberation-if, that is,
we are to create a genuinely post-Marxist ideology of liberation,
then we have to avoid the snares which Marxism did not, for all
its great achievement, avoid. These snares were not only, of
course, a matter of the nature of morality and the conditions
under which morality can have power in the world; among the
other snares was a lack of concern about philosophical truth, and
such a concern is a necessary precondition of answering the
questions about morality adequately and without illusion. Why
is this so?
In The German Ideology, Marx and Engels remarked that
"When reality is depicted, philosophy as an independent branch
of activity loses its medium of existence" ; and Marx elsewhere
put this by saying that philosophy stands to a genuine under-
standing of reality as onanism does to real sexual activity. These
aphorisms were, of course, aimed specifically at Hegelianism and
Young Hegelianism, doctrines which absurdly inflated the claims
of philosophy. But in discussing these pretensions, Marx and
Engels proceeded to treat as unproblematic or as already resolved
94 Against the Self-Images of the Age
questions and issues which later philosophy has illuminated~
but which even so have not been fully solved or resolved-but
from the study of which Marxism has insulated itself.
Two groups of questions in particular are crucial, and two non-
Marxist philosophical traditions have been important in contribut-
ing to the answers. The first group of questions will already be
clear. It concerns the nature of moral judgment. What do the key
evaluative words mean, words such as "good," "right," "virtue,"
"justice," "duty," "happiness," and the like? And to what kind
of standards with what kind of authority are we appealing when
we use them? Marxists have often shared with highly conservative
philosophers the view that a concern about the theory of meaning,
or about the nature of speech acts, is somehow a trivialization of
philosophy, a turning away from questions of substance. But it
has been precisely at the level of language that the moral inade-
quacies and corruptions of our age have been evident, and
certainly no less so by those with ideological stances than by others.
The key question for ideology-whether we (still) possess a
language in which we can say what we sometimes desperately want
to be able to say-cannot be answered until the philosophical
problems about meaning have been resolved.
The second group of questions concerns the explanation of
human action. If moral considerations are important, if socialism
is to have a human face, then we shall have to understand what
part reasoning and deliberation play in bringing about one sort of
action rather than another. Marx and Engels at the outset rightly
wished to draw a contrast between what really moved men to
act in certain ways and what the same men believed to have
moved them to act. This distinction is at the heart of the Marxist
theory of ideology. But Marx and Engels also asserted that men
could find reasons for action in the modern world which would not
only enable them to act effectively, but which would be such that
what they believed to be moving them to action would indeed
be what was in fact moving them to action. The empirical investiga-
tion of these questions cannot proceed successfully unless it is
preceded and accompanied by a philosophical account of the
relationship between the kind of explanation of human action in
terms of intentions, reasons, and purposes which is native to human
life itself and the kind of causal explanation which is familiar in the
natural sciences. Just these issues have been the focus of a good
deal of discussion by philosophers influenced by Wittgenstein,
Ryle, and Austin in the last two decades, and the questions in
moral philosophy which I have already instanced have provided a
Philosophyand ideology:Introduction.to Part Two 95
similar focus. Since these discussions have at their best exhibited a
care for rigor and for truth not always exhibited by those engaged
in the ideological disputes of the age, it is all the more important
that the bearing of these discussions on ideology should con-
tinuously be kept in mind. The investigations that form the subject
matter of the second part of this book are expressions of this
concern.
I spoke earlier of twophilosophical schools whose importance had
been overlooked by the Marxist tradition, and so far I have
mentioned only one. The other is that part of the British idealist
traditiop which culminated in the work of R. G. Collingwood. I
take it that Collingwood's outstanding merit was to have under-
stood that we cannot investigate a philosophical subject matter
adequately unless we take seriously the fact that such a subject
matter always has a historical dimension. That dimension is
missing in most work by philosophers within the analytical
tradition.
I have reprinted the essays in this second part as they stood,
without trying to produce a consistent and harmonious whole.
They represent stages in a single inquiry, and I am well aware
that they do not provide anything even approaching a unified
and systematic treatment. But their fragmentary and tentative
nature must not be allowed to detract from the importance of the
questions that they raise not only for the professional philosopher,
but also for all those who have a stake, whether they know it or
not, in the outcome of the ideological debates.
12

What morality is not1

The central task to which contemporary moral philosophers have


addressed themselves is that of listing the distinctive characteristics
of moral utterances. In this essay I am concerned to propound an
entirely negative thesis about these characteristics. It is widely
held that it is of the essence of moral valuations that they are
universalizable and prescriptive. This is the contention which I
wish to deny. I shall proceed by first examining the thesis that
moral judgments are necessarily and essentially universalizable and
then the thesis that their distinctive function is a prescriptive one.
But as the argument proceeds I shall be unable to separate the
discussion of the latter thesis from that of the former.

I
Axe moral judgments essentially and necessarily universalizable ?
The contention that they are is expressed in its most illuminating
form in R. M. Hare's paper on "Universalizability." 2 Hare
borrows his terminology from E. Gellner's paper on "Logic and
Ethics," 3 where Gellner distinguishes what he calls U-type and
E-type valuations. A U-type valuation is an application of "a
rule wholly devoid of any personal reference, a rule containing
merely predicates (descriptions) and logical terms. " 4 An E-type
valuation is one containing some uneliminable personal reference.
Hare's thesis is that moral judgments are U-type valuations.
To give a reason for an action is not necessarily to commit oneself
to such a valuation "for I see no grounds in common language for
1 Reprinted from Philosophy, 1957.
1 Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (1954-55), pp. 295-312.
3 Ibid., pp. 157--78.

'Ibid., p. 163.
96
What morality is not 97
confining the word 'reason' to reasons involving U-type rules. " 1
But Hare goes on to say that his thesis "is analytic in virtue of the
meaning of the word 'moral.' "
What this amounts to is made very plain in an imaginary
conversation which Hare constructs between a "Kantian" and an
"Existentialist." This runs as follows:
E. : You oughtn't to do that.
K. : So you think that one oughtn't to do that kind of thing?
E. : I think nothing of the kind; I say only that you oughtn't
to do that.
K.: Don't you even imply that a person like me in circum-
stances of this kind oughtn't to do that kind of thing when the
other people involved are the sort of people that they are?
E.: No; I say only that you oughtn't to do that.
K. : Axe you making a moral judgment?
E.:Yes.
K. : In that case I fail to understand your use of the word
"moral."
Hare's comment on this is: "Most of us would be as baffled as
the 'Kantian'; and indeed we should be hard put to it to think of
any use of the word 'ought,' moral or nonmoral, in which the
'Existentialist's' remarks, would be comprehensible. Had the
'Existentialist' said 'Don't do that,' instead of 'You oughtn't to
do that,' the objections of the 'Kantian' could not have been made;
this illustrates one of the main differences between 'ought' and
ordinary imperatives." 2
The crux then of Hare's position is the contention that when-
ever anyone says "I, you or he ought to do so-and-so," they are
thereby committing themselves to the maxim "One ought to do
so-and-so." This commitment is embodied in the meaning of the
word "ought" insofar as "ought" is used morally-and indeed,
Hare seems to say, in nonmoral uses of "ought" also. But is this
contention in fact correct? Consider the following example which
is borrowed from Sartre.3 One of Sartre's pupils was confronted
during the war with the alternatives of leaving France to join de
Gaulle or of staying to look after his mother. His brother had been
killed in the German offensive in 1940 and his father was a
collaborator. These circumstances had left him with a strong
feeling that he was responsible as a patriot and they had left his
1 Ibid., p. 278.
1 Ibid., pp. 304-5.
• L'Existentialisme est un Humanisme, pp. 3g-42.
98 Against the Self-Images of the Age
mother in a state of almost complete dependence upon him. What
should he do? Stay with his mother or escape to England? Sartre
uses this problem in order to argue that there are no "objective"
criteria by which such a choice may be made. Part of the force of
his argument is this. Someone faced with such a decision might
choose either to stay or to go without attempting to legislate for
anyone else in a similar position. He might decide what to do
without being willing to allow that anyone else who chose
differently was blameworthy. He might legitimately announce his
choice by saying, "I have decided that I ought to stay with my
mother." If he did so, his use of "ought" would not express any
appeal to a universalizable principle. It would not be a U-type
valuation, but it would be a moral valuation.
Two points need to be made about this example, The first
concerns the function of "I ought to do so-and-so" when it is
used to announce a decision in a case like that of Sartre's pupil.
Its use is plainly to commit oneself, to allow that if I do not do
what I say I ought to do, then I am blameworthy. It is a per-
formatory use of "I ought" in that its use makes one responsible
for performing a particular action where before saying "I ought"
one could not have been held responsible for performing that
action rather than some alternative one. To note this is to bring
out the oddity in Hare's treatment of the "Existentialist's" con-
tribution to his dialogue. For in this nonuniversalizable sense of
"ought" one could never say "You oughtn't" but only "I
oughtn't." To say "You oughtn't" and suppose that you had used
"ought" in this sense would be as odd as to say "You promise"
and suppose that thereby one had committed someone else to a
promise.
Secondly, it might be argued that the very possibility of a
problem such as that of Sartre's pupil presupposes the acceptance
of certain universalizable maxims as moral principles. If Sartre's
pupil had not accepted the maxims "One ought to assist one's
parents when they are in need" and "One ought to assist one's
country when it is in need" there would have been no problem.
What is important is that the clash between two principles need not
be resolved by reformulating one of the principles or formulating a
third one. Certainly this clash could be so resolved. Sartre's pupil
might have acted on the maxim "Duties to one's parents always
have precedence over duties to one's country." Had he done so
he would have legislated not only for his own but for all relevantly
similar situations. But in order to make his own decision he does
not need to so legislate. Now it seems to be a consequence of Hare's
What morality is not 99
position that if the decision between principles is itself to be a
moral decision it must itself rest upon the adoption of a universaliz-
able maxim. This, in the light of Sartre's example, could only be
defended by an a priori restriction on the use of the word "moral."
Such a restriction, however, would not be merely a restriction
upon our use of a word. For to adopt Hare's use of "moral" would
be to permit only one way of settling conflicts of principle (that of
formulating a new principle or reformulating an old one) to be
counted as genuinely a moral solution to a moral problem, while
another way-that of the nonuniversalizable decision ala Sartre-
would be ruled out from the sphere of morality. To do this is
plainly to do more than to offer a descriptive analysis of the
meaning of "moral." It is to draw a line around one area of moral
utterance and behavior and restrict the term to that area.
What one can conclude from this is twofold. First, not all, but
only some, moral valuations are universalizable. What leads Hare
to insist that all are is his exclusive concentration on moral rules.
For rules, whether moral or nonmoral, are normally universal in
scope anyway, just because they are rules. As Mr. Isaiah Berlin has
written in another context, "In so far as rules are general instruc-
tions to act or refrain from acting in certain ways, in specified
circumstances, enjoined upon persons of a specified kind, they
enjoin uniform behavior in identical cases."1 If this is so, then
there is nothing specific to moral valuation in universalizability and
in so far as moral valuations are not expressions of rules they are
not universalizable. Secondly, the exceptions are not simply cases
analogous to that of Sartre's pupil. A whole range of cases can be
envisaged where moral valuations are not universalizable. At the
one extreme would be those instances where in adopting a moral
position someone consciously refrains from legislating for others,
although they might have done so; where a man says, for example,
"I ought to abstain from participation in war, but I cannot
criticize or condemn responsible nonpacifists," but might have
said, "One ought to abstain from participation in war." In such a
case whether to make a universal or a merely personal judgment
is itself a moral problem. The fact that a man might on moral
grounds refuse to legislate for anyone other than himself (perhaps
on the grounds that to do so would be moral arrogance) would by
itself be enough to show that not all moral valuation is univer-
salizable. Or rather that once again this thesis can only be main-
tained by an a priori and quite unjustifiable restriction upon the
word "moral." In other words, a man might conduct his moral
1 "Equality," in Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (1955-56).
100 Against the Self-Images of the Age
life without the concept of "duty" and substitute for it the concept
of "my duty." But such a private morality would still be a morality.
More commonly, however, nonuniversalizable judgments occur
when a man finds that the concept of "duty ' has limits which
render it useless in certain situations of moral perplexity. Such is
the example of Sartre's pupil. And such are the cases at the other
end of our scale where moral valuations must be nonuniversalizable,
where it is logically impossible to universalize. This is the case with
what the theologians call "works of supererogation." A work of
supererogation is by definition not numbered among the normal
duties of life. Those duties-such things as keeping one's promises
and paying one's debts-are partly characterized by the fact that
the maxims which enjoin them are universalizable. But there are a
great many acts of moral worth which do not come within their
scope: one may be virtuous in the sense in which virtue is
demanded of everyone without being morally heroic. A moral hero,
such as Captain Oates, is one who does more than duty demands.
In the universalizable sense of "ought" it does not therefore make
sense to assert that Captain Oates did what he ought to have done.
To say of a man that he did his duty in performing a work of
supererogation is to contradict oneself. Yet a man may set himself
the task of performing a work of supererogation and commit
himself to it so that he will blame himself if he fails without
finding such a failure in the case of others blameworthy. Such a
man might legitimately say, "I have taken so-and-so as what I
ought to do." And here his valuation cannot, logically cannot, be
universalized.

II
Crucial to the argument so far that universalizability is not a
necessary characteristic of all moral valuation has been the
distinction between first-person and third-person uses of moral
valuation. Before the force of this distinction can be fully under-
stood, however, it is necessary to inquire what the function of
moral valuation may be. The argument of this section will be that
there are a great variety of uses to which moral utterance may be
put, none of which can claim the title of "the" function of moral
valuation. It will be useful to list some of the tasks which even
so familiar a form of moral judgment as "X ought to do Y" may
be set.
1. The expressionof indignationor other violent or mild emotion.
What moralityis not IOI

This is characteristically a function of third-person uses. "He


ought to put his foot down," we may say angrily, although we
might hesitate to advise him by saying, "You ought to put your
foot down," and if we did so we would be advising as well as, or
even rather than, expressing our emotion. Clearly, of course, we
might say "He ought to put his foot down" without any kind of
emotion, and here we would presumably be prescribing a course of
action. If we did this we would be committing ourselves to the
advice "You ought to put your foot down" even if we never diet in
fact utter this advice. This brings out already how the same form
of words may be put to quite different use in moral utterance.
Those emotive theorists who said that the function of moral
utterance was to evince emotion would therefore have been
correct if they had substituted the indefinite for the definite article.
2. The expressionof commandsor exhortations.This is of course
a second-person use. As Stevenson pointed out, we may often say
(to a child, for example) "You ought not to do that," meaning
simply "Don't do that." 1 We may, of course, and often do so use
"ought" that "You ought" has more than, or other than, impera-
tival force, but we need not do so. Hare in his dialogue allows that
the "Existentialist" would have spoken correctly had he said
"Don't do that" instead of "You oughtn't to do that." But he
does not consider the possibility that the substitution of "ought"
for an imperative might be something other than a universalizing
of the imperative. Yet clearly in ordinary usage the use of "ought"
might simply be an indication of the importance attached to the
imperative, as it could be in the case of the command to the child.
3. The appraisalof actions.We can appraise equally the past,
present, and future actions of ourselves and others, whether in
their absence or to their faces. This is therefore one of the most
general uses of "ought" whether in tense or in person. When
"ought" is used for purposes of appraisal, it differs from "good"
in that comparatives and superlatives are not available. "He did
what he ought to have done" or "He failed to do what he ought
to have done" are the only two verdicts available. So that appraisal
by use of "ought" is appraisal that implies a single standard. If
you made this use central to your· moral utterance you would
produce a morality akin to that of the Stoics, where to fall from
good in the slightest degree is to fall into evil. ("A man drowns in
six inches of water as easily as in six feet.") At this point it is
important to note that this use of "ought" is logically independent
of the imperatival use. That is, there is no inconsistency in saying
1 Ethics and Language, p. 21.
102 Against the Self-Images of the Age
"You ought to do this, but don't." Those philosophers who have
insisted on analysing moral utterance in terms of imperatives
would be forced to interpret this as meaning "Do this (Let anyone
in this sort of situation do this kind of thing), but don't," which
would be as nonsensical as any utterance of the form p. ,_, p.
But where the "ought" expresses an appraisal there is no in-
consistency. For however morally reprehensible it may be, there
is no inconsistency in pointing out what the moral appraisal of an
action would be and then suggesting that one act otherwise. Some
writers have attempted to argue against this by interpreting "You
ought to do this, but don't," as meaning "In this society most
people would consider that you ought to do this, but I think you
ought to do that." But while this might be what would be meant,
it need not be. A man might commit himself to a certain moral
appraisal but not use it as a guide for action-"This in the light of
morality is how your action would be appraised: but don't follow
the guidance of morality."
4. The giving of advice. This is a genuinely prescriptive
function of moral utterance. It is also one in which genuinely
universalizable maxims are employed. For when we advise some-
one to undertake a certain course of action we do so in virtue of
certain characteristics of their situation and certain characteristics
of the recommended course of action. But while this might seem
to be a use of "ought" which accords admirably with Hare's
analysis, there is one point that stands out for notice; namely,
that the giving of advice is always a question of second-person
utterance. So that while "You ought to do so-and-so" may express
a universalizable prescription when it is offered as advice, clearly
"I ought to do so-and-so" cannot function in the same way. For
one cannot advise oneself.
5. Persuasion. So much has been said so well on this subject
by Stevenson that the only necessary comment is to point out that
the present list of ways in which "ought" can be used merely
brings out the error of offering an analysis of "ought" which
restricts it to one of its possible uses.
6. The expression of one's own principles. This is the most
characteristic first-person use of "ought." But I do not think
many people say "I ought to do so-and-so" very often, and when
they do, it is usually, I suspect, "I ought to do so-and-so, but . .. "
or "I don't know what I ought to do over so-and-so." In other
words "I ought" is used to express doubt and perplexity as well as
and indeed perhaps as much as to give voice to moral assurance.
This point will need to be developed later.
What morality is not 103

III
This incomplete catalogue of uses of "ought" in simple sentences
such as "X ought to do Y" has one main point: moral philosophy to
date has been insufficiently lexicographical. Even a partial
enumeration of the differences already noted between first-,
second-, and third-person uses of "ought" (of which that between
a particular first- and a particular third-person use noted in the
discussion of Sartre's example now turns out to be only a parti-
cular case) should make us conscious of the need for a far wider
range of patterns of analysis than any contemporary writer has so
far offered. But, instead of enlarging on this topic here, a possible
reply to the arguments that universalizability is not a necessary
attribute of moral valuation of the form "X ought to do Y", and
that such valuations do not necessarilyhave a prescriptive function,
must be considered. Against these contentions the following
counterargument might be brought.
The essence of moral judgments it might be said is their imper-
sonality. When we judge morally it is at the heart of the matter
that we "do not make exceptions in our own favor" (Kant), that
the moral agent must "depart from his private and particular
situation" (Hume). When the moral agent judges an action he
judges therefore what anyone should do in that or relevantly
similar situations. When he appraises the action of another he
thereby commits himself to saying what anyone and a fortiori
he himself ought to have done. When he decides how to act he
thereby commits himself to an appraisal of any similar action by
anyone else. Thus appraisal, advice, and practical decisions are
inexorably linked together. But of these three, practical decisions
have the primacy; to appraise someone else's action is to say how
he ought to have acted and to give advice is to tell someone else
how to act. Moral language, or at least "ought", is employed par
excellence in guiding action. In this form the argument brings
out the interconnection of the claim that moral judgments
are essentially universalizable and the claim that they are essen-
tially practical and prescriptive. Its force is further brought out
by noting a consequence which Hare has drawn from the con-
clusions of this argument. Hare argues that to say that a man holds
a moral principle is to say that he at least sometimes acts on it. A
man who claims to believe in keeping promises but habitually
breaks them does not in fact hold the principle that one ought to
keep promises, according to Hare. Those who have objected to this
104 Against the Self-Images of the Age
contention have usually pointed to the problem of clxpor:a!or:, have
argued that if Hare were right we would not have the case of the
man whose practice is radically inconsistent with his principles.1 But
this objection takes no cognizance of the way in which the notion
of consistency is built into this argument at the theoretical level.
Take the example of a man who appraises actions by one
standard and guides his own conduct by another. This differs
from the case of the man who is guilty of weakness of will, for such
a man's conduct is consistent with his principles, or rather with
that set of his principles which he uses to guide his conduct.
He merely has two sets of principles. This is sometimes con-
demned by invoking the maxim "Practice what you preach"
which is also, of course, used to condemn weakness of will. We
condemn such a man because and if we disapprove of incon-
sistency between appraisals and principles of conduct. But while
such inconsistency may be morally objectionable, it is not-and
the fact that it can be comprehended to such a degree as to be
found morally objectionable shows that it is not-unintelligible.
Yet in the argument outlined above this is what it must be. For if
the meaning of the appraisal "He ought to have done Y" is even
partly "I ought to have done Y in those circumstances" (inter-
preted as "That is the maxim that would have governed my
conduct" not "That is the maxim by which I would have appraised
my conduct") then the man who asserts that he appraises by one
set of principles but acts by another speaks unintelligibly. In other
words, the view that I am criticizing makes consistency between
appraisals and principles of conduct a logical requirement. That
principles should be so consistent is built into the meaning of
moral words such as "ought." But the demand for consistency
is in fact a moral not a logical requirement. We blame a man for
moral inconsistency perhaps, but we do not find what he says
meaningless. Appraisals and principles of conduct are logically
independent, although in a liberal morality they are required to be
morally interdependent. And now we can understand why univer-
salizability is given such a central place by those philosophers
whose analyses are directed upon the concepts of liberal morality.
For the requirement that everyone shall be judged by the same
standard (the moral counterpart of the political principle that
everyone is to count as one and nobody as more than one) in the
sense that everyone shall judge everyone else by the standard by
which he judges himself is so basic to liberal morality that it is
1 E.g., P. L. Gardiner, "On Assenting to a Moral Principle," Pro-
ceedings of the Aristotelian Society, (1954-55).
What morality is not 105

converted from a requirement of morality into a requirement of


logic. It is not part of the meaning of "morality" tout court that
moral valuations are universalizable, but liberals tend to use the
word "morality" in such a way that this is made part of its mean-
ing. It is worth noting a consequence of this transition from
morality to logic, of a kind not unfamiliar in moral argument. If
we so characterize moral judgments that we mean by a "moral
judgment" an impersonal one, we make it impossible to approve
or disapprove morally of impersonality in judging. For if part of
the meaning of "ought," for example, is such that to say "X
ought" is to say "X would not be making an exception in his own
favor if he ... " or "X would be departing from his private and
particular situation if he ... " then to say "X ought not to make an
exception in his own favor" is to utter an empty tautology. This is in
essence the same argument as that which Moore used against
naturalism, an argument which, as Professor Prior has shown, was
anticipated in many ways by Cudworth and Adam Smith. But as
Prior has also shown, Moore's argument is not conclusive.1 A
tough-minded naturalist can save his position "by admitting that
the assertion that, say, pleasure and nothing but pleasure is good,
is for him a mere truism; and that if Ethics be the attempt to
determine what is in fact good, then the statement that what is
pleasant is good is not, strictly speaking, an ethical statement, but
only a way of indicating just what study is to go under the name of
'Ethics'-the study of what is actually pleasant, without any
pretence of maintaining that the pleasure has any 'goodness'
beyond its pleasantness." 2 Similarly an upholder of the univer-
salizability view of morality could accept the consequence that it
is a mere truism to say "X ought not to make exceptions in his own
favor" and contend that all he meant to achieve by this truism was
the definition of the field of morality. But if he made this his
contention a further consequence would follow (and a similar
consequence would follow for Prior's tough-minded naturalist);
namely, that he would have to abandon any claim to be offering
us a neutral logical analysis of moral language. For plainly
ordinary moral agents do disapprove of making exceptions in one's
own favor in nontruistic fashion (just as they hold that pleasure is
good in similar fashion). To assert that universalizability is of the
essence of moral valuation is not to tell us what "morality" means
or how moral words are used. It is to prescribe a meaning for
1 Logic and the Basis of Ethics (London and New York: Oxford Univer-
sity Press, 1949), Ch. I and passim.
1 Op. cit., p. 9.
106 Against the Self-Images of the Age
"morality" and other moral words and implicitly it is to prescribe
a morality.
Finally, one more feature of the prescriptive theory of moral
valuation must be examined briefly. A maxim may be said to
prescribe or to guide conduct in one of two ways. Clearly we might
describe conduct that accorded with a maxim as guided by it and
speak of it as the conduct prescribed by the maxim, if we were
willing to adduce the maxim to justify the conduct. A man who
habitually kept his promises might when cha}Jengedon a particular
occasion as to why he had put himself out to meet a friend or to
pay a debt avow "One ought to keep one's promises." It would be
natural to describe the man's conduct as guided by the maxim.
But this is not to say that up to the point where justification was
demanded the maxim ever entered his thoughts, at least since the
time that he learned it as a child. And thus the maxim guides con-
duct in a sense quite different from that in which a maxim may be
said to guide conduct if we explicitly consult it when perplexed as
to what we ought to do. Most of the actions discussed in moral
philosophy textbooks-promise-keeping, truth-telling and the
like-are in practice carried out without any sort of conscious
reference to maxims. So that in the more explicit sense of "guide,"
where part of what we mean by "guide" is "to give guidance,"
"to tell us what to do," the relevant maxims do not guide us when
we keep promises or tell the truth. They do not guide us because
we do not need to be guided. We know what to do. We tell the
truth and keep promises most of the time because it does not occur
to us to do otherwise. When we are tempted not to do these things
from some motive of self-indulgence, it would still not be true to
say that if we resist the temptation, the maxim guided our conduct.
What guided our conduct was our decision to abide by the conduct
prescribed by the maxim. So that in this sense "X ought to do Y"
prescribes a certain line of conduct but it does not guide us or tell
us what to do. That this is so is even more obvious when we con-
sider those cases where we have already noted a common use of
"ought," cases of moral perplexity. When Huckleberry Finn
wrestles with the problem of whether to return Jim, Miss Watson's
slave, he is not guided by the maxims of his morality, for his whole
problem is whether to abide by those maxims or not. The maxims
tell him that property is sacred and that Jim is merely property.
Nor is Huck guided by a new set of maxims, perhaps the anti-
slavery maxim that "One ought to treat no human being as a slave."
For Huck retains the same general attitudes that he was brought
up with. (When someone inquires if anyone has been injured in a
What morality is not
steamboat accident, he says "No'm, killed a nigger.") In fact in
deciding not to inform on Jim he feels wicked and thinks of him-
self as wicked. He thinks of himself in fact as making an exception
in his own favor, of favoring his own friend at the expense of
morality. He finds his way morally by means of an only half-
articulate sympathy. But he does not find it by universalizable
maxims or indeed by maxims at all.
When you leave the ground of conventional morality, you leave
the guidance of maxims behind. Yet it is just here that one needs
guidance. Where men pass from one set of maxims to another, or
act morally without maxims, there is an area where the logician
and the linguistic analyst are necessarily helpless. For they are not
presented with the kind of material which they need for analysis.
Only the phenomenologist can help us here and the kind of
phenomenology we need is that supplied by the novelist. It is
because the moral philosophers of existentialism have been
primarily concerned with this kind of situation that they have so
often resorted to the novel. For all that can be done is to exhibit
the passage of the moral agent through perplexity. To offer us a
maxim on which or in accordance with which the moral agent
finally acted is to tell us what the resolution of perplexity was but
not how the perplexity was resolved. In this clear-cut sense then
the maxims of morality do not guide us, nor do they prescribe
conduct to us. And to describe the function of moral valuation
in general or of "ought" in particular as prescriptive is highly
misleading unless this is made clear. The catalogue of possible uses
of "ought" needs to be supplemented by a catalogue of those
moral purposes for which "ought" and words like it and sometimes
any words at all can be of little or no use.
One last point relating moral perplexity to the claims made for
moral judgment as prescriptive and universalizable: here, as
everywhere in moral philosophy, much depends on the choice of
examples. Where there is real moral perplexity it is often in a
highly complex situation, and sometimes a situation so complex
that the question "What ought I to do?" can only be translated
trivially into "What ought someone like me to do in this kind of
situation?" This is important because this translation is often not
trivial at all. When I am puzzled it is often useful to pick out the
morally relevant features of the situation and of my position in it
and, having isolated them from the particular situation, I am in a
better position to solve my problem. But, where a situation is too
complex, phrases like "someone like me" or "this kind of situa-
tion" become vacuous. For I am the only person sufficiently "like
108 Against the Self-Images of the Age
me" to be morally relevant and no situation could be sufficiently
like "this kind of situation" without being precisely this situation.
But what situation could be complex in this way? The situation of
Fran~oise in Simone de Beauvoir's L'lnvitee or that of Mathieu in
Sartre's Les Chemins de la Liberte are examples that spring to mind,
for part of their problem is to decide which features of their
situation are relevant; part of their problem is to discover precisely
what their problem is. And this brings out the point that it is
because Sartre and Simone de Beauvoir are concerned with
morality of this kind and in this way that they present and can
only present their insights in the form of novels rather than of
logical analyses.
13

Hume on "is" and "ought" 1

I
Sometimes in the history of philosophy the defense of a particular
philosophical position and the interpretation of a particular
philosopher become closely identified. This has notoriously
happened more than once in the case of Plato, and lately in
moral philosophy it seems to me to have happened in the case of
Hume. At the center of recent ethical discussion the question of
the relationship between factual assertions and moral judgments has
continually recurred, and the nature of that relationship has
usually been discussed in terms of an unequivocally sharp dis-
tinction between them. In the course of the posing of this question,
the last paragraph of Book III, Part i, Section 1, of Hume's
Treatise has been cited over and over again. This passage is either
quoted in full or at least referred to-and with approval-by
R. M. Hare, 2 A. N. Prior, 3 P. H. Nowell-Smith," and a number
of other writers. Not all contemporary writers, of course, treat
Hume in the same way; a footnote to Stuart Hampshire's paper,
"Some Fallacies in Moral Philosophy," 5 provides an important
exception to the general rule. But very often indeed Hume's
contribution to ethics is treated as if it depended largely on this
one passage, and this passage is accorded an interpretation which
has acquired almost the status of an orthodoxy. Hare has even
spoken of "Hume's Law." 6
1 Reprinted from The Philosophical Review, 1959.
8 The Language of Morals (London and New York: Oxford University
Press, 1952), pp. 29 and 44.
8 Logic and the Basis of Ethics (London and New York: Oxford Univer-

sity Press, 1949), pp. 32-33.


4 Ethics (London and Baltimore: Penguin Books, 1954), pp. 36-38.
6 Mind, LVIII (1949), p. 466.
8 Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (1954-55), p. 303.
109
IIO Against the Self-Images of the Age
What Hume says is:
In every system of morality which I have hitherto met with, I
have always remark' d, that the author proceeds for some time
in the ordinary way of reasoning, and establishes the being of a
God, or makes observations concerning human affairs; when of a
sudden I am surpriz'd to find, that instead of the usual copula-
tions of propositions, is, and is not, I meet with no proposition
that is not connected with an ought, or an ought not. This
change is imperceptible; but is, however, of the last consequence.
For as this ought or ought not, expresses some new relation or
affirmation, 'tis necessary that it should be observ'd and ex-
plain' d; and at the same time that a reason should be given,
for what seems altogether inconceivable, how this new relation
can be a deduction from others, which are entirely different
from it. But as authors do not commonly use this precaution,
I shall presume to recommend it to the readers; and am per-
suaded that this small attention wou' d subvert all the vulgar
systems of morality, and let us see, that the distinction of vice
and virtue is not founded merely on the relations of objects,
nor is perceiv' d by reason. 1
The standard interpretation of this passage takes Hume to be
asserting here that no set of nonmoral premises can entail a moral
conclusion. It is further concluded that Hume therefore is a
prime opponent of what Prior has called "the attempt to find a
'foundation' for morality that is not already moral." Hume be-
comes in this light an exponent of the autonomy of morality and
in this at least akin to Kant. In this essay I want to show that this
interpretation is inadequate and misleading. But I am not con-
cerned with this only as a matter of historical interpretation.
The thread of argument which I shall try to pursue will be as
follows. First, I shall argue that the immense respect accorded to
Hume thus interpreted is puzzling, since it is radically inconsistent
with the disapproval with which contemporary logicians are apt
to view certain of Hume's arguments about induction. Secondly,
I shall try to show that if the current interpretation of Hume's
views on "is" and "ought" is correct, then the first breach of
Hume's law was committed by Hume; that is, the development
of Hume's own moral theory does not square with what he is
taken to assert about "is" and "ought." Thirdly, I shall offer
evidence that the current interpretation of Hume is incorrect.
1 Selby-Bigge, p. 469.
Hume on "is" and "ought" III

Finally, I shall try to indicate what light the reinterpretation of


Hume can throw upon current controversies in moral philosophy.

II
To approach the matter obliquely, how can we pass from "is"
to "ought"? In Chapter iv of The Language of Morals, Hare
asserts that a practical conclusion and a fortiori a moral conclusion
is reached syllogistically, the minor premise stating "what we
should in fact be doing if we did one or other of the alternatives
open to us" and the major premise stating a principle of conduct.
This suggests an answer to our question. If you wish to pass
from a factual statement to a moral statement, treat the moral
statement as the conclusion to a syllogism and the factual state-
ment as a minor premise. Then to make the transition all that is
needed is to supply another moral statement as a major premise.
And in a footnote to Chapter iii of Ethics we find Nowell-Smith
doing just this. He quotes the following passage from Bishop
R. C. Mortimer: "The first foundation is the doctrine of God the
Creator. God made us and all the world. Because of that He has an
absolute claim on our obedience. We do not exist in our own right,
but only as His creatures, who ought therefore to do and be what
He desires." 1 On this Nowell-Smith comments: "This argument
requires the premise that a creature ought to obey his creator,
which is itself a moral judgment. So that Christian ethics is not
founded solely on the doctrine that God created us :" 2 That is,
he argues that the inference, "God created us, therefore we ought
to obey him," is defective unless and until it is supplied with a
major premise, "We ought to obey our creator."
I can only make sense of this position by supposing that under-
lying it there is an assumption that arguments must be either
deductive or defective. But this is the very assumption which
underlies Hume's skepticism about induction. And this skepticism
is commonly treated as resting upon, and certainly does rest
upon, a misconceived demand, a demand which P. F. Strawson
has called "the demand that induction shall be shown to be
really a kind of deduction." 3 This is certainly an accurate way of
characterizing Hume's transition from the premise that "there
1 Christian Ethics (London: Black, 1950), p. 7.
2 Op. cit., p. 51.
3 Introduction to Logical Theory (London: Methuen; New York:
Barnes & Noble, 1952), p. 250.
II2 Against the Self-Images of the Age
can be no demonstrative arguments to prove, that those instances
of which we have had no experience resemble those of which we
have had experience" to the conclusion that "it is impossible for
us to satisfy ourselves by our reason, why we should extend that
experience beyond those particular instances which have fallen
under our pbservation." 1 Part of Hume's own point is that to
render inductive arguments deductive is a useless procedure.
We can pass from "The kettle has been on the fire for ten minutes"
to "So it will be boiling by now" (Strawson's example) by way of
writing in some such major premise as "Whenever kettles have
been on the fire for ten minutes, they boil." But if our problem
is that of justifying induction, then this major premise itself
embodies an inductive assertion that stands in need of justification.
For the transition which constitutes the problem has been justified
in the passage from minor premise to conclusion only at the cost
of reappearing, as question-beggingly as ever, within the major
premise. To fall back on some yet more general assertion as a
premise from which "Whenever kettles have been on the fire for
ten minutes they boil" could be derived would merely remove the
problem one stage farther and would be to embark on a regress,
possibly infinite and certainly pointless.
If then it is pointless to present inductive arguments as deduc-
tive, what special reason is there in the case of moral arguments for
attempting to present them as deductive? If men arguing about
morality, as Bishop Mortimer is arguing, pass from "God made
us" to "We ought to obey God," why should we assume that the
transition must be an entailment? I suspect that our inclination
to do this may be that we fear the alternative. Hare suggests that
the alternative to his view is "that although, in the strict sense of the
word, I have indeed shown that moral judgments and imperatives
cannot be entailed by factual premises, yet there is some looser
relation than entailment which holds between them." I agree with
Hare in finding the doctrine of what he calls "loose" forms of
inference objectionable; although I cannot indeed find this
doctrine present in, for example, Professor S. E. Toulmin's The
Place of Reason in Ethics which Hare purports to be criticizing.
And certainly entailment relations must have a place in moral
argument, as they do in scientific argument. But since there are
important steps in scientific argument which are not entailments,
it might be thought that to insist that the relation between factual
statements and moral conclusions be deductive or nonexistent
1 Treatise, I, iii, 6; (Selby-Bigge, pp. 89 and 91).
Hume on "is" and "ought" 113
would be likely to hinder us in elucidating the character of moral
arguments.
How does this bear on the interpretation of Hume? It might
be held that, since Hume holds in some passages on induction
at least that arguments are deductive or defective, we could
reasonably expect him to maintain that since factual premises
cannot entail moral conclusions-as they certainly cannot-there
can be no connections between factual statements and moral
judgments (other perhaps than psychological connections). But
at this point all I am suggesting is that our contemporary dis-
approval of Hume on induction makes our contemporary approval
of what we take to be Hume on facts and norms seem odd. It is
only now that I want to ask whether-just as Hume's attitude to
induction is much more complex than appears in his more scep-
tical moments and is therefore liable to misinterpretation-his
remarks on "is" and "ought" are not only liable to receive but have
actually received a wrong interpretation.

III
The approach will still be oblique. What I want to suggest next
is that if Hume does affirm the impossibility of deriving an
"ought" from an "is" then he is the first to perform this particular
impossibility. But before I proceed to do this, one general remark
is worth making. It would be very odd if Hume did affirm the
logical irrelevance of facts to moral judgments, for the whole
difference in atmosphere-and it is very marked-between his
discussion of morality and those of, for example, Hare and
Nowell-Smith springs from his interest in the facts of morality.
His work is full of anthropological and sociological remarks,
remarks sometimes ascribed by commentators to the confusion
between logic and psychology with which Hume is so often
credited. Whether Hume is in general guilty of this confusion is
outside the scope of this essay to discuss. But so far as his moral
theory is concerned, the sociological comments have a necessary
place in the whole structure of argument.
Consider, for example, Hume's account of justice. To call an
act "just" or "unjust" is to say that it falls under a rule. A single
act of justice may well be contrary to either private or public
interest or both.

But however single acts of justice may be contrary, either to


114 Against the Self-Images of the Age
public or to private interest, 'tis certain, that the whole plan or
scheme is highly conducive, or indeed absolutely requisite both
to the support of society, and the well-being of every individual.
'Tis impossible to separate the good from the ill. Property must
be stable, and must be fix' d by general rules. Tho' in one in-
stance the public be a sufferer, this momentary ill is amply com-
pensated by the steady prosecution of the rule, and by the peace
and order, which it establishes in society. 1
Is Hume making a moral point or is he asserting a causal sociolo-
gical connection or is he making a logical point ? Is he saying that
it is logically appropriate to justify the rules of justice in terms of
interest or that to observe such rules does as a matter of fact
conduce to public interest or that such rules are in fact justified
because they conduce to public interest? All three. For Hume is
asserting both that the logically appropriate way of justifying the
rules of justice is an appeal to public interest and that in fact
public interest is served by them so that the rules are justified. And
that Hume is clearly both justifying the rules and affirming the
validity of this type of justification cannot be doubted in the light
of the passage which follows.
And even every individual person must find himself a gainer on
balancing the account; since, without justice, society must
immediately dissolve, and everyone must fall into that savage
and solitary condition, which is infinitely worse than the worst
situation that can possibly be suppos'd in society.
Moreover, this type of argument is not confined to the Treatise;
elsewhere also Hume makes it clear that he believes that factual
considerations can justify or fail to justify moral rules. Such
considerations are largely appealed to by Hume in his arguments
in the essay "Of Suicide" that suicide is morally permissible.
To return to the justification of justice: Hume clearly affirms
that the justification of the rules of justice lies in the fact that their
observance is to everyone's long-term interest; that we ought to
obey the rules because there is no one who does not gain more
than he loses by such obedience. But this is to derive an "ought"
from an "is." If Hare, Nowell-Smith, and Prior have interpreted
Hume correctly, Hume is contravening his own prohibition.
Someone might argue, however, that Hume only appears to con-
travene it. For, if we ignore the suggestion made earlier in this
essay that the attempt to present moral arguments as entailments
1 Ibid., III, ii, 2; Selby-Bigge, p. 497.
Hume on "is" and "ought"
may be misconceived, we may suppose that Hume's argument is
defective in the way that Bishop Mortimer's is and attempt to
repair it in the way Nowell-Smith repairs the other. Then the
transition from the minor premise "Obedience to this rule would
be to everyone's long-term interest," to the conclusion "We
ought to obey this rule" would be made by means of the major
premise "We ought to do whatever is to everyone's long-term
interest." But if this is the defense of Hume, if Hume needs
defense at this point, then he is indefensible. For the locution
offered as a candidate for a major premise, "We ought to do what
is to everyone's long-term interest," cannot function as such a
premise for Hume since in his terms it could not be a moral prin-
ciple at all but at best a kind of compressed definition. That is, the
notion of "ought" is for Hume only explicable in terms of the
notion of a consensus of interest. To say that we ought to do some-
thing is to affirm that there is a commonly accepted rule; and the
existence of such a rule presupposes a consensus of opinion as to
where our common interests lie. An obligation is constituted in
part by such a consensus, and the concept of "ought" is logically
dependent on the concept of a common interest and can only be
explained in terms of it. To say that we ought to do what is to the
common interest would therefore be either to utter an aphoristic
and misleading truism or else to use the term "ought" in a sense
quite other than that understood by Hume. Thus the locution
"We ought to do what is to everyone's long-term interest" could
not lay down a moral principle which might figure as a major
premise in the type of syllogism which Hare describes.
The view which Hume is propounding can perhaps be illumi-
nated by a comparison with the position of J. S. Mill. On the
interpretation of Mill's ethics for which Professor J. 0. Urmson
has convincingly argued,1 Mill did not commit the naturalistic
fallacy of deriving the principle that "We ought to pursue the
greatest happiness of the greatest number" from some statement
about what we ourselves or all men desire. He did not commit
this fallacy for he did not derive his principle at all. For Mill,
"We ought to pursue the greatest happiness of the greatest
number" is the supreme moral principle. The difference between
Mill's utilitarianism and Hume's lies in this: that if we take some
such statement as "We ought to do whatever is to the advantage
of most people," this for Mill would be a moral principle which it
would be morally wrong to deny, but which it would make sense
to deny. Whereas for Hume to deny this statement would be
1 Philosophical Quarterly, III (1953), 33.
II6 Against the Self-Images of the Age
senseless,for it would detach "ought" from the notion of a consensus
of interest and so evacuate it of meaning. Roughly speaking, for
Mill such a principle would be a contingent moral truth; for
Hume it would be a necessary truth underlying morality.
Moreover, Hume and Mill can be usefully contrasted in another
respect. Mill's basic principle is a moral affirmation,independent
of the facts: so long as some course of action will produce more
happiness for more people than alternative courses will, it provides
at least some sort of effective moral criterion. But at any rate, so
far as that part of his doctrine which refers to justice is concerned,
it is quite otherwise with Hume. We have moral rules because we
have common interests. Should someone succeed in showing us
that the facts are different from what we conceive them to be so
that we have no common interests, then our moral rules would
lose their justification. Indeed the initial move of Marx's moral
theory can perhaps be best understood as a denial of the facts
which Hume holds to constitute the justification for social morality,
Marx's denial that there are common interests shared by the whole
of society in respect of, for instance, the distribution of property
meets Hume on his own ground. (We may note in passing that
the change from Hume's characterization of morality in terms of
content, with its explicit reference to the facts about society, to
the attempt by later writers to characterize morality purely in
terms of the form of moral judgments is what Marxists would see
as the significant change in philosophical ethics. Since I would
agree with Marxists in thinking this change a change for the worse
-for reasons which I shall indicate later in the argument-I have
been tempted to retitle this essay "Against Bourgeois Formalism
in Ethics.")
One last point on the contrast between Hume and Mill: since
Mill's basic principle in ethics is a moral principle, but Hume's is a
definition of morality, they demand different types of defense.
How does Hume defend his view of the derivation of morality
from interest? By appeal to the facts. How do we in fact induce
someone to do what is just? How do we in fact justify just actions
on our own part? In observing what answers we have to give to
questions like these, Hume believes that his analysis is justified. 1

IV
What I have so far argued is that Hume himself derives "ought"
1 Op. cit., Selby-Bigge, p. 498.
Hume on "is" and "ought" 117
from "is" in his account of justice. Is he then inconsistent with
his own doctrine in that famous passage? Someone might try to
save Hume's consistency by pointing out that the derivation of
"ought" from "is" in the section on justice is not an entailment
and that all Hume is denying is that "is" statements can entail
"ought" statements, and that this is quite correct. But to say this
would be to misunderstand the passage. For I now want to argue
that in fact Hume's positive suggestions on moral theory are
actually an answer to a question posed in the "is" and "ought"
passage, and that that passage has nothing to do with the point
about entailment at all. The arguments here are twofold.
First, Hume does not actually say that one cannot pass from an
"is" to an "ought" but only that it "seems altogether incon-
ceivable" how this can be done. We have all been brought up
to believe in Hume's irony so thoroughly that it may occasionally
be necessary to remind ourselves that Hume need not necessarily
mean more or other than he says. Indeed the rhetorical and
slightly ironical tone of the passage renders it all the more am-
biguous. When Hume asks how what seems altogether incon-
ceivable may be brought about, he may be taken to be suggesting
either that it simply cannot be brought about or that it cannot
be brought about in the way in which "every system of morality
which I have hitherto met with" has brought it about. In any case
it would be odd if Hume thought that "observations concerning
human affairs" necessarily could not lead on to moral judgments
since such observations are constantly so used by Hume himself.
Secondly, the force of the passage as it is commonly taken
depends on what seems to be its manifest truth: "is" cannot entail
"ought." But the notion of entailment is read into the passage. The
word Hume uses is "deduction." We might well use this word as a
synonym for entailment, and even as early as Richard Price's
moral writings it is certainly so used. But is it used thus by Hume?
The first interesting feature of Hume's use of the word is its
extreme rarity in his writings. When he speaks of what we should
call "deductive arguments" he always uses the term "demon-
strative arguments." The word "deduction" and its cognates have
no entry in Selby-Bigge's indexes at all, so that its isolated occur-
rence in this passage at least stands in need of interpretation.
The entries under "deduction" and "deduce" in the Oxford
English Dic_tionarymake it quite clear that in ordinary eighteenth-
century use these were likely to be synonyms rather for "inference"
and "infer" than for "entailment" and "entail." Was this Hume's
usage? In the essay entitled "That Politics may be Reduced to a
n8 Against the Self-Images ofthe Age
Science," Hume writes, "So great is the force of laws, and of
particular forms of government, and so little dependence have
they on the humors and tempers of men, that consequences
almost as general and certain may sometimes be deduced from
them as any which the mathematical sciences afford us." 1 Clearly,
to read "be entailed by" for "deduced from" in this passage
would be very odd. The reference to mathematics might indeed
mislead us momentarily into supposing Hume to be speaking of
"entailment." But the very first example in which Hume draws a
deduction makes it clear how he is using the term. From the
example of the Roman republic which gave the whole legislative
power to the people without allowing a negative voice either to
the nobility or the consuls and so ended up in anarchy, Hume
concludes in general terms that "Such are the effects of democracy
without a representative." That is, Hume uses past political
instances to support political generalizations in an ordinary
inductive argument, and he uses the term "deduce" in speaking
of this type of argument. "Deduction" therefore must mean
"inference" and cannot mean "entailment."
Hume, then, in the celebrated passage does not mention en-
tailment. What he does is to ask how and if moral rules may be
inferred from factual statements, and in the rest of Book III of
the Treatise he provides an answer to his own question.

There are, of course, two distinct issues raised by this essay so


far. There is the historical question of what Hume is actually
asserting in the passage under discussion and there is the philo-
sophical question of whether what he does assert is true and
important. I do not want to entangle these two issues overmuch,
but it may at this point actually assist in elucidating what Hume
means to consider briefly the philosophical issues raised by the
difference between what he actually does say and what he is
customarily alleged to say. Hume is customarily alleged to be
making a purely formal point about "ought" and "is," and the
kind of approach to ethics which makes such formal analyses
central tends to lead to one disconcerting result. The connection
between morality and happiness is made to appear purely con-
tingent and accidental. "One ought to ... " is treated as a formula
1 Essay III in Hume, Theory of Politics, ed. by F. Watkins (London
and Camden, N.J.: Thomas Nelson, 1951), p. 136.
Hume on "is" and "ought" 119
where the blank space might be filled in by almost any verb which
would make grammatical sense. "One ought occasionally to kill
someone" or "One ought to say what is not true" are not examples
of moral precepts for more than the reason that they are at odds
with the precepts by which most of us have decided to abide.
Yet if ethics is a purely formal study, any example ought to serve.
If a philosopher feels that the connection between morality and
happiness is somehow a necessary one, he is likely to commit, or
at least be accused of, the naturalistic fallacy of defining moral
words in factual terms. It is obvious why philosophers should
seem to be faced with this alternative of committing the natural-
istic fallacy or else making the connection between morality and
happiness contingent and accidental. This alternative is rooted
in the belief that the connections between moral utterances and
factual statements must be entailments or nothing. And this
belief arises out of accepting formal calculi as models of argument
and then looking for entailment relations in nonformal discourse.
To assert that it is of the first importance for ethics to see that
the question of the connection between morality and happiness
is a crucial one is not, of course, to allow that Hume's treatment
of it is satisfactory. But at least Hume did see the need to make
the connection, whereas the "is" and "ought" passage has been
interpreted in such a way as to obscure this need.
Secondly, the reinterpretation of this passage of Hume allows us
to take up the whole question of practical reasoning in a more
fruitful way than the formalist tradition in ethics allows. If anyone
says that we cannot make valid inferences from an "is" to an
"ought," I should be disposed to offer him the following counter-
example: "If I stick a knife in Smith, they will send me to jail;
but I do not want to go to jail; so I ought not to (had better not)
stick a knife in him." The reply to this may be that there is no
doubt that this is a valid inference (I do not see how this could be
denied) but that it is a perfectly ordinary entailment relying upon
the suppressed major premise "If it is both the case that if I do x,
the outcome will bey, then if I don't want y to happen, I ought
not to do x." This will certainly make the argument in question an
entailment; but there seem to me three good reasons for not
treating the argument in this way. First, inductive arguments could
be rendered deductive in this way, but, as we have already noted,
only a superstitious devotee of entailment could possibly want to
present them as such. What additional reason could there be in the
case of moral arguments that is lacking in the case of inductive
arguments? Moreover, a reason akin to that which we have for
5
120 Against the Self-Images of the A.ge
not proceeding in this way with inductive arguments can be
adduced in this use also, namely that we may have made our argu-
ment into an entailment by adding a major premise; but we
have reproduced the argument in its nonentailment form as that
premise, and anything questionable in the original argument
remains just as questionable inside the major premise. That
premise itself is an argument and one that is not an entailment;
to make it an entailment will be to add a further premise which will
reproduce the same difficulty. So whether my inference stands or
falls, it does not stand or fall as an entailment with a suppressed
premise. But there is a third and even more important reason for
not treating the transition made in such an inference as an entail-
ment. To do so is to obscure the way in which the transition
within the argument is in fact made. For the transition from "is" to
"ought" is made in this inference by the notion of "wanting." And
this is no accident. Aristotle's examples of practical syllogisms
typically have a premise which includes some such terms as
"suits" or "pleases." We could give a long list of the concepts
which can form such bridge notions between "is" and "ought" :
wanting, needing, desiring, pleasure, happiness, health-and these
are only a few. I think there is a strong case for saying that moral
notions are unintelligible apart from concepts such as these. The
philosopher who has obscured the issue here is Kant, whose
classification of imperatives into categorical and hypothetical
removes at one blow any link between what is good and right
and what we need and desire. Here it is outside my scope to argue
against Kant; all I want to do is to prevent Hume from being
classified with him on this issue.
For we are now in a position to clarify what Hume is actually
saying in the "is" and "ought" passage. He is first urging us to take
note of the key point where we do pass from "is" to "ought" and
arguing that this is a difficult transition. In the next part of the
Treatise he shows us how it can be made; clearly in the passage
itself he is concerned to warn us against those who make this
transition in an illegitimate way. Against whom is Hume warning
us?
Hume himself identifies the position he is criticizing by saying
that attention to the point he is making "wou'd subvert all the
vulgar systems of morality." To what does he refer by using this
phrase? The ordinary eighteenth-century use of "vulgar" rules
out any reference to other philosophers and more particularly to
Wollaston. Hume must be referring to the commonly accepted
systems of morality. Nor is there any ground for supposing Hume
Hume on "is" and "ought" 121

to depart from ordinary eighteenth-century usage on this point.


Elsewhere in the Treatise1 there is a passage in which he uses inter-
changeably the expressions "the vulgar" and "the generality of
mankind." So it is against ordinary morality that Hume is
crusading. And for the eighteenth century, ordinary morality is
religious morality. Hume is in fact repudiating a religious founda-
tion for morality and putting in its place a foundation in human
needs, interests, desires, and happiness.
Can this interpretation be further supported? The only way of
supporting it would be to show that there were specific religious
moral views against which Hume had reason to write and which
contain arguments answering to the description he gives in the "is"
and "ought" passage. Now this can be shown. Hume was brought
up in a Presbyterian household and himself suffered a Presbyterian
upbringing. Boswell records Hume as follows: "I asked him if he
was not religious when he was young. He said he was, and he used
to read The Whole Duty of Man; that he made an abstract from the
Catalogue of vices at the end of it, and examined himself by this,
leaving out Murder and Theft and such vices as he had no chance of
committing, having no inclination to commit them." 2 The Whole
Duty of Man was probably written by Richard Allestree, and it was
at once a typical and a popular work of Protestant piety, and it
abounds in arguments of the type under discussion. Consider, for
example, the following: "whoever is in distress for any thing,
wherewith I can supply him, that distress of his makes it a duty on
me so to supply him and this in all kinds of events. Now the ground
of its being a duty is that God hath given Men abilities not only for
their own use, but for the advantage and benefit of others, and
therefore what is thus given for their use, becomes a debt to them
whenever their need requires it .... " 3 This is precisely an argument
which runs from "the being of a God" or "observations con-
cerning human affairs" into affirmations of duty. And it runs into
the difficulty which Hume discusses in the section preceding the
"is" and "ought" passage, that what is merely matter of fact
cannot provide us with a reason for acting-unless it be a matter of
those facts which Hume calls the passions; that is, of our needs,
desires, and the like. Interestingly enough, there are other passages
where Allestree provides his arguments with a backing which
1 I, iv, z.
2 Boswell, "An Account of My Last Interview with David Hume,

Esq.," reprinted in Hume, Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion, ed. by


N. K. Smith (second ed., Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1948).
3 Sunday XIII: Sec. 30.
122 Against the Self-Images of the Age
refers to just this kind of matter. "A second Motive to our care of
any thing is the USEFULNESS of it to us, or the great Mischief
we shall have by the loss of it. . .. 'Tis true we cannot lose our
Souls, in one sense, that is so lose them that they cease to Be; but
we may lose them in another .... In a word, we may lose them in
Hell .... " 1 That is, we pass from what God commands to what we
ought to do by means of the fear of Hell. That this can provide a
motive Hume denies in the essay "Of Suicide": obviously in fact,
though he does not say so very straightforwardly, because he
believes that there is no such place.
The interpretation of the "is" and "ought" passage which I am
offering can now be stated compendiously. Hume is not in this
passage asserting the autonomy of morals-for he did not believe
in it; and he is not making a point about entailment-for he does
not mention it. He is asserting that the question of how the factual
basis of morality is related to morality is a crucial logical issue,
reflection on which will enable one to realize how there are ways in
which this transition can be made and ways in which it cannot. One
has to go beyond the passage itself to see what these are; but if one
does so, it is plain that we can connect the facts of the situation with
what we ought to do only by means of one of those concepts which
Hume treats under the heading of the passions and which I have
indicated by examples such as wanting, needing, and the like.
Hume is not, as Prior seems to indicate, trying to say that morality
lacks a basis; he is trying to point out the nature of that basis.

VI
The argument of this essay is incomplete in three different ways.
First, it is of certain interest to relate Hume's argument to con-
temporary controversies. On this I will note only as a matter of
academic interest that there is at least one recent argument in
which Hume has been recruited on the wrong side. In the dis-
cussion on moral argument between Hare and Toulmin, 2 Hare has
invoked the name of Hume on the side of his contention that
factual statements can appear in moral arguments only as minor
premises under the aegis of major premises which are statements of
moral principle and against Toulmin's contention that moral
arguments are nondeductive. But if I have reread Hume on "is"
1 Preface.
1 The Language of Morals, p. 45; Philosophical Quaf'terly, I (1950-51),
p. 372; and Philosophy, XXXI (1956), p. 65.
Hume on "is" and "ought" 123

and "ought" correctly, then the difference between what Hume has
been thought to assert and what Hume really asserted is very much
the difference between Hare and Toulmin. And Hume is in fact as
decisively on Toulmin's side as he has been supposed to be on
Hare's.
Secondly, the proper elucidation of this passage would require
that its interpretation be linked to an interpretation of Hume's
moral philosophy as a whole. Here I will only say that such a thesis
of Hume's as that if all factual disagreement were resolved, no
moral disagreements would remain, falls into place in the general
structure of Hume's ethics if this interpretation of the "is" and
"ought" passage is accepted; but on the standard interpretation it
remains an odd and inexplicable belief of Hume's. But to pursue
this and a large variety of related topics would be to pass beyond
the scope of this essay.
Finally, however, I want to suggest that part of the importance
of the interpretation of Hume which I have offered in this essay
lies in the way that it enables us to place Hume's ethics in general
and the "is" and "ought" passage in particular in the far wider
context of the history of ethics. For I think that Hume stands at a
turning point in that history and that the accepted interpretation of
the "is" and "ought" passage has obscured his role. What I mean
by this I can indicate only in a highly schematic and speculative
way. Any attempt to write the history of ethics in a paragraph is
bound to have a I066 and All That quality about it. But even if the
paragraph that follows is a caricature it may assist in an under-
standing of that which it caricatures.
One way of seeing the history of ethics is this. The Greek moral
tradition asserted-no doubt with many reservations at times--an
essential connection between "good" and "good for," between
virtue and desire. One cannot, for Aristotle, do ethics without
doing moral psychology; one cannot understand what a virtue is
without understanding it as something a man could possess and as
something related to human happiness. Morality, to be intelligible,
must be understood as grounded in human nature. The Middle
Ages preserves this way of looking at ethics. Certainly there is a
new element of divine commandment to be reckoned with. But the
God who commands you also created you and His commandments
are such as it befits your nature to obey. So an Aristotelian moral
psychology and a Christian view of the moral law are synthesized
even if somewhat unsatisfactorily in Thomist ethics. But the
Protestant Reformation changes this. First, because human beings
are totally corrupt their nature cannot be a foundation for true
124 Against the Self-Images of the Age
morality. And next because men cannot judge God, we obey God's
commandments not because God is good but simply because He is
God. So the moral law is a collection of arbitrary fiats unconnected
with anything we may want or desire. Miss G. E. M. Anscombe has
recently suggested that the notion of a morality of law was
effectively dropped by the Reformers ;1 I should have thought that
there were good grounds for asserting that a morality of law-and-
nothing-else was introduced by them. Against the Protestants
Hume reasserted the founding of morality on human nature. The
attempt to make Hume a defender of the autonomy of ethics is
likely to conceal his difference from Kant, whose moral philosophy
is, from one point of view, the natural outcome of the Protestant
position. And the virtue of Hume's ethics, like that of Aristotle
and unlike that of Kant, is that it seeks to preserve morality as
something psychologically intelligible. For the tradition which
upholds the autonomy of ethics from Kant to Moore to Hare,
moral principles are somehow self-explicable; they are logically
independent of any assertions about human nature. Hume has been
too often presented recently as an adherent of this tradition.
Whether we see him as such or whether we see him as the last
representative of another and older tradition hinges largely on how
we take what he says about "is" and "ought."

1 "Modem Moral Philosophy," Philosophy, XXXIII (1958), pp. 1-19.


Imperatives, reasonsfor action,
and morals1

The thesis that moral utterances are somehow or other essentially


imperatival, or at least that they resemble imperatives in some
important way, is interesting not only because of the possibility
that it may throw light on the nature of moral utterances, but also
because the project of explaining moral concepts with the aid of a
grammatical category, that of the imperative, obviously could have
consequences for our understanding of the possible relationship
between the study of language and philosophy. It is partly because
this essay is skeptical in intention that I do not pay regard to the
very different versions of the thesis that have been advanced.
Instead, what I have done initially is to examine first the nature of
the imperative mood, to see whether any kind of utterance is
necessarily expressed by means of it, and then the relation between
imperatives and reasons for action, in order to understand the
possible role of imperatives in practical discourse. It is only
finally and briefly that some considerations about moral discourse
obtrude themselves.

I
Jespersen says that "The imperative is used in requests, which
according to circumstances may range from brusque commands to
humble entreaties, the tone generally serving as a key to the exact
meaning." 2 Hare says that "An indicative sentence is used for
1 Reprinted from The Journal of Philosophy, 1965.
z Otto Jespersen, Essentials of English Grammar (London: Allen &
Unwin; New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston, 1933), p. 294. In A
Modern English Grammar on Historical Principles (Heidelberg: C. Winter,
7 vols., 1909-49; London: Allen & Unwin, 1927-50) Jespersen adds
wishes and permissions to requests.
125
126 Against the Self-Images of the Age
telling someone that something is the case; an imperative is not- it
is used for telling someone to make something the case." 1 This
concurrence of grammarian and philosopher, however, still leaves
one in some doubt. Both seem to assert that the class of imperative
sentences may be segregated by identifying their use or function.
But when Fanny Farmer says, "Take six eggs," she certainly
neither commands nor entreats and does not even request; and
when in giving an order an officer says, "The following will report
at the Guard Room at 18.00 hours: Smith, Jones, Robinson," an
indicative is being used to tell someone to do something. These
elementary examples throw an important initial doubt on whether
Jespersen and Hare have characterized the relationship between
grammatical form and linguistic function correctly. In order to
strengthen this doubt I want to inquire how, in trying to under-
stand the unfamiliar language of an alien culture, we might dis-
cover whether that language contained imperative sentences and
how to identify them.
The first point to be noted-from the earlier examples-is that
imperative sentences may be used to serve more than one purpose.
They are of course commonly used to tell some specific person to do
something; but they are also commonly used to tell anyone how to
do something. That the same form should serve both purposes is
easily intelligible; for a set of instructions in a cookbook or a
carpentry manual, when recited by a mistress to her servant or by
a master carpenter to an apprentice on a specific occasion as
directions for the performance of a specific task, becomes a set of
orders or requests. It remains true that the existence of the single
grammatical form in virtue of which this is possible is a contingent
feature of English, Latin, and other languages. So the first pre-
caution to be taken in examining an unfamiliar language would be
to inquire whether the two functions of telling someone to do some-
thing and of telling how to do something are served by a single form.
A second preliminary point is that, if attention were concentrated
on telling to, we should have to be careful to distinguish between
imperative sentences and sentences not of imperative form which
are expressions of desires or wishes, translatable as "I want you to
do ... " or "Would that you would do .... " Both classes of
sentence would be employed in utterances in which the naming of
an action to some specified person or range of persons would often
be followed by the performance of the action by those to whom
utterance was addressed, and the action would be performed
1 R. M. Hare, The Language of Morals (London and New York:
Oxford University Press, 1952), p. 5.
Imperatives, reasonsfor action, and morals 127

precisely because of what had just been said. But the reason for the
performance of the action would be quite different in the one case
from the other. "I did it because you wanted me to" is quite dif-
ferent from "I did it because you told me to." None the less, those
imperatives which are used to express requests are often inter-
changeable with expressions of a want. "I would like a lemonade,
please" can be interchanged with "Get me a lemonade, please,"
and the latter can thus function as an expression of a want.
This again is easily intelligible, for "The primitive sign of
wanting is trying to get," 1 and the utterance of an imperative as
either command or request is one form of trying to get. But it
follows that the segregation of genuinely imperative sentences
from sentences of the form "I want ... " is all the more difficult.
Nonetheless, this segregation is essential, both for the reason
already given-that the imperative usually affords the person to
whom it is uttered a different kind of reason for action from that
afforded by the expression of a desire-and also because the
imperative, when it is used to tell someone to do something, need
not in any way express the particular desire or wish of the speaker.
The bored officeron parade may in fact hope that when he issues the
command "Present arms!" all the troops will fall off their horses.
It follows from all this that the isolation of an imperatival form
in a language would be the isolation of a form available for a given
and quite wide range of functions, but that these functions do not
have any obvious unity, although each is related intelligibly to at
least one of the others. From this it seems to follow both that we
can have no a priori reason for expecting the occurrence of such a
grammatical form in any other language and also that in our own
language we cannot use the imperatival form to pick out a homo-
geneous and well-defined class of utterances. It will be at the very
least highly misleading to begin with the concept of an imperative
and then to explain the nature of, for example, moral injunctions
or some other use of language by comparing them to imperatives.
For all that is clearly segregated by the concept of an imperative is
a certain grammatical form. To emphasize this point, it is perhaps
worth while to examine a little further the relations between
telling to, telling how, and telling that.
The introduction of telling how would itself be sufficient to
destroy any neat pairing off of imperatives with telling to and
indicatives with telling that. The instructions by means of which
someone is told how to bake a cake or make a cupboard may equally
1 G. E. M. Anscombe, Intention (Oxford: Basil Blackwell; Ithaca,

N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1957), p. 68.


128 Against the Self-Images of the Age
well be expressed by imperatives or by indicatives; and, if
expressed by the latter, the instructions will take the form of
statements which are true or false about causes and effects. In this
case telling how and telling that would coincide, just as, in the case
where instructions are given to a specific person both to make and
how to make something, telling to and telling how may coincide.
What makes a particular utterance a case of telling to but not of
telling how, or of telling to and of telling how, or of telling to but
not of telling that, and so on is, therefore, not only a matter of the
sense and reference of what is said, but also a matter of who is
talking to whom with what intention and in what manner. Some-
times the sense and reference of the words alone without know-
ledge of the context would enable us to identify correctly the
purpose being served by the words; sometimes the same words
with the same sense and reference will be used for quite different
purposes, and what the purposes are will be correctly identifiable
only by identifying the nature and context of the utterance. And
what holds of sense and reference in this argument is also true of
grammatical form.
Moreover, so far I have used the expression "telling someone to
do something" as though it required no further explanation. But I
may tell someone to do something by way of warning, advising,
threatening, or ordering; and I may ask someone to do something
by way of requesting, beseeching, or praying. In all of these cases
I may use an imperative. But could I use an imperative to tell or to
ask someone to do something which did not fall under any of these
headings or under any similar heading? Can I intelligibly say,
"I didn't warn, advise, threaten, or order him to do it; I just
told him to do it"? Certainly there are cases where we can be clear
about someone else that he is telling someone to do something, but
where we are in no position to provide any further description of
what he is doing in so telling. But could there be cases where no
further description of the relevant type was applicable? Consider
what has to be stripped away to leave us with such a case.
If I advise, warn, or threaten you, I back up my imperative
implicitly or explicitly by giving you reasons for action; and it is
the character of the reasons that makes of the imperative a piece of
advice rather than a warning or a warning rather than a threat.
The tone of voice or the choice of words may convey that what is
being uttered is a threat, but what makes a threat a threat is the
implicit or explicit answers offered to the questions "And what if I
do not?" and "And what if I do?" addressed to the utterer of the
imperative. If I order or command you, what makes the imperative
Imperatives, reasonsfor action, and morals 129

an order or command is-in the standard case-the position of the


person who utters the imperative in some hierarchy of rank relative
to the person to whom the imperative is addressed. This has to be
qualified in at least two ways. First of all, not every imperative
uttered by a superior to an inferior is thereby constituted an order.
The requests or threats made in a private capacity by superior to
inferior do not count as orders because not made in due form. What
due form is varies with the type of hierarchy; in most armies an
imperative can be made into an order just by saying "This is an
order." Secondly, we characterize certain imperatives as orders
because the person who issues them behaves as if he were a superior
addressing an inferior when in fact he is not. So we may speak of
one person as ordering another about when neither is a member
of any hierarchy.
When an order is issued, the person to whom it is issued is
thereby given a reason and perhaps reasons for action. What the
reasons are depends upon what he believes the consequences of
disobeying the order may be and also upon what he believes the
point of giving and obeying orders of the relevant kind is. Thus, in
the case of orders and commands as well as in the case of warnings,
pieces of advice, and threats, what gives the imperative its character
as an utterance is the kind of reason that might be given by the
speaker for uttering the imperative and the kind of reason that
might be given by the hearer for acting on it. Therefore, to strip
away all character from the utterance other than that which the
bare imperative has by itself, to try and leave us with a bare case of
telling to, would be to leave us with an imperative which is un-
backed, either implicitly or explicitly, by reasons offered by the
speaker and which affords to the hearer no reason at all for
acting upon it.
Now, clearly, there could be such a form of utterance. Two men
quite unacquainted with each other are sitting on the same park
bench. The one says, "Pick up that cigarette end." How is the
other to take this? Suppose that he asks, "Are you asking me,
threatening me, or what?" and receives the reply, "I am just telling
you to." What is he or are we to make of this? We can certainly
understand the meaning of what is said, but could we understand
the nature of his utterance?
Having suggested the difficulty of giving a clear answer to this
question, I am now in a position to suggest some initial conclusions.
I began with the thesis that imperatives and indicatives are con-
trasted forms, each of which is used to serve a specific function,
respectively, that of telling someone to do something and that of
130 Against the Self-Images of the Age
telling someone that something is the case. Against this thesis I
have argued, first, that the imperative as a grammatical form is
used for a variety of purposes and, secondly, that, although im-
peratives are used to tell people to perform actions, telling someone
to do something is characteristically not just issuing an imperative,
but issuing an imperative backed up by the giving of a certain kind
of reason for action. The character of the imperatival injunction
derives from the character of this backing. Since the expression
of the reasons for action will be in indicative form, the relation
between such indicative expressions and such imperative expres-
sions becomes crucial to the discussion. But the argument so far
has shown that to concentrate on grammatical form alone would in
any case be misleading.

II
Philosophical inquiries into the relation of imperatives to reasoning
have tended to concentrate on the deductive relationships into
which imperative sentences may enter and have been conducted
with an eye to the alleged large dichotomies of fact and value,
describing and prescribing, and so on. Less ambitiously, I want to
make some more elementary points about the relationship between
imperatival injunctions and the reasons for action from which they
derive their specific character as threats, warnings, and the like on
the one hand and orders and commands on the other. The first is
that someone to whom an injunction in the form of a warning or a
threat is addressed may take up three attitudes toward it: he may
accept it, either by doing as he is enjoined to do or by taking pre-
cautions against the consequences of not so doing; he may refuse
to believe the statement that asserts the possibility or probability
of such consequences and, the.refore, not act as he is enjoined to do;
or again, he may believe the statement and yet think that it does not
adequately warrant obedience to the injunction. It is upon the
first and third cases that I wish to concentrate attention in order to
ask what may be the difference between a warranted and an
unwarranted injunction. Suppose a man threatened with dire
consequences if he does not take one course of action is advised
by a friend to take another incompatible course of action. The
blackmailer says, "Forge the check," saying or implying "or else
I will ruin your reputation." The friend says, "Don't forge the
check. You will always regret it." (Note incidentally that in this
example the imperatives are being used in an attempt to persuade.
Imperatives need not so be used. A man who seeks to advise need
Imperatives, reasonsfor action, and morals 131

not be seeking to persuade. This is a matter of his intentions and


not of the grammatical form of his utterance.) If the man addressed
could be sure either that he would not regret his action or that the
blackmailer could not ruin him, he would have no reason to do
other than he was enjoined, in the former case by the blackmailer,
in the latter by the friend. And if he did do other than he was
enjoined, his action would be irrational in the sense that it ran
counter to the only reason he had for acting in one way rather than
another. "I have reasons only for doing X and not Y, but I am
going to do Y and not X" is the paradigmatic avowal of
irrationalism in this case. To this there is a counterpart in the
issuing of imperatives.
"You have reasons only for doing X and not Y, but do Y and
not X" breaks no linguistic canons and is not inconsistent in the
sense of containing or entailing any contradictions, but· it is
irrational in that it urges irrationalism in the sense defined above.
AB such its utterance would be self-defeating, for it not only
provides no reasons for acting on it, but even provides reasons for
not acting on it. Thus the connection between an imperative and
the reason that backs it up is intelligible in terms of the connection
between an action and the reason that backs it up, and not in
terms of any direct logical link between imperative sentence and the
sentence expressing the reason. Now to return to the situation
where an agent is considering rival and incompatible injunctions,
each backed up by a reason which he takes seriously. He will not
act irrationally in choosing to have regard to one consideration
rather than the other, provided of course that his wants, needs,
purposes, and projects are not frustrated rather than advanced by
the consideration to which he chooses to have regard; but his so
choosing will precisely be an index of his preferring one kind of
consideration before another.
In a parallel way the man who issues an imperative and backs
it up with a reason is committing himself not to the view that the
reason he cites entails the imperative, but to the view that the
reason he is giving outweighs any other reason so far on the scene.
"Do X, although there are stronger reasons for doing not X but
Y" is self-defeating. It follows that the force of an imperative,
deriving as it does entirely from the reason that backs up the
imperative, is never clear until we know what reasons might be
offered to the agent for disregarding the imperative. Since in
principle there may always be more relevant reasons to be
considered than have been considered so far, any injunction is liable
to be disregarded, not because the reasons which back it up are not
132 Against the Self-Images of the Age
good reasons or do not seem good reasons, but because there may
always be reasons which outweigh them for t~at particular agent.
We ought, therefore, to note that not only does it always make
sense to say that "There is such and such a good reason for doing
X and not Y, but do Y and not X" but that to say this does not
imply any doubt either about the truth of what is alleged as a good
reason for doing X and not Y or about its standing as a good
reason. All that it implies is a belief that there are or may be
countervailing reasons.
It is clear that this last discussion is irrelevant to the relation
between those imperatival injunctions which express orders or
commands and the reasons there may be for regarding or dis-
regarding them. For it is of the nature of an order or command that
it makes a claim upon those to whom it is addressed precisely as an
order or command, and that is to say, in a way that makes the
existence of good reasons for regarding or disregarding it irrelevant.
The force of a threat varies with the power that backs it up; the
force of a command varies with the authority of the man who utters
it. The man who issues the command may have good or bad or no
reasons for issuing it; the man who obeys it may have good or bad
or no reasons for obeying it. But the command has its character as a
command quite independently of these reasons. Hence, commands
in this respect are different from threats, warnings, and pieces of
advice. It is legitimate, indeed necessary, to say of commands that
they too are imperatival injunctions backed up by reasons for action;
but the key reason for acting in response to a command addressed
to me is simply that it is a command addressed to me (supposing
me to be subject to the authority of whoever issues it).
Putting commands on one side, therefore, I want to draw some
@bviousconclusions from what has been said about those impera-
tival injunctions which constitute pieces of advice. Among the
statements by which I may back up imperatival injunctions in such
a way as to give advice will be found more than one type of "ought"
statement. There are, for example, statements of the form "You
ought to go to bed with so high a temperature,'' which typically
back up imperatival injunctions but which may be outweighed as
reasons by such statements as "But that article has to be finished
by tomorrow." Someone who in the light of such a consideration
disregards the injunction "So go to bed" can be quite consistent
in admitting that he ought to go to bed. That is, in the case of this
type of "ought" statement, I may, without inconsistency or lack
of sincere belief in and assent to the statement which provides the
reason for the injunction, disregard the consequent injunction.
Imperatives,reasonsfor action, and morals 133
In parallel fashion, someone who issues an injunction may say,
without inconsistency or irrationality or lack of sincere belief in
the "ought" statement, "You ought to do X and not Y, but do Y
and not X." But what type of "ought" statement is in question?
The meaning of "ought" in "You ought to go to bed with so high
a temperature" can be understood by treating the statement as
equivalent to "If you do not go to bed, you will fare badly."
Consider now another type of "ought" statement, of which an
example is "You ought to pay your taxes before January 1st,"
where the point of "ought" is to refer us to some established and
recognized rule, in this case a legal statute, and where "you ought"
may be expanded into "you are obliged to," an expression that
would make nonsense in the previous type of case. Clearly, this
type of statement, too, may be offered as a reason backing up an
imperatival injunction. And, just as in all other such cases, it may
be outweighed by counterreasons, so that someone who sincerely
believes such a statement to be true may without inconsistency
disregard it in his actions, and someone who issues an imperatival
injunction may say without inconsistency or irrationality, "You
ought to pay your taxes before January 1st, but don't"-provided
only that he can or hopes to be able to cite some other reason that
will outweigh it.

III
We are now in a position to summarize some of the difficulties that
stand in the way of the protagonists of any theory purporting to
assimilate moral utterances to imperatives. First of all, since
it was made clear that the imperatival form does not of itself
segregate any well-defined class of utterances, it is clear that some
better defined class of utterances that can be expressed by means of
imperatives would have to be picked out to provide a comparison
with moral utterances. Secondly, it was also made clear that, where
the class of utterances that can be characterized as instances of
telling to rather than of telling that or of tellinghow are concerned,
we must ask for some further characterization beyond that of
telling to. Now what has been said about commands and orders
makes it highly implausible that moral utterances could be
illuminated by comparison with them; it is, therefore, all the more
plausible that, if moral utterances are a form of or resemble
imperatival injunctions, the class of imperatival injunctions to be
examined is that which includes threats, warnings, and pieces of
134 Against the Self-Imagesof the Age
advice. But the account of this class of injunctions which has
already been given would appear to make any assimilation of
moral utterances to imperatives highly implausible, since that
account at least suggeststhat in moral discourse perfectly ordinary
and genuine imperatives may play a part and that the distinguishing
moral components of moral utterance will be found in the statement
of the reasons backing up the imperatival injunction and not in the
imperative itself. For just this was found to be the case with the two
types of "ought" statements so far briefly examined.
To this it may be replied that neither of these "oughts" is the
moral "ought." The first might be ruled out on the ground that
it is the "ought" of hypothetical and prudential injunctions
rather than that of moral injunctions, the second on the grounds
that it is the "ought" of legally and socially established codes, not
the "ought" of individual moral principle. The moral "ought"
is, therefore, to be sought elsewhere, and, when it is found, it will
turn out that "You ought to do X and not Y, but do Y and not
X"-is not a possible piece of advice if the "ought" is the moral
"ought." For the moral "ought" will have an imperatival character,
such that anyone who assents to a moral injunction assents to the
corresponding imperative. Indeed it has been held that to assent
sincerely to a moral injunction entails not only assenting to the
corresponding imperative but also acting on it when occasion
requires; and yet clearly, in the view that I have outlined, I may
sincerely assent to and believe the statement that you ought to do
something but yet tell you by means of an imperatival injunction
to do something else, and I may even sincerely assent to and
believe the statement that I ought to do something but find reasons
for doing something else.
It remains, therefore, to hunt out the moral "ought" and see if it
has a different relation to the imperative mood. Now it might
appear that this was bound to be a hopeless quest. For the first
type of "ought" was in fact that characteristic of those teleological
moralities in which the criterion of what a man ought to do is what
will enable him to fare well or badly, and some concept of what it
is for a man to fare well or badly underpins the morality. So the
heirs of Aristotle. And the second type of "ought" is characteristic
of these moralities in which belief in a divine law is fundamental,
and moral rules have a status similar to the status of legal statutes.
So the heirs of the Stoics and the Torah. Since these "oughts"
are therefore at home in moralities of such importance, how could
some other "ought" claim the title of "the" moral "ought" ? But
to pursue this line of argument might be to miss the point.
Imperatives, reasonsfor action, and morals 135
Suppose a society in which there was a moral ethos of either the
Aristotelian or the Judaeo-Christian kind or perhaps some
synthesis of the two. The uses of "ought" in such a society would
be as I have outlined, and its relation to imperatival injunctions
would also be as I have outlined. But now suppose also that belief
in the divine law declines and that the formerly shared conception
of what human well-being consisted in is no longer shared.
None the less, people continue to use the word "ought," but in new
contexts. Sometimes, indeed, they ask skeptically whether they
ought to obey the divine law or whether one ought to preserve
former conceptions of human well-being. The "ought" of these
inquiries clearly cannot be either of the "oughts" previously
current. When "ought" is now used to reinforce an imperatival
injunction, it will add little but emotive force. When used by
itself: "You ought to do X and not Y," what force is there left
for it to have but an imperatival force?
In such a situation emotivist and prescriptivist theories, indeed
any theory of a kind which assimilated "ought" to imperatival
injunctions, would tend to flourish. Nor would these theories be
wholly incorrect; for they would be describing correctly the role
in language which a certain class of sentences had assumed when
cut off from the background of beliefs necessary for them to be
understood as they had been in the past. Moreover, such theories
might well, if they enjoyed a vogue, help to propagate the linguistic
usages of which they furnished an analysis. But we should expect,
with such a degree of innovation, considerable linguistic strain.
The framework of our language would, one would expect, be such
that the claim that the form, "You ought to do X and not Y, but
do Y and not X," does not make sense or indicates insincerity or
embodies a contradiction would be implausible in all sorts of ways.
None the less, the inclination to make this claim, in order to
explain correctly how "ought" was now often being used, would
be widespread.
Just this may well be our situation. It is at least a plausible
hypothesis. If it is correct, then simply to conclude that the case for
assimilating moral utterances to imperatives could not be made
out would be to ignore changes that social history has brought
about in the linguistic relationships. And this would reinforce the
suggestion, which has been apparent throughout this essay, that
to attempt to characterize a given class of utterances by means of
an appeal to grammatical form is one of the less happy ways of
making use of linguistic classifications in the course of philosophical
inquiry.
"Ought"

I
Not only the suggestion that different societies have had widely
different moral beliefs, but also the more radical suggestion that
the conceptual schemes embodied in their moralities have differed
widely, would appear as a banal truism to any anthropologist.
From Vico to Karl Marx, moral philosophers too appeared willing
to entertain this prosaic suggestion. But the notion of a single,
unvarying conceptual structure for morality dies hard; and from
the eighteenth century to this day, the English utilitarians and
idealists, logical empiricists and analytical philosophers, have all
been willing to discuss moral philosophy on the assumption that
there was something to be called "the moral consciousness" or,
in a later idiom, "the language of morals." The questions "Whose
moral consciousness?" or "Which language?" have rarely, if ever,
been raised. Both a cause and a consequence of this situation is the
extremely short method with examples adopted by many writers.
Since the question "But is this how anyone in particular really
talks, and if so who?" is not considered relevant, since we are
ostensibly concerned with what can or what cannot be said and not
with what is as a matter of fact said, a self-indulgent imaginative
liberty is sometimes allowed to reign. Moral philosophers are
often able to discern and to decry this liberty in their immediate
predecessors : it is not unfashionable to pillory the abstract and
misleading character of Ross's use of perplexity over a promise to
return a book which I have borrowed as a paradigmatic example
of a moral dilemma or of Moore's famous choice between two
uninhabited worlds. But if the abbreviation of their own examples
by moral philosophers is a liberty, the short shrift which they
administer to the examples of others is more a form of intellectual
violence. I want to try and avoid such extreme methods in a
consideration of two recent attempts to characterize what have
136
"Ought" 1 37

come to be called evaluative expressions. I say "what have come


to be called" evaluative expressions because how one identifies or
segregates the revelant class of expressions is partially, at least,
dependent upon which philosophical theory one holds. The two
theories with which I am concerned are versions of prescriptivism
and naturalism. My procedure will be as follows. First I shall set
out the rival contentions. Then I shall argue that it is not only a
matter of observed fact that neither party to the dispute is able to
produce conviction in the other-which it certainly is-so that the
argument appears interminable and unsettlable, but also that
each party seems able to accommodate, to its own satisfaction at
least, every objection that can be brought against it by the other.
Lastly I shall try to inquire how we can escape from this highly
unsatisfactory situation.

II
By prescriptivism I understand the following set of positions:
1. That the utterance of a moral judgment commits the utterer
to the utterance of a corresponding imperatival injunction in
such a way that "You ought to do this, but don't" or "I ought to
do this, but don't" (addressed to me) are inconsistent expressions.
In cases where "You ought to do this, but don't" is not to be
construed as inconsistent, then the "ought" is some secondary,
derivative, perhaps inverted-commas use of "ought," perhaps with
the meaning "People in general think you ought, but don't."
2. That no moral, indeed no prescriptive, use of "ought" can
appear in a categorical judgment that is the conclusion of a valid
argument, if the premises of that argument are all factual assertions.
For such an argument to be valid, at least one of the premises must
contain a prescriptive "ought." No "ought" from "is."
3. That the only limitations upon our choice of moral
principles are those of syntactical form and of consistency; we
cannot choose a moral principle which we should not be prepared
to apply equally to others and to ourselves in relevantly similar
circumstances; and that in moral justification our chain of
reasoning will bring us at last to a set of first principles ; these
cannot be supported further by reasons, but must be adhered to
by choice.
4. That to call something good may often be to apply con-
ventionally accepted criteria for the goodness of whatever it is that
is called good. But it is also-except in inverted-commas cases-to
138 Against the Self-Images of the Age
endorse the criteria, if they are conventional, and this endorsement
expresses the agent's own choice of criteria.
5. That in ordinary language there are many expressions in
which, either in certain contexts or always, a prescriptive or
evaluative and a descriptive component are welded together. The
use of these creates an illusion that the applicability of a particular
description entails the making of a particular evaluative judgment.
But, in fact, it is always possible to separate the two components ;
their relationship is purely contingent, external, and conventional.
By naturalism, I understand the followil).gset of positions :
I. That evaluative conclusions may be validly derived from
factual premises by virtue of the criteria for the correct application
of certain evaluative expressions; that such criteria are factual and
that the relevant class of expressions includes the virtue words.
From the fact that you acted in such and such a way it follows
that you are courageous, and in being courageous you behaved as
a man ought to behave.
2. That the chain of justifications for holding that someone
ought to do something will lead back, not to an ultimate assertion
of principle resting upon a choice which can have no further
justification, but to an assertion that behavior of the kind in
question is a realization of or is productive of some recognized
human good, such as health and pleasure.
3. That the class of such goods can be delimited; that the
criteria for something's being a good are independent of the agent's
choices, and that therefore what I ought to do does not depend
on my choices, although what I am going to do may so depend.
4. That the question of what I ought (in the fullest moral sense)
to do can be raised and settled by me without the question of what
I am going to do being so raised, let alone settled.
5. That factual or descriptive and evaluative or prescriptive
are not mutually exclusive predicates of judgments, and that
a judgment which is both factual and evaluative is not a judgment
which combines two separable components; to say that it is
evaluative is to speak about the point of making it, while to say
that it is factual is to speak about how its truth or falsity is to be
determined.
The strategies and counter-strategies used by each of these
parties against the other are parallel ones, and their ritual pro-
cedures might be set out as follows. First, a counter-example is
cited by one party; secondly, the other produces its own account of
the counter-example; thirdly, the first party points out that some
crucial distinction is omitted by this account; fourthly, the other
"Ought" 139
party either accepts this omission with all its consequences, or
gives its own quite different account of the distinction. Now an
unlimited willingness to accept the consequences of their own
point of view, which characterizes the leading protagonists on both
sides, leads to an increasing doubt on the part of an observer as to
what the subject matter of this controversy in fact is. I propose
to follow through the course of two of these ritual engagements to
illustrate this point, one starting-point being taken from each side
of the controversy. But it may help to exhibit the inaccessibility of
each party to the other's polemics, if I follow through two argu-
ments in which essentially the same issue is at stake. We can put
this issue as follows. The individual agent comes upon the moral
scene with a set of wants and interests. He finds the members of
his society speaking an evaluative language such that the normal
usage is expressive of certain established standards. Naturalist
and prescriptivist are both prepared to agree that every established
society will speak a moral and evaluative language which does
express the conventionally accepted standards. What they dis-
agree about is whether this is purely a contingent union of dis-
parate elements, so that the key terms could be purged of their
descriptive meaning and so of their particular adherence to a
particular way of life, or whether it is impossible at the most
fundamental level to perform this task. Can the individual agent
construct a set of moral standards that are genuinely his own, or
can he only appeal to something that may be called a standard,
if he agrees to speak the language that he finds? In another idiom,
do we make or do we discover our values?
The central naturalist charge against prescriptivism in this
area of the controversy is that the prescriptivist cannot in impor-
tant cases distinguish evaluative judgments from the expression of
private wants and preferences. The central prescriptivist charge
against naturalism is that the naturalist cannot give any account
of evaluative innovation, that yet the possibility of such innovation
is always present. The naturalist, to spell it out more fully,
asserts that we cannot but consider certain dispositions virtues.
To this the prescriptivist may reply that a situation in which the
meanings of the moral expressions in our language guarantee that
the standards by which we decide what is or is not a virtue are
unalterable is a I984 situation; and moral language does not have
to be like Newspeak nor is it commonly likeNewspeak. The natural-
ist reply in turn will be that any particular moral scheme may be
criticized or transcended by reference to universal human goods,
such as happiness. To this the prescriptivist will rejoin that if
Against the Self-Images of the Age
"happiness" is invoked in this way it is as a prescriptive and not
as a descriptive term, and that the agent has a choice of whether
to invoke happiness in this way or not. And so on.
Or to begin the argument from the other side, the prescriptivist
asserts that for our ultimate principles we can give no justificatory
reasons which are other than a specification of what it would be
to live by such principles. To this the naturalist replies that if this
is so, the distinction between the assertion of a moral principle
and the expression of a private want or preference is obliterated.
The prescriptivist will deny this on the grounds that the expres-
sion of a want or preference is not universalizable; even if the agent
does as a matter of contingent fact want both himself to do
such-and-such and everyone else in relevantly similar circum-
stances to do such-and-such, this is not the same as being logically
committed, by one's adherence to the view that one ought oneself
to do such-and-such, to the view that so ought everyone else in
relevantly similar circumstances. The naturalist may admit this
distinction but will insist that there is another distinction between
the assertion of a moral principle and the expression of a want or
preference which the prescriptivist has obliterated. The prescrip-
tivist will reply that this further distinction-that between reason-
supported assertions and non-reason-supported assertions perhaps
-can be made in every case except that of fundamental moral
principles. And so on. Ad na:useam.
I do not doubt that both prescriptivists and naturalists will be
extremely dissatisfied with this portrayal; and there has been no
lack of peacemakers attempting to patch up things between them.
But I would like to suggest that no conclusive argument is found
at any point in these exchanges; conclusive, that is, in terms other
than those of the party that propounds them. And this raises the
interesting question: what are they arguing about? What is the
subject matter of the dispute? Ostensibly the language of morals,
or moral concepts. But moral utterance and moral practice might
be thought to pre-exist philosophical theorizing about morality,
to provide an independent subject matter, so that philosophical
theories would be tested by comparing them with the facts of
moral utterance and practice. To which the reply may be twofold:
first, that some past philosophical theorizing has played at least
some part in shaping later moral concepts, so that moral utterance
is not entirely innocent of philosophical preconceptions; and
secondly that in order to pick out moral utterance and practice (as
contrasted with legal or scientific, say) or in order to pick out
evaluative utterance and practice (as contrasted with predictive,
"Ought" 141

say), one already has to have a criterion and such a criterion will
imply more or less of a theory. The first point one may concede at
once. The force of the second may be brought out by considering
a parallel case.
Clearly, in picking out the legal rules of a particular community
from its other rules we need to approach the social facts with a
criterion; and this criterion will be more or less theory-laden.
When legal theorists, for example, began to examine law in certain
primitive societies, some of them concluded from the fact that
certain factors hitherto considered essential factors of any legal
system whatsoever were absent from the institutional arrange-
ments of these societies that such societies possessed no law at all.
This conclusion, however, totally obscured the genuine con-
tinuity between the sanction-backed public rules of these societies
and the later legal codes which had sometimes grown out of them.
This fact provided grounds for concluding not that such primitive
societies had no legal system, but that the definition of law and
the corresponding theories of law needed to be amended to
accommodate the new facts. This example shows plainly that we
are not necessarily the prisoners of our criteria or theories, even
in cases where we cannot segregate the relevant class of facts
without some initial minimal theoretical commitment.
It follows that if the argument between prescriptivism and
naturalism is not to be an empty and pointless contest, which has
by the very virtuosity of the contestants in the performance of
the task of redescription been deprived of that independent
subject matter, the characterization of which was the sole point
of the whole enterprise, one prerequisite is that as far as possible
both theories are matched against the facts, so far as these can be
independently delineated, and the tendency to redescribe the
facts in accordance with the requirements of the rival theories
must be curbed as far as possible. It is not too difficult to see how
this might be done. It is by approaching the linguistic facts at
first as much as possible in the mode of the lexicographer rather
than of the philosopher; by next setting the linguistic facts in
their social contexts; and finally by asking whether this does not
enable us to discriminate, in relation to the theories of both pre-
scriptivism and naturalism, the types of moral situation of which
each doctrine is the natural and convincing explanation and
analysis from the types of moral situation which one or the other
doctrine has to distort. In so doing we shall treat these doctrines
as hypotheses, which invoke a stylized model of argument to
explain the actual patterns of moral speech and controversy.
Against the Self-Images of the Age
The examples which I shall take are all stages in the history of
the word "ought" and of words in other languages translatable
into English as "ought".

III
"Ought'' and "should" are sometimes used interchangeably in
contemporary English. But "should" often has a subjunctive role
which "ought" never has. ("If you should not hear from me .... ")
Both "ought" and "should" can be used to give advice on any
topic whatsoever; both are sometimes used in such a way that
moral injunctions or advice are distinguished from either prudence
or expediency. "You ought to do so-and-so; how you would fare
if you did is another matter." This use of "ought" or "should"
is the latest in time to emerge. What precedes it is the general
advice-giving "ought" of hypothetical imperatives, whether of
skill or of prudence. If we work backward in time we shall find
that "the moral 'ought' " which is used to express the claims of
Duty (in the singular and with a capital letter), although it appears
prominently in the utterances of Kant, the Duke of Wellington,
George Eliot, and Mr. Gladstone (who wrote of "The two great
ideas of the divine will, and of the Ought, or duty ... "), does not
seem to appear before the eighteenth century.
If we are to properly distinguish the categorical "ought" of
final moral appeal from the "ought" of hypothetically expressed
general advice-giving, it must be done by citing more than the
logical distinction between categorical and hypothetical judgments.
For the general advice-giving "ought" may of course be used in
categorical expressions of advice: not, "You ought if ... " but
"You ought, since .... " What distinguishes the "ought" of final
moral appeal is that it can be used without reason-giving of any
kind, that its force does not depend upon the force of some
attached condition, whether fulfilled or unfulfilled, neither "if"
nor "since," but "Why ought you?" ... "You just ought."
The general advice-giving "ought" is in use from the high
Middle Ages onward. It has to be distinguished from the use in
which "ought" is equated with, indeed is the same word as,
"owe." This "ought" is used both of owing money, and also of
owing services by virtue of occupational status or kinship. "A man
ought to be ... " can mean "A man is owed the position of
being .... " (So Wyntoun writes that "Robert the Brus, Erle of
Karagh, aucht to succeed to be kynrike.") The earliest recorded
"Ought" 143
use of "ought" ("ahte") in English translates "debebat" (in the
sense of "owe" in the Vulgate) by "ahte to zeldanne." We thus
discover three stages in the use of "ought": a first in which "ought"
and "owe" are indistinguishable; a second in which "ought" has
become an auxiliary verb, useable with an infinitive to give advice;
and a third in which the use of "ought" has become unconditional.
We can now place expressions from other languages commonly
translated into English as "ought" in terms of these three stages.
The Greek 8e:i:vand its cognates can be used to express both the
first and the second stage, both what it is incumbent upon a man
to do as a such-and-such, and what a man ought to do if he wants
such-and-such; but not the third stage. The Icelandic "skyldr"
(ancestor of "should") never seems to go beyond the first stage.
It would seem therefore most illuminating to look at the Icelandic
and Greek social contexts for these linguistic facts, in order to
observe first the use of an "ought" that never goes beyond the
first stage and then the use of an "ought" that never goes beyond
the second.

IV

In the society of the Norse sagas, the rules defining social roles and
the obligations attaching to them include the rules of vendetta.
Obligation is tied to kinship so closely that a near kinsman is a
"skyldr fraendi"; and "o-skyldr," which might be naturally, if
clumsily, translated as "not connected to one by way of obligation,"
means "unrelated." In the saga of Gisli the Soursop, Vestein is
killed either by Thorkell or by Thorkell's emissary, and Thorkell
is killed in turn by Vestein's sons. Bork then says, "More I should
take up Thorkell's case than anyone else since he was my brother-
in-law." It follows from the facts that Thorkell has been killed
and that Bork is Thorkell's close kinsman, that Bork ought to
avenge Thorkell's death. What gives the rules by virtue of which
Bork cannot avoid this conclusion their authority is simply the
recognition of these rules by the entire community. Which rules
the community so recognizes and what these rules prescribe are
questions of fact. If we pursue the chain of reasoning by which a
moral conclusion is justified in such a society, it will run as fol-
lows: You ought to kill so-and-so. Why? Because he killed so-and-
so, who is your nearest kinsman. Why because he killed my nearest
kinsman, ought I to kill him? The rules so prescribe. Here the
chain of justifications terminates. There is no way for me to ask
144 Against the Self-Images of the Age
why I ought to obey the rules. Notice that each "Why?" is
answered by a factual assertion.
It would be equally distorting to try to give either a prescrip-
tivist or a naturalistic account of this morality. Suppose, for
instance, that a prescriptivist were to argue that as a matter of
contingent fact agents in such a society may infer the conclusion
"I ought to do such-and-such" from the premise "The rules
prescribe such-and-such" and so appear to derive an "ought"
from an "is"; but that they can do so only by virtue of tacitly
presupposing some unstated major premise, such as: "We ought
always to do what the rules prescribe." The historical facts about
Icelandic society have to be interpreted in the light of our a
priori understanding of the forms of valid arguments. But the
prescriptivist who tries to argue in this way is forced to misrepre-
sent the conceptual scheme of Icelandic morality. For on his own
terms, if the transition from "The rules prescribe such-and-such"
to "So I ought to do such-and-such" is to be legitimated by the
addition of a major premise to the effect that "We ought always
to do what the rules prescribe," the "ought" in the conclusion
has to be the same "ought" as the "ought" in the major premise.
Now the "ought" in the conclusion has its force only by virtue
of its use involving an appeal to the established rules; but this
feature must be missing from the "ought" in the newly supplied
major premise, since this "ought" cannot derive any force from
the very rules which it is being used to enjoin us to obey. Thus the
prescriptivist's attempt to bridge what he sees as a logical gap
fails. What was mistaken in his attempt from the outset was his
belief that there is a gap here waiting to be bridged. Why there is
not we can best understand by considering how "skyldr" ties
together "ought" and "owe." For the saga use of "skyldr" is
parallel to our use of "owe."
Whether I owe you money or not, how much I owe you, and
when the debt falls due for payment are questions of fact settled
by discovering the truth about antecedent transactions between
us, whether you lent me money and so forth. The institutional
framework of rules governing monetary transactions in general
and borrowing and lending in particular is such that given that I
received $5 under certain conditions I now owe you $5 ; just so
in the saga, given that the sons of Vestein killed Thorkell under
certain conditions, Bork now owes Thorkell's kinsmen their
death. Bork can of course ask: "Given that I ought to kill the sons of
Vestein, shall I do it?" But when all the facts are settled, he can-
not still ask: "But ought I to do it?" For that he ought to do it is
"Ought" 145
just one of the facts, in the only sense and use of "ought" available
to him.
But now the prescriptivist might retort that Bork's "ought"
has just been compared to "owe," and that although it may be a
question of fact whether I owe you $5, the question of whether I
ought to pay what I owe can always be raised, and that this ques-
tion is not a question of fact. But the prescriptivist's ability and
our ability to raise this question depends upon the availability
of an "ought" that is just not present in the language spoken by
Bork. What is required for that "ought" to be available is that a
new use be introduced, and that is to say, in this case, a new
social practice. Now it is clearly logically possible that at any time
someone may innovate radically. But the fact that this is always
logically possible does not entail that such an ability to innovate
was in fact present. Such an ability requires a detachment from
the established institutional rules which has yet to come on the
scene, which itself has certain social preconditions.
If the prescriptivist cannot make the "ought" expressed by
the saga's "skyldr" conform to his pattern of analysis, it is of
course also true that the naturalist cannot hope to succeed in this
project either. For the termination of the chain of justifications
in the sagas is simply the assertion of the relevant rules ; there is
no citing of some human good which will be procured by whatever
action is in question. Indeed, the fact that obedience to the rules
will produce disaster for a man is sometimes noted in the sagas,
not merely by the narrator, but by the agent himself. And this
contributes not at all to showing that the agent therefore ought
not to do what the rules prescribe. In a precisely similar way,
you may show me that if I pay my debts the results will be dis-
astrous for me or my creditors or both; but this does not show in
any way that I do not after all owe them money. Thus, this first
use of "ought" gives aid and comfort neither to prescriptivist nor
to naturalist.
It is of course open to either or both to say that this is a special
type of case, which we only recognize as morality and which we
only characterize by translating its key expressions with words
like "ought," because it can be and was as a matter of history
later on transformed into the kind of moral scheme which fits the
prescriptivist or naturalist pattern. But this, although perhaps
true, does not affect any of the preceding arguments.
Against the Self-Images of the Age

Consider now a quite different type of example. In Xenophon's


Oeconomicus, Socrates reports a conversation with an ideal
Athenian gentleman, Ischomachus, who is in high repute as
xiycx86c;and who is deeply concerned about knowing & 8e~
xcx1o.oc;
1tomv (what he ought to do). It becomes clear that he is considered
an ideal character because he occupies himself in promoting his
health and strength, his military skills, and his private fortune.
He does what he ought because he pursues these ends, and these
ends stand in no further need of justification. This account of
Ischomachus reminds us of Hume: '' Ask a man why he usesexercise;
he will answer becausehe desires to keep his health. If you then
inquire, why he desireshealth, he will readily reply, becausesickness
is painful. If you push your inquiries further and desire a reason
why he hatespain, it is impossible he can ever give any. This is an
ultimate end and is never referred to any other object." 1 The chain
of justifications ends with the citation of a good beyond which it
would not be possible to go. What a man ought to do, then, is
what he ought to do if he is to achieve certain desired ends. The
"ought" of the morality of the Oeconomicusappears to be no other
than the ordinary general advice-giving "ought" of the second
stage in the development of "ought" in English. The naturalist
could have no objection to assenting to this; the prescriptivist,
however, would be forced to assert that we could only hold that we
ought (in any full and proper moral use of "ought") to do what will
as a matter of fact produce health and other such goods, if we also
believe that we ought to pursue health and other such goods. And
that whether I believe that or not, or whether Ischomachus
believes that or not, must depend upon the ultimate moral prin-
ciples chosen by myself or by lschomachus. To this the naturalist
may rightly reply that the answer to the question of whether
health, for example, is a good cannot depend upon the agent's
choice of principles or criteria or anything else. What makes
health a good is that it is a characteristic object of human desire;
and a society in which health was not so desired would scarcely
be a human society. In the face of this contention prescriptivists
are, I think, faced with a choice of alternative strategies. An
unreformed prescriptivist may make the barren and boring
rejoinder that even if health is so desired, I still have to decide
1 Jnquiry, I, 5.
"Ought" 147
whether I hold that I and others ought to fulfill this desire. This
rejoinder is barren and boring because in the vocabulary available
to Ischomachus the question of whether I ought to pursue health
could only be the question of whether health was among the goods;
no other "ought" is available. A reformed prescriptivist might
admit this, however, and recommence the argument by pointing
out that in the relatively narrow circles in which Ischomachus
moved a short and succinct list of human goods is taken for
granted. But what when a wider perspective opens, what when
competing sets of goods confront the agent with alternative and
incompatible goods? The reformed prescriptivist, that is, abandons
any part of his original view which entails the consequence upon
which so much scorn has been lavished, that anything at all could
be a good. He allows that only that which is a characteristic object
of desire can be a good, and perhaps leaves open the question of
the range of possible objects of desire. Instead he fastens attention
upon a situation where there are competing sets of goods. In such
a situation the agent who is able to assert both that "You ought to
do X if you want A" and "You ought to do Y if you want B," still
has to inquire, "But which goods ought I to pursue, A or B ?"
Ischomachus may argue from "is" to "ought" by saying that
"Health is a good for man, horse-riding will make me healthy, so
I ought to ride," but this apparent naturalistic pattern of argu-
ment is only possible for lschomachus because he accepts without
question one out of all the possible sets of competing goods.
To this it may be conceded that such an argument from "is"
to "ought" only has practical force or consequence for a man who
recognizes health as good for him; but this is to allow that, given
the accepted set of objects of desire in a society such as that of an
Athenian gentleman, moral discourse and argument will be
precisely as naturalism portrays them. Yet the reformed pre-
scriptivist has made it possible to begin to see more clearly what
a moral scheme amenable to prescriptivist analysis would be like.
Suppose a morally pluralist society in which there are two or
more competing moral schemes, with alternative and incompatible
goods; in such a society a man might ask-would sometimes be
unable to avoid asking-which of these moralities he ought to
live by. A naturalist might suggest to him that although he-cannot
avoid asking "Which of these moralities shall I live by?" since
he is not asking what a given established set of rules pre-
scribed with Bork, nor what will produce one or more out of a
given set of desirable ends with lschomachus, he cannot ask "What
ought I to do?" To this the prescriptivist might for the moment
Against the Self-Images of the Age
simply note that as a matter of fact "ought" is used in this way
on occasion; and a third example may clarify how, as a matter of
history, this came to be the case.

VI
Question XI: How we ought to aid our parents when in want ...
Question XVI: What reward is proposed by God for obedience
to parents ...
Question XX: With what punishments children are visited who
are neglectful of this commandment ... 1

Consider the "ought" of Christian theism. The theistic moral


scheme of Christianity perhaps provides both an example of a
moral scheme only amenable to a naturalistic analysis and also
a background which explains some of the characteristics of those
post-theistic moralities which are most obviously amenable to
prescriptivist analysis. We can distinguish three layers in the
theistic moral scheme. The first is the thesis that God created
men with a determinate human nature, so that only certain ends
are genuinely desired by them. At this level theism provides
metaphysical underpinning for some form of teleological morality
in which moral precepts are of the form already noticed in the
Greek example, "You ought to do so-and-so, if and since you want
such-and-such." Unlike most other such forms of morality it is
not necessary to the theistic moral scheme that there shall be a
lack of awareness of alternative moralities. What matters is simply
the belief that God alone is in a position to know what will satisfy
human nature--for He created it.
The second layer in theistic morality is suggested by Hobbes'
answer to the question why we dignify the prudential precepts
of reason with the name of moral "laws." The answer, says Hobbes,
is: because they are commandments of God. As divine command-
ments, the precepts of morality are given an additional sanction.
The first and best reason for obeying the precepts is that by so
doing you avoid the fate of those who gain the whole world but
lose their own souls; however, for those who do not see the point
of giving up the whole world, there is the sanction of eternal
rewards and eternal punishments.
To say that you ought to do so-and-so is therefore both to give
1 Catechism of Cone. Trent. Pt. 111.
"Ought" 149
advice and to refer to the force of a body of rules established in the
cosmos by God, with the status of law. Doing what the rules
prescribe and doing what will secure your happiness do in fact
coincide. But in the course of Christian history two other elements
entered. The first was an increasing conviction among theologians
(most radical perhaps among Protestants but also influential
among Catholics) that the corruption of human nature is such that
men cannot perceive what their human nature really wants or
needs at all. What God prescribt:s will in the end satisfy their
wants, but from a human point of view the Divine Will appears and
must appear as a series of incomprehensible and inscrutable fiats.
In consequence, from Occam onward the question "Why ought I
to do what God commands?" becomes more and more difficult to
answer. The Thomist answer, the Christian version of the Greek
answer-"Because this will satisfy your most fundamental desires
as a man"-is no longer available to those sensitive to their cul-
tural situation; for the gap between the observed facts about what
men want and the allegedly revealed propositions as to what God
prescribes for them is now only to be bridged by faith.
The question "Why ought I to do what God commands?" is
first raised in the modern literature by that great heroic innovator,
Milton's Satan. When Satan raises the question of "Why ought
we to obey God?" it is not merely a prudential inquiry; he is an
angel of principle. No reason can be found, he in effect argues, why
I should obey any law that I do not utter to myself. But the
"ought" of theism survived his and other doubts about God's
commandments. Theistic characteristics still cling-in a some-
what paradoxical way-to the "ought" that is historically used to
pose the moral doubts about theism. Now if an "ought," the use
of which presupposes theistic beliefs, is in fact used to question
the standpoint of theism, we would expect an internal incoherence
in this use of "ought" to be manifest. For it could at least be
plausibly maintained that such an "ought" would have to fulfill
the following apparently inconsistent requirements: ( 1) its theistic
character entails that it must involve an appeal to a law, that is,
to a set of established and identifiable rules; (2) its Occamist and
post-Reformation inheritance entails that this appeal to a law must
not be confused with any formulation of prudential recipes about
what will serve our happiness; (3) it must be available for use in
asking whether any authority whatsoever, including divine autho-
rity, ought to be obeyed; (4) it must be a law which we utter to
ourselves; (5) obedience to this law presupposes that although in
trying to obey it we are not using our happiness in any way as a
Against the Self-Images of the Age
goal determining what we ought to do, none the less to do what the
law prescribes must be crowned by happiness, if the whole enter-
prise is not to be pointless.
The incoherence of these requirements is clear: it centers
upon the notion of something which has the authority of a law and
yet which no one utters to us except ourselves. But clearly some
such incoherence in the use and sense of "ought" might well be
produced in the course of the secularization of a Christian morality,
especially of a Protestant morality. And this suggests that we should
give more credence than we are accustomed to do to Kant's claim
that his moral theory expresses articulately the presuppositions
latent in ordinary moral discourse. (Kant himself was ambivalent
about this view of his enterprise: compare the title of the first
part of the Grundlegung with the complaint that the assorted moral
principles of his age comprised a "mishmash" and that the
philosopher has to introduce a superior principle of unity.)
Neither Satan nor Kant can claim to be the first prescriptivist;
but in their joint insistence on autonomy they helped to father
the categorical "ought" of nineteenth-century invocations of
Duty, an "ought" which furnished an ultimate ending for the
chain of moral justifications and so is the immediate ancestor of
the "ought" of prescriptivism. This "ought" is criterionless:
the philosopher who throws most light on it is perhaps Sidgwick,
who has earned abuse from Miss Anscombe precisely because of
his fidelity in analysing a use of "ought" peculiar to his own age.
Sidgwick would dearly have liked to be able to reduce all categorical
imperatives to hypothetical imperatives; but he had to report in
the end an ineliminable categorical element in moral discourse,
that which drives him to the use of the word "intuition." It has
been insufficiently remarked that the use of "ought" statements to
make categorical moral judgments not supported by further
reasoning does not originate with philosophical theorizing, but is
a feature of ordinary non-philosophical moral discourse in the last
two hundred years; theories such as intuitionism, emotivism, and
prescriptivism can all be viewed as attempts to provide a philoso-
phical account of a use of language which is best explained as a
survival from a theistic age. The breakdown of the framework of
theistic belief has left behind a family of concepts which now, as it
were, have to find a status in isolation from the context in which
they originated. But if this were the whole story, the problem of
their status would not be so acute as it is.
"Ought"

VII
It is a banal commonplace that the breakdown of the theistic
framework produced a morally plural society; and in such a
society prescriptivism comes into its own. The reformed pre-
scriptivist whom I characterized earlier no longer insists that
anything can be a good or any principle a moral principle. In-
stead, he points out, when one has listed the recognized and
recognizable human goods one is faced with a large and indefinite
variety of competing alternatives. The admission that pain is an
evil is equally consistent with the morality of the sagas or the
Spartans, in which its point is to provide occasions for manifest-
ing fortitude and courage; the morality of the Christians in which
it is to be alleviated wherever possible; and the morality of de
Sade in which the infliction of pain is an expression of the agent's
liberty and autonomy. How does one choose between these
moralities? There is no way of taking the admitted list of human
goods and finding criteria for judging between such moralities;
for in the competition between moralities goods are matched
against goods, and there is no superior criterion of judgment.
In the modern world the sphere of morality is essentially the sphere
of tragedy as Hegel defined it. Consider, to take a quite different
type of example, some features of Kierkegaard's argument in
Either/Or.
In Either /Or Kierkegaard exhibited the necessity for a criterion-
less choice between two ways of life : the aesthetic, in which the
good of pleasure is allowed an overriding character, and the ethical,
in which the goods of a dutiful life are allowed an overriding
character. Suppose I try to find some criterion which will enable
me to decide between these two on impersonal grounds, some
criterion which will liberate me from the subjectivity of criterion-
less choice. If I ask: "Which life will satisfy my wants?" then I have
already in choosing this criterion chosen the aesthetic. If I ask:
"Which life ought I to pursue?" then the "ought" is the "ought"
of Duty, and I have already chosen the ethical life. Considerations
such as these led Kierkegaard to conclude that one can do no more
than offer rival descriptions of the two lives; the reader is then left
to choose, and the moral to be drawn is that no description can
possibly determine his choice.
His choice may of course be expressed simply by "~ shall choose
such-and-such"; but there is a modern use of "ought" according
6
Against the Self-Images of the Age
to which he might express a choice that he recommends to every-
one and which expresses his commitment to recommend it to
everyone by saying, "So I ought to choose so-and-so." This
"ought" is the "ought" of the prescriptivist analysis. In other
words, the argument that prescriptivism is always a correct
account of moral language because it is found to be a correct
account of these peculiarly modern situations of radical choice is
one that I have rejected throughout this essay; but this does not
entail that it is an incorrect account of these choice situations. For
in such situations ultimate moral principles do have to be chosen;
no description of the alternatives confronting us logically entails
any conclusion about what we ought to do or to choose, and
perhaps it is even the case that the only available criterion of
whether we have adopted one particular alternative is its embodi-
ment in our actions in the form of obedience to self-addressed im-
peratival injunctions. All that has been abandoned to naturalism
as regards this type of example is the claim that anything what-
soever could be a good.

VIII

It is perhaps possible that there should exist a society in which all


"oughts" were of the first kind which I examined, that exemplified
in the saga's "skyldr"; but almost certainly there never was. It is
clear that even if there was not in the language of the sagas a
single-word equivalent to the "ought" in "If you want this, you
ought to do that," what is expressed by this sentence is also
expressible by "If you want this, do that." And it is difficult to
envisage a form of society without a use for that type of sentence;
difficult, although perhaps not impossible. It is not only clear that
there could be, but clear that there have been societies with
"oughts" only of the first and second, or only of the second kind.
England in the Middle Ages appears to be one. The specific
notion of a duty or duties or of an obligation or obligations may in
such a society give goods for uttering injunctions which makes use
of this "ought," but it is not specifically tied to notions of this
kind. Such societies have moralities of which naturalism provides
an adequate account. It is only perhaps in modern society that
we have "oughts" of all three stages marked by the dictionary.
The fact that this is so, and the further fact that this is not ade-
quately recognized by moral philosophers, is responsible for some
recent controversies in which general theses derived from prescrip-
"Ought" 1 53

tivism or naturalism have been tested against examples, without


inquiry ever being made as to the character of the examples, that
is, as to which stage in the history of "ought" they exemplify.
Consider in this respect John Searle's "How to derive 'Ought'
from 'Is' "and Max Black's "The Gap between 'Is' and 'Should' ." 1
Searle constructs an argument in which we pass through a series
of statements each of which he contends to be factual by means of
a series of logical transitions each of which he contends to be an
entailment from "Jones uttered the words: I hereby promise to ... "
to "Jones placed himself under an obligation to ... " to "Jones
ought to .... " Searle's prescriptivist critics have argued either
that there is a suppressed premise, embodied in the institutional
rules governing promising, to the effect that everyone ought to
keep their promises, or else that one of his inferences is illegitimate.
But what they (and perhaps Searle himself) have not understood is
that promising is an institution in our society comparable to
vendetta in Icelandic society, in which the established rules are
such that if you make a promise to someone, you ought to do
whatever it is, in this sense, that you owe it to him. That, "If you
have made a promise, you ought to keep it," is guaranteed only
when the use of "ought" is of this kind, an "ought" of the first
type. I can always ask, using either the advice-giving sense of
"ought" or the prescriptive "ought", whether I ought to keep this
particular promise or any promise at all, and I can do this in cases
where there is no question of conflict of obligations. Searle's
critics would be quite right in contending that from the fact that I
made a promise it does not follow-if "ought" is used in either
of these two latter ways-that I ought to keep it. Searle would be
quite right in contending that if "ought" is used as it was when it
was the same word as "owe," then it does follow from the fact
that I made a promise that I ought to keep it and no additional
major premise is necessary. But the argument of Searle's critics
never in fact meets Searle's argument, because the presence of
these two radically different "oughts" in the language is not allowed
for by either party.
Equally, Max Black's naturalism leaves prescriptivism funda-
mentally untouched and for a similar reason. Black argues that an
argument from the premise that a given course of action wciuld
cause pain, while some alternative course of action would be identi-
cal in every way but that it would not cause pain, to the conclusion
that therefore we ought to pursue the latter rather than the former
course is a valid deductive argument in which the transition from
1 Both in The Philosophical Review, 1964.
1 54 Against the Self-Images of the Age
"is" to "should" or "ought" is made legitimately. An unreformed
prescriptivist would presumably and unfortunately invoke the
suppressed major premise gambit (Hare's paper on Pain and Evil,
suggests that he might follow that course); but a reformed pre-
scriptivist would simply point out that although it is undeniable
that pain is an evil and that the gratuitous infliction of pain is an
evil, and that it is this which warrants Black's argument, it is only
in the rarest of contexts that gratuitous pain is and could be a
matter for moral judgment. We teach children to infer from "That
would be gratuitous infliction of pain" to "So I ought not to do it."
But the moment the infliction of pain is a possibility in a context
where, say, Christian, Nietzschean, and Sadean moralists were at
odds, questions of fundamental choice would arise which could in
no way be settled by an appeal to the legitimacy of that inference.
It is not surprising that some would-be naturalists have tried to
assimilate all evils to pain, all goods to pleasure, and the logical
character of the concept of pleasure to that of pain. For it is just in
such narrow contexts of child morality that the naturalist account
is adequate. It only fails when we pass outside. Hence I conclude
that just as Searle and his critics did not distinguish the first type
of use of "ought" from the second and third, so Black does not
distinguish the second, or naturalist use, from the third, or
prescriptivist. The nursery, like classical Greece or medieval
Europe, is one of the natural homes of naturalism. But societies
change and people grow up.

IX

Two main theses have now emerged from my argument: the first
that naturalism and prescriptivism are most plausibly understood
not as rival accounts of the whole field of moral or even of evalua-
tive discourse, but as accounts of different types of moral and
evaluative discourse. These types of discourse I have tried to
discriminate in terms of three uses of "ought" which recur suc-
cessively in the history of that word in the English language and
English-speaking society. But I have also maintained that all three
uses of "ought" occur in current English and I want now to con-
sider this fact. Just as prescriptivism, in order that it could be
understood as a correct account of those fundamental moral
choices on which existentialist moral philosophers have laid so
much emphasis, had to be amended, so naturalism, in order that
it can be understood as a correct account of those situations in
"Ought" 1 55

which, because of the existing social framework and vocabulary,


fundamental choice cannot arise, must also be amended. For
naturalists advance against prescriptivists, as I have already
remarked, the argument that it must always be possible to dis-
criminate between moral judgments on the one hand and expres-
sions of personal preference on the other. And they complain that
upon a prescriptivist analysis, as equally upon an emotivist, this
distinction disappears. What is not clear, however, is the nature
and grounds of the contention that it must always be possible to
discriminate in principle-not necessarily always in practice, of
course, in particular cases-between moral judgments and ex-
pressions of personal preference. For the a priori claim that this
distinction must always be applicable fails with precisely those
uses of "ought" which are correctly characterized by prescripti-
vists. That is, it is not the prescriptivist who in his theoretical
account obliterates a distinction implied in all the ordinary uses
of "ought" by moral agents and moral critics. It is rather that in
certain types of situations-those of fundamental choice-the use
of "ought" by such agents and critics is such that this distinction
can no longer be applied. Is such a use of "ought" necessarily
unintelligible or incoherent? I have suggested that it is partially
intelligible as a survival, first of all from those immediately post-
theistic humanists for whom Duty was still the ghost of the divine
commandments sitting crowned upon the grave thereof, and
secondly from Christian theism. But it is also intelligible in the
sense that its use is rule-governed and embodied in contemporary
social practice. A reformed naturalism therefore would have to
allow, if it aspired to be a description of the language we have,
that although the distinction between moral judgment and personal
preference holds in all those contexts of which naturalism is the
correct account, it does not hold for every intelligible use of
"ought." But the naturalist point, once it is understood not to
impugn the correctness of the prescriptivist account of fundamen-
tal choice, still has force in another direction.
The use of "ought" in moral injunctions-just because it has
the past history it has-always suggests an appeal to some criterion,
whether a socially established rule or a precept about how some
desired good is to be obtained. When in modern society an "ought"
finally emerges such that the injunctions which it is used to formu-
late have no greater authority than is conferred upon them by the
speaker's own choices, even if there are no conceptual grounds for
accusing the speaker of unintelligibility, there are certainly grounds
for accusing him of trading upon the prestige which belongs to
Against the Self-Images of the Age
other present, and even more to past, uses of "ought" ; so that his
"ought" has the semblance of an appeal to an impersonal criterion,
while it is in fact only the mask for his personal preferences. In a
morally pluralist society such as ours moreover it is at points where
much is at stake-in certain fundamental choices-that this
modern use of "ought" is most likely to involve deception and
self-deception. Understanding this use of "ought" in the light of
prescriptivism therefore might comprehensibly lead to the con-
clusion that in the cases where prescriptivism is correct, no honest
man would want to continue to use "ought." For the good of
truthfulness is not one which we are free either to regard or to
discard. But to pursue the implications of this conclusion would
take me beyond moral philosophy.
Some more about "ought"

In his paper "Does Moral Philosophy Rest On A Mistake?"


published in 1912, H. A. Prichard either explicitly makes or clearly
assumes four main points about the word "ought" and its uses.
The first point-and the order in which I put them is not the same
as Prichard's-is that there is a proper linguistic form for judg-
ments expressing the idea that he takes to be conveyed by the word
"ought." "The word 'ought,'" he asserts, "refers to actions and
to actions alone. The proper language is never 'So and so ought to
be,' but 'I ought to do so and so.' Even if we are sometimes moved
to say that the world or something in it is not what it ought to be,
what we really mean is that God or some human being has not
made something what he ought to have made it" (p. 4 ).
Secondly, Prichard declares that "An 'ought,' if it is to be
derived at all, can only be derived from another 'ought' " (p. 4).
The example given is that from the premise that certain medicines
will heal our disease we cannot derive the conclusion that we ought
to take those medicines. Thirdly, Prichard makes it clear that he
regards the word "obligation" as the abstract noun corresponding
to the verb "ought." He passes from the one to the other in a way
which makes it clear that he believes that "I ought to do so and
so" means the same as "I have an obligation to do so and so.''
Moreover it may be true of me-as indeed it seems it must on
occasion be true of me, if this equivalence of meaning is to be
preserved-that I have an obligation, without my having an obli-
gation to any particular person.
Fourthly, in connection with both "ought" and "obligation"
Prichard makes it clear that what it is the case that I ought to do is
both logically and causally independent of what it is the case that I
want or of what will make me happy or of what will be good for me
or for others or for both or of what will be productive of good and
so be an exercise of a virtue. Prichard does not therefore conclude
that morality has two parts, one concerned with what he calls
157
Against the Self-Images of the Age
obligation and one concerned with what he calls the virtues.
He concludes instead that the pursuit of the virtues has no part
in morality and reserves the word "morality" strictly for the
realm of obligation.
A first response to these four points, made or presumed as they
are so brusquely-and it is indeed Prichard's central point in
writing his paper that on these matters philosophical argument is
redundant and out of place-might well be that Prichard has
simply himself made a series of mistakes. First of all, it is just not
true that whenever we use the word "ought" in a categorical
assertion we mean or even imply that someone ought to do or
ought to have done something. "The weather ought to be better
tomorrow," or "The solution ought to be a prime number," com-
mit me to judgment on neither men nor God if it goes on raining
or the solution to my algebraic problem is "14." Secondly, it is
equally false that we cannot derive categorical conclusions con-
taining the word "ought" from premises that do not contain it.
There are valid arguments of many different kinds which exem-
plify this point. From the premises that "If you stick a knife in
him, you will go to prison" and "You do not want to go to prison,"
it certainly follows that "You ought not to stick a knife in him."
From the premise that "He is a sea captain," it certainly follows
that "He ought to do whatever a sea captain ought to do."
Thirdly, although the word "obligation" has come to be used as
the abstract noun corresponding to the verb "ought," this is not its
only or its primary use. The concept of an obligation is originally
a narrower and more specialized concept; an obligation derives
from a promise or a contract. Thus an obligation is always an
obligation to some particular person or persons. This narrower
concept of obligation may be contrasted with a corresponding
concept of duty. A duty arises from a status or an office, not from
a promise or a contract. As a father I have a duty to my children;
as an employer I have obligations toward my servants. But
Prichard in his other writings uses the notion of duty precisely as
he uses that of obligation. In his paper on "Moral Obligation,"
written a quarter of a century after "Is Moral Philosophy Based
Upon A Mistake?" he not only asserts that "we, in our ordinary
unreflective state of mind, regard statements of the form 'X ought
to do so and so,' 'X has the duty of doing so and so,' and 'X is
morally bound to do so and so' as equivalent in meaning," but
also that he regards "X has a moral obligation to do so and so" as
equivalent in meaning, too. He does, however, make one crucial
point that is missing in the earlier paper. For he distinguishes
Some more about "ought" 1 59

between a moral sense of "ought" and a non-moral sense, and in so


doing provides himself with an answer to the counter-examples
which I produced to his first two points. It is quite clear that
Prichard would in fact have said that the "ought" in these ex-
amples was used in a non-moral sense. But now let us look at the
position to which he is committed in consequence. For Prichard
"X has an obligation to do so and so" and "X has a duty to do so
and so" cannot and do not represent two different types of
ground or reason which may be offered to support the conclusion
that "X ought to do so and so"; nor could it be the case in Pri-
chard's view that one man might argue for the conclusion that
"X ought to do so and so" on the ground that it would make X
happy and another man might argue for the conclusion that "X
ought to do so and so" on the ground that X has an obligation to do
so and so and these two men might be offering different reasons in
support of the same conclusion. They would in fact be coming to
two different conclusions. That this would be Prichard's view is
made clear in his discussion of Kant on categorical and hypotheti-
cal imperatives where Prichard insists that "the distinction ... is
really not . . . one between two statements containing the word
'ought' made on different grounds, but one between two state-
ments in which 'ought' has a completely different meaning" (p. 91 ).
ThusPrichard's original insistence that morality is limited to the
realm of obligation has now become the claim that there is a
distinctive sense which "ought" has when it is used to express the
distinctive demand that morality makes of us. The characterization
of this demand in Prichard has a certain circular quality. Prichard
speaks of a feeling of imperativeness, but he never characterizes
this imperativeness except as that which obligation makes us feel.
What morality is not is clear: everything done from desire, or for
an end, is not done from a sense of obligation and is not matter
for morality. The contrast is therefore between a set of obligations
which constitute morality and the rest of human life, especially
our desires and our pursuit of happiness, and for the expression of
this contrast a special moral sense or use-let us say, neutrally,
a special type of occurrence-of "ought" is required.
My question now is: "Is there-or as it will turn out, more
appropriately, was there-such a type of occurrence of 'ought'?"
How are we to decide whether a given word has more than one
sense or use? I wish to answer this question without fatally
entangling myself in the thickets of contemporary linguistics and
it is partly in order to achieve this that I have used the weak
expression "type of occurrence" ; but this wish is perhaps bound
160 Against the Self-Images of the Age
to be idle. But what I can do is to provide a case where the dis-
tinction to be made will provide us with at least provisional
criteria for distinguishing different types of occurrences of the
same word and then see whether in this particular sense of "type
of occurrence" there is a special moral type of occurrence of
"ought." To provide my initial exemplar I turn to the earlier
history of the word "ought" and its cognates: 3e:i:vin Greek,
debere in Latin and ahte in Anglo-Saxon and Middle English
all mean both what we mean by "ought" and what we mean
by "owe." But there comes a time in the history of each lan-
guage when "ought" and "owe" are discriminated. Even when
the same word is used, as debere continues to be used in Latin, for
example, the question "Do I owe this to X ?" is discriminated
from the question "Ought I to give this to X ?" in such a way that
"I ought to give to X what I owe to X" becomes non-tautological.
Can I therefore take it that the successful discrimination of two
types of occurrence of a verb has been achieved if in the use of a
sentence where the verb is used twice the statement made has a
form that would normally be tautological, and yet the statement in
question is clearly not tautological? The answer is clearly "no";
this cannot be a sufficient. condition for the achievement of the
discrimination of two senses, since we can produce clear counter-
examples. Pontius Pilate's "What I have written, I have written"
is non-tautological, but this in no way suggests that there are two
senses of the verb "to write." It might then be suggested that what
we need to do is to add a second condition, namely that if one use
of the verb in question is negated, then a contradiction is not
produced. For a contradiction would have been produced if
Pilate had asserted "What I have written, I have not written,"
thus showing that the non-tautological repetition is a type of
emphatic locution and does not involve two senses. But there
could, I think, be no plausible counter-examples to the claim that
where two verbs are used in a sentence the form of which would
normally ensure that any statement it was used to make would be
tautological, and the statement thus made is clearly not tautological,
and in addition one at least of the verbs can be negated without the
statement being thereby transformed into a contradiction, two
types of occurrence are involved. So similarly "I ought to give
what I owe" is non-tautological, even in languages where the
same word might recur; "It is not the case that I ought to give
what I owe" is certainly not a contradiction. What use can we
make of this tentative finding to evaluate Prichard's claim about
"ought?"
Some more about "ought" 161

The attitude that I want to take to Prichard's claim involves


applying to the interpretation of Prichard an argument that
R. G. Collingwood originally deployed against Prichard's interpre-
tation of Plato. Collingwood rightly objected to Prichard's attempt
to show that he, Prichard, was right and that Plato was grossly
mistaken in what Prichard took to be their rival accounts of
morality. For, argued Collingwood, what Plato was talking about
was just not the same as what Prichard was talking about: "a
Greek word like 8ei cannot be legitimately translated by
using the word 'ought' if [my italics] that word carries with it
the notion of what is sometimes [i.e., by Prichard] called 'moral
obligation.' " Was there any Greek word or phrase to express that
notion? The "realists" (Prichard and his school) said there was;
but they stultified themselves by adding that the "theories of
moral obligation" expounded by Greek writers differed from
modern theories such as Kant's about the same thing. How did
they know that the Greek and the Kantian theories were about the
same thing? Oh, because 8e~ (or whatever word it was) is
the Greek for "ought.'' "It was like," Collingwood went on,
"having a nightmare about a man who had got it into his head
was the Greek for 'steamer,' and when it was
that TPL~p'1)c;;
pointed out to him that descriptions of triremes in Greek
writers were at any rate not very good descriptions of steamers,
replied triumphantly, 'That is just what I say. These Greek
philosophers . . . were truly muddle-headed and their theory
of steamers is all wrong.'" In order not to make about Prichard the
mistake which Prichard made about Plato and Aristotle, we have to
ask what Prichard was talking about and whether we can locate his
subject matter historically. I would like to offer historical evidence
on two points.
The first concerns the homogenization of the ordinary moral
vocabulary. It is not only in the writings of philosophers from Kant
to Prichard, but in the writings of politicians and novelists too
that we can perceive the loss of any feeling for the more specific
meanings of words such as "duty" and "obligation.'' "Duty"
becomes not the singular of "duties" but a noun that is dis-
tinguished from that singular by not having a plural. There are of
course philosophers such as Green and Bradley who resist this
trend, but the Duke of Wellington, George Eliot, and Mr.
Gladstone are all on Prichard's side. Moreover it is precisely
these who homogenize the moral vocabulary who find themselves
confronted with a single, simple contrast between the demands of
morality and those of the ends of life and the claims of desire.
162 Against the Self-Images of the Age
"There is not much happiness for any of us in this life, but we can
all of us ride straight ahead and do our duty," said the Duke of
Wellington and W. S. Gilbert's Pirates of Penzance, subtitled
The Slave To Duty, is precisely a joke about how the concept of
duty has got out of hand in this respect. We recognize Prichard's
"feeling of imperativeness" when George Eliot in her famous
talk with F. W. H. Myers in the garden of Trinity College,
Cambridge, spoke of " . . . how peremptory and absolute" are
the demands of duty. (Myers gives "Duty" a capital letter in his
account.) But what then of the word "ought"? Do we find a
special sense of it?
The Oxford English Dictionary asserts that there is. But almost
every example that it cites is far from conclusive, and some
certainly not to the point at all.
At least an indication that we do find such a sense is provided
by Gladstone's capitalization of "Ought," strongly reminiscent
of Myer's capitalization of "Duty," when he speaks of the "Ought"
that constitutes morality. But we have other sources here. One is
the Victorian novel. Consider the following passages of dialogue
from Is He Popenjoy? (1878) by Anthony Trollope. The first
was:
". . . I think one should always promise to do everything that
is asked. Nobody would be fool enough to expect you to keep
your word afterwards and you'd give a lot of pleasure."

"I think promises ought to be kept, Captain de Baron."

"I can't agree to that. That's bondage, and it puts an embargo


on the pleasant way of living that I like. I hate all kinds of
strictness, and duty, and self-denying, and that kind of thing.
It's rubbish ... " (pp. 120-21 ).

It is certainly the case that a passage like this is in no way con-


clusive in suggesting that "ought" is being used in a special moral
sense. But there is at least one relevant point about such a passage.
Not only is "ought" used in such a passage in conjunction with
the notion of duty, but it is not used, and I think it is never used, in
either the novels of Trollope or indeed in those of George Eliot,
in such a way that a premise about what will make someone
happy supports a conclusion about what one ought to do. Ordinary
Victorian conversation, insofar as Trollope and George Eliot
record it, is Prichardian and neither Platonic, nor Aristotelian, nor
Some more about "ought"
Benthamite. Indeed I have only found one use of "ought" so
far in either novelist which is not in a moral context. I have
already said that I do not take this to be conclusive. For the
Prichardian claim, as I am now interpreting it, is that moral
considerations are not just one ground for which conclusions about
what agents ought to do can be devised, but that there is a
specifically moral sense of "ought" and the passages cited from
Trollope and George Eliot do not force us to take the Prichardian
view although I think that they strongly suggest it. Consider,
however, a second passage from Is He Popenjoy?
"I'm quite sure Lord George Germain never in his life did
anything that he ought not to do. That's his fault. Don't you
like men who do what they ought not to do?"
"No," said Mary, "I don't. Everybody always ought to do
what they ought to do ... " (p. 81).
The first speaker contrasts liking people with judging whether
they do what they ought to do; the second speaker, Lady Germain,
accepts the distinction in order to deny that if the criterion were
liking then men ought not (that is, had better not, if they want
to be liked) to do what they ought to do. The addition of the word
"always" makes it even clearer that "Everybody always ought to
do what they ought to do" is used by Trollope and his character
to deny that sometimes people ought not to do what they ought
to do. The intelligibility of this denial entails that the test which
I specified earlier for deciding whether in one particular type of
sentence two senses or uses-two types of occurrence-of a word
do or do not occur has in fact been applied. For this denial would
result in a contradiction unless two senses or uses of "ought"
were being used in the sentence "Everybody always ought to do
what they ought to do." It is the second "ought" which is clearly
the moral "ought" of which Prichard speaks.
Before I pass on to discuss this question further, I ought perhaps
to say a little more about my attempted manoeuver to avoid
entanglement with linguistics. I have cited one example of a case
in the history of "ought" where we might be strongly tempted to
say that two senses of "ought" were involved: that in which "I
ought" has to be discriminated from "I owe" and that in which
the moral or Prichardian "ought" has to be discriminated from
the ordinary advice-giving or prudential "ought." The reason
why we perhaps ought to resist this temptation is that in con-
temporary linguistics strong grounds are alleged for only in the
Aga£nst the Self-Images of the Age
last analysis explaining differences in the meaning of two state-
ments expressed by the same sentence by adducing different
senses of the same word. One alternative possibility in the present
case would be to understand the second Prichardian "ought" in
"Everybody always ought to do what they ought to do" as a type
of occurrence of "ought" in which there is a systematic deletion,
explicable possibly in terms of maxims governing conversational
proprieties. My difficulty with this suggestion is in knowing how
to characterize the deletion in question. If it is suggested that
what has been deleted is some such phrase that would give us a
rewriting of "Everybody always ought to do what they ought to
do" as "Everybody always ought to do what the rules of morality
prescribe that they ought to do," then we should have to ask what
is meant in this context by the rules of morality. If my cultural
analysis is correct, then these rules can only be expressed for
Prichard and his cultural allies by using the very "ought" that we
are trying to analyse. Hence we shall be involved in useless
circularity. But there may well be some other characterization of
the difference between the two "oughts" in Trollope's sentence in
terms of a deletion, and my argument certainly should not be
taken to imply that this is not so. For my immediate purposes, the
difference between one type of occurrence of "ought" and another
has now been adequately characterized, and it is in any case
clear to me that in one ordinary language sense of "meaning,"
differences in what I have called type of occurrence are called
differences in meaning. I shall therefore continue for my own
purpose to use the words "meaning" and "sense" in this way
without (in another sense of "sense") much sense of shame.
I therefore provisionally conclude that in the main Prichard is
not giving us an incorrect account of the use and meaning of a
word "ought" with the use and meaning of which we are all
familiar, but a correct account of one use and one meaning of
"ought" with which many of us at least-and there will be
variations here perhaps with age, social class, and place of up-
bringing-are unfamiliar. I also think it possible that there was a
tendency in the mid and late nineteenth century and early
twentieth century, at least in certain social groups in England, for
this "ought" of which Prichard speaks to become the dominant
or even the only use of "ought" so that where the general advice-
giving "ought" which I have paraphrased by "had better" would
have been used in other milieus various equivalent locutions are
used. If this were so, it might explain why in 1912 Prichard
thinks that in giving his account he is simply explaining the meaning
Some more ohout "ought" 165
and use of "ought" as such, whereas in 1937 he is more modestly
discriminating and explaining one meaning and use of "ought" as
contrasted with others.
One final historical remark: the moral "ought" explicated by
Prichard is not to be found before the late eighteenth century, just
as it is in the latter part of the eighteenth century that "duty" and
"obligation" begin to discard their more distinctive meanings
(although they never do this entirely) and in consequence it
ceases to be the case that premises about duty, premises about
obligation, and premises about happiness may all lead to one and
the same conclusion about what men ought to do in one and the
same sense of "ought." Insofar as morality is defined as Prichard
defined it, morality, like the railway and the polka, is an innovation
of the nineteenth century; and like the railway and the polka its
appearance or survival is perhaps intelligible only against a
particular cultural background.
For if we now take Prichard's characterization with some
seriousness we must surely become extremely puzzled in yet
another way. Consider three characteristics of the use of the
Prichardian "ought." First, when I tell someone or say to myself
that he or I ought to do so and so, in this sense of "ought" I
am not just-or perhaps at all-telling someone or myself to do
something even if a recognition that I ought so to do involves me
in a feeling of imperativeness. I am, it seems clearly, in Prichard's
view offering a particular type of reason for doing whatever it is.
Secondly, however, this reason cannot itself be supported by
further reasons, unless the sentences which express them also
contain the Prichardian "ought." Thus the kind of explication
of a type of statement which is given by considering what types of
reason might be offered either for asserting or for denying it must
be completely lacking. The only answer we are given by Prichard
to the question of how we can know that it is or is not the case
that we ought in the Prichardian sense to do so and so is that "the
only remedy lies in actually getting into a situation which occasions
the obligation, or-if our imagination be strong enough-in
imagining ourselves in that situation, and then letting our moral
capacities of thinking at this work." The example that Prichard
has just given is that of a "doubt whether we ought, for example,
to pay our debts" and Prichard must therefore mean that the way
to settle this doubt is to imagine that we are in debt or, if our
imaginations are not strong enough, actually to get into debt.
This is bizarre, but the bizarrerie perhaps belongs to the whole
notion of what Prichard calls "the immediacy of our appre-
166 Against the Self-Images of the Age
hension" of what we ought to do. He also uses the expression
"self-evidence" of this alleged apprehension.
Thirdly, it is clear that so far as the meaning of the key ex-
pressions, "ought," "obligation," "duty," and the like is con-
cerned, as they are understood by Prichard, no subjectivist
account can be correct. For in saying that I ought to do I in no
way express my own choice, preference, feelings, or attitudes; for
only I know what I ought in this sense to do, these all still remain
to be determined. That this is so is clear from the whole tenor of
Prichard's discussion; and it is equally clear in Trollope and
George Eliot. For Trollope the demands of "ought" are counter-
posed to those of "liking"; and for George Eliot the problem is
how to relate the demands of right action to the realm of feelings
left out of the definition of right action in the moral scheme of
some of these characters whom she represents in order to criticize.
"But yet sometimes when I have done wrong," says Maggie
Tulliver to her brother, "it is because I have had feelings that you
would be the better for, if you had them." The demands of
morality are in no way expressions of personal preference.
These three characteristics of the moral "ought" ought to
puzzle us in much the way that Captain Cook and his sailors were
puzzled when they first encountered the word "taboo". For they
found that to say that a class of actions was taboo was apparently
not to just say that actions of that particular kind were prohibited,
but to point to some particular kind of reason for the prohibition.
Yet since no further reason could be given for giving this reason,
the nature or the reason being adduced for the prohibition remained
completely obscure. Had the eighteenth-century inhabitants of
Polynesia had philosophers among them, Captain Cook's seamen
would doubtless have learnt that a taboo, if it can be derived at all,
can only be derived from another taboo, or that taboos are matter
for the immediacy of our apprehension, or even, if things had
gone far enough, that "taboo" is the name of a non-natural
quality. But Polynesia is not Oxford or Cambridge, nor the
eighteenth century the twentieth. Yet I find no reason to treat
either time or place differently from the other, and consequently
find no reason to suppose that my investigation of Prichard's
claims and of the social background of those claims ought to differ
radically from an anthropologist's or an anthropologically minded
historian's investigation of eighteenth-century Polynesia. We
should all of us, I think, be a little surprised if an elucidation of
the concept of taboo were to be a central feature of a book called
The Language of Morals, as a book by one of Prichard's successors
Some more ahout "ought" 167
is entitled, or of one called Moral Obligation, as Prichard's
collected papers were entitled by another of his successors. There
are a variety of moral schemes in different times and places for the
philosopher to investigate and some sense of this variety may be
necessary if we are not to treat our local moral schemes as timeless
and universal conceptions, something that we should rightly
judge an absurdity in Polynesians, although it is not in fact
Polynesians who need this reminder. Suppose that we do in fact
treat the Prichardian "ought" as the anthropologist treats the
Polynesian "taboo," what would be the outcome?
We make a social practice intelligible by placing it in some
context where the point and purpose of doing things in one way
rather than another is exhibited by showing the connection between
that social practice and some wider institutional arrangements of
which it is a part. So the passing of a verdict has to be understood
in the context of a legal system, and the concept of a home run has
to be understood in the context of baseball. When we cannot
make a practice intelligible by supplying such a context, there are
two possibilities. The first is that we have not been adequately
perceptive or understanding in our investigation of that particular
social order ; the other is that the practice just is, as it stands,
unintelligible. One hypothesis which we may advance as a result
of coming to the latter conclusion, a hypothesis which has the
additional merit, if it is independently supported, of supporting
the latter conclusion, is that the practice in question is a survival.
That is to say, we explain the practice in its present form by
supposing that it is the historical product of an earlier practice
which existed in a social context that has now been removed and
of the consequences of the removal of that context. What do I
mean by a context? A set of beliefs expressed in institutionalized
social practice. Hence what I want to maintain is that the use of
the Prichardian moral "ought" can perhaps only be made intelligible
as a social practice by supposing it to be a survival from a lost
context of beliefs, just as the eighteenth-century Polynesian
use of "taboo" can perhaps only be made intelligible by supposing
it to be a survival from a lost context of beliefs.
Consider two earlier forms of moral scheme. The first is that
embodied in Humean utilitarianism. Hume takes it that when one
asserts for anyone that he ought to do so and so, one is appealing
to a standard of justice or of obligation or of virtue-one is
expressing the sentiment of adherence to that standard and
appealing to the sentiment of adherence in others-which
standard is to be justified by showing us that it gives us all what
168 Against the Self-Images of the Age
we want. What we want is a matter of our passions and the passions
which compose human nature are a determinate set. Moreover
not only is this so, but the passions are such that if any two men
have the same rational powers and the same information, then
they will agree on what it is that ought to be done. This happy
coincidence secured by the contingent facts of human psychology,
this pre-established having of the emotions and of the desires, is
the presupposition of Hume's moral scheme. Now there seem to
me strong reasons for believing that Hume, unlike later utilitarians,
gives us a true report of the passions, but not of the passions
as they are biologically, not of some basic human nature, but of the
passions as they were ordered in one particular cultural and social
order. That order was shattered and fragmented by the impact of
those changes which at the level of high art are the Romantic
movement. With that movement the presupposition of any moral
scheme of the type represented by Hume is removed; the passions
and the sentiments confront the established rules and ends in
such a way as to constitute a set of problems for morality rather
than its foundation. It is upon this that Kant, who is essentially a
post-Sorrows of Werther moralist, remarks; it is this that Jane
Austen confronts in the character of Marianne in Sense and
Sensibility. There is no longer a determinate set of passions,
let alone a pre-established harmony in our desires. If therefore
men are to continue to assert that they ought to do what they
formerly asserted that they ought to do, it will have to be on
some new basis or in some new way.
As with the emotions formerly presupposed, so also with the
theology formerly presupposed. That Christian scheme according
to which God created man so that he had a determinate human
nature, the desires of which would be frustrated if he did not
follow the precepts of morality, and according to which what God
commands is what will in the end satisfy that nature, was destroyed
by the Protestant insistence that human nature is so depraved
that the commandments of God must appear to us as arbitrary
fiats. The chaos of Romantic emotion and the arbitrariness of
Protestant moral theology have one classic imaginative repre-
sentation in James Hogg's Memoirs of a Justified Sinner. It is only,
be it noted, in post-Protestant cultures that the moral "ought"
ever appears. And it appears precisely in the period when the judg-
ment that men ought to do so and so can no longer be supported
by appeal to the nature that God created and the purposes toward
which the commandments of God are directed.
Detached from a theological scheme and a scheme of the
Some more about "ought" 169
emotions, both of which were embodied in the vocabulary and in
the norms which defined the transactions of daily life, what should
we expect to happen to the use of "ought"? There are clearly a
number of possible outcomes. But clearly one might be that
men would go on saying that one ought to do so and so, expecting
their utterance to be endowed with the same locutionary and
allocutionary force-or lack of it-as before, but unable now when
pressed to offer the same or any other justification. What had
formerly been a conclusion from premises, resting on certain
presuppositions which made the necessary inferences possible,
will now become a type of statement which can be derived from
nothing other than a more general statement of the same type.
"An 'ought', if it is to be derived at all, can only be derived
from another 'ought.' " Deprived of its rationale, the use of this
"ought" would necessarily be unsusceptible of further explication,
and the continuance of its use would be in a real sense superstitious.
But this judgment perhaps sounds unnecessarily harsh. Yet
consider how the moral or Prichardian "ought" was in fact
used. The central features of its use can be brought out by
comparing the following three imaginary dialogues:
I. A. Sir, return to me that copy of Warburton's sermons.
B. Why?
A. Sir, you have promised to return it and therefore you
ought to return it.
B. But why should I keep promises?
A. Sir, promise-keeping, as Mr. Hume has shown in his
Treatise,is an institution invented to produce benefits
for beings who desire, as you desire and I desire, to
rely on our expectations of each other.
B. Sir, your appeal to the passions has enslaved my
reason. Here is your book.
2. A. Sir, return to me that copy of The Languageof Morals.
B. Why?
A. I choose to ask for this, I do ask for it. Give it to me.
Let anyone who has borrowed a book give it to its
owner.
B. Why should your preferences interest me?
3· A. Sir, return to me that copy of Moral Obligation.
B. Why?
A. You ought to return what you have borrowed.
170 Against the Self-Images of the Age
B. Why?
A. I can give you no further answer. For I am using the
distinctively moral "ought." You just ought, and if
you cannot see this, I cannot help you.

In the first of these dialogues the force of "You ought" is


entirely derived from the force of the impersonal standard of
utility, understood as Hume understood it. There is a genuine
backing of the injunction to act in a certain way, by the giving of a
reason. In the second dialogue, there is no such backing of the
injunction at all; the injunction is presented as the expression of
the naked will of the speaker and unless the hearer has some
reason to regard the will of the speaker-because, for example,
he hates or loves, has hopes of or fears of the speaker-he has been
afforded no reason at all for doing what he has been enjoined to do.
But that this is so has been made entirely clear by the speaker's
use of imperatival form and of expressions which are plainly no
more than expressions of personal preference and choice.
In the third dialogue however matters are very different. The
use of "ought" makes it sound as if the situation is the same as in
the first dialogue, as though there is the giving of a reason for
following the injunction to action, by means of an appeal to an
impersonal standard. But the inability to back up this use of
"ought" by any further reason-giving renders this appearance
entirely deceptive. The hearer has in fact been given no more
reason to follow the injunction than he was in the second dialogue,
but the appeal to naked will has been clothed with the semblance
but not the reality of reason-giving by the use of the Prichardian
"ought." It is considerations such as these that suggest that the
use of such a word as "superstition" may not be out of place.
This is not a matter of the intentions of particular individuals.
Where a particular use of the word "ought" is an established.
social practice a particular individual may well use it without the
intention of exercising bluff or deception upon his hearers. But
his hearers will in fact be bluffed or deceived, whatever the speaker
intends, just insofar as they attach a seriousness and a force to
what he says which they would not attach to the utterance of
imperatives or expressions of personal preference and choice.
That this is so throws light on the theory of moral utterance that
immediately succeeded Prichard's intuitionism. Emotivism has
always been an implausible theory about the meaning of moral
words and sentences. "Good," "right," and "ought" involve an
appeal to some standard which expressions of preference or choice
Some more about "ought" 171

or imperatival expressions do not involve; and as R. M. Hare


pointed out, statements containing evaluative expressions have
or can have logical relation to each other and to other statements
which expressions genuinely used as expressions of feeling ("What
a splendid day!" or "Hurrah for the red, white and blue!") do
not and cannot have. Hence Stevenson was in error when he
represented his analyses as offering even rough and approximate
equivalences of meaning between classes of expression. But
Stevenson's version of Emotivism can be more fruitfully under-
stood in another way. For the account of the Prichardian or
distinctly moral "ought" which I have given would lead us to
conclude that when this "ought" was being used, agents who
believed themselves to be doing other and more than expressing
their own feelings and attitudes were in fact doing no other and
no more than that. In a precisely similar way religious language
when it survives into a non-religious and irreligious culture may
change its use without changing its meaning. There have been
times and places when a man who said "God give me patience!"
would necessarily have been uttering a prayer; but a man in our
culture who says "God give me patience I" may not be praying-
for the practice of prayer presupposes a context of belief which is
often now lacking-but expressing his feelings of exasperation. The
words have not changed their meaning; but the expression has
changed its use. Emotivism understood as a theory of use, and not
as a theory of meaning at all, turns out to be true not of morality
in general, but rather of what morality came to be at a particular
period of time. To put the point in another idiom, Prichard
presents us with the self-image of one particular morality, taken
at its own face value. He never pierces below the ideological
surface. Stevenson does just this. But Stevenson, like Prichard,
accepts too much from the morality itself. He takes it, for example,
to be a characterization of morality as such, that disagreement may
always be interminable, whereas this is a characterization only of
moralities which are detached from any background of beliefs,
whether theological or naturalistic, which supply established and
ultimate criteria. Stevenson, like Prichard, lacks any sense of the
historical dimension of morality. Hence his theory is not a true
theory of moral utterance, but a true theory of intuitionist moral
utterance, if we understand by intuitionism not merely the doctrine
of a group of philosophers, but the doctrine of a social milieu.
The Prichardian or distinctively moral "ought" was a ghost and
it is a ghost that still walks in certain quarters, although more and
more obviously, like other ghosts, a survival. Yet so long as it
Against the Self-Images of the Age
survives, morality involves a degree of bluff and deception that
can only have the effect of engendering cynicism whenever it is
once more expressed. This paper is therefore not only an attempt
at analysis; it is also hopefully an exorcism.
17
Pleasure as a reason for action1

It is often said nowadays that to understand pleasure we must


understand it as affording us a reason for or an explanation of
action. It is only from the standpoint of the agent that we can avoid
being misled. Both Professor Nowell-Smith 2 and Mr. Manser 3 have
argued along these lines; and Dr. Kenny 4 has written that "pleasure
is always a reason for action" and has elucidated what he means
by a footnote: "I do not mean that a thing's being pleasant is
always a sufficient reason for doing it; there may be strong reasons
for abstaining. I mean merely that it is always silly to ask a man
why he wants pleasure." When I first saw this point made, I had
the perhaps not uncommon philosophical experience of immediately
finding it both lucid and convincing, but then afterwards gradually
becoming less and less clear about the source of my conviction.
The reasons for my obfuscation are as follows. In one crucial sense
anything can afford an agent with a reason for action. It depends
upon what the agent wants and upon the projects in which he is
engaged. Moreover, without having any strong reasons for
abstaining from what will give me pleasure, I may not be at all
moved by the prospect of pleasure. As I write this essay I can list
a dozen activities or experiences which would afford me pleasure.
I have no strong reason for abstaining; I do not particularly enjoy
writing essays; I am not writing with a great sense of urgency;
I have the time and the money to indulge myself. Yet I do not
rush to open a Guinness or Mr. P. G. Wodehouse's new novel. So
that far from its being silly to ask me why I do not apparently
1 Reprinted from The Monist, Vol. 49, No. 2 (1965) with permission of
The Open Court Publishing Co., La Salle, Illinois.
2 P.H. Nowell-Smith, Ethics (London and Baltimore: Penguin Books,
1954), p. 132.
3 A. Manser, "Pleasure," Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 1958.
4 A. Kenny, Action, Emotion and Will (London: Routledge & Kegan
Paul; New York: Humanities Press, 1963), p. 134.
173
174 Against the Self-Images of the Age
want pleasure at the moment, it is a question that I find forced
upon me. But if this question makes sense, there is at least a prob-
lem as to why "it is always silly to ask a man if he wants pleasure."
For one might expect the two questions to stand or fall together.
This is the problem to which I address myself in this essay. But in
order to do so I must first take up certain points from recent
discussions which are in danger of preventing a solution.

I
There are two classical treatments of pleasure, the Benthamite 1
and the Aristotelian. 2 If I deal with them in that rather than in the
chronological order, it is because in recent philosophical writing
about pleasure, the Benthamite view has provided the target
for attack, the Aristotelian view the weapons. It seems clear
that Bentham treated both "pleasure" and "pain" as the names of
sensations. These sensations are distinct existences which may,
and on occasion do, exist without being accompanied by any act
of will. It is not entirely clear whether Bentham himself thought
the connection between pleasure and pain on the one hand, and
acts of will and actions on the other, to be purely contingent or
not. For one thing it is "the idea of pleasure" rather than the
sensation which has an effect on the will, according to Bentham.
But Bentham certainly appears to believe, first, that in all cases
where I take pleasure in or enjoy something, what constitutes the
pleasure or enjoyment is an accompanying sensation, which
exists over and above the object of pleasure or enjoyment; and,
second, that when I do something for pleasure or enjoyment and
achieve it, the pleasure or enjoyment is a sensation separately
identifiable from the means by which I procure the sensation.
Bentham gives fifty-eight synonyms for "pleasure"; his use of the
notion of synonymity reinforces the view that he takes there to be
a single, simple concept of pleasure, so that "enjoyment" for
example means precisely what "pleasure" means and names
precisely what "pleasure" names.
In Aristotle's view, which is far less tidy than Bentham's,
pleasure is analysed at one point in terms of unimpeded activity
and at another in terms of its resemblances and differences to an
1 J. Bentham, Principles of Morals and Legislation (New York: Hafner,
1948), Chapter 4 and elsewhere.
2 Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics (London and New York: Heinemann

and Putnam (Loeb), 1926), Book VII and Book X.


Pleasure as a reasonfor action 175
end. Both analyses derive from Aristotle's belief that, if I do some-
thing because I enjoy doing it, my action is not a means to a
separately identifiable end, my enjoyment. He therefore finds
himself at one stage arguing that to enjoy doing what one is
doing is simply to do whatever it is without hindrance; and at
another that, although pleasure is a reason for acting and that to
get pleasure from doing something is a criterion of success in
action, we cannot identify any specific type of action in terms of its
being a means to pleasure. I have used the words pleasure and
enjoyment indifferently to convey Aristotle's views; he himself
uses the single word ~3ov~ and appears to believe that he is
dealing with a single concept.
In recent discussions the Aristotelian stress upon pleasure as not
separately identifiable from the enjoyed activity has been force-
fully deployed against the Benthamite view. None the less, the dis-
cussion has had three unsatisfactory features. First of all, too
often pleasure, enjoyment, liking, happiness, and the rest have
been treated as if Bentham and Aristotle were right in seeing a
single concept here. Secondly, if pleasure is not separately identi-
fiable as an end-state to which actions are a means, a short sharp
refutation of hedonism is obviously available. But too short and
too sharp a refutation. Clearly hedonism does treat pleasure as an
end and equally clearly as an end among other alternative and
rival ends. For hedonism bids us to pursue pleasure rather than
other goals. But in the Aristotelian view pleasure supervenes upon
activity successfully carried through; it cannot be the end of
activity. And moreover in the Aristotelian view since pleasure is
specified in terms of successful activity and not vice versa, pleasure
cannot be a criterion for choosing among ends. Pleasure supervenes
on every achieved end. It follows that hedonism makes no sense.
Yet hedonism is in fact fully intelligible as a set of recommended
moral choices. And it is so, first, because the hedonist uses
the word "pleasure" in a sense which needs to be discriminated
from other senses of that word-as neither the Aristotelian view
nor the Benthamite does discriminate it; and, secondly, because in
treating pleasure in his sense as an end, the hedonist treats
pleasure as intrinsically bound up with certain activities and certain
experiences rather than others-whereas in both the Aristotelian
and the Benthamite view pleasures can, logically, be had from any
activity. Now perhaps any activity or experience can be enjoyed in
some sense; but only some give pleasure in the hedonist's sense.
It may be objected that I am unjustifiably restricting the use
of the word "hedonist," for the word has been used to characterize
Against the Self-Images of the Age
the views of both of those who hold that as a matter of fact we
all do pursue pleasure or happiness, these terms being used in-
differently (so the Abbe Bremond called the Jansenists "panhed-
onists") and of those who hold that we ought to pursue pleasure
rather than other possible ends. It is as a mere matter of con-
venience that I invoke the latter rather than the former use, my
model for a hedonist being Norman Douglas rather than the
Abbe de Saint-Cyran. I am interested in the word "pleasure" as
it is used in connection with beer and pickles, oysters and cham-
pagne, racecourses, dogtracks, and what Lord Denning in his
report called "popsies." · There is, then, something of an initial
difference of interest from those philosophers who have treated as
paradigm cases of pleasure digging, going for walks, fishing, and
even writing philosophical papers. This difference of interest is
connected not only with a belief that a family of interconnected
concepts has been misunderstood by treating them as if they were
all one and the same concept, but also with a concern that the
role of the senses and of sensations in pleasure has received
insufficient attention.
This is the third defective feature of contemporary discussions.
Convinced, and rightly convinced, that Bentham was mistaken in
identifying pleasure with a sensation, philosophers have tended
to neglect both sensations and the senses and to concentrate on
enjoyable activities. I can thus redefine the goal of this essay in
terms of these two points: to discriminate different concepts of
pleasure and enjoyment, with a view to clarifying the role of the
senses and of sensations in pleasure, and at the same time to make
clear in what different senses pleasure can be a reason for action.

II
First of all, then, to remark some of the variety of concepts:
x. "Heureux qui, comme Ulysse ... " (du Bellay); "0 happy is
the man who hears instruction's warning voice" (Ps. i, Scots
metrical version). The use of "happy" to express a verdict on a
man's life depends upon a sense of "happy" in which a man may
truly be called happy who has suffered a great deal, as well as a man
who has prospered.
2. I may be called happy in the above sense, because during my
life I have enjoyed myself on many occasions. But, in giving this
supporting reason for the verdict, I am using "enjoy" to mean
something other than "be happy." I can enjoy a game, a holiday,
Pleasureas a reasonfor action 1 77
a friend's company, digging, editing a Greek text. My motive in
doing these things need not be a wish for enjoyment for me to
enjoy whatever it is; I may play games or dig for the sake of my
health and edit a text because I need to earn money, and yet
enjoy what I do. Whether I enjoy what I do or not is a question
that others may answer by observing whether or not I try to
prolong the activity, appear absorbed in it, yawn, and so on. But
my own testimony is highly important, although not necessarily
always conclusive.
3. An activity, a sensation, a sight or sound, a work of art, a
taste, a smell may be called pleasant or ·unpleasant, enjoyable or
unenjoyable. In so characterizing it, I do not commit myself to
having enjoyed it or found it pleasant on any particular occasion.
It may well be that it takes experience to find it pleasant, or it
equally may well be that familiarity dulls the pleasure. " ... 'I add
to them, in the laying out of grounds, a third and distinct character,
which I call unexpectedness.' 'Pray, sir,' said Mr. Milestone,
'by what name do you distinguish this character when a person
walks around the grounds for the second time?' " (Peacock).
Moreover, when I call something pleasant or enjoyable, although
I may not be able to give reasons for my characterization, it
always makes sense to ask for them. I may call a drink pleasant
because it is refreshing, a holiday enjoyable because it combined
sun and sea with the opportunity to look at paintings. If I call
something pleasant or enjoyable I am saying, or at least giving
my hearers to understand, that the standard criteria for that sort
of thing's being an enjoyable one have been satisfied, at least where
there are such criteria. And commonly there are.
4. Pleasure as a distinct object of pursuit might be said to
consist in the enjoyable qualities of those activities, sensations,
tastes, and the like, which are, and can only be, sought for the
sake of the pleasure found in them. And certainly even if I not only
enjoy nursing the sick or working on an automobile production
line, but do these things because I enjoy them, I cannot be said to be
devoting myself to pleasure in this sense. Yet to say this would be to
attend to one end of a spectrum only, a spectrum which must be de-
fined partly in terms of this end of the scale and partly in terms of
the contrast between activities which can only be carried on for the
sake of pleasure and activities which could in no sense be said to be
pursued only for pleasure's sake, even when we enjoy them. For
there are many activities which carried on in one type of context
could only be done for pleasure, but which in another type of
context could be carried on for other reasons. Such is fishing. And
Against the Self-Images of the Age
there are activities which embody values so central to human life
that although they are highly productive of pleasure, they could not
be undertaken without some attention to those values and so could
not be done purely for pleasure. Such is mountaineering. But there
are at the opposite end of the spectrum from that of which I first
spoke, when the activities to which I wanted to draw attention
were eating and drinking what is not designed to prevent hunger
and thirst, the enjoyment of tastes and smells, sensual pleasure, and
all those items to which the OED may be taken to be referring
when it gives as its second definition of "Pleasure": "In bad sense:
Sensuous enjoyment as a chief object of life or end in itself."
The most important ground on which I have distinguished
between these four concepts is the difference in each case in what
would make statements embodying them true or false. This
attention to truth-conditions, rather than to syntactical distinctions
or I idiomatic nuances, is necessary because the words used to
express these concepts are, in contemporary English as contrasted
with the English of earlier generations, often interchangeable.
There are indeed idiomatic points to be made of philosophical
interest: tastes, smells, and sensations are usually said to be
pleasant or pleasurable, activities to be enjoyable. In this way
different parts of the spectrum of pleasure are distinguished in
ordinary usage. But for most idioms that make use of some form
of "enjoy" and its cognates there is an equivalent idiom using
"please" or "pleasure." It is because of these facts that it would be
equally wrong either to assert with Bentham that "pleasure" and
"enjoyment" are synonyms or simply to deny Bentham's assertion.
Hence also the misleading character of all such assertions is that
pleasure is a species of enjoyment. For such assertions presuppose
what is not the case, that the vocabulary of pleasure and enjoyment
is a currency with fixed values. In my own elucidation I have
annexed certain words for certain concepts in an arbitrary but,
I hope, tolerably lucid way.
Some of the relations between the four concepts I have sketched
are fairly clear: that a man has enjoyed much of his life is a good
reason, although it may not be a sufficient one, for calling him
happy; that an experience or activity was pleasurable may be
cited as an explanation for having enjoyed it. But others of the
relationships are more complex. The one on which I wish to lay
stress is that between first-person reports of what I do or did take
pleasure in or enjoy and statements about an experience or
activity being enjoyable, pleasant, or pleasurable. When asked
why I enjoyed an experience or why the experience was enjoyable
Pleasureas a reasonfor action 179
I may in both cases point to features of the experience which
made it enjoyable. But if I fail to enjoy an experience and am
asked to explain why I so failt;_d,I may do one of two things. I
may say that the experience just was not enjoyable, and I may
cite features of the experience which made it unpleasant. Or I may
account for my lack of enjoyment alternatively by explaining
that although the experience had all the features of an enjoyable
experience, none the less I failed to enjoy it because something was
wrong with me: I had a cold, I was overtired, or even-the
residual category-I just did not feel like it.
I lay stress on these alternative directions in which explanation
may move (in calling them alternatives I do not mean to imply
that it could not be the case both that the experience had un-
pleasant features and that I was in no fit state to enjoy it), both
because this contrast between pointing to the state of the agent
and pointing to the features of his experience or activity will
recur later in the argument, and because attention to it enables us to
diagnose certain errors. Ryle opens a discussion of pleasure by
asking what sort of difference the difference is between a walk which
one enjoys and a walk which one does not enjoy. The point of his
question is partly to bring out that the difference is not that one
walk is accompanied by a certain specific sensation and that the
other is not. With this no one but a Benthamite could quarrel. But
the question, as Ryle poses it, is almost as misleading as a Bentha-
mite answer to it would be; for the form of the question suggests
that one is looking for a single answer. And this is the kind of
answer Ryle gives. A walk that one enjoys is one which has
absorbed one's attention. So Ryle has written:
To say that a person has been enjoying digging ... is to say that
he dug with his whole heart in his task; i.e., that he dug,
wanting to dig, and not wanting to do anything else (or nothing)
instead. His digging was a propensity fulfilment. His digging
was his pleasure, and not a vehicle of his pleasure. 1
This passage contains a mixture of true and false, When Ryle
explains enjoying digging in terms of wanting to dig he gives us
an important clue to a correct analysis. But he presents this clue
as though there were only one answer to such questions as: "Why
did you enjoy digging today?" or "What is the difference between
that walk yesterday which you enjoyed and the one today which
1 Gilbert Ryle, "Pleasure," Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society,
Supplement, 1954 and The Concept of Mind (London: Hutchinson; New
York: Barnes & Noble, 1949), p. 108.
180 Against the Self-Images of the Age
you did not enjoy?" In fact the moment it is clear that we are
talking about digging or walking on a specific occasion it also
becomes clear that our enjoyment or lack of it has to be connected
with features specific to the occasion. The difference between the
walk today and the walk yesterday may be the difference between
a walk when the sun was shining and a walk when it was cold and
wet or the difference between a walk with Sarah who is charming
and adores you and a walk with Selina who is boring and dislikes
you. Suppose that it is objected that this is not the type of case
Ryle had in mind. For a walk with Sarah is not the same activity
as a walk with Selina, and a walk in the sun is not the same activity
as a walk in the rain. What about the case where you enjoy and
fail to enjoy the same activity on two successive occasions ?
The answer can only be that in that case the answer must be
looked for in your state of body or mind and not in the activity.
Again there will be no one general answer. You may on one
occasion have had a cold or been overtired, or on the other have
just had good news or felt unusually well.
So that we have to pass from the walking or the digging to the
enjoyment by way of features of the walking or the digging. What
makes these features relevant to cite is the fact that they are of a
kind recognized as making a walk or a dig pleasurable. "I enjoyed
the walk because the sun was shining" is intelligible as it stands ;
"I enjoyed the walk because of the cold drizzle" is not. Of course
when someone says "I enjoyed ... " his assertion does not mean
the same as an assertion about what made the occasion enjoyable.
What his assertion does mean, however, will not be understood if,
as Ryle does, in the earlier of the discussions cited, we try to
connect the enjoyment solely with the agent's mode of activity.
Professor W. B. Gallie,1 and Mr. C. C. W. Taylor 2 have both,
for example, taken pleasure to be some form, mode, or species of
attention. A general view of their case has been given by Professor
H. L. A. Hart 3 who has written approvingly that,
the outlines at least of a new and more realistic [than the
Benthamite] analysis are clear. The elements previously treated
as mere empirical evidence of a separately identifiable sensation
of pleasure have now been introduced into the analysis of
pleasure. The wish for prolongation of the activity or experience
1 W. B. Gallie, "Pleasure," Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society,

Supplement, 1954.
2 C. C. W. Taylor, "Pleasure", Analysis, Supplement, 1962.
3 H. L.A. Hart, "Bentham," Proceedings of the British Academy, 1962.
Pleasureas a reasonfor action
enjoyed; the resistance to interruption; the absorbed or rapt
attention; the absence of some further end beyond the activity
enjoyed-these are surely conceptually and not merely
empirically linked with pleasure.

But these elements have by no means all the same status in


relation to pleasure. Clearly it is right to link, for example, a
wish for prolongation to enjoyment; but equally clearly that one is
raptly attending to something is neither a necessary nor a sufficient
condition for enjoyment. My attention may be absorbed by
the thumbscrew's increasing pressure; my sleepy lack of attention
may constitute part of what is enjoyable about lying on in bed,
half-listening to the sounds of everyone else departing for work.
The mistake of those who have focused attention on attention
is the opposite of one of Bentham's errors. Bentham wished to
make the relation between pleasure and its external manifestations
entirely contingent; these writers wish to make pleasure actually
consist in its external manifestations. But while such mani-
festations as absorption and attention are perhaps highly character-
istic of enjoyment, they are at best a criterion used by the observer
to justify his third-person judgment on someone else's enjoyment.
If someone says "I enjoy ... " or "I enjoyed ... " or "I am
enjoying ... " he is not saying that he is attending or is absorbed.
The criteria of enjoyment and the meaning of "enjoy" cannot
be understood apart from one another, but they must none the less
be distinguished.
At first sight a wish to prolong an experience or activity is
no more intimately connected with enjoyment than attention is.
For I may wish to prolong an experience which I am not enjoying
(I do not enjoy the patient's struggle not to die, but I usually wish
to prolong it and I may wish to prolong my stay at the bedside too);
and I may wish to cut short an activity which I am enjoying very
much. So that a wish to prolong is neither a necessary nor a
sufficient condition of enjoyment. But if I have nothing else to do
and if I do not wish to prolong an experience, I could not claim
to be still enjoying it. The first condition has to be added, if we
are to state a necessary condition for enjoyment accurately. But
that this is a necessary condition of enjoyment is itself a conse-
quence of a more central feature of enjoyment. If I enjoy an
activity or experience, then I am satisfiedwith that activity or experi-
ence, as a way of spending time. To put the notion of satisfaction in
its deservedly central place, we must again take up Ryle's point
that a man who enjoyed digging "dug, wanting to dig, and not
182 Against the Self-Images of the Age
wanting to do anything else (or nothing) instead." Clearly, as it
stands, the last point is incorrect. A man may want to do some-
thing other than what he is doing and yet enjoy what he is doing.
There is indeed no paradox in a man's wanting to do something
which he would not enjoy while doing something that he does
enjoy. So a man may want to be called up in wartime because he
considers it his duty to fight, although he knows he will hate the
army, but still enjoy continuing his peacetime pursuits. Moreover,
the sense in which a man who enjoys doing something must
want to do it needs further clarification. A man may want to do
something, do it, and not enjoy doing it. For him to enjoy doing
it he must find in doing it that it is something he wants to do and
would want to do even if it served no further end. Whether
prior to doing it he wanted to do it or not is irrelevant. Furthermore,
a man could not be said to enjoy doing something unless he
wanted to do it again, provided only that there were not grave
reasons in favor of not so doing, such as harm to himself or
someone else. It is in this sense that enjoyment consists in the
satisfaction of desire.
This analysis of enjoyment also applies when sensations, tastes,
and smells are in question rather than activity. A sensation I
enjoy, or from which I get pleasure, is one I want to feel in the same
sense that when I feel it I want to feel and have felt it and would
want to feel it even if it served no further end and even if it were
not part, as it well may be, of a wider context of enjoyment. So
sexual enjoyment is not just a matter of sensations, but the
sensations are found pleasant even apart from the activity which
gives them their context. Yet just at this point there is reason to
pause in the argument. If I say that I took pleasure in an experience
or enjoyed an activity, am I identifying my pleasure or enjoyment
as distinct from the experience or activity? I have already sug-
gested that it always makes sense to ask what made the experience
or activity pleasurable and that the answer will be to point to
features of the experience or activity. I may of course find an
experience or activity pleasurable and be unable to pick out the
relevant features. But if I can, they must, as I have also already
suggested, be recognizable as pleasure-giving or enjoyable
characteristics. In order to be so recognizable, a characteristic
must give pleasure on standard occasions to most people. But
what is the force of "most" here? If we recognize a characteris-
tic as pleasure-giving, are we merely allowing that as a matter of
purely contingent fact it is the sort of thing which most people
happen to enjoy? Or are we asserting that some characteristics
Pleasureas a reasonfor action
may be enjoyable as such, as it were, or pleasant as such? That is,
are we asserting that if someone failed to find some particular
characteristic of a certain experience or activity pleasurable we
would have grounds for saying more than that he had minority
tastes?
The question can be put most sharply in terms of the sensations,
tastes, and smells which are so important to sensual pleasure. Is it
the case that most of us merely happen to like certain sensations,
tastes, and smells? Can we identify and characterize them in-
dependently of their being pleasurable? The belief that we can is
expressed most cogently by Mr. R. M. Hare 1 and expressed in
terms not of pleasure, but of pain.

III

"Objection might be taken to the claim that there could be a


'bare sensation' of pain which was not disliked. What, it might be
asked, would such an experience be like? Can we imagine such
an experience? I think that I can not only imagine it, but have had
it .... " So Hare, and much of his argument applies not only to
pain but to what he calls "unpleasant sensations" -itches,
tickles, electric shocks, and the like-and we can understand how
a partly parallel treatment of pleasure could be given. 2
In the course of his argument Hare makes five important
points. He begins by criticizing Professor Kurt Baier3 who had in
turn been criticizing Ryle's view that "pain is a sensation of a
special sort which we ordinarily dislike having." 4 Baier had criti-
cized Ryle's view that the connection between pain and dislike is
a contingent one and had written that "whatever sorts of sensa-
tions we like and dislike, we only call pains those which we
dislike." Hare points to the fact that there are many different types
of sensation which we dislike (as there are also of course distinct
1 R. M. Hare, "Pain and Evil," Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society,
Supplement, 1954.
2 For Hare's own brief account see R. M. Hare, Freedom and Reason

(London and New York: Oxford University Press, 1963), pp. 125-29.
I would not want the case on pleasure, which I have constructed in
outline from Hare's views on pain, to be treated as though Hare could be
held responsible for it.
3 K. Baier, The Moral Point of View (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University

Press, 1958), pp. 268ff.


4 Ryle, op. cit., p. 109.
7
Against the Self-Images of the Age
types of pleasurable sensations) and that we can segregate one
group from these, the group of pains-that is, "burning pains,
stinging pains, stabbing pains, aches, etc."-which is bound to-
gether therefore by something more and other than the fact of
dislike. Hare then concedes that it may be that the use of the word
"pain" in ordinary English does imply dislike; but if so this fact
of usage can be countered by inventing a new term to name the
sensation apart from our dislike of it.
Hare then draws two arguments from physiological evidence.
The first is based on reports by experimental subjects in which
the intensification of a sensation to the point to which it was
painful is commented on in such a way by those who suffered it
that Dr. C. A. Keele wrote that "the element of unpleasantness
seems to be superimposed on a sensation which runs through the
whole range." 1 That is, the same sensation is recognized as being
when less intense painless but when more intense painful. So we
can identify the sensation apart from its "painful", thatis, dislikable
qualities. The second piece of physiological evidence is drawn
from experience of lobotomy. Patients who have had this operation
appear still to feel pain, but their dislike of it appears to be reduced.
The two final points to which I wish to draw attention are not so
much arguments for Hare's case as an answer to a possible objec-
tion and a statement of part of his purpose in propounding the
earlier arguments. The possible objection is that we learn the
meaning of the word "pain" when we are young only in contexts
where dislike is being manifested. Hence we would have to grasp
the meaning in such a way "that there is an analytic connection
between having a pain and a manifestation of dislike." Hare's
reply is that
the teaching procedure would work perfectly well if the con-
nection between pain and the manifestations of dislike were not
analytic but contingent, provided that cases of pain without the
manifestations, or vice versa, were rare. For me to succeed in
teaching children the use of the word "pain", it is sufficient
for me correctly to guess, on one or two occasions, that they are
in pain because they are doing what normally manifests dislike
of pain.
Finally Hare points out that an argument used against his own
distinction between descriptive and evaluative judgments has
been that "I am in intense pain" is both descriptive and-because
1 The Assessment of Pain in Man and Animals, edited by Keele and Smith,
as cited by Hare in "Pain and Evil", op. cit.
Pleasure as a reason for action 185
pain is necessarily disliked and to dislike something is clearly to
evaluate it-evaluative, and that therefore Hare's distinction
breaks down. But on the basis of his earlier arguments Hare replies
that we must distinguish between reports of the sensation of pain
and avowal of the dislike of pain. The first is description, the
second evaluation,1 and even if our ordinary use of "pain" com-
bines them there is no necessary or logical connection between
them.
This last point of Hare's is more relevant to my present argu-
ment than might appear. The critics to whom Hare refers surely
went quite the wrong way about impugning Hare's distinction.
For even if they could produce an example of a judgment which
was both descriptive and evaluative, they would not thereby have
shown that there were not two distinct classes of judgment. The
discovery of borderline cases is evidence for, not against, the
existence of borderlines. My own objection to Hare's view is that it
presents the distinction between what is factual or descriptive and
what is action-guiding or evaluative as a distinction between two
classes of judgment or kinds of statements. Whereas, in fact,
whether a statement is factual is a matter of what is said in it and
of how it would be shown to be true or false; whereas whether a
statement is action-guiding or evaluative depends on such matters
as the intention with which and the context in which and the
audience for whom it is uttered. Consider the difference between
the statement "The White House is on fire" uttered as a news
report by a broadcaster and uttered as a warning by a Presidential
aide to the President. The same statement with precisely the same
meaning can be put to very different uses, and to suppose that by
putting a statement to a different use one had necessarily thereby
changed its meaning would only be possible if one had illegiti-
mately conflated the notions of meaning and use. It is worth
making this point, even if the key question thereby raised of the
meaning of such a word as "good" has to be put on one side,
because it brings out the fact that a statement only provides
someone with a reason for action if it is relevant to his wants or
needs. Outside the context of human wants and needs no statement
can function as such a reason. The question that I posed at the
end of the last section was whether there are predicates of a
factual kind which have meaning and application only in terms of
desire and aversion; that is, whether there are kinds of property
which can only be identified and characterized if we identify them
1 I have compressed this argument and the reader is referred to Hare's

own exposition.
186 Against the Self-Images of the Age
as objects of desire or aversion. If there are such predicates and
properties, their existence presupposes that certain desires and
aversions are standard for human beings, standard not only in
being statistically usual, but in providing norms for desire, to such
an extent that our descriptive vocabulary embodies these norms.
Hence certain types of statements would furnish us with reasons
for action in a special sense. Hare's view on pain might be genera-
lized into the contention that there are no such statements.
My first problem about Hare's thesis is equally a problem about
the statements of Ryle and Baier from which Hare's exposition
started. All speak of sensations which we dislike. Now certainly
we dislike many sensations, and pains are among these; but the
variations in my dislike of my pain are not to be confused with
variations in the pain. That is, it is just not the case that the more
painful my pain the more I dislike it. For my dislike may intensify
or lessen depending on how well able I feel to bear the pain; and
there are times when I may feel better able to bear a greater pain
than I am able to bear with equanimity at other times. Equally,
my dislike of the same pain of unchanging intensity may vary
greatly. Thus, the connection between pain and characteristic
pain behavior is unlikely to be elucidated at all by putting this
concept of liking or disliking in the center of the picture.
Consider instead the notion of "the same sensation." What
are the criteria for identity or similarity of sensation? Certainly
identity of stimulus is not enough. It always makes sense to inquire
whether the same stimulus is producing the same sensation as it
did before, or whether it is producing the same sensation in you
as it is in me. Equally, reactions to sensations vary. It makes sense
to inquire whether the same sensation produces the same or
different reactions in me as it does you, or in me at different times.
But what criterion have we for characterizing sensations at all,
if this is so? It is considerations such as this that lead either to
skepticism or to behaviorism. The behaviorist attempt to outlaw
the sensation itself breaks down, among many other reasons,
because I may, when I cannot observe a stimulus, infer correctly
what it is from a sensation (as when I infer that someone has
stabbed me in the back). But the comparison of one sensation with
another-which is presupposed, for example, in such correct
inferences to true conclusions-is only possible because a relatively
uniform intervening sensation between stimulus and behavioral
response is presupposed. Take the notions of tickles and itches.
We have to acquire these notions in terms both of their charac-
teristic causes and of the characteristic responses to such causes.
Pleasure as a reason for action 187
If tickling in certain parts of the body did not characteristically
produce laughter, we should lack the concept of a tickle. Again,
if a feeling did not characteristically produce an impulse to
scratch we should hesitate to call it an itch.
When I speak of a behavioral response, I mean a natural,
primary response; I may always learn to inhibit such responses,
and there is no logical limit to such learning. So the notion of an
itch that I do not any longer want to scratch or a tickle that pro-
duces no laughter is perfectly intelligible. So is the notion of a pain
that produces neither clutching nor screaming. But is it then true
that having used the behavioral concomitants to acquire a sensa-
tion vocabulary, I can then use the vocabulary without any
behavioral reference? Consider the notion of severe and less
severe pain. What can this be but pain to which the natural response
would be more and less extreme forms of avoidance or aversion
behavior? Or, if one prefers, pain which requires more or less in-
hibition of such behavior. Equally, the same pain must be pain
whose natural response would be avoidance behavior of the same
degree, although it must also be pain of the same kind-stabbing,
throbbing, or aching, for example. What otherwise could "the
same pain" mean? Suppose the reply to this is: the criterion of
identity is just that the two feel the same, they are phenomenolo-
gically identical. Can we make sense of the notion of two sensations
feeling the same but being associated with different natural
behavioral responses? If this were so, ascriptions of sameness of
sensation in different people would not be possible. Predicates
ascribing sensation would be egocentric predicates, which they
are not in fact. Of course, we have the concept of the phenomeno-
logical feel of sensations; but the vocabulary in which we express
it depends on a notion of sensations as comparable, which depends
in turn on the association of sensation with behavioral responses.
This dependence is neither purely contingent, as Hare supposes,
nor purely analytic. In fact, half our difficulties have arisen from
too rigid an application of an analytic/synthetic dichotomy.
Consider a parallel case, that of fear. We certainly have feelings of
fear, which sometimes simply arise in us inexplicably and which
we recognize by their phenomenological feel, although we may
know perfectly well that at that moment there is nothing to be
afraid of. Should we therefore conclude that the connection be-
tween feelings of fear and the belief that something harmful or
dangerous is at hand, which occurs in the majority of cases of fear,
is a purely contingent connection? This absurd conclusion is
avoided by distinguishing between primary cases of fear and
188 Against the Self-Images of the Age
secondary cases. We are only able to use the concept in the secon-
dary cases because we understand it in its primary application.
So also with pain. There may be cases where we wish to assert
an identity of sensation, sufficient to call the sensation "pain"
between the central cases where the notion of pain is conceptually,
though not analytically, tied to the notion of avoidance behavior
and the marginal cases where learned inhibition or physiological
interference has broken the link between the felt sensation and the
behavior. If we say this, we are of course committed to disagreeing
with Hare's view that we teach and learn the word "pain" by
means of a guess based on the presence of a purely contingent
criterion of pain, the external behavior. That Hare has to use
the word "guess" to express his view is important; if he were
right, there would always be room for doubt as to whether I had
learned to understand the word correctly. But this doubt would
apply to everybody, and where such a doubt applied there would
be no sense to the notion of a correct understanding of the word.
That is, the consequence to be drawn from Hare's view would in
fact be that we had no clear concept of pain at all.
The view that I have outlined allows of course for the occur-
rence of cases of many kinds where pain is not accompanied by
avoidance behavior; some of these cases present us with no diffi-
culty at all, others such as the lobotomy cases are genuinely hard
to understand. But it is crucial to note that the difficulty in under-
standing them does not arise from any philosophical theory about
the meaning of "pain" and kindred words but from the language
itself. The ordinary speaker is as puzzled as the philosopher by
the avowals of such patients. The same is true of masochism.
The relevance of all this to pleasure has now to be brought out.
It is, I hope, clear that there is no logical barrier to the existence
of a vocabulary of pleasurable sensations, in which the identifica-
tion of the sensation is tied to a certain type of behavioral response,
so that where the response was lacking we should have at least a
strong ground for inquiring whether the sensation could be the
same. What is said of sensations would apply equally to tastes and
smells. Let us apply the account I have given of pain to a parallel
case of pleasure. If I put my hand in the fire and let it roast there,
it can be explained either that I have trained myself to be heroi-
cally stoical in the face of pain and have some good reason for my
action or that I am physiologically abnormal or anesthetized. What
cannot be said is that I feel the pain just as anyone else would, am
neither stoical nor abnormal or anesthetized, but just do not mind
the pain. For my behaviour is a sufficient reason for concluding
Pleasureas a reasonfor action 189
that if I am not being stoical, then, whatever I feel, it is not in any
possible sense pain. Equally, if I when thirsty drink cold water
from a mountain stream, and then spit it out in disgust, it may be
explained that the water is polluted or that my mouth or throat is
in an abnormal condition. But what cannot be said is that there is
nothing wrong with the water and that my mouth and throat are in
a normal condition, but that I just find the taste of cold water,
which most people like, intolerable. For that someone finds such
a taste intolerable is a sufficient reason for concluding that the
taste cannot be the same taste that the rest of us experience. If
someone finds sexual sensations not pleasurable but painful, he
does not remark to himself that his likes and dislikes are those of a
minority; he looks for a physiological cause of his abnormality.
That is to say, we do in fact treat certain tastes and sensations
as pleasurable as such. If someone does not take pleasure in these,
we look for an explanation of his failure in terms of the state of
his body or his mind. The taste of cold water is not especially
pleasurable perhaps; the tastes of Guinness or Chateau Yquern
can be liked or disliked; we allow a wide range of variation to
taste. But there is a limit to this range beyond which we explain
lack of pleasure as we do lack of pain, in terms of the subject's
discrepancy from norms of desire, norms which are embodied in
parts of our vocabulary of pleasure and pain.
When I report what I enjoy, I am, unless there is reason to
believe that I am insincere, the final authority on the truth of my
report. When I report that an experience was or was not enjoyable
or a sensation pleasurable, I can without insincerity be saying
what is false. For the standard of the enjoyable and the pleasurable
is not private, but public. De gustibus est disputandum. To call
something pleasurable, therefore, is partly to say that it embodies
the object of desire from the standpoint of the norms of desire.
If I tell you that there is a fun-fair at the end of the pier I only give
you a reason for going to the end of the pier if you happen to like
fun-fairs and want to enjoy one now. If I tell you that fun-fairs
are pleasurable, I may give you reason to believe that you would
like them. Thus, statements about what is pleasurable do afford
us in a special sense reasons for action. So the statement which
I quoted from Dr. Kenny at the outset turns out to be true. It is
also of course true that the prospect of pleasure will not move
me to action unless I want pleasure at the given moment. But to
ask why I want pleasure is indeed, as Dr. Kenny suggested,
wrong-headed; because the notion of pleasure is the notion of a
property of certain activities and experiences which are treated as
Against the Self-Images of the Age
standard objects of desire, which help to define not merely the
desired, but the desirable. And to ask why I want what is desirable
would only have point if I was thought to be in some way abnormal
or perverse. That is, it may on occasion be asked why I should
want pleasure. Moreover there are other desirable objects as well
as pleasure; so that it makes sense to ask why I do not want pleasure
at this moment. But it is after all not therefore true that, if a man
wants pleasure, one can intelligently ask why. It is pleasant to dis-
cover that this obvious truth is an obvious truth after all.
The antecedents of action 1

I
We are haunted by the ghosts of dead concepts. The trouble with
ghosts is that they do not replace the living satisfactorily and yet
do not leave us with an entirely vacant hearth either. One such
dead concept is the concept of the will; its ghost is the philo-
sophical theory that the line which can be drawn between what is
a human action and what is a mere happening is such that actions
cannot have causes in the way that happenings can. When I speak
of the concept of the will I do not, of course, refer to pellucid
colloquialisms as in "Where there's a will there's a way" or "a
strong will"; I refer to the concept built up in post-medieval
philosophical psychology-in Hobbes, in Hume, and in Kant, for
example.
The exercise of the will in Hobbes distinguishes human action
from animal behavior because it presupposes a capacity for
deliberation. "In deliberation, the last Appetite, or Aversion,
immediately adhering to the action, or to the omission thereof, is
what we call the WILL; the Act (not the faculty) of Willing." 2
The exercise of the will in Hume distinguishes human action
from muscular or nervous responses because it involves con-
sciousness. "I desire it may be observed, that, by the will, I mean
nothing but the internal impression we feel, and are conscious of,
when we knowingly give rise to any new motion of our body, or
new perception of our mind." 3 The exercise of the will in Kant
marks out the human action from mere physical movement by
making action movement in accordance with and in obedience to
1 Reprinted from British Analytical Philosophy, edited by Bernard
Williams and Alan Montefiore (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul;
New York: Humanities Press, 1966).
2 Leviathan, I, 6.
3 Treatise, II, iii, 1.
191
Against the Self-Images of the Age
precepts or rules. "Everything in nature works according to
laws. Rational beings alone have the faculty of acting ... accord-
ing to principles, i.e., have a will." 1
The concept of acts of will which emerges from these quotations
is one according to which the will is a special kind of efficient cause,
the necessary cause of any human action. To make an act of will is
to make a conscious and rational decision. It is to embody a pre-
cept for action in an instruction to oneself. Saying to oneself "So
I will do such-and-such" sets one's limbs in motion. On occasion
one may fail to set one's limbs in motion, just as any other cause
may fail to operate if prior causes intervene. One's limbs are
paralysed or shot away. The first requirement in explaining an
action therefore is to assign a proximate cause to the action by
pointing to a prior act of will. In Hobbes and Hume appetite or
aversion inspire and inform such acts; in Kant the causal chains
which terminate in inclination may always fail to operate because of
the prior intervention of that uncaused cause, the autonomous
rational will obeying its self-imposed categorical imperative.
This ancestry makes it less surprising that the concept of acts of
will was later called upon to play opposite parts by different
philosophers. In the mechanistic psychology which the utilitarians
took over from Hartley all human actions are the determinate
effects of prior causes, and in the causal chain the act of will is the
immediate cause of the action. To some anti-determinist writers
the will is the intervening cause which prevents human action being
the mere outcome of events in the brain or the nervous system.
So participants of both determinism and free will invoke "the
will." For both parties, acts of will possess two characteristics
which are used by later writers to attack their existence: they are
events distinguishable from actions, always as a matter of contin-
gent fact preceding them; and they are events necessarily con-
nected with actions in that without them what followed would
not be an action. It was in this way that H. A. Prichard, for ex-
ample, wrote of acts of will. And it is in this way that his critics
have written of them in order to cast doubt on their existence.
But the point at which genuinely sharp criticism of the concept of
the will began was not here; it was the dualism which the concept
implied that first attracted hostile critical attention.

1 Fundamental Principles, II.


The antecedents of action 1 93

II
The doctrine of acts of will from Hume to Prichard was formu-
lated by philosophers who accepted a dualist view of body and
mind, and to this extent were true children of Descartes. This
dualism may have been refuted by Hegel, but in England, until
recently, Hegel and mystification were almost synonymous. The
refutation of Cartesian dualism was therefore in England the work
not of Hegel but of Professor Gilbert Ryle, a chapter of whose
The Concept of Mind is explicitly devoted to the will, but whose
argument throughout the book is extremely relevant.
The central argument of The Concept of Mind is that the criteria
for the application of those expressions which we use to describe
mental activity are all criteria of success or failure in performance
in the realm of overt behavior, and that therefore we neither
need nor have reason to postulate a realm of specifically mental
acts above and behind such behavior. Foremost among the
reasons which have misled philosophers into supposing that there
are such mental acts is a false view that those bodily movements
which are to count as human actions must have a special sort of
mental cause. The application of this doctrine to what I shall now
call the traditional view of acts of will is obvious.
Ryle in The Concept of Mind does not (at least nor usually) want
to deny the occurrence of any of the familiar "inner" events, such
as twinges or pains at one end of the scale or musings and interior
monologues at the other. What he does want to deny is that these
could have the characteristics which mental acts are alleged to have
in the traditional doctrine. In the case of acts of will, Ryle argues
that we cannot identify such acts (which he calls volitions) with
"such other familiar processes as that of resolving or making up
our minds to do something" or setting ourselves to do something.
For we know that there are many human actions which do not, in
fact, follow on such familiar processes, without thereby ceasing
to be human actions. But in the traditional doctrine any action
springs from an act of will. Hence these familiar processes and
events cannot be what the traditional doctrine wished to identify
as such acts.
Moreover, and here we return to Ryle's central argument, when
we describe actions by using such characteristic predicates as
"voluntary" or "responsible" or "done on purpose" or when we
insist that such-and-such a movement was not an action ("He was
1 94 Against the Self-Images of the Age
pushed," "He slipped"), we seek to establish the truth of our
description by reference to properties of the overt performance.
We never deem it logically appropriate to inquire as to the presence
or absence of acts of will. But if the traditional doctrine were
correct, this would be the appropriate and the only appropriate
question.
Ryle himself seems to place great weight on another line of
argument with which it is less easy to be happy.
No one ever says such things as that at 10 a.m. he was occupied
in willing this or that, or that he performed five quick and easy
volitions and two slow and difficult volitions between midday
and lunch-time .... Novelists describe the actions, remarks,
gestures and grimaces, the daydreams, deliberations, qualms
and embarrassments of their characters; but they never mention
their volitions. They would not know what to say about them.
This appeal to what "no one ever says" or to what everybody does
say is in itself ambiguous. It may simply be a way of underlining
the point that actions can be adequately characterized in all
possible ways without bringing in the notion of acts of will and
that the occurrence of such acts is therefore an unnecessary hypo-
thesis. But it suggests something else, in the form in which Ryle
advances it; namely, treating ordinary nonphilosophical modes
of speech as canonical for philosophical analysis.
If this is the thesis, it may once again be construed in two ways.
A weak and unobjectionable version of the thesis is simply that
any distinctions marked in ordinary language are likely to point to
differences which philosophers ignore at their peril. But there is
a stronger version of the thesis which must appear much more
disputable. This is the thesis that "ordinary language is in order,
just as it is" and that in the elucidation of what human action is,
common speech is not merely a source of suggested distinctions,
but provides us with hard criteria.
A quite different type of argument, which Ryle has used against
what he takes to be mythological mental acts, has been advanced by
A. I. Melden, specifically against the occurrence of volitions. 1
Melden argues that the concept of a volition involves an infinite
and vicious regress. For, on the traditional view, to move my limbs
I must first perform an act of will. But an act of will is itself an
action which I peform. And every action has to be preceded by an
act of will. So the performance of an act of will must itself be
preceded by an act of will, and so proceed ad infinitum. So an
1 Free Action (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1961), Ch. 5.
The antecedentsof action 195

infinite number of acts must precede any action and no action


could ever be performed. This argument is clearly valid and
effective, and, like Ryle, Melden supposes that whatever the
traditional theorists were talking about when they spoke of acts
of will, they were not speaking of our familiarly experienced making
of resolutions, coming to decisions, and so on. About this one
might be faintly dubious, if one remembered what Hobbes and
Hume and Kant actually said. But for the moment let us put these
doubts on one side.

III
The act of will was presented as the cause of the human action.
But if there are no acts of will, as Ryle and Melden argue, do
actions lack causes? Or have they quite other causes than acts of
will? The discussion which has followed on from attempts to
answer these questions can only be fruitful if we distinguish care-
fully between three senses of "cause," or at least between three
ways in which causal questions can arise. There is first of all what
is usually spoken of as Humean causality. This is the view of
causality which springs from one of Hume's several and incom-
patible accounts and which was further developed by J. S. Mill.
In this view one event is the cause of another, if and only if events
of the former type have uniformly been observed to precede
events of the latter type, and events of the latter type have uni-
formly been observed to follow events of the former type. The
occurrence of the earlier event is both a necessary and a sufficient
condition of the occurrence of the later event.
It is this concept of causality whose application has aroused
controversy over determinism. If actions are the determined
outcome of prior events, and presumably of prior physiological
events, it has seemed difficult to draw a distinct line between an
action and a mere reflex, and certainly difficult to draw the kind of
distinction which would lead us to impute responsibility in one
case and not in the other. It is, perhaps, because overtones of the
determinist controversy lie in the background that discussions of
the causality of actions have been directed so overwhelmingly
toward Humean causality. But, in fact, no discussion could be
carried to a successful conclusion unless it attended to at least two
other senses or analyses.
One of these is the sense of "cause" which is equivalent to
"necessary, but not necessarily sufficient, condition," a sense which
Against the Self-Images of the Age
is apparently rather than really simple. For very often when we
speak of "the" cause of an event, for instance at a coroner's court
in assigning responsibility for an accident, we point to a condition,
by itself necessary but not sufficient for the occurrence of the
accident. We do so when events were in train such that without
the condition in question being satisfied the event would not have
occurred. Tak.en by itself the condition was necessary but not
sufficient. Tak.en in conjunction with all the other prior events, its
satisfaction was sufficient to bring about the accident. So it is with
the ice patch on the otherwise safe road. The point to note here is
that what is by itself only a necessary condition for the occurrence
of an event can be used to bring about the event, or can be re-
ferred to in giving a causal explanation of the event provided only
that we know when its addition to other conditions is sufficient to
produce the event. But by referring to such an occurrence as a
cause we do not commit ourselves either to a generalization of the
form "Whenever ice patches occur there is an accident" or to one
of the form "There is never an accident unless there is an ice-
patch," but only to one of the form "Whenever such-and-such
other conditions occur, then, if there is an ice patch, there will be
an accident." The importance of generalizations of this type needs
much more attention, but for the moment we should only note
that the task of detecting necessary conditions as it leads up to this
type of generalization is inseparable from the task of detecting
sufficient conditions and thus of formulating generalizations of
the Humean type.
The third sense of "cause," or the third point about the sense
of "cause," is one that is not incompatible with but required by the
other two. This is the sense which was underlined by Professor
H. L.A. Hart and Mr. A. M. Honore in Causation and the Law.
Here a cause is a lever, a means of producing some other event.
There could be no well-established Humean generalizations
unless we were able to interfere with the course of nature and so
discover whether apparently uniform sequences were genuine ones
or not. But the Hart-Honore analysis brings out the importance
for causality of the concept of what would have happened if the
cause had not operated. All causal explanation presupposes a
background of generalizations about what occurs in the absence
of the cause. This is true of both cause understood in Hume's
sense and of cause understood as necessary condition.
The antecedents of action 197

IV
This very inadequate sketch of causality is a necessary prelude to
examining the two main attempts to show that actions cannot
have causes, at least in the Humean sense. The first of these derives
from an attempt to correct the assumption that the necessary and
sufficient conditions of human action are to be found in prior
physical events, an assumption which depends upon a companion
assumption that human actions are in fact only extremely complex
physical movements.
Against whom is this insistence directed? The answer is that a
great deal of physiology and psychology has taken it for granted
that this is correct. All attempts to explain human action by building
cybernetic models assume that human actions are of the same
kind as the movements of such models. The greatest of the
behavior theorists of modern psychology, Tolman and Hull, set
themselves the explicit goal of explaining human actions as very
complex exemplifications of fundamentally simple patterns of
physical movement. Those philosophers who have tried to show
the falsity of this have clearly wanted a concept or set of concepts
which will perform the function that the traditional concept
of the will performed. But they have moved in a quite different
direction.
In an article which tries to show that Hobbes and Hull were
both essentially pursuing the same goal of mechanical explana-
tions of human action, R. S. Peters and H. Tajfel have pointed
out that bodily movements cannot be the genus of which human
actions are a species, because the same bodily movements can be
used in performing quite different actions and the same action
can be performed by means of quite different bodily movements.
So these bodily movements which are employed in writing a man's
name may be used in signing a check, or giving an autograph, or
authorizing a representative. Equally, the same action of paying a
debt may be performed by those bodily movements involved in
signing a check or by those involved in handing over coin. In
other words, the criteria which we imply in judging that two bodily
movements are the same or different are quite other than the
criteria which we use in judging that two actions are the same or
different.
Actions then cannot be identified with bodily movements. But
while in the traditional view actions were bodily movements plus
Against the Self-Images of the Age
something else-namely, an act of will-for the more recent view
this is equally incorrect and misleading. For to speak of human
actions is to speak at a different logical level from that at which we
speak of bodily movements. To call something an action is to
invite the application of a quite different set of predicates from
that which we invite if we call something a bodily movement. If I
say "I moved my arm," I do not say either the same or more than I
say if I say "My arm moved." I bring what occurred under a
different form of description. We can bring out this difference in a
number of ways. First, if we ask "Why did your arm move?" we
invite a causal answer including perhaps a story about conditioned
reflexes and a story about muscles and nerves. If we ask "Why did
you move your arm?" we invite a story about intentions and
purposes. Equally, if on being asked to explain a piece of be-
havior I start to give an account in terms of muscular and nervous
mechanisms, I thereby treat the behavior as a piece of physical
movement and not as an action. If, on the other hand, I talk about
purposes, goals, desires, intentions, or the like, I thereby treat the
behavior as an action. Secondly, if I say "I moved my arm," then
the question "What reason did you have for doing that?" is
always in place, even if the answer is, "I do not know why I did it."
To say "I do not know" here is not to say "There is a reason, but
I am ignorant of it" (except in psychoanalytic contexts, which
demand special treatment). It is to say in effect "I had no reason,
though I might have had." And nobody can know my reasons or
lack of them, unless I tell or otherwise betray them. J-lere I have
special and unique authority. But when it is a case where it is
appropriate to say "My arm just moved," I have no such special
authority in giving explanations. What is needed is not the
authority of the agent as to his own intentions and purposes but
the authority of the physiologist on matters concerning condi-
tioned reflexes, nerves, and muscles.
Thirdly, in the standard cases at least where I say "I moved my
arm," there is no room for the question "How do you know?" The
reason for this can be brought out as follows. The point of asking
"How do you know?" is to ask for the credentials of a claimant to
knowledge in cases where the claimant to knowledge may be in
either a better or worse position to back up his claim. "Pegasus
won the 3.30." "How do you know?" "I was on the course," "I
saw it on television," "My bookmaker told me," "I saw it in a
dream" are all possible answers-of quite different value. But
where self-knowledge of my own present actions is concerned,
there is no question of being in a better or worse position to know.
The antecedents of action 1 99

And so there is no room for the question, "How do you know what
you are doing?" But there is room for the question "How do you
know?" where not actions but bodily movements are the subject
of the inquiry. Usually, of course, the answer is very simple:
"How do you know your arm moved?" "I felt it move," But from
a partially anesthetized man, lying so that he could not see his arm,
the answer "I saw it in the mirror" would make sense. And so
would any other answer which appealed to observation or inference.
Whereas this type of answer would make no sense as a reply to
the question: "How do you know that you moved your arm?"
(Indeed, this question, as I have already pointed out, lacks point
except perhaps in some very special contexts. It does not follow
that a man may not say "I moved my arm" outside those contexts
and be mistaken. Where the question "How do you know?" lacks
application there is still room for error.)
Fourthly, in cases where it is appropriate to say "I moved my
arm" rather than "My arm moved" the future tense used before
the event would express an intention, not a prediction, if used in
the first person. Moreover, if it is appropriate to say of the event
afterward "I moved my arm," then neither I nor anyone else
could predict that I would move my arm except on the basis of a
knowledge of my intentions. It does not however follow, as has
sometimes been argued, that where an event is the object of my
intention it cannot be the object of my prediction. What does
follow is that the expression of my intention is never the expression
of my prediction. But the expression of an intention and the ex-
pression of a prediction can be closely related; for if I express an
intention, I license others to predict. Of course, whether they are
wise to predict or not depends upon the evidence they possess as
to how far I am usually faithful to my declared intentions. Now
their beliefs (or their knowledge) on this point will be expressible
upon occasion in the form of Humean generalizations. Moreover,
I can acquire such knowledge about myself. A man may come to
recognize his own reliability or unreliability. Consequently, even
if it is psychologically out of the way, it is not conceptually odd
for a man to say "I fully intend to do it tomorrow, but I know how
unreliable I am, and so perhaps you are right and I will fail to do
it again tomorrow." What is more, in the very framing of his
intentions a man's self-knowledge and predictions about his own
reliability inevitably come into play. Hence, in cases where it is
appropriate to say "I shall move my arm," prediction is dependent
upon knowledge of intention, but intention need not be entirely
divorced from prediction ; nevertheless, prediction depends not
200 Against the Self-Images of the Age
at all on knowledge of intention where it is in place to say "My
arm will move."
Fifthly, the point of distinguishing between "My arm moved"
and "I moved my arm" is brought out very clearly in just those
borderline cases where we are uncertain which to say. We are all
familiar-from novels if not from experience-with cases where,
as we say,' the body seems to have taken control. In Sartre's
novel L' Age de Raison the hero-no, the protagonist-Mathieu,
intends to say to his mistress "I love you" and finds himself saying
"I don't love you." Do we describe this as something he said or as
words (or perhaps sounds) that come out of his mouth? Is it action
or bodily movement? How we answer the question in this parti-
cular context does not matter for our present purposes. What does
matter is that we cannot evade asking it, that we cannot escape
the distinction between action and bodily movement.
Yet what follows about causality? Only that if we are to look
for the causes of human actions, then we shall be in conceptual
error if we look in the direction of the causes of the physical
movements involved in the performance of the actions. It does not
follow that there is no direction in which it would be fruitful to
search for antecedent events which might function as causes.
What has suggested this further conclusion is the way in which
the investigation of concepts very close to the concept of action,
such as that of intention, has been carried through. Wittgenstein
wrote: " 'I am not ashamed of what I did then, but of the inten-
tion which I had.' 1 And didn't the intention reside also in what I
did. . . .'' 1 Just because the intention resides in the action, it
comes too close to it to play a causal role; nor could we say what
the action was, apart from specifying the intention to at least some
degree. An intention, unlike a cause, does not stand in an external,
contingent relation to an action. When Miss G. E. M. Anscombe
investigates the concept systematically in Intention, the whole
discussion moves away from any kind of explanation in terms of
causality, a topic to which Miss Anscombe alludes only in rare
passages. One, but only one, reason why this is so can be brought
out by considering how either in the kind of case which Miss
Anscombe would classify as one of "mental causality" (I am
startled by a noise and jump) or in the hard case where I make a
decision and later act on it (with which Miss Anscombe does not
deal) we should be missing the point if we looked for a Humean
generalization to connect the noise and the jump or the decision
and the action. I can know that I jumped because of the noise or
1 Philosophical Investigations, Part I, para. 644.
The antecedents of action 201

that I acted because of the decision and know perfectly well that
the generalizations "Whenever there is a noise of that sort, I
jump in this way" and "Whenever I decide to do something, I
do it" are false. Hence this kind of explanation of these actions at
least must be in terms other than those of causality. Beginning
from this point, the argument is sometimes generalized in the
following way.
It is bodily movements which are to be causally explained and
not human actions. Human actions are made intelligible by re-
ference to intentions, purposes, decisions, and desires. These do
not function as causes. They do not function as causes for at least
two distinct reasons. The first is that to say "He did it because he
intended so-and-so," or "He did it because he decided to" or
"He did it because he wanted to" is in each case not necessarily
to refer to two separately identifiable events, the doing on the one
hand and the intending or desiring or deciding on the other.
There may be cases where we first frame an intention, come to a
decision, or experience a desire and then act; but the concepts of
intention, decision, and desire are equally applicable where the
action is itself the expression of intention, decision, or desire and to
refer to our intention, decision, or desire in either explanation or
justification of our action is not to refer to an antecedent event.
But a cause must, so it is argued, always be a separate event from
that which is its effect. So intentions, decisions, and desires can-
not be causes. Secondly, intentions, decisions, and desires cannot
be causes, for they are not causally but logically related to the
relevant actions. How do I know that this intention relates to this
action? Not by any observed correlation such as would be rele-
vant in the case of causality. But because both intention and
action are mine and the intention contained a description of the as
yet unrealized action. The action is related to the intention as
being what is described in the forming of the intention. "I'll have
another cigarette in ten minutes' time." When I light up in ten
minutes, I am faithful to my intention, but my intention has not
made me light up.
Considerations such as these are invoked to support one of two
theses. Either the weaker assertion is made which I have already
described, that actions are to be explained in terms of intentions
and kindred concepts and therefore, insofar as this is the case,
they are not to be explained causally ; or else the stronger assertion
that causal explanations are out of court altogether so far as actions
are concerned: Unfortunately, the most extended statement of this
case is ambiguous to a certain extent. Melden says:
202 Against the Self-Images of the Age
What I shall be concerned to deny ... is that the term "cause"
when employed in these sciences (physics and physiology) is
applicable to those matters which, familiarly and on a common-
sense level, we cite in order to explain action: the motives,
desires, choices, decisions, etc., of human beings. I do not,
of course, deny that there are appropriate senses of "cause"
which can be intelligibly employed in these cases.1
And again he writes:
Indeed, it must appear problematic at best that the physiological
psychologist who purports to be attempting to explain human
action is addressing himself to his ostensible subject matter. 2
While still later he says :
Here (in cases where I am predicting what someone whom I
know will do) nothing is hidden; it is because I understand him,
not because I am aware of events transpiring in some alleged
mechanism of his mind or body, that I am able to say what he
will do. 3
These quotations can lend themselves to an interpretation in
which all that Melden claims is that to explain actions citing
purposes, intentions, desires, and the like is not to assign causes
(in the Humean sense) or to another interpretation in which
Melden is claiming that causal interpretations of human actions
are ruled out of court altogether on conceptual grounds. The
second quotation-apart from the fence-sitting use of "it must
appear problematic at best"-seems to ensure that the latter is
meant, but what I will presently try to do is to show that while the
latter thesis is certainly untenable, even in the former interpreta-
tion, Melden's thesis needs amendment. Before that, however, an
even more radical version of this view must be considered. It is
more radical because it is more systematic. It arrives at the same
conclusions as Melden's, but it derives them from independent
foundations. The best-known exposition of this point of view is
Dr. Friedrich Waismann's in Language Strata. Waismann wished
to campaign against the view that language is unitary, all of a piece,
that truth, rationality, and meaningfulness are one and the same
for every sort of statement. Against this he urged the notion of
language as composed of different strata, each with its own criteria
1 Free Action, pp. 16-17.
1 Ibid., p. 72.
3 Ibid., p. 208.
The antecedentsof action 203
of truth and meaning. An expression may be ambiguous in that it
can figure in different contexts in different strata, and so take on
different meanings. With this thesis so far my present argument
does not require me to raise any questions. But Waismann then,
although he allows that there are relationships between strata,
characterizes the ambiguity of the word "action" in such a way as
to exclude relationship between the stratum in which it is proper
to speak of causes and that in which it is proper to speak of motives.
It follows that anything which can be explained by reference to
motives cannot be explained by reference to causes and vice versa.

In like manner we say that each stratum has a logic of its own
and that this logic determines the meaning of certain basic terms.
In some respects this is obvious. Whether a melody is a sequence
of air-vibrations, of a succession of musical notes, or a message
of the composer, depends entirely on the way you describe it.
Similarly, you may look at a game of chess, or on the pattern of a
carpet from very different aspects and you will then see in them
very different things. Notice how all these words-"melody,"
"game of chess," etc.-take on a systematic ambiguity according
to the language stratum in which you talk. The same applies to
"doing a sum," "writing a letter," or to any action indeed. An
action may be viewed as a series of movements caused by some
physiological stimulus in the "Only rats, no men" sense; or as
something that has a purpose or meaning irrespective of the way
its single links are produced. An action in the first sense is deter-
mined by causes, an action in the second sense by motives or
reasons.It is generally believed that an action is determined both
by causes and by motives. But if the causes determine the action,
no room is left for motives, and if the motives determine the
action, no room is left for causes. Either the system of causes is
complete, then it is not possible to squeeze in a motive; or the
system of motives is complete, then it is not possible to squeeze
in a cause. "Well now, do you believe that if you are writing a
letter you are engaged in two different activities?" No; I mean
that there are two different ways of looking at the thing; just as
there are two different ways of looking at a sentence: as a s~ries
of noises. produced by a human agent; or as a vehicle for thought.
For a series of noises there may be causes but no reasons; for a
series of words expressing thought there may be reasons, but no
causes. What is understood is that the word "action" has a
systematic ambiguity. 1 (pp. 30-31).
1 Language Strata, pp, 30--31.
Against the Self-Images of the Age

V
What is at stake in these arguments? Not only philosophical
clarity, but also the question of the nature of the human sciences.
For if philosophical argument can show that actions cannot have
causes, then a good deal of science is fatally confused, since
scientists do in fact attempt to offer causal explanations of action.
Some physiologists have, indeed, done us a disservice by offering
explanations of reflexes and calling these explanations of action,
but in more than one field there appear to be genuine, if tentative,
causal explanations of action. I refer to criminology and also to
the study of the effects of drugs. (The study of hypnosis is
interesting, but raises special issues.)
Some changes in the chemistry of the body which are brought
about by taking drugs correlate with highly specific alterations in
behavior. More than this, we can alter the way in which people
behave by inducing such changes in body chemistry. These
changes range from the medical use of insulin in highly artificial
laboratory experiments to buying a man a drink. What is correlated
with the chemical change is a type of action and not just a type of
bodily movement. That is to say, the framing of intentions,
deliberations, reflection on wishes and desires and the like all play
their normal roles. It may be that in many cases the type of action
which is produced by the chemical changes cannot be narrowly
specified. That is, we can say that to give this type of man this
type of drug will make him act more irritably or unscrupulously
or excitably rather than specify in more detail what he will do.
But in these cases we are none the less involved in explaining
behavior.
Again, in criminology the work that has shown that there is a
hereditary element in criminality is much to the point. The key
studies on inherited characteristics in human beings are those
which compare the degree to which such characteristics are shared
by two siblings in the case of monozygotic and dizygotic twins
respectively, for it would seem an unassailable conclusion that a
clearly higher concordance in cases of monozygotic twins would
indicate a hereditary factor. This is how the existence of a
hereditary factor in tuberculosis was established for a study in
New York in 1934, for example, which showed a 63 per cent
concordance in monozygotic twins and only an 18 per cent con-
cordance in dizygotic, while one in London in 1957 showed a 30
The antecedentsof action 205

per cent concordance in monozygotic and only a 13 per cent


concordance in dizygotic. Now, in exactly the same way, a
hereditary factor in adult criminality can be established. For on the
basis of five studies we have a concordance with monozygotic
twins of 68 per cent and one with dizygotic of only 35 per cent. I
need to insist that what were studied here were criminal actions,
and that the fact that nobody supposes that heredity is more than a
partial (and perhaps not enormously important) explanation of
criminality does not make this any the less a causal explanation.
Nor, if it makes sense to use such figures to provide an explanation,
could it make nonsense if the figures turned out to be different,
to be, for example, 100 per cent in the case of monozygotic
twins and zero per cent in the case of dizygotic. This would make
our explanation somewhat less partial.
What then are we to make of this situation in which some
philosophers appear to assert that causal explanations of human
action cannot be given, while some scientists assert that they have
produced them? Can we safely treat the scientists as we would
treat men who claimed to have invented a perpetual motion machine?
Or are the philosophers like the old lady at the zoo who looked
at the giraffe and said "It's impossible"?

VI

Let us begin with the most general form of the argument that
actions cannot have causes, Waismann's. It is beyond the scope of
this essay to question in general terms the widely influential, but
profoundly misleading view of language contained in Waismann's
paper. What one must note is that unless there were expressions
and criteria which transcended the divisions between his language
strata, he could not distinguish them in the way he does. He can,
for instance, recognize, and has to recognize in order to specify
the ambiguity of "action" in the way he does, that certain move-
ments caused by physiological stimuli use the movements which
are the "single links" of this particular action and of no other.
So that we are able to say "These movements" (one stratum of
language) "belong to this action" (a quite different stratum). It
follows that statements are not necessarily confined to one particular
logical order or type or stratum (however these are specified).
And now we have to note that an expression that cannot be so
confined is the word "cause" and its logical kith and kin. For
Waismann speaks of the bodily movement by which an action is
206 Against the Self-Images of the Age
"produced." And "produce" is certainly a causal verb. Moreover,
he speaks of a melody as though to speak of a sequence of air
vibrations is to remain within one language stratum, but to speak
of a succession of musical notes is to move to another. But clearly
one cause, in a perfectly acceptable and unambiguous sense of
"cause," of a set of notes succeeding one another in a piece of music
to which we are listening is precisely the sequence of air vibrations
which the orchestra have produced. Without having read Wais-
mann, we might well want to say that the notion of color is of a
different logical order from that of a wavelength of light. But we
unhesitatingly explain alterations in color as caused by changes in
the wavelength of light. So that, although the notion of bodily
movements may be of a different logical order from that of an
action, it certainly cannot follow that the word "cause" is restricted
to the stratum to which "bodily movement" belongs and denied to
the stratum to which "action" belongs.
If we then disallow Waismann's contentions, the arguments that
actions cannot have causes are best dealt with not by denying the
importance of the type of example to which such arguments
appeal, but by considering counter-examples. The suggestion will
be that all the ordinary senses of causality apply in some cases to
human actions and that therefore the "ordinary language" use of
"cause" in this connection is by no means as remote from Humean
causality as some suggest. (For an "ordinary language" use, con-
sider: "The Minister, receiving the Woman at her father's or
friend's hands, shall cause the Man with his right hand to take the
Woman by her right hand ... " [Book of Common Prayer, Form
of Solemnization of Matrimony.]
The first example is of giving a reason or affording a motive as
causes. I may discover that when you are in a certain frame of
mind I can get you to act by giving you information which
affords a motive or a reason. Your action bears testimony to the
fact that it was this motive or reason on which you were acting
(as returning a ring with a reproachful letter is testimony that the
girl's motive arises from her information about the man's behavior).
Thus the connection between affording the motive and the
action is not one of a Humean kind; we do not depend on a
universal generalization of whose truth we need to be assured in
order to make the connection. Even if another occasion affording
the same kind of motive does not produce the same action, we
should not have grounds for doubting what caused the girl to act
in the way she did on the first occasion. And the word "caused" is in
place precisely because of our third sense of causality. Affording a
The antecedents of action
motive or a reason is performing a separately identifiable_and
desirable act, the performance of which is a lever that produces as
its effects an action. And it is quite compatible with the thesis that
motives, reasons, decisions, and intentions cannot be causes that
affording motives, giving reasons, giving grounds for decisions,
and for framing intentions can be. Nor is this merely something
that others can do to me; I can in deliberation do this to myself.
(This is not to be committed to the view that deliberation is
always conversation with oneself, but only to the view that it can
on occasion be.)
Secondly, "the" cause of an action may, like "the" cause of an
accident, be a necessary condition, the satisfaction of which is with
other circumstances sufficient to produce the action. An insult
may not make me violent when I am sober; and when I am even
mildly drunk I may be extremely pleasant except when and until I
am insulted. So the insult plays in relation to the action the part
that the icy patch on the road plays in relation to the accident.
Thirdly, we are already well on the way to formulating explana-
tions of actions in terms of Humean causality. I am puzzled by
why I become angry when playing cards. Both others and myself
presently observe that it occurs five minutes after I have started to
lose. This connection is uniformly observed to hold until I
become aware of it. People who wish to make me angry have
learned that I become angry and perform angry actions if they
bring about my defeat at cards. This is a perfect case of Humean
causality and nothing is affected if I change my behavior on
discovering its cause. For the generalization which needed to be
discovered by observation was that "Whenever I am losing at cards,
and so long as I do not know what is going to happen to my
behavior as a result, I shortly after become angry." Or it may
be that I cannot alter my behavior. Obviously, it does not follow
that I am inevitably going to be angry; but if I wish to avoid
angry behavior then I must not lose at cards, and probably I
must not play cards.
These examples only skim the topic of the causality of action.
What they do show is the danger of any generalization of the
form "Actions cannot have causes" or even "Actions cannot have
Humean causes." Such generalizations are necessarily as erroneous
as were the generalizations of the eighteenth-century mechanists
who thought of every action as caused. What we need is a much
fuller characterization of the concept of the human person in which
the role of both causes on the one hand and of motives, reasons,
and intentions on the other will become clear. But about two
208 Against the Self-Images of the Age
distorting features of the discussion hitherto we can now perhaps
become clear.
The first is that the dichotomy "logical connection" or "causal
connection" is much too easy, here as elsewhere. Consider the
kind of case where an insult always leads to taking offense. "Every
Celt when insulted uses whatever weapons lie to hand" can be the
expression of a good Humean generalization (even if false). Now
the description of the first action as "an insult" and of the second
as "taking offense" brings them under descriptions which are
conceptually and internally related. But the two events are
separately identified and we can correlate them. We know what it
would be for the causal generalization to be falsified by an insult not
causing offense or offense being taken without insult. The root
error here is to think of actions as standing in relationship to the
agents' motives and reasons or to other agents' behavior inde-
pendently of the alternative forms of description under which
behavior can fall.
The second distorting factor is the fear of determinism. This
perhaps springs from accepting a determinist view of the Hume-
Mill concept of causality. But to show that an action is caused is
not necessarily to show that it must have happened, that the
agent could not alter what he did. For to assign a cause to a
happening is to go some way to informing us both how to produce
and how to inhibit the happening in question. It follows from
this that to assign causal explanations to actions is not to show
that the actions in question are inevitable and unalterable. Nor
does it even follow that if the explanations in question are explana-
tions of my actions, I cannot alter them. But it certainly does
follow that the more I know about possible and actual causal
explanations of my behavior the more likely I am to be able to
intervene successfully and control what I do. Free, responsible,
controlled behavior is, then, behavior where I have at least the
possibility of successful intervention (though this is to state only a
necessary, and not a sufficient, condition for being entitled to
characterize a piece of behavior in this way).
This argument needs one addition. My freedom as an agent
depends upon my ability to frame intentions which are capable of
being implemented. This capability is dependent on the reliability
of my beliefs about the world and about myself: it is not just that
given motives, desires, and intentions of a certain sort, I act. A
presupposition of successful action is a knowledge of what I will
do unless I intervene in various ways. So the concept of intention
cannot be understood in isolation from the role of belief and
The antecedents of action 209
knowledge in our behavior. The way in which this is so is brought
out most clearly by the argument of Stuart Hampshire in Thought
and Action, especially Chapter 3. Hampshire uses the distinction
between intention and prediction in a much more illuminating way
than it is used by those who are trying to separate action and
causation. For, as I argued earlier, there is a positive connection
between intention and prediction. Unless I am able to predict what
will happen if I do and again what will happen if I do not frame a
given intention, I am in no position to frame intentions at all.
Thus, what I can intend depends upon what I can predict, and
the dependence of the concept of human action upon the concept of
intention does not exclude the possibility of prediction based on
causal explanation from the realm of human action, but actually
depends upon that possibility. That others can predict my actions
does not matter unless they are able to predict what these are, no
matter what my intentions are. My freedom consists, as Hampshire
has argued, not in my unpredictability but in my ability to form
clear intentions and to implement them. And this freedom depends
on my ability to intervene in causal sequences, including those
which have resulted in parts of my own behavior to date.
The mistake that we might make in conclusion would be to
suppose that because my main argument has been an attack on
the generalizations of others, nothing definitive follows from it.
I followed through the attack on the doctrine of acts of will and
showed that the corollary to its destruction was the need to
elaborate a much more complex view of the person. But some
very simple conceptual truths still need emphasis, and one of them
at least belonged to the view of the will which Ryle and Melden
attempted to destroy.
The exponents of the traditional doctrine of acts of will were
clearly wrong to hold that every act of a rational agent is preceded
by an act of will which is its cause. They took what they thought
to be the paradigm case of rational action, deliberation leading
to conscious decision which issues in action, and supposed
that the characteristics of the paradigm case must hold in every
case. But were they wrong in their characterization of the
paradigm? Where I act without deliberation or on impulse,
where I provide one of the cases which appear to Ryle and Melden
to destroy the traditional doctrine, what makes me responsible
for what I do? Or where causal explanations of my anger are in
place, what, if anything, makes me responsible? Presumably, that I
could, had I reason so to frame an intention, decide not to do what
I in fact do, not to let my impulses have their way or not to be
210 Against the Self-Images of the Age
angry; that I could deliberate (the "could" means here that it
makes sense to speak of my deliberating; in many actual occasions I
might have no time or opportunity to deliberate) and decide on
some other course of action. In other words, that I could perform
an act of will in the traditional sense. If we read Hobbes, Hume
and Kant as characterizing not the necessary prerequisites for
something to be classed as an action but as characterizing the type
of action which one must be able to perform on occasion, the type
of intervention, inhibiting one course of action or unleashing
another, which one must be able to make on occasion if one is to
be classed as a responsible and rational agent at all, then the
arguments of Ryle and Melden become irrelevant. For acts of will
are, as the traditional authors clearly state, the familiar and un-
assailable processes of resolving, deciding, and intending and not
the mysterious and occult "volitions" with which Ryle and Melden
make so much play. There is nothing here with which novelists
and ordinary agents are not familiar in their everyday transactions ;
and there is no requirement that every action shall be preceded by
a volition, which may result in an infinite regress. There is only
the requirement that we shall recognize that it is in virtue of what
they can be and not of what they always are that men are called
rational animals.
The idea of a social science 1

My aim in this essay is to express dissent from the position taken


in Mr. Peter Winch's book 2 whose title is also the title of this
essay. Winch's book has been the subject of a good deal of mis-
understanding, and he has been accused on the one hand of
reviving familiar and long-refuted views3 and on the other of
holding views so eccentric in relation to social science as it actually
is that they could not possibly have any practical effect on the
conduct of that science.4 In fact, however, Winch articulates a
position which is at least partly implicit in a good deal of work
ah-eady done, notably in anthropology, and he does so in an
entirely original way. He writes in a genre recognizable to both
sociologists and philosophers. Talcott Parsons and Alain Touraine
have both found it necessary to preface their sociological work by
discussions of norms and actions and have arrived at rather different
conclusions from those of Winch; the importance of his work
is therefore undeniable.

I
"Wittgenstein says somewhere that when one gets into philo-
sophical difficulties over the use of some of the concepts of
our language, we are like savages confronted with something
from an alien culture. I am simply indicating a corollary of this:
that sociologists who misinterpret an alien culture are like philo-
sophers getting into difficulty over the use of their own concepts."
1 © Aristotelian Society, 1967. Reprinted from the Aristotelian Soeiety
Supplementary Volume 1967, pp. 95-u4.
2 The Idea of a Social Science (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul,
1958).
3 See, for example, Richard Rudner, The Philosophy of Social Science

(Englewood, N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1967), pp. 81-83.


4 See A. R. Louch's review in Inquiry, 1963, :273.
211
212 Against the Self-Images of the Age
This passage (p. 114) epitomizes a central part of Winch's thesis
with its splendid successive characterizations of the figure baffled
by an alien culture; a savage at one moment, he has become a
sociologist at the next. And this is surely no slip of the pen.
According to Winch, the successful sociologist has simply learned
all that the ideal native informant could tell him ; sociological
knowledge is the kind of knowledge possessed in implicit and
partial form by the members of a society rendered explicit and
complete (p. 88). It is not at first entirely clear just how far
Winch is at odds in this contention with, for example, Malinowski,
who insisted that the native Trobriander's account of Trobriand
society must be inadequate, that the sociologists' account of
institutions is a construction not available to the untutored
awareness of the native informant. 1 For Winch of course is
willing to allow into the sociologist's account concepts "which
are not taken from the forms of activity which he is inves-
tigating; but which are taken rather from the context of
his own investigation," although he adds that "these technical
concepts will imply a prior understanding of those other
concepts which belong to the activities under investigation."
Perhaps this might seem sufficient to remove the apparent
disagreement of Winch and Malinowski, until we remember
the conclusion of Malinowski's critique of the native informant's
view. The sociologist who relies upon that view, he says, "obtains
at best that lifeless body of laws, regulations, morals and con-
ventionalities which ought to be obeyed, but in reality are often
only evaded. For in actual life rules are never entirely con-
formed to, and it remains, as the most difficult but indispensable
part of the ethnographer's work, to ascertain the extent and
mechanism of the deviations." 2 This makes two points clear.
First, Malinowski makes a distinction between the rules
acknowledged in a given society and the actual behavior of
individuals in that society, whereas Winch proclaims the proper
object of sociological study to be that behavior precisely as
rule-governed. The second is that in the study of behavior
Malinowski is willing to use notions such as that of mechanism
which are clearly causal; whereas Winch warns us against
comparing sociological understanding with understanding in
terms of "statistics and causal laws" and says of the notion of
1 Bronislaw Malinowski, The Sexual Life of Savages in North-Western

Melanesia (New York: Harcourt, Brace & Jovanovich; London: Routledge


& Kegan Paul, 1932), pp. 425-29.
a Ibid., pp. 428-29.
The idea of a socialscience 213

function, so important to Malinowski, that it "is a quasi-causal


notion, which it is perilous to apply to social institutions" (p. 116 ).
It does appear therefore that although Winch and Malinowski
agree in seeing the ideal native informant's account of his own
social life as incomplete by comparison with the ideal sociologist's
account, they do disagree about the nature of that incompleteness
and about how it is to be remedied. My purpose in this essay
will be to defend Malinowski's point of view on these matters
against Winch's, but this purpose can only be understood if one
reservation is immediately added. It is that in defending Malinow-
ski's views on these points I must not be taken to be endorsing
Malinowski's general theoretical position. I have in fact quoted
Malinowski on these matters, but I might have quoted many other
social scientists. For on these matters Malinowski speaks with the
consensus.

II
"A regularity or uniformity is the constant recurrence of the
same kind of event on the same kind of occasion; hence statements
of uniformities presuppose judgments of identity. But ...
criteria of identity are necessarily relative to some rule: with the
corollary that two events which count as qualitatively similar from
the point of view of one rule would count as different from the
point of view of another. So to investigate the type of regularity
studied in a given inquiry is to examine the nature of the rule
according to which judgments of identity are made in that inquiry.
Such judgments are intelligible only relatively to a given mode
of human behavior, governed by its own rules" (pp. 83-84).
This passage is the starting point for Winch's argument that
J. S. Mill was mistaken in supposing that to understand a social
institution is to formulate empirical generalizations about regu-
larities in human behavior, generalizations which are causal and
explanatory in precisely the same sense that generalizations in
the natural sciences are. For the natural scientist makes the
relevant judgments of identity according to his rules (that is,
the rules incorporated in the practice of his science) ; whereas the
social scientist must make his judgments of identity in accordance
with the rules governing the behavior of those whom he studies.
Their rules, not his, define the object of his study. "So it is quite
mistaken in principle to compare the activity of a student of a
form of social behavior with that of, say, an engineer studying
the working of a machine. If we are going to compare the social
214 Against the Self-Images of the Age
student to an engineer, we shall do better to compare him to an
apprentice engineer who is studying what engineering-that is,
the activity of engineering-is all about" (p. 88).
What the type of understanding which Winch is commending
consists in is made clearer in two other passages. He says that
although prediction is possible in the social sciences, it "is quite
different from predictions in the natural sciences, where a falsified
prediction always implies some sort of mistake on the part of
the predictor: false or inadequate data, faulty calculation, or
defective theory" (pp. 91-92). This is because "since understand-
ing something involves understanding its contradictory, someone
who, with understanding, performs X must be capable of envis-
aging the possibility of doing not-X" (p. 91 ). Where someone
is following a rule, we cannot predict how he will interpret what is
involved in following that rule in radically new circumstances;
where decisions have to be made, the outcome "cannot be definitely
predicted," for otherwise "we should not call them decisions."
These points about prediction, if correct, reinforce Winch's
arguments about the difference between the natural sciences and
the social sciences. For they amount to a denial of that symmetry
between explanation and prediction which holds in the natural
sciences. (It has been argued often enough that this symmetry
does not hold in the natural sciences; Professor Adolf Griinbaum's
arguments in Chapter 9 of the Philosophy of Space and Time
seem a more than adequate rebuttal of these positions.) But when
we consider what Winch says here about decision, it is useful to
take into account at the same time what he says about motives
and reasons. Winch treats these as similar in this respect: that
they are made intelligible by reference to the rules governing
the form of social life in which the agent participates. So Winch
points out that "one can act 'from considerations' only where
there are accepted standards of what is appropriate to appeal to"
(p. 82) and argues against Ryle that the "law-like proposition"
in terms of which someone's reasons must be understood concerns
not the agent's disposition "but the accepted standards of reason-
able behavior current in his society" (p. 81).
From all this one can set out Winch's view of understanding
and explanations in the social sciences in terms of a two-stage
model. An action is first made intelligible as the outcome of
motives, reasons, and decisions; and is then made further in-
telligible by those motives, reasons, and decisions being set in the
context of the rules of a given form of social life. These rules
logically determine the range of reasons and motives open to a
The idea of a social science 215

given set of agents and hence also the range of decisions open to
them. Thus Winch's contrast between explanation in terms of
causal generalizations and explanations in terms of rules turns
out to rest upon a version of the contrast between explanations
in terms of causes and explanations in terms of reasons. This latter
contrast must therefore be explored, and the most useful way
of doing this will be to understand better what it is to act for a
reason.
Many analyses of what it is to act for a reason have written
into them an incompatibility between acting for a reason and
behaving from a cause, just because they begin from the apparently
simple and uncomplicated case where the action is actually
performed, where the agent had one and only one reason for
performing it, and where no doubt could arise for the agent as to
why he had done what he had done. By concentrating attention
upon this type of example, a basis is laid for making central to the
analyses a contrast between the agent's knowledge of his own
reasons for acting and his and others' knowledge of causes of his
behavior. For clearly in such a case the agent's claim that he did
X for reason Y does not seem to stand in need of any warrant
from a generalization founded upon observation; while equally
clearly any claim that one particular event or state of affairs
was the cause of another does stand in need of such a warrant.
But this may be misleading. Consider two somewhat more com-
plex cases than that outlined above. The first is that of a man
who has several quite different reasons for performing a given
action. He performs the action; how can he as agent know whether
it was the conjoining of all the different reasons that was sufficient
for him to perform the action or whether just one of the reasons
was by itself alone sufficient or whether the action was over-
determined in the sense that there were two or more reasons, each
of which would by itself alone have been sufficient? The problem
arises partly because to know that one or other of these possibilities
was indeed the case entails knowing the truth of certain unfulfilled
conditionals.
A second case worth considering is that of two agents, each
with the same reasons for performing a given action; one does
not in fact perform it, the other does. Neither agent had what
seemed to him a good reason or indeed had any reason for not
performing the action in question. Here we can ask what made
these reasons or some subset of them productive of action in the
one case, but not in the other? In both these types of case we
need to distinguish between the agent's having a reason for
8
216 Against the Self-Images of the Age
performing an action (not just in the sense of there being a reason
for him to perform the action, but in the stronger sense of his
being aware that he has such a reason) and the agent's being
actually moved to action by his having such a reason. The im-
portance of this point can be brought out by reconsidering a
very familiar example, that of post-hypnotic suggestion.
Under the influence of post-hypnotic suggestion a subject
will not only perform the action required by the hypnotist, but
will offer apparently good reasons for performing it, while quite
unaware of the true cause of the performance. So someone
enjoined to walk out of the room might, on being asked why he
was doing this, reply with all sincerity that he had felt in need of
fresh air or decided to catch a train. In this type of case we would
certainly not accept the agent's testimony as to the connection
between reason and action, unless we are convinced of the un-
truth of the counter-factual. "He would have walked out of the
room, if no reason for doing so had occurred to him" and the
truth of the counter-factual, "He would not have walked out
of the room, if he had not possessed some such reason for so
doing." The question of the truth or otherwise of the first of
these is a matter of the experimentally established facts about
post-hypnotic suggestion, and these facts are certainly expressed
as causal generalizations. To establish the truth of the relevant
generalization would entail establishing the untruth of the second
counter-factual. But since to establish the truth of such causal
generalizations entails consequences concerning the truth or
untruth of generalizations about reasons, the question inevitably
arises as to whether the possession of a given reason may not be the
cause of an action in precisely the same sense in which hypnotic
suggestion may be the cause of an action. The chief objection
to this view has been that the relation of reason to action is internal
and conceptual, not external and contingent, and cannot therefore
be a causal relationship ; but although nothing could count
as a reason unless it stood in an internal relationship to an action,
the agent's possessing a reason may be a state of affairs identifiable
independently of the event which is the agent's performance
of the action. Thus it does seem as if the possession of a reason by
an agent is an item of a suitable type to figure as a cause, or an
effect. But if this is so then to ask whether it was the agent's
reason that roused him to act is to ask a causal question, the true
answer to which depends upon what causal generalizations we
have been able to establish. This puts in a different light the
question of the agent's authority as to what roused him to act;
The idea of a socialscience 217

for it follows from what has been said that this authority is at
best prima facie. Far more of course needs to be said on this and
related topics; but perhaps the argument so far entitles us to
treat with skepticism Winch's claim that understanding in terms
of rule-following and causal explanations have mutually exclusive
subject matters.
This has obvious implications for social science, and I wish
to suggest some of these in order to provide direction for the rest
of my argument. Clearly if the citing of reasons by an agent,
with the concomitant appeal to rules, is not necessarily the citing
of those reasons which are causally effective, a distinction may be
made between those rules which agents in a given society sincerely
profess to follow and to which their actions may in fact conform,
but which do not in fact direct their actions, and those rules
which, whether they profess to follow them or not, do in fact
guide their acts by providing them with reasons and motives for
acting in one way rather than another. The making of this
distinction is essential to the notions of ideology and of / alse
consciousness,notions which are extremely important to some
non-Marxist as well as to Marxist social scientists.
But to allow that these notions could have application is to
find oneself at odds with Winch's argument at yet another point.
For it seems quite clear that the concept of ideology can find
application in a society where the concept is not available to the
members of the society, and furthermore that the application of
this concept implies that criteria beyond those available in the
society may be invoked to judge its rationality; and as such it
would fall under Winch's ban as a concept unsuitable for social
science. Hence there is a connection between Winch's view that
social science is not appropriately concerned with causal generali-
zations and his view that only the concepts possessed by the mem-
bers of a given society (or concepts logically tied to those concepts
in some way) are to be used in the study of that society. Further-
more, it is important to note that Winch's views on those matters
necessarily make his account of rules and their place in social
behavior defective.

III
The examples which Winch gives of rule-following behavior
are very multifarious: games, political thinking, musical com-
position, the monastic way of life, an anarchist's way of life, are all
218 Against the Self-Images of the Age
cited. His only example of non-rule-governed behavior is "the
pointless behavior of a berserk lunatic" (p. 53), and he asserts
roundly "that all behavior which is meaningful (therefore all
specifically human behavior) is ipso facto rule-governed." Winch
allows for different kinds of rules (p. 52); what he does not
consider is whether the concept of a rule is perhaps being used so
widely that quite different senses of rule-governed are being con-
fused, let alone whether his account of meaningful behavior can
be plausibly applied to some actions at all.
If I go for a walk, or smoke a cigarette, are my actions rule-
governed in the sense in which my actions in playing chess are
rule-governed? Winch says that "the test of whether a man's
actions are the application of a rule is . . . whether it makes
sense to distinguish between a right and a wrong way of doing
things in connection with what he does." What is the wrong
way of going for a walk? And, if there is no wrong way, is my
action in any sense rule-governed? To ask these questions is to
begin to bring out the difference between those activities which
form part of a coherent mode of behavior and those which do not.
It is to begin to see that although many actions must be rule-
governed in the sense that the concept of some particular kinds
of action may involve reference to a rule, the concept of an action
as such does not involve such a reference. But even if we restrict
our attention to activities which form part of some coherent
larger whole, it is clear that rules may govern activity in quite
different ways. This is easily seen if we consider the variety of
uses to which social scientists have put the concept of a role and
role concepts.
Role concepts are at first sight peculiarly well-fitted to find a
place in the type of analysis of which Winch would approve.
S. F. Nadel wrote that "the role concept is not an invention of
anthropologists or sociologists but is employed by the very
people they study," and added that "it is the existence of names
describing classes of people which make us think of roles." It
would therefore be significant for Winch's thesis if it were the
case that role concepts had to be understood in relation to causes,
if they were to discharge their analytic and explanatory function.
Consider first a use of the notion of role where causal questions
do not arise. In a society such as ours there are a variety of roles
which an individual may assume or not as he wills. Some
occupational roles provide examples. To live out such a role
is to make one's behavior conform to certain norms. To speak
of one's behavior being governed by the norms is to use a sense
The idea of a socialscience 219

of "governed" close to that according to which the behavior of


a chess player is governed by the rules of chess. We are not
disposed to say that the rules of chess or the norms which define
the role of a headwaiter constrain the individual who conforms
to them. The observation of the rules constitutes the behavior
and what it is; it is not a causal agency.
Contrast with this type of example the inquiry carried on by
Erving Goffmann in his book Asylums. One of Goffmann's con-
cerns was to pose a question about mental patients: how far are the
characteristic patterns of behavior which they exhibit determined,
not by the nature of the mental disorders from which they suffer,
but by the nature of the institutions to which they have been con-
signed? Goffmann concludes that the behavior of patients is
determined to a considerable degree by institutional arrangements
which provide a severely limited set of possible roles both for
patients and for the doctors and orderlies with whom they have to
deal. Thus the behavior of individual patients of a given type
might be explained as the effect of the role arrangements open
to a person of his type. In case it is thought that the role structure
of mental hospitals only has a causal effect upon the patients
because they are patients (and the implication might be that they
are not therefore rational agents but approach the condition of
the exception Winch allows for, that of the berserk lunatic) it is
worth noting that Goffmann's study of mental hospitals is part of a
study of what he calls "total institutions." These include monas-
teries and armed services as well as mental hospitals. A successful
terminus to his inquiry would therefore be the foundation of
generalizations about the effects upon agents of different types of
character of the role structure of such different types of institution.
If Winch were correct, and rule-governed behavior were not
to be understood as causal behavior, then the contrast could not be
drawn between those cases in which the relation of social structure
to individuals may be correctly characterized in terms of control
or constraint and those in which it may not. Winch's inability
to make this contrast adequately in terms of his conceptual
scheme is the counterpart to Durkheim's inability to make it
adequately in terms of his; and the resemblance of Winch's
failure to Durkheim's is illuminating in that Winch's position is,
roughly speaking, that of Durkheim turned upside down. Durk-
heim in a passage cited by Winch insisted, first, "that social life
should be explained, not by the notions of those who participate in
it, but by more profound causes which are unperceived by con-
sciousness" and, secondly, "that these causes are to be sought
220 Against the Self-Images of the Age
mainly in the manner according to which the associated individuals
are grouped." 1 That is, Durkheim supposes, just as Winch does,
that an investigation of social reality which uses the concepts
available to the members of the society being studied, and an
investigation of social reality which utilizes concepts not so
available and invokes causal explanations of which the agents
themselves are not aware, are mutually exclusive alternatives. But
Durkheim supposes, as Winch does not, that the latter alternative
is the one to be preferred. Yet his acceptance of the same dichotomy
involves him in the same inability to understand the different ways
in which social structure may be related to individual action.
Durkheim's concept of anomie is the concept of a state in
which the constraints and controls exercised by social structure
have been loosened and the bonds which delimit and contain
individual desire have therefore been at least partially removed.
The picture embodied in the Durkheimian concept is thus one
according to which the essential function of norms in social life is to
restrain and inhibit psychological drives. For Durkheim, rules
are an external imposition upon a human nature which can be
defined independently of them; for Winch, they are the guide-
lines of behavior which, did it not conform to them, could
scarcely be human. What is equally odd in both is the way in
which rules or norms are characterized as though they were all of
a kind. Durkheim is unable to recognize social structure apart
from the notions of constraint and control by the structure ;
Winch's concept of society has no room for these notions.
Just as Winch does not allow for the variety of relationships in
which an agent may stand to a rule to which his behavior con-
forms, so he does not allow also for the variety of types of deviance
from rules which behavior may exhibit. I quoted Malinowski
earlier on the important gap between the rules professed in a
society and the behavior actually exhibited. On this Winch might
well comment that his concern is with human behavior as rule-
following, not only with mere professions of rule-following,
except insofar as professing to follow rules is itself a human and
(for him) ipso facto a rule-following activity. Moreover he ex-
plicitly allows that "since understanding something involves
understanding its contradictory, someone who, with under-
standing, performs X must be capable of envisaging the possibility
of doing not-X." He makes this remark in the context of his
discussion of predictability; and what he does not allow for in
this discussion is that in fact the behavior of agents may exhibit
1 Review of A. Labriola's Essays on Historical Materialism.
The idea of a social science 221

regularities of a Humean kind and be predictable just as natural


events are predictable, even though it can also be characterized
and in some cases must also be characterized in terms of following
and deviating from certain rules. That this is so makes it possible
to speak not only, as Malinowski does in the passage quoted
earlier, of mechanisms of deviation, but also of mechanisms of
conformity. Of course those who deviate from the accepted
rules may have a variety of reasons for so doing, and insofar as
they share the same reasons their behavior will exhibit rule-
following regularities. But it may well be that agents have a
variety of reasons for their deviance and yet deviate uniformly
in certain circumstances, this uniformity being independent of
their reasons. Whether in a particular case this is so or not seems
to me to be an empirical question and one which it would be well
not to attempt to settle a priori.
I can put my general point as follows. We can in a given
society discover a variety of systematic regularities. There are
the systems of rules which agents professedly follow; there are
the systems of rules which they actually follow; there are causal
regularities exhibited in the correlation of statuses and forms of
behavior, and of one form of behavior and another, which are
not rule-governed at all; there are regularities which are in them-
selves neither causal nor rule-governed, although dependent for
their existence perhaps on regularities of both types, such as the
cyclical patterns of development exhibited in some societies; and
there are the interrelationships which exist between all these.
Winch concentrates on some of these at the expense of the others.
In doing so he is perhaps influenced by a peculiarly British
tradition in social anthropology and by a focus of attention in
recent philosophy.
The anthropological tradition is that centered on the work of
Professor E. E. Evans-Pritchard, work which exemplifies the
rewards to be gained from understanding a people first of all in
their own terms. Winch rightly treats Evans-Pritchard's writing
as a paradigm case of a social scientist knowing his own business, 1
but neglects the existence of alternative paradigms. Edmund
Leach, for example, in his Pul Eliya, a village in Ceylon has
remarked how ecological factors do not in fact genuinely figure in
the explanatory framework of Evans-Pritchard's The Nuer. Now
it is clear that such factors may affect the form of social life either
in ways of which the agents are conscious (by posing problems to
1 In "Understanding a Primitive Society," American Philosophical
Quarterly, Vol. I, No. 4.
222 Against the Self-Images of the Age
which they have to formulate solutions) or in ways of which
they are unaware. This elementary distinction is perhaps not
given its full weight in a recent discussion by Walter Goldschmidt 1
in which the very problems discussed by Winch are faced from
the standpoint of an anthropologist especially concerned with
ecological factors. Goldschmidt offers the example of the high cor-
relation between agnatic segmentary kinship systems and nomadic
pastoralism as a form of economy. He argues that nomadic
pastoralism, to be a viable form of economy, has to satisfy require-
ments which are met most usually by segmentary lineages, but
"age-sets can perform some of the same functions-especially
those associated with the military-with equal effectiveness.... "
Goldschmidt's claim is at least superficially ambiguous. He might
be read (at least by a critic determined to be captious) as asserting
that first there are economic forms, these pose problems of which
the agents become aware and segmentary or age-set patterns are
constructed as solutions by the agents. Or he might be read (more
profitably, I imagine) as moving toward a theory in which social
patterns (including kinship patterns) represent adaptations (of
which the agents themselves are not aware) to the environment and
to the level of technology prevailing. It would then in principle be
possible to formulate causal laws governing such adaptations, and
work like Leach's on Pul Eliya or Goldschmidt's on East Africa
could be placed in a more general explanatory framework. This
type of project is at the opposite extreme from Evans-Pritchard's
concern with conceptual particularity.
Secondly, in Winch's account the social sciences characterize
what they characterize by using action descriptions. In his
stress upon these, Winch follows much recent philosophical
writing. It is on what people do and not what they are or suffer
that he dwells. But social scientists are concerned with the causes
and effects of being unemployed, having kin relations of a particular
kind, rates of population change, and a myriad of conditions of
individuals and societies, the descriptions of which have a logical
character other than that of action descriptions. None of this
appears in Winch's account.

IV
The positive value of Winch's book is partly as a corrective to
1 Comparative Functionalism (Berkeley: University of California Press,

1966), pp. 122-24.


The idea of a social science 223

the Durkheimian position which he rightly cast-igates. But it


is more than a corrective because what Winch characterizes as
the whole task of the social sciences is in fact their true starting-
point. Unless we begin by a characterization of a society in its
own terms, we shall be unable to identify the matter that requires
explanation. Attention to intentions, motives, and reasons must
precede attention to causes; description in terms of the agent's
concepts and beliefs must precede description in terms of our
concepts and beliefs. The force of this contention can be brought
out by considering and expanding what Winch says about Durk-
heim's Suicide (p. 110 ). Winch invites us to notice the connection
between Durkheim's conclusion that the true explanation of
suicide is in terms of factors outside the consciousness of the
agents themselves such that the reasons of the agents themselves
are effectively irrelevant and his initial decision to give the term
"suicide" a meaning quite other than that which it had for those
agents. What is he inviting us to notice?
A number of points, I suspect, of which one is a central insight,
the others in error. The insight is that Durkheim's particular
procedure of giving to "suicide" a meaning of his own entails
the irrelevance of the agent's reasons in the explanation of suicide.
Durkheim does in fact bring forward independent arguments
designed to show that reasons are either irrelevant or inaccessible,
and very bad arguments they are. But even if he had not believed
himself to have grounds drawn from these arguments, he would
have been unable to take reasons into account, given his decision
about meaning. For Durkheim arbitrarily equates the concept
of suicide with that of doing anything that the agent knows will
bring about his own death and thus classifies as suicide both the
intended self-destruction of the Prussian or English officer who
shoots himself to save the regiment the disgrace of a court martial
and the death in battle of such an officer who has courageously
headed a charge in such a way that he knows that he will not
survive. (I choose these two examples because they both belong
to the same category in Durkheim's classification.) Thus he
ignores the distinction between doing X intending that Y shall
result and doing X knowing that Y will result. Now clearly if
these two are to be assimilated, the roles of deliberation and the
relevance of the agent's reasons will disappear from view. For
clearly in the former case the character of Y must be central to
the reasons the agent has for doing X, but in the latter case the
agent may well be doing X either in spite of the character of Y, or
not caring one way or the other about the character of Y, or
224 Against the Self-Images of the Age
again finding the character of Y desirable, but not desirable
enough for him for it to constitute a reason or a motive for doing
X. Thus the nature of the reasons must differ in the two cases,
and if the two cases are to have the same explanation the agent's
reasons can scarcely figure in that explanation. That is, Durk-
heim is forced by his initial semantic decision to the conclusion
that the agent's reasons are in cases of what agents in the society
which he studies would have called suicide (which are included as
a subclass of what he calls suicide) never causally effective.
But there are two further conclusions which might be thought
to, but do not in fact, follow. It does not follow that all such
decisions to bring actions under descriptions other than those
used by the agents themselves are bound to lead to the same
a priori obliteration of the explanatory role of reasons; for this
obliteration was in Durkheim's case, as I have just shown, a con-
sequence of certain special features of his treatment of the concept
of suicide, and not a consequence of any general feature of the
procedure of inventing new descriptive terms in social sciences.
Secondly, from the fact that explanation in terms of reason ought
not to be excluded by any initial decision of the social scientist,
it does not follow that such explanation is incompatible with
causal explanation. Here my argument in the second section of
this essay bears on what Winch says about Weber. Winch says
that Weber was confused because he did not realize that "a con-
text of humanly followed rules . . . cannot be combined with a
context of causal laws" without creating logical difficulties, and
he is referring specifically to Weber's contention that the manipu-
lation of machinery and the manipulation of his employees by a
manufacturer may be understood in the same way, so far as the
logic of the explanation is concerned. So Weber wrote, "that in
the one case 'events of conciousness' do enter into the causal
chain and in the other case do not, makes 'logically' not the
slightest difference." I also have an objection to Weber's argu-
ment, but it is in effect that Weber's position is too close to
Winch's. For Weber supposes that in order to introduce causal
explanation he must abandon description of the social situation
in terms of actions, roles, and the like. So he proposes speaking
not of the workers being paid, but of their being handed pieces of
metal. In so doing Weber concedes Winch's point that descriptions
in terms of actions, reasons, and all that falls under his term "events
of consciousness" cannot figure in causal explanations without a
conceptual mistake being committed. But in this surely he is
wrong.
The idea of a socialscience 225
Compare two situations: first, one in which managers minimize
shop-floor trade-union activity in a factory by concentrating
opportunities of extra overtime and of earning bonuses in those
parts of the factory where such activity shows signs of flourishing ;
and then one in which managers similarly minimize trade-union
activity by a process of continual transfers between one part of the
factory and another or between different factories. In both cases
it may be possible to explain the low level of trade-union activity
causally by reference to the managers' policies; but in the former
case the reasons which the workers have for pursuing overtime
and bonuses can find a place in the explanation without it losing
its causal character and in both cases a necessary condition of
the managers' actions being causally effective may well be that the
workers in question remain ignorant of the policy behind the
actions. The causal character of the explanations can be brought
out by considering how generalizations might be formulated in
which certain behavior of the managers can supply either the
necessary or the sufficient condition or both for the behavior
of the workers. But in such a formulation one important fact
will emerge; namely, that true causal explanations cannot be
formulated-where actions are concerned-unless intentions,
motives, and reasons are taken into account. That is, it is not
only the case as I have argued in the second section of this essay
that a true explanation in terms of reasons must entail some
account of the causal background; it is also true that a causal
account of action will require a corresponding account of the
intentions, motives, and reasons involved. It is this latter point
that Durkheim misses and Winch stresses. In the light of this it is
worth returning to one aspect of the explanation of suicide.
In modern cities more than one study has shown a correlation
between the suicide rate for different parts of the city and the
proportion of the population living an isolated, single-room
apartment existence. What are the conditions which must be
satisfied if such a correlation is to begin to play a part in explaining
why suicide is committed? First it must be shown that at least a
certain proportion of the individuals who commit suicide live in
such isolated conditions; otherwise (unless, for example, it was
the landlord of such apartments who committed suicide) we
should find the correlation of explanatory assistance only insofar
as it pointed us toward a common explanation of the two rates.
But suppose that we do find that it is the individuals who live in
such isolated conditions who are more likely to commit suicide.
We still have to ask whether it is the pressure on the emotions of
Against the Self-Images of the Age
the isolation itself, or whether it is the insolubility of certain other
problems in conditions of isolation which leads to suicide. Unless
such questions about motives and reasons are answered, the
causal generalization "isolated living of a certain kind tends to
lead to acts of suicide" is not so much an explanation in itself as
an additional fact to be explained, even though it is a perfectly
sound generalization and even though to learn its truth might
be to learn how the suicide rate could be increased or decreased
in large cities by changing our housing policies.
Now we cannot raise the questions about motives and reasons,
the answers to which would explain why isolation has the effect
which it has, unless we first of all understand the acts of suicide
in terms of the intentions of the agents and therefore in terms of
their own action descriptions. Thus Winch's starting-point
proves to be the correct one, provided it is a starting-point. We
could not even formulate our initial causal generalization about
isolation and suicide, in such a way that the necessary question
about motives and reasons could be raised later, unless the ex-
pression "suicide" and kindred expressions which figured in our
causal generalizations possessed the same meaning as they did
for the agents who committed the acts. We can understand very
clearly why Winch's starting-point must be substantially correct
if we remember how he compares sociological understanding
with understanding a language (p. u5). The crude notion that
one can first learn a language and then secondly and separately
go on to understand the social life of those who speak it can only
fl(?urish where the languages studied are those of peoples whose
social life is so largely the same as our own, so that we do not
notice the understanding of social life embodied in our grasp of
the language; but attempts to learn the alien language of an alien
culture soon dispose of it. Yet the understanding that we thus
acquire, although a necessary preliminary, is only a preliminary.
It would be equally harmful if Winch's attempt to make of this
preliminary the substance of social science were to convince, or if
a proper understanding of the need to go further were not to allow
for the truth in his arguments.

These dangers are likely to be especially inhibiting in the present


state of certain parts of social science. Two important essays by
anthropologists, Leach's Rethinking Anthropology and Gold-
The idea of a socialscience 227
schmidt's Comparative Functionalism (to which I have referred
earlier), focus upon problems to which adherence to Winch's
conclusions would preclude any solution. At the outset I con-
trasted Winch with Malinowski, but this was in respects in which
most contemporary social scientists would take the standpoint
quoted from Malinowski for granted. We owe also to Malinowski,
however, the tradition of what Goldschmidt calls "the detailed
internal analysis of individual cultures" with the further com-
parison of institutional arrangements in different societies resting
on such analyses. This tradition has been criticized by both Leach
and Goldschmidt; the latter believes that because institutions are
defined by each culture in its own terms, it is not at the level of
institutions that cross-cultural analyses will be fruitful. The former
has recommended us to search for recurrent topological patterns
in, for example, kinship arrangements, with the same aim of
breaking free from institutional ethnocentrism. I think that both
Leach and Goldschmidt are going to prove to be seminal writers
on this point and it is clear that their arguments are incompatible
with Winch's. It would therefore be an important lacuna in this
essay if I did not open up directly the question of the bearing of
Winch's arguments on this topic.
Winch argues, consistently with his rejection of any place for
causal laws in social science, that comparison between different
cases is not dependent on any grasp of theoretical generalizations
(pp. 134-6), and he sets limits to any possible comparison by his
insistence that each set of activities must be understood solely in
its own terms. In so doing he must necessarily reject for example
all those various theories which insist that religions of quite
different kinds express unacknowledged needs of the same kind.
(No such theory needs to be committed to the view that religions
are and do no more than this.) Indeed in his discussion of Pareto
(pp. 104-n) he appears to make such a rejection explicit by the
generality of the grounds on which he rejects Pareto's comparison
of Christian baptism with pagan rites. I hold no brief for the theory
of residues and derivations. But when Winch insists that each
religious rite must be understood in its own terms to the exclusion
of any generalization about religion or that each social system must
be so understood to the exclusion of any generalization about
status and prestige, he must be pressed to make his grounds precise.
In his later discussion of Evans-Pritchard, one aspect of Winch's
views becomes clear; namely, the implication of his remark that
"criteria of logic are not a direct gift of God, but arise out of, and
are only intelligible in the context of, ways of living or modes of
Against the Self-Images of the Age
social life" (p. 100 ). Winch's one substantial point of difference
with Evans-Pritchard in his treatment of witchcraft among the
Azande is that he thinks it impossible to ask whether the Zande
beliefs about witches are true. 1 We can ask from within the Zande
system of beliefs if there are witches and will receive the answer
"Yes." We can ask from within the system of beliefs of modern
science if there are witches and will receive the answer "No." But
we cannot ask which system of beliefs is the superior in respect of
rationality and truth; for this would be to invoke criteria which
can be understood independently of any particular way of life, and
in Winch's view there are no such criteria.
This represents a far more extreme view of the difficulties of
cultural comparison that Goldschmidt, for example, advances.
Both its extreme character and its error can be understood by
considering two arguments against it. The first is to the effect
that in Winch's view certain actual historical transitions are made
unintelligible; I refer to those transitions from one system of
beliefs to another which are necessarily characterized by raising
questions of the kind that Winch rejects. In seventeenth-century
Scotland, for example, the question could not but be raised, "But
are there witches?" If Winch asks, from within what way of social
life, under what system of belief was this question asked, the only
answer is that it was asked by men who confronted alternative
systems and were able to draw out of what confronted them in-
dependent criteria of judgment. Many Africans today are in the
same situation.
This type of argument is of course necessarily inconclusive;
any historical counter-example to Winch's thesis will be open to
questions of interpretation that will make it less than decisive.
But there is another important argument. Consider the statement
made by some Zande theorist or by King James VI and I, "There
are witches" and the statement made by some modern skeptic,
"There are no witches." Unless one of these statements denies
what the other asserts, the negation of the sentence expressing
the former could not be a correct translation of the sentence
expressing the latter. Thus if we could not deny from our own
standpoint and in our own language what the Azande or King
James assert in theirs, we should be unable to translate their
expression into our language. Cultural idiosyncracy would have
entailed linguistic idiosyncracy and cross-cultural comparison
would have been rendered logically impossible. But of course
translation is not impossible.
1 American Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. I, No. 4, p. 309.
The idea of a socialscience 229
Yet if we treat seriously, not what I take to be Winch's mistaken
thesis that we cannot go beyond a society's own self-description,
but what I take to be his true thesis that we must not do this except
and until we have ·grasped the criteria embodied in that self-
description, then we shall have to conclude that the contingently
different conceptual schemes and institutional arrangements of
different societies make translation difficult to the point at which
attempts at cross-cultural generalization too often become little
more than a construction of lists. Goldschmidt and Leach have
both pointed out how the building up of typologies and classifi-
catory schemes becomes empty and purposeless unless we have a
theory which gives point and criteria to our classificatory activities.
Both have also pointed out how, if we compare for example
marital institutions in different cultures, our definition of "marriage"
will either be drawn from one culture in terms of whose concepts
other cultures will be described or rather misdescribed, or else
will be so neutral, bare, and empty as to be valueless.1 That is, the
understanding of a people in terms of their own concepts and
beliefs does in fact tend to preclude understanding them in any
other terms. To this extent Winch is vindicated. But an opposite
moral to his can be drawn. We may conclude not that we ought
not to generalize, but that such generalization must move at
another level. Goldschmidt argues for the recommendation: Don't
ask what an institution means for the agents themselves, ask
what necessary needs and purposes its serves. He argues for
this not because he looks for functionalist explanations of a
Malinowskian kind, but because he believes that different institu-
tions, embodying different conceptual schemes, may be illumi-
natingly seen as serving the same social necessities. To carry the
argument further would be to raise questions that are not and
cannot be raised within the framework of Winch's book. It is
because I believe writers such as Goldschmidt are correct in
saying that one must transcend such a framework that I believe
also that Winch's book deserves close critical attention.

1 See Kathleen Gough, "The Nayars and the Definition of Marriage,"


in P. B. Hammond, ed., Cultural and Social Anthropology (New York:
Macmillan); E. R. Leach, "Polyandry, Inheritance and the Definition of
Marriage with Particular Reference to Sinhalese Customary Law,"
in Rethinking Anthropology (London: Athlone Press); and Goldschmidt,
op. cit., pp. 17-26.
20

Emotion, behavior and belief

In this essay I intend to attack behaviorism and I may therefore


seem to have an initial obligation to specify precisely which of the
many kinds of behaviorism I am attacking. But this I do not need
to specify, since my arguments, if correct, hold against anything
that it would be worth calling behaviorism. Consider for example
the following four theses about the emotion of resentment, all of
which might be called behaviorism.
1. "Smith resents what Jones did" means the same as some
specifiable statement or set of statements about Smith's behavior.
2. "Smith resents what Jones did" is true, if, and only if, some
specifiable statement or set of statements about Smith's behavior
is true.
3. Although "Smith resents what Jones did" does not mean
the same as some statement or set of statements about Smith's
behavior, there is nothing more to Smith's feeling resentful than
that Smith behaved, and was disposed to behave, in certain speci-
fiable ways.
4. Although it is not the case that "Smith resents what Jones
did" is true, if, and only if, some specifiable statement or set of
statements about Smith's behavior is true, it is the case that if it
is true that "Smith resents what Jones did" is true, then either
some specifiable statement or set of statements about Smith's
behavior is true, or else some special explanation is necessary as
to why the behavior which, if it had occurred, would have made
that statement or those statements true did not occur.
These theses are importantly different. The truth of ( 1) entails
the truth of (2), but not vice versa; the truth of (3) entails the
truth of (2 ), but the falsity of ( 1) ; and the truth of (4) entails the
falsity of ( 1 ), ( 2 ), and ( 3). But, different as they are, they all have
in common the following thesis: there is a connection between the
emotion of resentment and certain specific and specifiable forms
of behavior such that, even if there is more to resentment than the
230
Emotion, behavior and belief 231

exhibition of the behavior in question and even if resentment may


be felt without the behavior in question being exhibited, none
the less behavior of that specific kind is the behavior-which-is-ex-
hibited-when-resentment-is-expressed-in-behavior. I understand
this thesis in such a way that it entails, first, that the connection
between behavior and emotion is not merely contingent, as the
connection between a twitching of my ear and my feeling resent-
ment might be (it might just happen to be the case that whenever
I feel resentment my ear twitches) and, second, that there is a
limited and specifiable number of forms of behavior in which
and through which resentment may be exhibited. It is precisely
this last point that I wish to deny, and the argument of the first
section of this essay will be directed to showing that resentment
and some other emotions may be expressed by any form of be-
havior whatsoever, and that there is, therefore, no necessary
connection between some emotions at least and particular forms of
behavior.

I
A man who yesterday chatted pleasantly with an academic
colleague today crosses the street to avoid meeting him. Why?
He has in the interval read a review of his latest book by this
colleague and resents what he takes to be his unjust verdict. He
expresses his resentment by crossing the road. Suppose that he
knew that this colleague had a peculiar love of a rare fruit which
he could only procure at one store; he might then buy up the entire
stock of that fruit and so express his resentment. Or suppose that
he knows that what his colleague prizes is an invitation to a
particular party; he might then express his resentment by inter-
cepting the invitation. Crossing a road, buying up fruit, stealing
mail: these actions have. nothing in common with each other and
yet they can all express resentment. Precisely because there is no
characteristic which they have to possess in order to function as
expressions of resentment, precisely because, except as possible
expressions of resentment, there is no reason for including these
items in the list rather than any others, it seems plausible to suppose
that any action whatsoever can function as an expression of
resentment.
Consider now three possible criticisms of this argument. Surely,
it might be argued, all such items of behavior do fall under some
one single description other than "resentful" ; they are all, for
Against the Self-Images of the Age
example, items of hostile behavior. This is of course true, but it
does not affect my point. First of all, just as any action at all can
be an expression of resentment, any action at all can be a hostile
action. Crossing a road, buying up fruit, stealing mail can all be
hostile in specific contexts, just as they can be resentful in specific
contexts. To this it might be objected that there are some actions
which could not be hostile, if by that is meant "directed to the
harm of others" ; how could suicide be in this sense hostile? The
answer is, of course, that there is a well-recognized class of suicides,
the so-called "revenge" suicides ("I'll kill myself and that will
teach them a lesson!") where the point of the suicide is precisely
that it is a hostile action. Moreover, the variety of types of action
which can be characterized as expressions of resentment can also
be characterized as hostile just because "hostile" is partially
synonymous with "resentful," in turn because resentment is a
species of hostility. So that the fact that we can find another
description under which all these actions fall does not in any way
show that we have found an additional common characteristic
shared by all these action~.
A second objection to my thesis might be that I am able to
understand all these actions as expressions of resentment only by
establishing a context of a given kind. It is not crossing the road
or buying fruit or stealing mail that is the expression of resentment,
but crossing-the-road-to-avoid-speaking-to-someone-who-has-un-
justly-criticized-me or buying-fruit-especially-desired-by-some-
one-who-has-unjustly-criticized-me, and so on. This is in a way
correct. We are only able to construe the actions in question as
behavior expressive of resentment by connecting them with the
reasons that the agent has for doing what he does. But these reasons
cannot be identified with what the agent does nor are they ex-
hibited in doing what he does. Certainly it is only because the
action is done for a certain kind of reason that it is an expression of
resentment. But to say this is to say that qua action, and qua the
action that it is, the relation between the action and the resentment
is purely contingent. To make the point in this way does perhaps
help us to understand better why many philosophers may have
thought otherwise. They may have envisaged the action under
some description, such as the descriptions above, that links the
action to the reason for performing it and passed from asserting
truly that such a description is conceptually connected with the
characterization of the emotion in question as resentment to
asserting falsely that the action itself was not merely contingently
connected to the resentment.
Emotion, behaviorand belief 233
A third point might be raised not so much as an objection to my
initial thesis as an objection to drawing possibly illegitimate con-
clusions from it. For it might be suggested that while what I have
said is true of the emotion of resentment, it is not true of emotions
in general. What is special about the emotion of resentment? A
man cannot be said to resent something unless he has a particular
type of belief. He must believe that he has been wronged in the
light of what it is established that a man in his position has a right
to expect. Unless he has such a belief, what he feels may be
characterized perhaps as anger but not as resentment. What then
of anger? Is there some belief which a man who is said to be angry
must possess? It is clearly the case that usually and characteristi-
cally a man who is angry believes that something has been done
that is harmful to or an affront to himself or his interests or those
about whom he cares. But is it not sometimes the case that a man
just feels angry? And, therefore, does not anger perhaps differ in a
not irrelevant way from resentment?
The relevance of this point to the argument is as follows. In the
case of resentment it is because the circumstances, tastes, and
other relevant characteristics of the person against whom resent-
ment is directed are indefinitely variable that the actions which
may express that resentment are indefinitely variable. Hence, the
indefinite variability of the actions which express resentment is
connected with the belief which a man to whom resentment is
correctly ascribed must possess. But if in the case of anger there
is no such belief, then may not anger be connected with behavior
expressive of anger in some way quite different to that in which
resentment is connected with behavior expressive of resentment?
It is important to stress first that where anger is divorced from
the belief that usually and characteristically accompanies it,
(namely, the belief that some identifiable person has done some
identifiable harm), we are confronted not with anger as it basically
is (that is, with the emotion in a pure form, so to speak), but
rather with an uncharacteristic and marginal case, which is less
easily intelligible to us than anger in its usual form and which we
understand by its resemblance to these forms. (Try to imagine a
culture in which everyone is all the time in a rage with no one in
particular about nothing in particular, but is never angry with
specific individuals about specific harms. I am inclined to think that
we would treat this as a different emotion.)
Secondly, anger in these special cases is not in fact unaccom-
panied by belief; it is just that the belief is expressed in sentences
containing more variables. The belief that someone or anyone has
234 Against the Self-Images of the Age
done something harmful or affronting to me, although I know not
who or what, is still a belief, and the belief that connects the
feelings accompanying it to other feelings of anger. Hence anger,
like resentment, is connected with a belief and although the belief
is a less complex one, the persons or actions against whom anger
is directed are as indefinitely variable as are the objects of resent-
ment. Hence also the forms of behavior by means of which anger
too may be expressed are indefinitely variable.
I take it therefore that the lack of any necessary connection
between emotion and behavior holds in the case of anger as well
as in that of resentment. But if anger and resentment resemble
each other in this way, how do they differ? It seems plausible to
suggest that the only difference is in the beliefs of the agents in
question. The emotion of anger involves the belief that someone,
whether I deserve it or not, has done harm or has affronted me or
my interests or those about whom I care; the emotion of resent-
ment involves the belief that someone has done undeserved harm
or offered an undeserved affront to me or my interests. The dif-
ference is not in the phenomenological feel of the two emotions:
introspective reports do not reveal different sensations in the case
of anger from those present in the case of resentment. Nor is the
difference in the behavior through which each is expressed, since
each may be expressed in the same behavior. The beliefs alone
provide a difference.
To this it may be retorted that the relationship of anger to
resentment is a special case. For after all resentment is a species of
anger. It may therefore be true that the felt quality of the emotion
and the behavior do not differ in this case. But if, instead of asking
for the difference between anger and resentment, we were to
inquire what is the difference between anger and elation or be-
tween resentment and gratitude, the same would not hold.
Consider resentment and gratitude. To feel grateful is to feel
pleased that someone has done more for your good or for the good
of those about whom you care than you had a right to expect.
But like resentment any kind of behavior may express gratitude;
the fact that one emotion is one of pleasure in something and the
other of displeasure at something does not entail that the very
same behavior may not express gratitude which expresses resent-
ment. If I am grateful to you for what you have done and I know
that you resent what someone else has done, I may express my
gratitude to you by doing to him what if you did it to him would
express your resentment. Hence the difference between gratitude
and resentment is not a difference in behavior. I take it that it is
Emotion, behaviorand belief 235
also not a difference in the felt quality of inner states. The feelings
of a man in the extremity of an emotion such as gratitude is
customarily described by novelists in ways that are remarkably
like the ways in which the feelings of a man in the extremity of an
emotion such as fear are described. His throat goes dry, his temples
throb, his pulse rate rises, his eyes prick with tears, and so on.
The physiological symptoms of emotion seem remarkably constant
and the physiologists seem to agree with the novelists about this.
If I conclude then that the difference between emotions lies in
the belief and not in the behavior, I cannot possibly identify
emotions with patterns of behavior. But a behaviorist might try
at this point to recover his position by an argument of more
general import. For he might contend that the notion of belief
itself is to be analysed in terms of behavior, asserting that "X
believes that p" is logically equivalent to or means the same as
"X has a disposition to manifest certain patterns of behavior" and
also that to manifest a belief is to manifest patterns of behavior, so
that the appropriate evidence which would warrant the assertion
that "X believes that p" is that X has on occasion exhibited the
relevant behavior. In order for these assertions to be defensible,
the behavior in question would have to include what X says as well
as what X does, what some behaviorists have quaintly called
"linguistic behavior." More specifically it is what X asserts and not
just what X says which has to be included in the list of relevant
items: unless on certain types of possible occasions a man was
prepared to assert that p and to deny that p he could not be said
to believe that p. It follows, therefore, that if the notion of belief
is to be analysed in terms of behavior, the behavior in terms of
which it is analysed must include acts of assertion and denial.
But not what is it to assert that p? It is to give one's hearers or
readers to understand that one believes that p and that p is worthy
of belief. That is to say, the notion of assertion has to be explained
by referring to the notion of belief. So it turns out that the notion
of belief has not been analysed in terms of behavior, for the type of
behavior to which reference has to be made in the course of the
analysis can itself only be understood by referring to the concept
of belief. The concept of belief is at least as fundamental a concept,
and possibly a more fundamental concept than that of behavior.
To this it might be answered that to assert and to deny are just
forms of behavior. There is clearly a sense in which this is true.
If I say of someone that he behaved disgracefully in denying that
he was to blame, I say something intelligible to every user of
standard English. But in this idiomatic sense of "behavior" we
Against the Self-Images of the Age
cannot give a behaviorist account even of behavior. For to assert
of someone that he asserts that p is to go beyond saying that he
utters the sentence "p" even if he did in fact assert that p by
uttering the sentence "p." It is to construe his utterance in terms
of his intention in uttering the sentence. The intentions that
inform that utterance, like all intentions, presuppose beliefs. So
that we have once again, in the course of trying to analyse the
concepts of belief, been brought back to it.
Finally it ought to be noticed that in discussing behaviorism
I have not ascribed to the behaviorist that extreme view which
equates behavior with physical movement. When I argued that
there are at least certain emotions which can be expressed by any
behavior whatsoever, my examples-those of crossing the road,
buying fruit, and stealing mail-were all examples of actions and
their descriptions were descriptions which specified an intention
embodied in what was done. If the behaviorist wants to insist
that he means more than this by behavior, that in his view be-
havior has not been characterized adequately until it is charac-
terized by the emotions it expresses, if any, and that therefore
resentful behavior for example is just a species of behavior and
not behavior informed by something other than that behavior,
namely an emotion, his thesis becomes trivial. If he wants, on the
other hand, to insist that he means less than this by "behavior,"
perhaps equating behavior with physical movement, then my
preceding arguments hold with as great or greater force than they
do against behavior equated with human action.
The outcome of my arguments is then that behavior stands in
indirect and complex relationship to emotions. Without accepting
classical introspectionism, the introspectionist and indeed ordinary
language usage according to which we speak of emotions as lying
behind behavior and as being concealed as much as revealed by it
does not seem exaggerated. But if this is so, what are we to say
about our knowledge of the emotions of others? How far can we
know what they feel?

II
Paul Ziff in his About Behaviorism considers the contention that
"You can in principle if not in fact always find out whether or not
I am behaving in certain ways. But you cannot even in principle
always find out whether or not I am angry," and even waiving all
difficulties about the locution "you can in principle find out" finds
Emotion, behaviorand belief 237
what he takes to be two fatal objections to it. One which I shall
not consider, since I agree with it, is that it is fal~e that you can in
principle always find out how I am behaving. The other objection
he puts as follows: "You can in principle always find out whether
or not I am angry because I can tell you. Hence you need attend
only to my verbal behavior. (I assume that it would be generally
odd to speak of my being mistaken about whether or not I am
angry.) To suppose that you cannot in principle find out whether
or not I am angry would be to suppose that I cannot in principle
tell you whether or not I am angry. I find such a supposition
unintelligible." Agreeing with finding this last supposition un-
intelligible, I still want to disagree with the main point.
From the fact that, if I am angry, I can always tell you that I am
angry, it does not follow that from what I say you can always tell
if I am angry or not. The reason for this is that I can always
deceive you by lying or otherwise misleading you and that I can
always simply refuse to reveal what I feel. The use of "can in
principle," which Ziff overgenerously adopts from the anti-
behaviorists whom he is criticizing, is one source of trouble. For it
may lead us to concede not only that I may always when angry
tell you that I am, but also that your knowledge of my anger is
unproblematic. But it isn't.
When Ziff talks of verbal behavior, he may be suggesting that
what I say about my emotions stands to my emotions in the same
relationship that the behavior which expresses my emotions
stands to my emotions. But this is surely false either in a behaviorist
or in a nonbehaviorist view. In a behaviorist view it is false because,
in that view, my having an emotion consists in my exhibiting a
certain pattern of behavior: the behavior which expresses the
emotion is the emotion. But when I tell you what I feel, I do not
express the emotion, I report it. Or rather, I may be expressing the
emotion in the act of reporting it or not, but I am certainly report-
ing it. This is partly a matter of to whom I am speaking. If I am
angry with you and I say "I am angry with you," I am undoubtedly
expressing my anger in the act of reporting it. But if I am angry
with you and say to someone else "I am angry with Smith," then
it would be odd to say that I was expressing my anger. It is in any
case utterances and neither sentences nor statements that are
expressive of emotion, and utterances may certainly stand to an
emotion just as other behavior stands to it. But what I say when I so
utter does not stand in the same relationship to the emotion, and as
a counterpart of my thesis that in certain cases at least emotions
do not stand to the behavior that expresses them in such a way
Against the Self-Images of the Age
that there is any conceptual connection between the characteriza-
tion of the emotion and that of the behavior. I now want to develop
a second key thesis to the effect that statements about their own
behavior made by agents are not expressions of that behavior
at all because statements about their own behavior made by
agents stand in no different relationship to that behavior than do
statements made by others about their emotions. I thus have to
attack directly the Wittgensteinian view that first-person reports
are-just because they are expressions of feeling-not symmetrical
with second- and third-person ascriptions.
Against this I want to contend that there is no asymmetry, so
far as emotions are concerned (and if I restrict the point to emotions
in this essay this must not be taken to imply that I hold different
views about sensations), between first-person sentences on the one
hand and second- and third-person sentences on the other or
between statements expressed by means of first-person sentences
and statements expressed by means of second- and third-person
sentences. I take it that to understand personal pronouns at least
two conditions must be satisfied: first no one understands personal
pronouns who does not understand that they are blanks for which
personal proper names may be substituted. I do not understand
personal pronouns unless I am able to make the inference from
hearing someone say "MacIntyre is drunk" to "He is saying that
I am drunk." To have understood this is to be able to see what is
wrong with attempts to suggest that for "I" what can be sub-
stituted is not a proper name, but a description such as "the
present speaker." Of course, first-person statements can often be
correctly paraphrased by statements using such expressions as
"the present speaker." But "the present speaker" is not neces-
sarily self-referential in the way that "I" is. While I am speaking,
someone may say "The present speaker is drunk" and he would not
normally be taken to mean that he is drunk, but that I am; while
if I hear someone say "MacIntyre is drunk," I must if I under-
stand him see that it follows that if what he says is true then I am
drunk, but I do not need to have even learned the use of the
expression "the present speaker" to understand "I" and to use it
correctly.
Secondly, it is a condition of my understanding personal pro-
nouns that I understand that if I say truly of you that "You are
drunk," then you are able to say truly of yourself (provided that you
are not too drunk-perhaps this is what "can in principle" means)
"I am drunk"; and I can say truly of you to a third person, "He is
drunk" ; and in addition that if you can say truly of me that "You
Emotion, behavior and belief 239
are drunk," then I can say truly of myself "I am drunk"; and so on.
In other words, to have extricated oneself from the egocentric
predicament-insofar as this is a matter of grammar rather than
of beliefs-is a necessary condition for the exercise of the ability
to use those parts of speech which are held by some philosophers
to generate it.
It is these facts about personal pronouns which make it clear
that if the sentence "MacIntyre is angry" can be used truly to
make a statement about me, then "I am angry" can be used by me
to make the same true statement. This statement is, let us say, on
this particular occasion true, but it could have been false. The
statement made by my saying "I am angry" truly is thus a state-
ment which stands in the same relationship to my anger that the
statement "MacIntyre is angry" said by someone else stands to it.
But if this is so, then the statement cannot be an expression of my
anger, let alone the sentence. Certainly I may so utter the sentence
"I am angry" with clenched lips, gnashing teeth, and all the con-
ventional accompaniments of anger, whatever they are, in such a
way that my utterance is an expression of my anger. But my
utterance of "E =MC 2 " can be an expression of my anger in just
the same way as my utterance of "I am angry."
It is not to the point that I cannot be mistaken about whether
MacIntyre is angry if I am MacIntyre. I cannot be mistaken
because I cannot fail to have all the necessary evidence for what
I assert. But whenever I have all the necessary evidence for what
I assert, I cannot be mistaken either. Placed with vision unimpaired
in front of a tray containing a bottle and two glasses, I cannot be
mistaken in asserting that here are a bottle and two glasses. Yet of
course in both cases although I cannot be mistaken as to what is
true and what is false I can of course knowingly assert what is
false. Thus Ziff's acknowledgement that sometimes at least I can
only know whether you are angry if you will tell me implies that
I cannot know whether you are angry or not unless I know that
you are a trustworthy reporter of your emotions. But can I ever
know this?
It is not just that a great deal of behavior does not bear its
meaning on its face and that we cannot tell what intentions inform
it simply by observing it, because it is susceptible of more than
one and perhaps of many interpretations. But behavior which is
qua behavior unambiguous can be put to the service of a pretence,
just as assertions can be lies. This is the point at which to note
that when behaviorists have assimilated what I say to my behavior,
using such expressions as "linguistic behavior" or "verbal
240 Against the Self-Images of the Age
behavior" they have been wrong not so much in that they assimi-
lated them as in that they tried to reduce uses of language to forms
of behavior instead of seeing that certain forms of behavior are
best understood as at least resembling uses of language. One
reason why one of the key positions of this essay has not been
accepted by some philosophers-namely, that any behavior at all
can be expressive of certain emotions at least-is that there is a
behavioral iconography of emotion. That is, there are certain
forms of behavior which are by convention understood to sym-
bolize the presence of a particular emotion. To exhibit such be-
havior is equivalent to saying "I am angry" (or whatever emotion
is in question). It is because of this symbolic character of such
behavior-of shaking the fist and clenching the teeth in relation
to anger, for example-that it can be put to different uses just as
speech can. In Japan and Korea there is a tradition of visiting a
recently bereaved person who will then laugh and joke with his
guests without making reference to the bereavement. The host by
doing this asserts to his guests that he does not wish to burden
them with his grief; the guests assert in reply that they would not
wish to burden the host with the belief that he has in fact burdened
them with his grief. It is the conventional, symbolic character of
the behavior that makes this possible. So far as this iconographic
aspect of behavior is concerned, the conventions could, of course,
be other than they are. We could express anger by touching our
toes or gratitude by performing cartwheels. If it is objected that
very often the behavior expressive of anger or gratitude is evoked
from us by some action, is not a voluntary, deliberate, or controlled
response, it must be pointed out that very often too what we say
about our emotions is similarly evoked. An involuntary utterance
of a statement about my behayior does not, because it is involun-
tary, lose its conventional character. So too with behavior sym-
bolic of emotion.
There is, of course, a difference between speech and such
symbolic behavior which ought to be noted. I cannot use such
behavior to indicate to you that I am angry without being taken to
have expressed and not merely indicated the fact of my anger.
But this difference does not affect the preceding argument. What
follows from that argument is that whether I say to you that I am
angry or show you that I am angry I may be misleading you,
and from this, two additional consequences follow. The first is
that over large areas I can sometimes have no way of knowing
what you feel. Any performance of behavior by you, no matter
how extended, may be a pretence at the service of some further
Emotion, behavior and belief
unrevealed intention and emotion. This gap between performed
behavior on the one hand and intention and emotion on the other
is what goes unnoticed in a sociological perspective such as
Erving Goffmann's, in which there is nothing to human beings
but their performance of the behavior appropriate to different
roles and the behavior (equally and in precisely the same way
rule-governed) necessary to produce the behavior appropriate to
the roles. I introduce the doctrines of Goffmann in The Presenta-
tion of Self in Everyday Life at this point because in identifying
what is omitted from an account of social stituations which is
restricted to overt performances I have identified not merely what
is omitted from this particular piece of sociological inquiry and
description, but what it is at once essential and very difficult to
include. The early behaviorists believed that their doctrine pro-
vided the only basis for a scientific knowledge of human beings
and believed that such knowledge could have a firmer basis than
our everyday knowledge of each other has. Goffmann resembles
them in believing that the notion of "a true self" behind the role-
and rule-governed performances is an antiscientific myth per-
petrated by those who, as he puts it, wish to keep part of the
human world "safe from sociology." But in liquidating the dis-
tinction between the self and its performances, Goffmann loses
sight of the way in which we can only take what others do seriously
if we trust what they say on certain key occasions.
It is not just that the possibility of deception and of being misled
are so large; it is also that our beliefs about others have to be
founded so largely on trust if the preceding arguments are correct.
I may argue on an inductive basis about other people's emotions
insofar as these are not exhibited in or deducible from their
behavior; but however well contrived my inductive learning
policies are, the evidence from which I argue will include at crucial
points what others have said; and my willingness to treat what they
have said as trustworthy or untrustworthy cannot itself be induc-
tively based. Why not? Could I not learn that Smith is generally
trustworthy about his inner life too? The problem here is that we
could only derive well-founded inductive generalizations about
the connection between a man's trustworthiness in his monetary
transactions, say, and his trustworthiness in reporting his emotions
if we already had independent access to his emotions-which we
do not. Every piece of behavior is open to doubt. Does this entail
skepticism about the emotions of others? Or to compare the not
quite ridiculous with the not completely sublime, does my con-
clusion about the emotions of other people resemble Kant's
Against the Self-Images of the Age
conclusion about God: that the removal of knowledge has left room
for faith?
To put matters like this would be unhelpful; for clearly faith
in God is something that is dispensable. It is indeed of the essence
of faith that one can fail to have it. But if our beliefs about the
other people depend upon a presumption of their trustworthiness,
so that there is indeed a moral element in our beliefs about others
-and those who have wanted to mark a difference in this respect
between our knowledge of nature and our knowledge of others
have thus been right-it is not the case that we can rationally
decide not to make this presumption. For emotions are not
occurrences in the lives of individuals, insulated from similar
occurrences in the lives of other individuals. As Hume points out
in his discussion of sympathy in the Treatise, what I feel is in
large part a response to what I take others to feel or not feel. You
are resentful of my lack of gratitude at your generosity in the
face of my anger at your lack of sympathy for my depression over
your sentimentality. Such chains of emotion are characteristic
of the emotional life ; the plot of a novel often traces just such a
chain. It follows that systematic skeptical doubt about the emo-
tions of others, based on an acknowledgement of the opaque
quality of their behavior and a refusal to trust their avowals,
would produce an inability to respond to others, for we would
not know to what to respond and the reliefs that inform our
emotions would not specify adequate intentional objects for our
emotions. We have to trust one another at this basic level or be
paralysed in our humanity. This is not a choice.
There is one final point worth attending to. Small children
exhibit certain emotions spontaneously before they have learned
to pretend and about their emotions animals never learn to pre-
tend. So in these cases the element of trust in avowals is obviously
absent. Rage is an example of this. Small children also sometimes
learn in the case of certain other emotions to exhibit behavior
symbolically expressive of the emotion before they have learned
to feel the emotion. This is often true in the case of gratitude.
But what they have to learn in order to exhibit adult emotions
involves them in learning how to pretend, how to be ironic, how
to lie, and how to produce these stock responses which sustain
fatigued human relationships. In so doing they become, like the
adult world, opaque. Behaviorists were in the right when they
stressed that sometimes we want to claim that we can recognize
what others are feeling better than they can; but in repudiating
what introspectionists seemed to imply-that we are all continually
Emotion, behaviorand belief 2 43

opaque to each other all the time-they may have underrated the
extent to which we are very often opaque to each other a great
deal of the time. Misunderstanding and not understanding are
at the core of human life, a fact perhaps standing in the way of the
project of scientific inquiry about human beings, even if we view
it as an obstacle to be circumvented rather than as a final barrier.
This conclusion I find disconcerting. But perhaps the nature of
reality is such that we ought to have learned by now never to be
disconcerted at being disconcerted.
21

Rationality and the explanation


of action

I
It is distinctly unfashionable to attempt to characterize and to
understand the history of human societies in terms of an opposition
between reason and irrationality. There was a time-in the closing
decades of the last century-when to do so was in fashion. Anthro-
pologists such as Frazer and Tylor, historians of thought such as
Lecky and Dickson White all took the possibility of so doing for
granted ; and it is of course in part against their parochialism and
against that misdescription of other cultures and other ages which
resulted from too great a confidence in the categories of their own
age that we have been reacting. Or overreacting, as I shall argue in
this essay. It is not that I want to return to the concepts of rationa-
lity and irrationality of the late Victorian Age; it is rather that I
do not want to see the perception of those concepts as culture-
bound to lead to a blindness to the importance of ascriptions of
rationality and irrationality in the human sciences.
The contemporary attitude is strikingly exemplified in the
strictures passed by H. R. Trevor-Roper 1 on the nineteenth-cen-
tury liberal historians of witchcraft, strictures with which it would
be difficult to quarrel. None the less, even if with Trevor-Roper we
reject such notions as that intellectual history is "a direct contest
between reason and faith, reason and superstition," we may find
reasons for holding that, when we have conceded that, as Trevor-
Roper holds, "such a distinction between 'reason' and 'supersti-
tion' is difficult to maintain, the making of some such distinction is
unavoidable. Indeed, we may find those reasons in Trevor-Roper's
own essay. Trevor-Roper explains the European witch-craze of the
sixteenth and seventeenth centuries as the outcome of certain social
1 "The European Witch-Craze" in Religion, the Reformation and Social
Change (London; Macmillan, 1967).
244
Rationality and the explanation of action 245
strains and conflicts. He speaks of "a scapegoat for social frustra-
tion," of "the mythology of the witch-craze" as "the articulation of
social pressure" and of "social tension." I do not want to, I am of
course not competent to question the truth of his explanation; but I
do want to try to understand its logical structure, and the attempt
to do this will lead me to use terms which are not used by Trevor-
Roper himself. I hope therefore that I do not misrepresent. When
it is said that social pressures generate a belief, as Trevor-Roper
asserts that social tensions between the people of the mountains
and the people of the plains partly generated the sixteenth-century
belief in witches, I take it that something like the following is
meant. A certain social situation generates certain emotions, in this
case a certain kind of fear. Emotions are intentional; that is, they
presuppose beliefs and we cannot characterize the emotion except
in terms of the relevant object of belief. So an expression of
fear is the expression of a belief that something harmful or
dangerous is at hand. The belief may, of course, be false; and of
course the frightened person may both express his fear and yet
assert sincerely that he does know that there is really nothing to be
afraid of. But where an emotion is generated which has no adequate
intentional object, such an object will under certain circumstances
be supplied. Jews, witches, and Communists have all at certain
periods been available as such objects for fear; not the Jew, the
witch, or the Communist of course as he or she is, but as the social
stereotype has him or her. The form of explanation is thus as
follows: we explain the belief as brought into being by a need to
supply a rationale for the emotion; and we explain the emotion as
generated by the social structure.
It is noteworthy that, although Trevor-Roper scorns the use of
"superstition" by Lea and Lecky, he himself is quite prepared to
call the belief in witches "a mythology" and a "fantastic" mythology
at that, and perhaps this is not as marginal a matter as he himself
seems to think. For we have to ask whether the type of explanation
which he advances would be equally appropriate for the explana-
tion of any set of well-established beliefs, or whether we must not
distinguish a class of beliefs for which it would be appropriate
and a class for which it would be inappropriate. Consider, for
example, the beliefs of a deviant minority in the early seventeenth
century, beliefs whose incompatability with the socially established
doctrines of the dominant institutions led to some sporadic
persecution. I refer to the astronomers. If we ask why by 1630
most astronomers believed that Jupiter had satellites, the explana-
tion must begin not only from Galileo's observations, but from
Against the Self-Images of the Age
what had become accepted canons of observation and of argument.
If we ask why those canons were accepted, the only possible
answer will be a historical one. This history may reveal to us
certain conditions which appear to have been necessary prere-
quisites for the exercise of the rationality embodied in those
canons; but just because they will only be necessary conditions,
they will in no way provide an explanation of, for example, why
those canons rather than any others were adopted. Moreover,
what such a history would not and could not reveal to us would
be antecedent sufficient conditions, sufficient, that is, to bring
about the social practice of arguing in terms of those canons. My
reasons for asserting this can be put as follows. Once we have
asserted that the explanation of why men came to believe and
believed something or other is that their behavior and procedures
were governed by the appropriate rational criteria, we have
already in so doing asserted that they had made themselves in-
dependent of these psychological or social factors which on
occasion lead men to act or to believe regardless of where reason
points. If some antecedent condition, such as a form of social
structure or the prevalence of certain emotions, is sufficient to
produce a belief, irrespective of the reasoning appropriately to be
invoked, then explanation in terms of the procedures of rationality
is clearly out of place. So when Trevor-Roper cites the beliefs of
modern anti-Semitism, of medieval anti-Semitism, and of
McCarthyism as parallels to the sixteenth- and seventeenth-
century witch-craze, he points to, although he does not formulate
precisely, a generalization of the form "Whenever the social struc-
ture is of a certain kind, beliefs of a certain kind will be generated
independent of any rational support they may or may not have."
In cases where such a generalization holds, the belief in question
will clearly be generated if the antecedent sufficient conditions are
satisfied, whatever the state of the processes of argument and
deliberation appropriate to the rational formation of such a belief.
Where, however, a belief is intelligible only in terms of an ante-
cedent process of reasoning and could only be generated as the
outcome of such a process, it would follow that its being held
cannot be ascribed to antecedent sufficient conditions of the kind
invoked by Trevor-Roper to explain the witch-craze.
It thus appears that there is at least a preliminary case for
holding that not all beliefs are to be explained in the same way.
The form of explanation appropriate to rational beliefs seems to be
not the same as the form of explanation appropriate to irrational
beliefs. We can well understand at a semi-intuitive level why this
Rationality and the explanation of action 247
should be so. To characterize a belief as irrational is to charac-
terize the intellectual procedures and attitudes of those who hold
it. It is to say in effect-at least in the extreme case-that the
believer is invulnerable to rational argument. But to say this is
precisely to say that the belief is held as the outcome of ante-
cedent events or states of affairs which are quite independent of
any relevant process of appropriate deliberation. Thus, pace
Trevor-Roper, a crucial distinction between rationality and
irrationality or superstition must continue to be made and we
cannot simply remark, as he does, that we have now learned that
the mental structures of one age are not the same as the mental
structures of another. For the explanation of rational belief
terminates with an acccount of the appropriate intellectual norms
and procedures; the explanation of irrational belief must be in
terms of causal generalizations which connect antecedent con-
ditions specified in terms of social structures or psychological
states-or both-with the genesis of beliefs.
Suppose to this it were to be retorted that the explanation of
rational beliefs cannot terminate with an account of the relevant
norms and rule-governed procedures. For any social practice
which is informed by such a body of norms and procedures must
itself be explained by references to prior antecedent conditions.
This retort might be grounded in the conviction that every event
or state of affairs must have a cause. Now certainly one may be
able to identify many conditions necessary for the establishment
and maintenance of such social practices and more especially
conditions which favor or inhibit their institutionalization. But
sufficient conditions? What could these be? The notion of a
causal explanation for the genesis of an intellectual tradition is like
the notion of such an explanation for the genesis of a style of
painting. All attempts to give such explanations have foundered.
The most that any specification of antecedent conditions can give
us (as Antal unintentionally demonstrated in his work on Floren-
tine painting) is a set of necessary and predisposing conditions
which might be shown to make a given audience receptive to
works of art characterized as falling under some very general
description. But the style which in fact procures the reception
always does so by virtue of characteristics which escape such
descriptions. The specific characteristics of Florentine painting
which make it great painting can in no way be deduced from the
market situation of the Florentine painter. As with art, so with
astronomy or arithmetic.
Two points ought to be noted about the argument so far. The
9
Against the Self-Images of the Age
first is that, even if we accept it, Trevor-Roper's strictures upon
the liberal historians of thought remain justified to a very large
degree. This is because what is in question in his discussion is not
merely the propriety of ascribing rationality or irrationality to the
beliefs which the social historian and the sociologist study; there
is also the question of whether the liberal historian's conception
of rationality was coherent and adequate. In fact it was not, for
they tended to confuse the question of rationality with that of
truth. This confusion has often been repeated ;1 the importance
of not repeating it will emerge later in my argument. For the
moment I will simply point out that "true" and "false" are
predicated of what is believed, namely of statements, and the truth
or falsity of a statement is a matter quite independent of whether
that statement is believed by anyone at all. Rationality is predi-
cated of the attitudes, dispositions, and procedures of those who
believe; a man who uses the best canons available to him may
behave rationally in believing what is false, and a man who pays
no heed to the rules of evidence may behave irrationally in believing
what is true. The parochialism of the liberal historians of the late
Victorian Age lay in their treating as one of the criteria of rationality
assent to the truth of certain propositions which they them-
selves affirmed; false belief they took to be a symptom of irrationa-
lity. In taking this to be the case, they certainly believed what is
false and they were perhaps irrational in so doing. For what
entitles us to call the belief in witchcraft irrational is not its
falsity, but the fact of its incoherence with other beliefs and
criteria possessed by those who held it.
Secondly, I would like to emphasize that this preliminary thesis
-that the type of explanation appropriate to a rational belief is
different from that appropriate to an irrational belief-is to be
distinguished from the thesis that human actions cannot be
causally explained. I have advanced reasons for denying this
thesis elsewhere.2 But it is of course the case that the present thesis
is not without implications for the explanation of actions. What
some of these are will be considered in the third section of this
essay. Before I consider them, however, another issue must be
raised.

1 Most recently in the European Journal of Sociology, 1967, by S. Lukes,


p. 62., and J. Torrance, p. 276.
2 "The Antecedents of Action," pp. 191-210 and "The Idea of a
Social Science," pp. 211-29.
Rationality and the explanation of action 249

II
From the conclusion of my argument in the previous section-
that the explanation of the genesis and maintenance of irrational
beliefs must be of a different order from the explanation of the
genesis and maintenance of rational belief-it follows that the
sociologist cannot, in setting himself the task of such explanation,
abstain from judgment concerning the rationality or irrationality
of the beliefs which he studies. It follows that the "neutrality"
thesis expressed by Bryan Wilson for the sociology of religion
can only be held in a tempered version. Bryan Wilson has argued
that the sociologist of religion, so long as he studies religious
belief and the religious believer qua sociologist, may and ought to
remain neutral as to the truth and reasonableness of the beliefs
which are part of the object of his study. Qua man he will doubtless
be theist or atheist, Catholic, humanist, or Parsee. But this need
not affect his work as a sociologist. About this thesis I should want
to make two comments. The first is that, for reasons I have already
given, the question of the truth or falsity of the belief studied
is to some degree independent of the question of its rationality;
but, although this distinction must not be ignored, truth and
rationality are both conceptually and empirically related. For to
advance reasons is always to advance reasons for holding that a
belief is true or false; and rational procedures are in fact those
which yield us the only truths of which we can be assured. Thus,
to recognize a belief as rationally held is to lay oneself open to at
least the possibility of its truth. Hence, if the sociologist qua
sociologist must, in order to determine what form of explanation
is appropriate to the genesis and maintenance of the beliefs which
he is studying, pass a verdict upon the reasonableness or unreason-
ableness of the procedures of those who hold the belief, he may
find that he is at least partially committed in respect of truth or
falsity.
Secondly, we must not as a result of the present argument ela-
borate a picture of the sociologist as approaching his material with
his canons of rationality which he uses to sit in judgment upon the
irrationalities of those whom he studies. We must distinguish at
least two elements in rationality. The first element is a matter of
language. To understand what is said in a given culture, we must
learn to classify the forms of utterance, to distinguish assertions
from requests, wishes from commands, and so on. We shall not
250 Against the Self-Images of the Age
be able to do this except on the assumption that the laws of logic
are embodied in the linguistic practice of the community which
we are studying. If we cannot identify negation and such laws as
,....,1>=1'
,...., as embodied in this practice, I do not understand how
we can be confident in our identification of the speech acts of
assertion and denial. It follows that any notion of pre-logical
thought, if it is taken to be thought which displays no regard for
the laws of noncontradiction, for example, is extremely difficult to
understand. Perhaps Levy-Bruhl never did seriously mean any-
thing as extreme as this-although in his earlier writings he does
seem to. So far as this element in rationality is concerned then,
there is no question of us judging the rationality of alien cultures
in terms of our criteria. For the criteria are neither ours nor theirs,
but simply the criteria, and logic is the inquiry which formulates
them.
This has sometimes been recognized, however, in such a way
as to draw a sharp and quite misplaced contrast between this
element and another. For it is suggested that on matters of sub-
stance, rather than matters of logic, what is believed to be a good
reason for holding a certain belief in one culture will appear as
in no way a good reason for holding that belief in the context of
another culture. Hence, it appears that what is counted as rationa-
lity in one culture must be something quite different from what is
counted as rationality in another. Peter Winch has written that
"We start from the position that standards of rationality in
different societies do not always coincide." 1 In his view we thus
can speak of our criteria and of theirs, where criteria rationality
are concerned. But this view fails-quite apart from the point
about logic made above-for two reasons. First, no belief is
rational or irrational except relative to some other belief or beliefs.
Thus, to predicate rationality or irrationality of the complete set
of beliefs held in a given culture is always a mistake. To say that
a belief is rational is to talk about how it stands in relation to other
beliefs, given a background of yet further beliefs as to what
counts as a good reason for holding beliefs on a particular type of
subject matter in a given culture. Because this is so, we can only
ascribe rationality to others on the basis of their criteria of rationa-
lity. Or rather, the distinction between ours and thei.rsagain breaks
down. If we indict others for contradiction or incoherence, the
contradiction or incoherence is a feature of their beliefs, but the
standards of contradiction and incoherence must be the same for
1 "Understanding a Primitive Society," American Philosophical Quar-

terly, 1964, p. 317.


Rationality and the explanation of action 251

them and for us. Secondly, as we have been urged by anthro-


pologists such as Leach and Beattie, we have to be careful how to
construe the genre to which any particular utterance or set of
utterances belongs. We cannot begin to evaluate the rationality of
procedures until we know what is being said on the relevant
occasions, and we cannot know what is being said until we know
into what genres the utterances of a given culture may be classified.
But now consider an apparent counter-example to my thesis.
In Purity and Danger Mary Douglas has argued that the pollu-
tion and taboo rules of primitive societies are not to be construed
as, for example, unsophisticated exercises in practical hygiene.
When we place these rules in the context of the world-view of the
way of life of the people who uphold them, we begin to under-
stand the connection for those people between the notion of harm
or danger and the notion of an anomaly. An anomalous person or
animal or thing, one that cannot be fitted into the classificatory
scheme whereby the world is grasped, threatens the order of the
cosmos. The response to the recognition of its presence is not to
revise the classificatory scheme or to modify the beliefs under-
lying or springing from it ; it is to expel the offending instance.
Now the procedures in which this response is embodied are
notably different from what we have learnt from Pierce and Popper
to regard as characteristic of science. What is anomalous relative
to our present classificatory schemes, what constitutes a counter-
example to our present beliefs, is to be sought for in order that
we may revise and modify our present beliefs and expectations.
So far as science is concerned, the discovery of an anomaly is
always a victory. Surely it may then be argued the procedures of
science and the procedures described by Mary Douglas cannot
both be called rational. If the scientific mode of dealing with
counter-examples is rational, then the primitive mode must be
irrational. But to judge thus would surely be to judge their
procedures in terms of our criteria, in just the way that I have
suggested need not occur.
We must at once grant that if a contemporary scientist adopted
the attitude to the classification of animal species which, in Mary
Douglas's interpretation, was exhibited by the writer of Leviticus
we should at once have to suppose him at least prima facie guilty
of irrational behavior. But notice that in ascribing irrationality to
him we should be pointing to the incoherence and incompatibility
between the beliefs and criteria which he already possessed and his
new behavior. It is not just that his behavior would be at odds
with what we believe to be appropriate; it would be at odds with
252 Against the Self-Images of the Age
what we know him to believe to be appropriate. But in the prac-
tices codified by the writer of Leviticus, there is no such inco-
herence; those who engaged in such practices were not trying to
be Linnaeus and failing. The point of their enterprise was quite
different. Can we say what it was?
Here my previous point about the need to identify genres
correctly becomes crucial. To a Frazer, who classified primitive
rites as inept technology, we are apt to reply that such rites are
not science but, for example, a kind of po~try or drama. Thus
John Beattie asserts that magic is not technology but "the acting
out of the expression of a desire in symbolic terms" (Other
Cultures, p. 72 ). I am not competent to question Beattie's ethno-
graphic findings, insofar as these are empirical. It is, however,
right to wonder whether, sophisticated as we are, we may not
sometimes at least continue to make Frazer's mistake, but in a
more subtle way. For when we approach the utterances and
activities of an alien culture with a well-established classification
of genres in our mind and ask of a given rite or other practice "Is it
a piece of applied science? Or a piece of symbolic and dramatic
activity? Or a piece of theology?" we may in fact be asking a set of
questions to which any answer may be misleading-although
doubtless Beattie's answers are far less misleading than Frazer's.
For the utterances and practice in question may belong, as it were,
to all and to none of the genres that we have in mind. For those
who engage in the given practice the question of how their
utterances are to be interpreted-in the sense of "interpretation"
in which to allocate a practice or an utterance to a genre is to
interpret it, as a prediction, say, rather than as a symbolic ex-
pression of desire, or vice versa-may never have arisen. If we
question them as to how their utterances are to be interpreted,
we may therefore receive an answer which is sincere and yet we
may still be deceived. For we may, by the very act of asking these
questions, have brought them to the point where they cannot
avoid beginning to construe their own utterances in one way
rather than another. But perhaps this was not so until we asked the
question. Perhaps before that time their utterances were poised
in ambiguity. It would follow that questions of rationality and
irrationality cannot be appropriately posed until in a given culture
the relevant utterances are given a decisive interpretation in terms
of genres. Myths would then be seen as perhaps potentially
science and literature and theology; but to understand them as
myths would be to understand them as actually yet none of these.
Hence the absurdity involved in speaking of myths as misrepre-
Rationality and the explanation of action 253
senting reality; the myth is at most a possible misrepresentation of
reality, for it does not aspire, while still only a myth, to be a
representation.
In the cases where we are right to allocate utterances and
practices to genres, it is with reference to the speakers' own
implicit or explicit allocations that we ascribe rationality or
irrationality. In the areas where we would be mistaken in so
allocating utterances, we are not entitled to ascribe either. In
both cases it is clear that, even though we are now concerned
with criteria other than those with which formal logic is concerned,
there is once again no question of being able to distinguish be-
tween our criteria of rationality (the anthropologists' or sociolo-
gists') and their criteria (those of the agents whose culture is the
object of study). Rationality is nobody's property. It is necessary
to re-emphasize this point in order even more clearly to discrimi-
nate the position defended in this essay from that of the Victorian
defenders of reason, and in order to show that a rationalist stand-
point is not merely (as Winch takes it to be) the ideological
standpoint of a Western culture which aspires to be the judge of
others without being judged itself. The argument of this essay
implies the possibility of ascribing irrationality to modern Western
culture on precisely the same grounds as we should make this
ascription elsewhere. One final footnote to this section of the
argument: the community of shared rationality to which I have
argued that all recognizably human societies must belong must of
course also be a community of shared beliefs to some extent. For
there are some commonsense beliefs (about day and night, the
weather and the material environment generally) which are in-
escapable for any rational agent.

III
If we discriminate the rational and the irrational in the way that
I have suggested in the second section of this essay, and if the
form of explanation appropriate to irrational beliefs differs from
that appropriate to rational beliefs, as I have suggested in the first
section, what follows so far as the explanation of action is con-
cerned?
Beliefs and actions are, after all, intimately related, since it is a
central feature of actions that they are expressive of beliefs ; and
this is not just a contingent fact about actions. An action is identi-
fiable as the action that it is only in terms of the agent's intention.
2 54 Against the Self-Images of the Age
An intention can only be specified in terms of a first-person
statement. The expressions used in formulating such a statement
(even if the agent does not himself formulate it explicitly) will
presuppose certain beliefs on the agent's part. An everyday in-
tention to spray my roses to kill the green-fly or an exceptional
intention to assassinate an archduke and liberate Bosnia alike pre-
suppose an extended web of beliefs, botanical in the one case,
political in the other. It is for this reason that it is possible to
predicate of actions characteristics which it is the province of logic
to consider. An action may be consistent or inconsistent with an
agent's other beliefs, and one action may be consistent or incon-
sistent with another in terms of the beliefs presupposed. As
Aristotle pointed out, an action may conclude a syllogistic argu-
ment in a way analogous to that in which the utterance of a state-
ment may. It follows that the sociologist or anthropologist will
not even have succeeded in identifying correctly the actions which
are the object of his study unless and until he has identified the
web of beliefs expressed in those actions.
It is important to underline this because there is a tendency,
perhaps at its strongest in contemporary political science, to
suppose that the object of study in the human sciences is behavior,
and "behavior" is an expression understood in these quarters in a
behaviorist sense. Haunted by the ghosts of philosophical con-
troversies about dualism, such theorists wish to analyse all
mental predicates in behavioral terms and "belief" is an important
candidate for such an analysis. But no such analysis can succeed in
the case of "belief" at least. For all such analyses must, as their
proponents allow, include reference to what they quaintly call
"linguistic behavior." More particularly, if we try to analyse
the notion of belief in behavioral terms, then to say that someone
believes that such-and-such is the case will have to be analysed
not only in terms of dispositions to do and to expect certain things,
but also in terms of dispositions to say certain things. What sort of
disposition to say will be involved? The answer must be a dis-
position to make certain assertions. But what is an assertion? It is
the utterance of a statement in such a way as to give a hearer or
reader to understand that the statement is believed by the speaker
or writer and is worthy of belief. Thus, the notion of belief has not
been analysed away into behavioral terms, for the notion of asser-
tion-which any analysis that sought to be convincing would have
to employ-can itself be understood only in terms of the notion of
belief. So the notion of belief turns out to be ineliminable, and the
contemporary project of a science of behavior is seen to invert the
Rationality and the explanation of action 255
proper relationship between belief and action. Actions must be
understood in terms of their character as expressions of belief;
beliefs are not simply patterns of behavior plus dispositions to
produce such patterns.
I have already noted that to say that rational belief cannot be
explained in causal terms is not to say or to imply that actions, even
the actions of a man who acts upon a rational belief in a rational
way, cannot be explained in causal terms. Indeed, as I have
argued elsewhere,1 to treat an agent's actions as the outcome of the
reasons which he possessed for acting in the way that he did is
precisely to point to one kind of cause as operative and to exclude
other possible causal explanations. The notion that an agent's
having a reason to do something may be the cause of his doing it
is necessary if we are to distinguish reasons which are genuinely
effective from mere rationalizations which are not. But although
actions can have causes (in the sense of sufficient and not merely
of necessary conditions), the close link between actions and beliefs
would suggest that the asymmetry between the explanation of
rational belief for which I have argued ought to entail some
asymmetry between the explanation of rational action and the
explanation of irrational action. That it does so is made clear if we
consider two distinct types of cases which lie at opposite ends of a
dimension on which the relation of belief and action can be
charted.
At one end of this spectrum there is the case where an agent acts
rationally on the basis of his beliefs ; at the other end there is the
case where the agent's beliefs only affect his actions in the most
minimal way. There are cultures where the occurrence of the
latter type of case is a characteristic feature of social life ; in parts
of Latin America, for example, belief in sacramental monogamous
marriage is part of the Catholicism of the inhabitants, but the
actual forms of their sexual unions rarely, if ever, conform to the
Catholic pattern. There are other cultures (Campbell's account of a
Greek highland village is one example) where the professed beliefs
of the agents actually inform the detail of their day to day social
life. The difference between these types of cases is in the first
instance a difference in what requires explanation. For actions
which accord with the beliefs of an agent stand in need of no
further explanation than do the beliefs themselves; actions which
do not so accord clearly do stand in need of an independent
explanation, and the gap between belief and action itself requires
to be explained. It follows that once again there is an asymmetry,
1 See pp. 215-17.
Against the, Self-Images of the Age
although a rather different one. Where actions do accord with
beliefs, the form of explanation will be one in which the whole
complex of belief and action is to be explained together; and when
the beliefs are rational, explanation will terminate with the account
of the norms involved. Where, on the other hand, the beliefs are
irrational or the actions do not accord with beliefs, explanation
will 'have to go beyond the delineation of the relevant norms; for
1

we shalf need to know at least why discrepancies and incoherencies,


contradictions and other irrationalities are tolerated by the agents
concerned. Sociological discovery will be an uncovering of those
mechanisms which blind agents to or enable them to ignore the
irrationalities of their own social order. Hence, the asymmetry
in what demands explanation will be matched by an asymmetry
in the forms of explanation given. Irrational action-whether
irrational because expressive of irrational beliefs or because of
inconsistency between beliefs and actions-will be explicable in
terms other than those in which rational action is to be explained,
just as irrational beliefs are to be explained in terms other than
those in which rational beliefs are to be explained.
The nature of the gap between belief and action has tradi-
tionally provided matter for the philosophical problem of &xpixa!ix.
But treatments of that problem fastened upon the gap that some-
times exists between the moral beliefs of an individual agent and
his actions. The gap with which I am concerned here is one that is
institutionalized so that there is a systematic discrepancy be-
tween the norms dominant in the culture and the characteristic
behavior of agents in that culture. For the problem of rationality
is a problem of the relationship of the beliefs and norms which
define the roles which structure action in a given social order and
the beliefs and norms of the agents whose behavior is charac-
teristically governed or defined by these roles. Consider, for
example, the contrast between a society such as Britain
where articulate beliefs about the hierarchy of status and class
cohere well with the role-governed behavior of agents in
status and class situations and a society such as the United
States where behavior expresses an implicit recognition of
hierarchies of status and class, the existence of which at the
level of articulate belief a surprisingly large proportion of the
population deny. What needs to be explained is why this contradic-
tion is tolerable and the hypotheses about comparative rates of
mobility or about social identity which are sometimes advanced on
this subject will only have explanatory power if they can explain
this. To adopt this perspective may be procedurally important
Rationality and the explanation of action 257
for the empirical investigator in directing his attention to one set
of facts rather than another. If we wish to explain the civil rights
movement among American Negroes, for example, we shall do
well to pause and ask what needs to be explained. Is it why since
1953 Negro students have acted on the beliefs which they are
taught in school that all American citizens, indeed all men, have
certain rights? or is it, rather, why they failed for so long or were
unable to act on their beliefs? If the latter, we shall expect no
general, as it were positive explanation of the Negro civil rights
movement, but only a series of explanations of why the different
particular obstacles to such a movement were removed in the early
1950s. These examples are large, obvious, and unsophisticated, but
perhaps the obviousness will compensate for the lack of sophistica-
tion.

IV

Consider now an example of a very different kind. The weight of


my initial argument was directed against the contention that we
did not need to discriminate between rational and irrational
beliefs in order to explain the origin and the maintenance of those
beliefs. But I now wish to press further another contention, namely
that in discriminating between what is rational and what is irra-
tional we must not mistake the standards of normal belief and
behavior in our own age for the standards of rational belief and
behavior as such. This mistake seems to me embodied in Norman
Cohn's The Pursuit of the Millennium. It is to the point that
Cohn's exploratory apparatus is psychological and that he appears
to believe that the key psychological terms which he deploys can
be deployed without reference to the criteria of the culture which
is the object of his inquiry. So we find in his pages 1 the following
argument: J. A. Boullan, the nineteenth-century sectarian, was
declared by psychiatrists on the evidence of his actions and his
handwriting to suffer from paranoia; J. A. Boullan's beliefs and
behavior resemble those of the late medieval Brethren of the Free
Spirit; therefore the medieval Brethren of the Free Spirit may be
presumed to have suffered from paranoia. Now to suffer from
paranoia is precisely to have delusions as to one's importance and
as to one's relations to others. But which beliefs count as delusions
and which as rational is a matter of the standards of a given time
and place.
When we examine the case of Thomas Munzer, for example-
1 1962 edition, pp. 185-86.
Against the Self-Images of the Age
of whom Cohn treats-we find that Munzer accepts, just as his
Protestant and Catholic enemies did, the standard of scripture.
But he is more, rather than less, rational than they in interpreting
scripture, if anything. For he takes at their face value certain New
Testament injunctions, for which his opponents have to provide
special explanations. Munzer, after much careful study, took on the
office of a propheta, an office of whose place in the early church he
read in the New Testament, but which he found absent in six-
teenth-century churches. It is very difficult to see that Munzer's
apocalyptic reading of the New Testament is less rational than the
faith of the bishops who condemned Munzer or of Luther, both
of whom have to flout New Testament texts in which they pro-
fessedly believe.
Cohn's error resides in making the content of beliefs and not
their irrationality the criterion of their being delusional. It is not
perhaps surprising that apocalyptic prophesying should be con-
demned in a book whose ethos is as much a reflection of the climate
in which the end-of-ideology thesis was born as Cohn's is. But the
true conclusion to be drawn reflects not on the rationality of those
sixteenth-century revolutionaries, such as Munzer, whom Cohn
so dislikes, as on the defensibility of contemporary views of the
nature of rationality.

Two final morals: the first is that, if I am correct in supposing


rationality to be an inescapable sociological category, then once
again the positivist account of sociology in terms of a logical
dichotomy between facts and values must break down. For to
characterize actions and institutionalized practices as rational or
irrational is to evaluate them. Nor is it the case that this evaluation
is an element superadded to an original merely descriptive element.
To call an argument fallacious is always at once to describe and to
evaluate it. It is highly paradoxical that the impossibility of deduc-
ing evaluative conclusions from factual premises should have been
advanced as a truth of logic, when logic is itself the science in
which the coincidence of description and evaluation is most
obvious. The social scientist is, if I am right, committed to the
values of rationality in virtue of his explanatory projects in a
stronger sense than the natural scientist is. For it is not only the
case that his own procedures must be rational; but he cannot
escape the use of the concept of rationality in his inquiries.
Rationality and the explanation of action 259
A second moral is that, if my arguments are correct, then the
social scientist cannot evade the task of deciding what types of
arguments and evidence are logically appropriate in different
areas ; he must be able to decide what constitutes the rationality of
a scientific belief, or a moral belief, or a religious belief. But to do
this is to do philosophy. It follows that the relationship of social
science to philosophy must be other than the relationship of
natural science to philosophy. The philosopher cannot be merely
an external commentator on the social sciences; for philosophical
arguments will actually enter into and forge critical links within
the sociologist's explanations. The expulsion of philosophy from
the social sciences-or at least the restriction of philosophy to
post eventum comment on the social scientist's concepts and pro-
cedures-turns out to be another lost positivistic cause. Happily
or unhappily, the philosophers cannot be restricted merely to
interpreting the social sciences; the point of their activity is to
change them.
22

Is a scienceof comparative politics


possible?

There was once a man who aspired to be the author of the general
theory of holes. When asked "What kind of hole-holes dug by
children in the sand for amusement, holes dug by gardeners to
plant lettuce seedlings, tank traps, holes made by roadmakers ?"
he would reply indignantly that he wished for a general theory
that would explain all of these. He rejected ab initio the-as he saw
it-pathetically common-sense view that of the digging of dif-
ferent kinds of holes there are quite different kinds of explanations
to be given; why then he would ask do we have the concept of a
hole? Lacking the explanations to which he originally aspired, he
then fell to discovering statistically significant correlations; he
found for example that there is a correlation between the aggre-
gate hole-digging achievement of a society as measured, or at least
one day to be measured, by econometric techniques, and its
degree of technological development. The United States surpasses
both Paraguay and Upper Volta in hole-digging. He also discovered
that war accelerates hole-digging ; there are more holes in Vietnam
than there were. These observations, he would always insist,
were neutral and value-free. This man's achievement has passed
totally unnoticed except by me. Had he however turned his talents
to political science, had he concerned himself not with holes, but
with modernization, urbanization or violence, I find it difficult to
believe that he might not have achieved high office in the APSA.

I
The ultimate aim of this paper is constructive; the skepticism
which infects so much of my argument is a means and not an end.
I do not want to show that there cannot be a general science of
political action, but only to indicate certain obstacles that stand in
260
ls a scienceof comparativepolitics possible? 261

the way of the founding of such a science and to suggest that the
present practice of so-called political science is unlikely to over-
come these obstacles. In writing more specifically of comparative
political science I do not wish to suggest that there could be any
other sort of political science; this the APSA recognized when it
merged what was its section devoted to comparative politics into
the general body. It is with the claim to be using legitimate
comparativemethods which could enable us to advance and to test
genuine law-like cross-culturalgeneralizations that I shall initially
be concerned. I shall not be concerned to question the possibility
of genuine and relevant comparison and even of cross-cultural
comparison for other purposes: to exhibit the march of the
Weltgeist through history, for instance, or to draw moral lessons
about the respective benefits of barbarism and civilization. These
may or may not be reputable activities; I shall not argue for or
against them here. I shall be solely interested in the project of a
political science, of the formulation of cross-cultural, law-like
causal generalizations which may in turn be explained by theories,
as the generalizations of Boyle's Law and Dalton's Law are
explained by the kinetic theory of gases ; all that I say about the
problem of comparability must be understood in this particular
context. Moreover, my skepticism about any alleged parallel
between theorizing about politics and theorizing about gases will
not initially be founded on the consideration of the character of
human action in general. I shall not argue, for example, that
human actions cannot have causes, not just or even mainly because
I believe that this proposition is false, but because I believe that,
even if its falsity is agreed, we still have substantial grounds for
skepticism about comparative political science. My method of
proceeding in the first part of my argument will be as follows: I
shall examine in turn the claim to have formulated law-like
generalizations about political attitudes, about political institutions
and practices, and about the discharge of political functions. I
shall then in the second part of my argument suggest an alternative
strategy to that now customarily employed, although the change
in strategy will turn out to also involve a change in aim.

II
The study of political culture, of political attitudes, as it has been
developed, seems to rest upon the assumption that it is possible
to identify political attitudes independently of political institutions
262 Against the Self-Images of the Age
and practices. There are at least two reasons for thinking this
assumption false. The first derives from Wittgenstein, who
pointed out that we identify and define attitudes in terms of the
objects toward which they are directed, and not vice versa. Our
understanding of the concept of fear depends upon our under-
standing of the concepts of harm and danger and not vice versa.
Our understanding of the concept of an aesthetic attitude depends
upon our understanding of the concept of a work of art. It follows
that an ability to identify a set of attitudes in one culture as
political, and a set of attitudes in some second culture as political,
with a view to comparing them must depend upon our ~aving
already identified as political in both cultures a set of institutions
and practices toward which these attitudes are directed. In other
words, the ability to construct comparative generalizations about
attitudes depends on our already having solved the problem of
how to construct comparative generalizations about institutions
and practices. The notion of political culture is secondary to and
parasitic upon the notion of political practice.
It follows that a necessary condition of a comparative investiga-
tion of political cultures is that the argument about the compara-
bility of political institutions should have a certain outcome; but
this is only a necessary end not a sufficient condition. It is also
necessary if political attitudes are to be the subject of comparative
inquiry that other attitudes shall be susceptible of comparison of
a certain kind. I can explain what I mean by this by citing an
example from The Civic Culture (Chapter IV, pp. 102-5) where
Almond and Verba argue that Italians are less committed to
and identified with the actions of their government than are
Germans or Englishmen, offering as evidence the fact that the
Italian respondents, as compared with the English and German
respondents to their survey, placed such actions very low on a list
of items to which they had been asked to give a rank order in terms
of the amount of pride they took in them. At no point do Almond
and Verba pause to ask whether the concept of pride is the same
in the three different national cultures, that is, to ask whether the
different respondents had after all been asked the same question.
But in fact the concept of pride(" ... si sente piu' orgoglioso ... ")
in Italy is not the same as that pride in England. The notion of
taking pride in Italian culture is still inexorably linked, especially
in the South but also in the North, to the notion of honor. What
one takes pride in is what touches on one's honor. If asked
to list the subjects which touched their honor, many Italians would
spontaneously place the chastity of their immediate female
Is a science of comparative politics possible? 263
relatives high on the list-a connection that it would occur to very
few Englishmen to make. These notions of pride and honor
partially specify and are partially specified by a notion of the
family itself importantly, if imperfectly, embodied in the actualities
of Italian family life. Hence we cannot hope to compare an Italian's
attitude to his government's acts with an Englishman's in respect
of the pride each takes; any comparison would have to begin from
the different range of virtues and emotions incorporated in the
different social institutions. Once again the project of comparing
attitudes independently of institutions and practices encounters
difficulties. These particular difficulties suggest that a key question
is: what are the units in each culture which are compared to be?
To this question I shall of course return; but let me note that the
difficulty which I have exemplified in the preceding argument
is contingent on Almond and Verba's particular procedures. It
does not arise from the project of comparison as such. For the
difficulty which arises over any comparison between English and
German culture on the one hand, and Italian on the other, from
relying on the in fact false assumption that these cultures agree in
their concept of pride would not arise in the same way if Italian
attitudes were to be compared with Greek, for example. Not that
there would not be other and perhaps more subtle pitfalls, but
these would not arise merely because concepts of pride and
honor are not shared.
We can now pose our problem in the following way: we wish
to find identifiable units in different societies and cultures about
which we may construct true causal generalizations. Political
attitudes, for the two reasons I have given, are implausible can-
didates; what about political institutions and practices? The first
point to be made here is that in turning to the discussion of
political institutions and practices we have not left behind the
topic of political attitudes. For attitudes to and beliefs about
institutions and practices may sometimes be purely external
phenomena; that is, the institution or the practice is what it is
and does what it does independently of what certain people think
and feel about it. But it is an obvious truism that no institution
or practice is what it is, or does what it does, independently of
what anyone whatsoever thinks or feels about it. For institutions
and practices are always partially, even if to differing degrees,
constituted by what certain people think and feel about them.
Consider the example of a currency system: a given type of
piece of paper or of metal has the value that it has not only because
it has been issued by a duly constituted authority, but because it is
Against the Self-Images of the Age
accepted as having that value by the members of a particular
currency-using population. When this condition is not generally
satisfied, as in Germany and Austria in 1923, the currency ceases
to have value, and thus ceases to be currency. So also with an
army: an officer has the authority that he has not only because his
commission has been issued by a duly constituted authority, but
because he is accepted as having that status by the men serving
under him. When this condition is not generally satisfied, as in
Russia in 1917, an officer ceases to have authority, and thus ceases
to be an officer. Since such beliefs about social institutions are
partially constitutive of social institutions, it is impossible to
identify the institution except in terms of the beliefs of those who
engage in its practices. This fact is ignored in general by those who
wish to define political science as the study of political behavior,
with a view to thereby providing a public, neutral subject matter
for scientific enquiry. But if we identify behavior except in terms
of the intentions and therefore of the beliefs of the agents we shall
risk describing what they are doing as what we would be doing if
we went through that series of movements or something like it
rather than what they are actually doing. Nor do we avoid this
difficulty merely by finding some description of the behavior in
question which both the agents themselves and the political
scientist would accept. For clearly both agents and political scientist
might apply the description "voting behavior" to what they do,
but yet have a quite different understanding of what it is to vote.
But now what bearing does all this have upon the project of
comparing political institutions and practices?

III
I take it that if the generalizations which political scientists con-
struct are to be part of a science, then among the conditions which
must be satisfied is this: that we shall be able to distinguish
between genuine law-like generalizations and mere def acto generali-
zations which hold only of the instances so far observed. I under-
stand by this distinction, as many others have understood by it,
the difference between a generalization the assertion of which
commits one to the assertion of a set of corresponding counter-
factual conditionals and a generalization which does not so com-
mit one. In the natural sciences the ground for treating a generaliza-
tion as a law is generally not merely that as a matter of fact no
plausible counter-examples have yet been produced. It is also nor-
Is a science of comparative politics possible? 265
mally required that it be supported by a body of theory. But what
then of these generalizations which we wish to assert as genuine law-
like generalizations before we have any well-established theory?
What about the generalizations of Kepler or of Galileo before
Newton formulated his laws? What about Boyle's Law or Dalton's
Law before the establishment of the kinetic theory? At this point
the problems of confirmation theory become real.
The particular finding of confirmation theory that is relevant is
that the degree to which a positive instance does genuinely confirm
a generalization is in part a matter of the kind of environment in
which it is found. For the greater the extent of the radically
different environments in which confirmatory instances of a genera-
lization are found, the less likely it is that the generalization is
only confirmed in certain contingent environmental circumstances.
Now it is a matter of contingent fact that nature is so structured
that this condition is normally realizable. For nature could have
been otherwise. If black ravens on being taken into laboratories
for pigmentation tests, or if black ravens on being observed in the
Arctic-in the course of our seeking confirmation or otherwise
of the generalization that all ravens are black-promptly turned
into philosphers of science or clouds of dust, generalizations about
ravenly nigritude could not be as well founded as they are. But in
fact the character of social life is such that in some respects it
resembles this imaginary nature rather than nature as it-for-
tunately for natural scientists-is.
Consider for example the alleged generalization that in two-
party electoral systems the two parties will tend to move together
in their policies and the alleged explanation for this generalization,
that this is because neither party can hope to win those voters
attracted by the furthest opposed wing of the other party, but only
those nearest to it. Hence where, for example, the parties and their
wings can be placed on a Left-Right dimension, each party tends
to move its policies toward the center, having no hope of winning
votes from the extreme Right or Left. Now consider two different
kinds of attempts to provide counter-examples to this generaliza-
tion. An example of the first would be Greece before the coup
d'etat of the colonels. This seems to be a straightforward refuta-
tion of the generalization, even if we remember that a single
counter-example in the natural sciences is never adequate to
refute a well-established theory or a generalization with a huge
weight of evidence supporting it, such as the generalization that
all solids except bismuth, cast-iron, ice, and type metal expand
when heated. For here we have nothing like a well-supported
266 Against the Self-Images of the Age
theory or generalization; it is rather as if the seventh raven we
were to come across was colored magenta. Now consider a quite
different kind of attempt to provide a counter-example.
Suppose that someone were to point to the rival parties in
Sierra Leone immediately before the army seized power there,
and to offer them as a counter-example. We ought at once to
remember what Ruth Schachter wrote of African mass parties:
"They and their cultural affiliates were interested in everything
from the cradle to the grave-in birth, initiation, religion, marriage,
divorce, dancing, song, plays, feuds, debts, land, migration, death,
public order-and not only electoral success." At once the question
cannot but be framed: "Why do we think of these as parties, rather
than as, say, churches?" The answer, that they have some of the
marks of American political parties, and that they call themselves
parties, does nothing to show that in fact the meaning of "party"
is not radically changed when the cultural context is radically
changed, or that even if it is not changed the: description has not
become inapplicable. The intentions, the beliefs, the concepts
which inform the practices of African mass parties provide so
different a context that there can be no question of transporting
the phenomena of party to this context in order to provide a
suitably different environment for testing our generalization.
Where the environment and where the culture is radically dif-
ferent the phenomenon is viewed so differently by those who
participate in it that it is an entirely different phenomenon. In
just this respect does society differ from nature. That is to say,
the provision of an environment sufficiently different to make the
search for counter-examples interesting will normally be the
provision of an environment where we cannot hope or expect to
find examples of the original phenomenon and therefore cannot
hope to find counter-examples.
Note that my thesis is not that to transplant a phenomenon such
as party is to subject it to causal influences which transform it.
That is doubtless true. But the difficulty of studying political
parties in alien social environments to test a generalization con -
structed about political parties in familiar social environments is
not like the difficulty of studying viruses : that their own causal
properties and/or those of the environment cause them to mutate
too rapidly and too often. If this were the type of difficulty that we
encountered in formulating cross-cultural generalizations about
politics, then we might well ask if we could not insulate the object
of study in its new environment from the disturbing causal
influences at work. To ask this would be to mistake my point
ls a scienceof comparativepolitics possible? 267
which is not about causal interference with the phenomenon of
party, but with the absence of the same concept of party, or perhaps
of any concept of party, as we understand it, in the alien culture.
Let me now consider a possible objection to this thesis which
would base itself upon my choice of examples. A quite different
choice of examples might provide us with more plausible candidates
for cross-cultural generalization. Consider the alleged (and quite
possibly false) generalization that in the government of cities, if
a single non-transferable vote for single members is the method of
election, then there will be over a certain time span a tendency
for a two-party system to flourish. This seems to hold in the
United States. But it might hold in other alien environments, even
environments of an exotic kind, where we could identify the system
as two-party, even if unclear in what sense the parties were parties.
But this is surely therefore an example of at least a possible cross-
cultural comparison which provides us with a law-like generaliza-
tion and is therefore lethal to my entire thesis. Let me at once
concede that I take this generalization to be law-like in that it
does indeed entail counter-factual conditionals, and let me further
concede that the counter-factuals in question might be true. But
I do not concede that it injures my thesis. Why not?
The reason for not conceding that this example, if true, would
injure my thesis is intimately connected with the fact that I should
not be extremely surprised if the generalization in question did
turn out to be true of cities outside North America as well as in
North America. For what could make the generalization true, if
true, is that voters prefer in general not to waste their votes in
voting on matters that concern the administration of their daily
lives; and it requires only a minimal and a very untheoretical
understanding of the electoral system produced by such a voting
procedure to understand that in the majority of cases votes for a
third party will be wasted. The considerations from which we
can deduce this particular generalization are thus concerned with
human rationality in general; they do not have any specific con-
nection with politics and they do not belong to political science,
but to our general understanding of rationality. This will be true
of all generalizations which concern the formal structures of
human argument, even if they appear in political clothing, furnish-
ing us with explanations of particular political choices and actions.
So it must be, for example, with all applications of the theory of
games to politics.
My thesis about the legitimacy or otherwise of the project of
accumulating a stock of cross-cultural generalizations about
Against the Self-Images of the Age
political behavior to furnish the empirical foundation for a political
science, as I have developed it so far, can now be stated disjunc-
tively: either such generalizations about institutions will neces-
sarily lack the kind of confirmation they require or they will be
consequences of true generalizations about human rationality
and not part of a specifically political science.
To complete this part of my argument I must now make three
further observations. The first is that my statement of the diffi-
culties in constructing true and warranted cross-cultural generali-
zations about political institutions is obviously akin to the argu-
ments which some anthropologists-notably Edmund Leach and
Walter Goldschmidt-have developed about cross-cultural gene-
ralizations in their discipline. But Goldschmidt has then argued
that it is not institutions, but functions, or rather institutions only
as serving certain functions, which we ought to aspire to compare;
and this contention has already been advanced by some political
scientists. We are, that is to say, to begin by identifying the same
function in different societies and then to inquire how quite
different institutions have this same effect; for I take it that to say
that X performs, serves, or discharges a given function always
entails that X is the cause of a particular effect, even if this does
not exhaust the meaning of the statement in which function was
ascribed. It is certainly not a final objection to this project that
most political scientists who have tried to specify the functions in
question have produced nothing but statements about institutions
and their effects in which the word "function" may appear, but
could be replaced not only without loss, but with gain. "Wherever
the political party has emerged, it appears to perform some com-
mon functions in a wide variety of political systems ... the organi-
zation called the party is expected to organize public opinion and
to communicate demands to the center of governmental power and
decision . . . the party must articulate to its followers the concept
and meaning of the broader community ... the party is likely to
be involved in political recruitment . . . These similarities of
function ... suggest that the political party when the activities
of a political system reach a certain degree of complexity, or
whenever the notion of political power comes to include the idea
that the mass public must participate or be controlled. " 1 In a
passage like this, the notion of function can be replaced entirely
by either the notion of effect or the notion of purpose. When
we so replace it, we notice also that the transition from previous
1 J. LaPalombara and M. Weiner, eds., Political Parties and Political
Development (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press).
ls a science of comparative politics possible? 269
to tentative conclusion requires no reliance on any factual genera-
lizations anyway; it is merely a matter of drawing out the con-
sequences of definition. But even if in the writing of political
scientists as sophisticated as LaPalombara and Weiner the
function of the use of "function" is unclear, it does not follow
that this has to be so. But the condition of its not being so is that
we should have some criteria for identifying the functions served
by political institutions which is other than, and independent of,
the aims and purposes of political agents and the effects of political
institutions. The provision of such a criteria would require the
identification of a system, using the word "system" precisely, so
that concepts of feedback and equilibrium are applicable on the
basis of quantitative data which will provide values for variables
in differential equations. I scarcely need stress the remoteness
of this goal from the present state of all political science; if we
match the requirements that have to be satisfied to identify
such a system-which would involve, for example, being able
to distinguish between change that is part of the movement of
items through the system, change that is itself part of the struc-
turing of the system, and change that is the system decaying by
providing ways of measuring rates of change for all three-then
a work like David Easton's A Systems Analysis of Political Life
looks like a mad, millenarian dream. I therefore take it that any
attempt to answer my argument by suggesting that cross-cultural
generalizations about institutions may be provided by means of a
prior account in terms of functions is bound to fail.
My second observation is that my argument does not imply any
undervaluation of the importance of the work done by political
scientists in establishing both the facts about particular institutions
and the very limited generalizations they do establish. That the
conditions under which these generalizations hold necessarily
remain unclear to us for the kind of reason that I have given
does not mean that we do not need the best that we can get in this
case, which is what they give us; only this kind of accumulation
of data in no way leads toward the construction of a science. I
shall later suggest an alternative context in which these empirical
labors could perhaps be viewed more constructively. For the
moment I note that it is Machiavelli who ought to be regarded as
the patron saint of political studies and not Hobbes, and for this
reason: Hobbes believed-as presumably Almond and La-
Palombara and Easton (although Easton, in ways that I do not
entirely understand, tries to distinguish his enterprise from that of
Hobbes) believe-that the fortuitous, the surprising, the unpre-
Against the Self-Images of the Age
dieted, arise in politics only because our knowledge of political
motions is less adequate than our knowledge of planetary motions.
Given time, labor, and foundation grants-the contemporary
version of royal patronage--an unpredicted revolution-but for
the sheer complexity of human affairs-ought to be as disgraceful
to political scientists as an unpredicted eclipse to astronomers.
But Machiavelli realized that in political lifefortuna, the bitch god-
dess of unpredictability, has never been dethroned. To any
stock of maxims derived from empirically founded generalizations
the student of politics must always add one more: "And do not
be surprised if in the event things turn out otherwise." The need to
include this maxim follows from my argument, just as it follows
from Machiavelli's.
My third observation is that in the history of political theory we
have more than once been here before, and notably in the dispute
between James Mill and Macaulay. James Mill argued, although in
the interests of a quite different conclusion, even more that we
cannot find reliable empirical generalizations about political
behavior: "Absolute monarchy under Neros and Caligulas ... i~
the scourge of human nature. On the other side, the public of
Denmark ... under their absolute monarch are as well governed as
any people in Europe . . . the surface of history affords, there-
fore, no certain principles of decision." Mill then proceeded to
argue from this that we ought to turn instead to the type of psy-
chology favored by the utilitarians for our explanations, that there
is no specifically political science. Against him Macaulay argued
that the empirical facts about government do yield genuine law-
like generalizations, not least generalizations of a kind which
enable us to predict future actions with great confidence. And
it is clear that this practical use of law-like generalizations provides
Macaulay with a crucial motive. The claim to technical expertise
on the part of the political scientist is closely bound up with the
defense of the possibility of formulating law-like generalizations.
If the latter fails, the former is gravely impaired. When in our time
on the basis of his generalizations Lipset predicts totalitarian
horrors as the outcome of widespread political participation, he
turns out to be the true heir of Macaulay who, on the basis of his
generalizations, predicted cultural ruin if "the great number" were
allowed to participate in government; "they will commit waste of
every sort in the estate of mankind, and transmit it to posterity
impoverished and desolate," so that "in two or three hundred
years, a few lean and half naked fishermen may divide with owls
and foxes the ruins of the greatest of European cities ... " In
ls a scienceof comparativepolitics possible? 271

both Macaulay and Lipset the claims of political science are


closely linked to a claim about the political status of the political
scientist, to a claim about the possession of political expertise,
which entitles the political scientist to advise government. This
claim too demands inquiry; but a prerequisite for such inquiry is a
further development of my central argument.

IV

My doubts about identifying institutions in different cultures as


"the same" and therefore as interestingly different are of course
compatible with a recognition of the massive fact that the same
actions are regularly performed in quite different cultures. One
class of such actions are those that derive from implicit imitation.
It is of course not necessarily or always the case that if one person
imitates another he does what the other does. Indeed it is some-
times the condition of successful imitation that he who imitates
shall not do what the other does precisely in order to seem to do
what the other does. But when the intention to perform the same
action as another is present, we always have an intelligible question
as to why, if the corresponding action or its consequences or both
are not the same as those produced by the agent imitated, they are
not so. Of course it may be that even a particular intention to
perform certain actions cannot be intelligibly embodied in some
cultures; Don Quixote is the classical example. But we do have
clear cases where the same intention is embodied in two different
cultures, such intentions as to apply Roman Law or the Code
Napoleon, or to bring about some particular course of economic
development. What we shall achieve if we study the projects
springing from such intentions are two or more histories of these
projects, and it is only after writing these histories that we
shall be able to compare the different outcomes of the same inten-
tion. We shall not, that is to say, begin by collecting data in the
hope of formulating causal generalizations; we shall begin by
looking at cases where a will to achieve the same end was realized
with greater or lesser success in different cultural contexts.
There is of course a notable formula which seems to prescribe
this approach: "Men make their own history, but they do not
make it just as they please. They do not make it under cir-
cumstances chosen by themselves, but under circumstances
directly encountered, given and transmitted from the past."
But when Marx wrote these words he did not discriminate what
272 Against the Self-Images of the Age
was implied by this approach from a search for causal generaliza-
tions, and he does not do so at least in part because he treats
what he calls the circumstances of action only as a causally
effective and limiting environment and not in addition, or rather
primarily, as a context of meaning-conferring symbols and rules.
So Marx speaks of "the burden of history" in the very next
sentence and Engels speaks of history as a "series of parallelo-
grams of forces," and it is this model of Engels which creates for
Plekhanov the problem of the role of the individual in history
(since an individual can be no more than a point at which some
force operates). But the question with which Marx began in
the Eighteenth Brumaire does not require an answer in terms of
causal generalizations and parallelograms of forces. For what
Marx asks then is why, when someone aspires to perform the
same actions as a predecessor in some earlier cultural period-as
the English Puritans aspired to be Old Testament Israelites or the
French Revolutionary Roman republicans or Louis Napoleon
to do the deeds of Napoleon I-the actions should be so different.
A full answer to Marx's question would provide a genuine
starting point for historical comparison, but such an answer
could only be provided by first writing a history of each of these
episodes.
I therefore take it that if we wish to have a science of compara-
tive politics, one first step is the writing of a series of comparative
histories; that comparative history is a more fundamental discipline
than comparative politics. But then the crucial question arises:
what can we legitimately expect the study of comparative history
to yield? And one of the best ways of answering this question is to
ask what the study of comparative history has in fact yielded.
Consider for example Isaac Deutscher's thesis about revolutions.
Deutscher asserted that in the English, French, and Russian
revolutions the same "broad scheme of revolutionary development"
could be discerned. This scheme involves three stages: a first
stage in which "popular energy, impatience, anger and hope"
burst out, and "the party that gives the fullest expression to the
popular mood outdoes its rivals, gains the confidence of the masses
and rises to power" ; a second stage in which during the war on
behalf of the revolution the leaders of the revolutionary party and
the people are so well in accord that the leaders "are willing and
even eager to submit their policies to open debate and to accept
the popular verdict" ; and a third stage in which weariness and
ruthlessness divide party and people, so that the revolutionary
party cannot listen to, but must indeed suppress the voice of the
Is a scienceof comparativepolitics possible? 273
people, thus in consequence splitting itself between the holders of
revolutionary power and the caretakers of the purity of revolu-
tionary doctrine. This pattern holds of "any party of the revolution,
whether it be called Independent, Jacobin or Bolshevik."
That there are such patterns revealed by the rare studies of
comparative history that we already possess and that there will be
more is clear. But how are we to understand them? When we
assert the recurrence of such a pattern, what are we asserting?
Deutscher himself, following Engels and Plekhanov, understood
this pattern of revolutionary behavior deterministically. Hence
followed his very different assessment of Trotsky's relation to
Stalin from Trotsky's own non-deterministic assessment of that
relationship. Deutscher treats each stage, as he specified it, as
satisfying both a necessary and a sufficient condition for .the
occurrence of the next stage, as he specified it ; hence he takes
it that Trotsky, the caretaker of revolutionary purity, could not
but have failed to hold power, since maintaining the revolutionary
doctrine and holding power are causally incompatible.
The evaluation of Deutscher's specific contentions about
revolution is not relevant to my present argument; but the con-
tention Deutscher almost takes for granted, namely that the
discernment of recurring patterns in history has as its end-product
the formulation of law-like generalizations, is precisely what I
want to question. For when I suggested that the study of compara-
tive politics would certainly benefit from, and perhaps require, a
prior writing of comparative history, I did not intend to imply that
what comparative history will provide us with is merely a stock of
more adequate materials for the construction of these cross-
cultural, law-like generalizations which the present methods of
orthodox political science aspire to but in fact fail to provide;
that the comparative history is not so much an alternative, as
merely a necessary prelude to proceeding as before. What I want to
suggest is that it is characteristic of the causal knowledge which
history does provide us with that the antecedent conditions in
terms of which we explain historical outcomes are sometimes
necessary conditions for the occurrence of some specific outcome,
but are never sufficient. If this is so, then the patterns which we
discern in comparative history will always be de facto guides
yielding Machiavellian maxims, rather than Hobbesian laws. But
is it so? Is comparative political science, even when based on
comparative history, precluded from formulating law-like
generalizations ?
To cast light on this, compare the situation of the political
274 Against the Self-Images of the Age
scientist with that of the political agent. The political agent
confronts a situation in which he wishes to produce certain
outcomes. He wishes, for example, to maintain two-party demo-
cracy in a new state, or he wishes to overthrow that state by
revolutionary action. The situation he confronts consists of other
political agents: party politicians, soldiers, trade union leaders,
trade union rank and file, and so on. Some of each of these groups
are keen readers of such works as Political Man, Voting, Permanent
Revolution, and so on. Each of these derives certain inductively
grounded maxims from these works; in an earlier age the maxims
had different sources-Livy, Plutarch, what Napoleon did, or
political folk wisdom-but the situation was essentially the same.
The difficulty in applying the maxims is that the factors in the
situation confronting the agent include the beliefs of every other
agent about what each agent other than himself will do in applying
the maxims, including the beliefs of every agent about what
every other agent believes about his beliefs. "I know you know I
know you know I know" is a crucial piece of poetic wisdom for
political as well as for sexual behavior. The perception of any
pattern or regularity in the behavior of the other actors, or in the
behavior characteristic of this particular type of situation, is what
particularly invites deviation from the pattern. "They all knew
what Napoleon would have done," said Grant of the Union
generals. "The trouble was that the rebel generals didn't know
about Napoleon."
The key part that beliefs play in defining political situations, and
the fact that beliefs are always liable to be altered by reflection
upon the situation, including reflection about the beliefs of other
agents, has a crucial consequence: that we cannot ever identify a
determinate set of factors which constitute the initial conditions
for the production of some outcome in conformity with a law-like
regularity. To claim that we could identify such regularities and
such sets of factors would be to claim that we can understand what
occurs in politics independently of a knowledge of the beliefs of the
agents, for it would be to claim that the beliefs do not play a
causal role in political outcomes.
It makes no difference at this point if the alleged law-like
regularity is framed in probabilistic terms: when the alleged
probability of an outcome is ·7, the prediction is as vulnerable to
reflection by agents as when the alleged probability of an outcome
is 1. The conclusion that political agents are bound to be prone to
error in their predictions of what other agents will do, and hence of
political outcomes, has one important merit other than that of
Is a scienceof comparativepolitics possible? 275
following validly from my premises: it would appear to be true.
Nor is its truth incompatible with the fact that some political
agents produce more correct predictions than others. It would
perhaps be cynical to explain this latter fact by pointing out that
given an entirely random relationship between prediction and
outcome in a sufficiently large population of predictors, predictions,
and outcomes, certain predictors would consistently predict
correctly, just as certain predictors would consistently predict
incorrectly. But without resorting to either cynicism or the
theorems of statistics one can point out that success at prediction in
practical affairs, including political affairs, can never be embodied
into a method which can be taught, precisely because the maxims
relied upon are open-textured and open-ended, and the sense of
when which maxim is relevant cannot itself be unpacked into a set
of maxims.
It may be asked: when I conclude that political agents cannot
find law-like generalizations to aid them in their actions (other of
course than those crucial and rock-like law-like generalizations of
the physical senses which are available to us all, such that a bullet
accelerates in the way that all moving bodies do, and that when a
man's skull is crushed by an ice pick he dies), what is the force of
"cannot"? Do I mean only that we have at the moment no
technique for identifying determinate sets of antecedent conditions
of the relevent kind, but that such a technique might well be dis-
covered? Or do I mean that there is some confusion in the nature of
such a technique? Am I saying what the limits of inquiry are as of
now, or what the limits as such are?
I am strongly inclined to say that at the moment we have no
grounds for answering this question as it stands in either way. We
lack even the most minimal theoretical background against
which to raise such questions. To say this is not to ignore the
empirical work done by both psychologists and sociologists on
such topics as prejudice, cognitive dissonance, and the relation of
roles to beliefs; it is to say that the results of empirical studies in
this field (which are not always obviously consistent with each
other) are exceptionally difficult to interpret and to assess, in part
just for the type of reason that I have given.
What I have been arguing in this latter part of my essay is that
the political agent cannot rely on law-governed regularities in his
activities. But just those premises, which entail that conclusion,
entail that the political scientist is in no better position in this
respect than the political agent. The political scientist may claim to
know inore (quantitatively, as it were) than many political agents;
Against the Self-Images of the Age
but his knowledge is not of a different kind, and there seems no
reason to believe that the chances that he will be able to apply the
inductively grounded maxims which he derives from his studies
in the course of political action successfully are any higher than
they are for any other political agent.
If this is so, then the case for Machiavelli against Hobbes
rests not merely on the impossibility of testing these law-like
generalizations to which a true science of comparative politics
would have to aspire; it derives also from the nature of the
subject matter of political science. For the most that any study of
comparative politics based upon comparative history can hope to
supply us with in the foreseeable future is def acto generalizations
about what has been an obstacle to or has facilitated certain types
of course of action. There is available for the formulation of this
type of generalization no vocabulary for political scientists
which is essentially more sophisticated than the vocabulary of
political agents themselves. And the advice given by political
scientists turns out to be simply the advice given by a certain
genre of political agent, agents as partial, as socially conditioned,
as creative and as wayward as any others.
To this the defender of orthodox political science might well
feel bound to reply as follows. Qua scientist, he may claim, he
has a vocabulary that is not available to political agents; and he has
this neutrality precisely because he restricts himself to the facts and
to theorizing about them in an uncommitted way. Your redefinition
of the tasks of political studies would, he might complain, destroy
this neutrality. For the model of explanation implicit in your view
of the relation of comparative history to comparative politics is as
follows: Men in two different cultures seek to implement the same
intention in action. Either their actions or the consequences of
their actions may differ. If they do, by examining what was present
in the one case and absent in the other, you make inferences as to
what the obstacles or diversions were in either or both cases. You
then explain in terms of the presence or absence of these obstacles
or diversions the success or failure of the respective projects. But
this is in fact a model of explanation familiar in our everyday
understanding of action; and when we apply it in everyday life
we cite as explanations for the success or failure of men's projects,
not merely the external obstacles which they faced or the lack of
such obstacles, but such factors as their reasonableness or un-
reasonableness, their courage or their weakness, their willingness
or reluctance to commit injustice and so on. That is to say, your
model of explanation is that used by ordinary men in their political
Is a scienceof comparativepoliticspossible? 277
and other actions to assess themselves and each other and it is of
the essence of this mode of explanation that we may cite in
explanation evaluations both of intelligence and of moral character.
The strength of orthodox comparative political science, this
objector will go on, is that it has broken decisively with the evalua-
tive commitments of the world of action. Just because it aspires
to study these scientifically, it cannot share them. It must instead
be objective in a sense that requires that it be neutral and value-
free.
I accept from this objection the characterization of my own
standpoint. It would certainly be an open empirical question
whether it ever was in fact true that this or that project failed
because of the unreasonableness or the injustice of the agents; but
a priori nothing could rule out the possibility of these being true
and relevant explanations. Political science would become in a
true sense a moral science. But I do not take this to be in any way
an objection. For what is the alternative, as it is exemplified in
comparative political science as it is now usually practiced?
The type of comparative political science of which I have been
highly critical is indeed generally and deeply committed to the view
that its inquiries and explanations are indeed value-free. This
results in an attempt to allow evaluative expressions into political
life only in intentional contexts, in oratio obliqua, or in quotation
marks. Hence, as John Schaar has pointed out,1 such notions as
those of legitimacy are in fact defined in terms of belief. Lipset
says that "Legitimacy involves the capacity of the system to
engender and maintain the belief that the existing political
institutions are the most appropriate ones for the society"
(Political Man, p. 77) and Robert Bierstedt writes that "In the
tradition of Weber, legitimacy has been defined as the degree to
which institutions are valued for themselves and considered
right and proper." 2 These definitions are clearly mistaken in any
case; not only would there be no contradiction in holding that a
government was entirely legitimate, but that its institutions
were morally ill-suited to a particular society, but in a society
where this latter was widely believed, it would not follow either
that the government was, or that it was considered, illegitimate.
But it is not mere definitional ineptitude that I am concerned with
here. Suppose that we define, as Lipset and the Weberian tradition
according to Bierstedt do, evaluation in terms so that where "X"
1 "Legitimacy in the Modem State," in Green and Levison, eds.,
Power and Community.
2 "Legitimacy," in Dictionary of Social Sciences, p. 386.
Against the Self-Images of the Age
is an evaluative expression it is always defined so that "A is X" is
equivalent in meaning to an expression of the form "A is believed
by some class of persons to be Y" where "Y" is another evaluative
expression. Suppose further that, as both Lipset and some
Weberians do, we try to explain legitimacy in terms of stability or
vice versa. What is clear is that the original definitional move has
preempted on a crucial causal and explanatory question: is it
only beliefs about what is legitimate, what is appropriate, what is
right which can be causally effective, or can the legitimacy of an
institution, the appropriateness of an institution or an action, or the
rightness or the justice of an action, themselves be causally
effective? The definitional move of Lipset and Bierstedt removes
a priori the possibility of a certain class of characteristics of
intention and urgency being relevant in giving causal explanations.
Lipset and Bierstedt are thereby taking sides in an ancient
philosophical argument: is it important for the ruler to be just,
or is it only important for him to be thought to be just? What
Lipset and Bierstedt do in defining legitimacy is not unlike what
Thrasymachus did in defining justice and what Glaucon and
Adeimantus did in developing Thrasymachus' case. We may now
recall that Thrasymachus too claimed to be merely reporting
how the world went, to be a neutral and value-free observer.
My thesis on this last point can indeed be summarized as follows:
to insist that political science be value-free is to insist that we
never use in our explanations such clauses as "because it was un-
just" or "because it was illegitimate" when we explain the collapse
of a policy or a regime; and to insist on this is to agree with Thrasy-
machus-even if for different reasons-that justice plays no part
and can play no part in political life. The insistence on being
value-free thus involves the most extreme of value commitments.
Hence I take it to be no objection to the methodology which I
propose that it is clearly not able to purge its explanations of
evaluative elements.
Note that I have offered no arguments at this point for believing
that Thrasymachus is, as a matter of fact, mistaken; what I have
done is to suggest that those who maintain the stance of orthodox
comparative political science are committed by their starting
point and not by the empirical findings to the view that he was
right. And this raises one more kind of doubt about their view.
For the response to my parable about the man who aspired to be
the author of the general theory of holes might well have been that
such a man is intellectually misguided, but practically harmless.
When, however, one has to recognize that this kind of intellectual
Is a scienceof comparativepolitics possible? 279
mistake is allied to a Thrasymachean attitude to morality, it
becomes clear that if this type of enterprise is to be ranked as a
joke, it must be classed with the more dangerous kinds of practical
jokes.
23
Political and philosophical epilogue:
a view of The Poverty of Liberalism
by Robert Paul Wolff 1

Since I intend to criticize some of Mr. Wolff's positions 2 very


sharply, I ought at the outset to express both my agreement with
and my sense of indebtedness to him. In the task of criticizing
liberalism from the Left in a way more creative than that of many
Left polemics I am his ally; and Mr. Wolff has opened up the
debate with a battery of arguments at once forceful and suggestive,
from which we mayall leam. It is thus not just because I aspire to be
captious that I concentrate upon our disagreements. My strategy
will be to begin with a set of genuine, but relatively superficial
objections; to then suggest why these lead on to a profounder set
of objections to Wolff's view of liberalism; and finally to object to
Wolff's own radicalism.
Wolff's argument involves three central contentions (among
others). The first is that the liberal case stands or falls with the
utilitarian case. Wolff identifies liberal doctrine with the utilitarian
doctrine of John Stuart Mill without apparent qualification. The
second is that liberalism is an appeal only to individual and in-
dividualist values. Wolff asserts that liberalism values social
relationships only as means to the ends of individuals and that
liberalism lacks any concept of community as an end or of
communal life as a source of ends. The third contention of
Wolff's, which I wish to take up initially, is one that concerns
not Wolff's depiction of liberalism, but his own alternative stance.
Wolff distinguishes himself from some other radicals by arguing
that in modern American society "the people" are not in fact
deprived of power, and deprived in such a way that they have no
for Political
1 This paper will appear in the Proceedingsof the Conference
Theory, New York, 1970.
• The Poverty of Liberalism(Boston: Beacon Press, 1969).
a8o
Political and philosophicalepilogue
remedy, by a power elite. They are in fact ruled by default and
evil policies such as those which issued in the Vietnam War were
carried on with the active connivance of a public that was "too
stupid or too vicious" (p. I 14) to do otherwise.
All three points invite sharp comment. The first in particular
invites the rejoinder that liberalism has in its time associated
itself with and derived its warrant from many very different and
indeed mutually incompatible theories, and hence that there is no
reason to associate it peculiarly with utilitarianism. Locke, the
French materialists, and T. H. Green are very different types of
thinkers from J. S. Mill and from each other; but each provided
philosophical support for attitudes that could certainly claim to
be liberal. Moreover, on the second point it is clear that T. H.
Green, who has as good a claim as any thinker to be called liberal,
had a keen sense of the defects of individualism and of the
importance of community as a source of ends as has Wolff.
Liberalism was often, but certainly not always or necessarily,
individualist in its values. On the third point I only want to note
that Mr. Wolff has himself taken up an essentially liberal stand-
point; that if "the people" do have constitutional access to the
means of wielding power and they fail to use this access to institute
enlightened policies, then they are either stupid or vicious.
Liberalism, that is, views the people as either powerless or else
morally responsible for political outcomes. That "the people"
might have constitutional access to the means of wielding power,
but suffer from an ideologically distorted vision which itself has
deep social roots, and that this might be true in America today is a
possibility which never seems to enter the liberal purview.
I shall return to this last point; but for the moment I shall note
only that Wolff's portrait of liberalism is highly selective and
appears arbitrarily selective. Yet I take this objection to his
views to be relatively superficial, since, if what Wolff has given us
is a partial and distorted cartoonists' version of liberalism rather
than an adequate portrait, this is what liberalism itself in any one
of its many versions also offers us in the course of presenting each
particular version of liberalism as the essential doctrine. Why does
liberalism present itself in this way? A much more serious defect
in Wolff's presentation is that he offers us no means of answering
this question. This may be because he does not notice two crucial
aspects of liberalism, both of which must play an essential part in
any explanation of why liberalism has been both able and willing to
ally itself at various times and places with such a wide variety of
philosophical theories and of factual analyses.
Against the Self-Images of the Age
The first aspect of liberalism is that revealed by putting to
liberalism a question that needs to be put to any political position
which allies itself with a philosophical theory. In what relationship
does the politics stand to the philosophy? When a particular
political agent or group of political agents assert both a set of
political principles and a philosophical theory in association with
these principles (and the same would hold incidentally for a
sociologicalor other such theory), the practical principles and the
philosophical theory may stand in either of two quite different
relationships. On the one hand the philosophical theory may
consist, partially or wholly, in elucidations of the key expressions
used in the statement both of the political principles and of their
application to particular cases. In such a case, if we do not under-
stand the philosophical theory, we shall fail to understand the
political principles. But the theory and the principles may stand
in a quite different relationship. For the theory may provide not an
elucidation of the principles, but a mask behind which their true
meaning and importance is concealed. The theory may be an
ideological instrument, which enables those who profess the
principles to deceive not only others but also themselves as to the
character of their political action. I have already noticed that Wolff
does not allow for the possibility of ideological distortion in his
own explanations; I now want to stress the importance of his
failure to see liberalism in a variety of guises as ideology.
It is important that Wolff in his abstinence from the concept of
ideology is at one with the latest of liberalism's ideological masks,
the end-of-ideology thesis. But before I go on to ask about the
ideological content of all nineteenth- and twentieth-century
versions of liberalism, including this one, I want to notice another
central feature of liberalism unnoticed by Wolff. Liberalism
always appears accompanied by and allied to, not only philo-
sophical theories, but also political and economic stances of a non-
liberal kind; belief in a free market economy and belief in welfare
statism are both stances of this sort. The reason that this is always
so and must alwaysbe so is that liberalism by itself is essentially neg-
ative and incomplete. It is a political doctrine about what cannot
be justified and what ought not to be permitted: interference of a
variety of kinds with individual liberty. This essentially negative
character of liberalism derives from its eighteenth-century ante-
cedents. Liberalism was the doctrine used to undermine the
authoritarianism and the authority of the ancienregime.What is
liberal in the writings of Jefferson and of Robespierre and their like
are their demonstrations of the unjustifiable character of censor-
Political and philosophicalepi,logue
ship, of alien rule, of denial of the suffrage, of arbitrariness in the
courts, and of the enforcement of religious practice. It is from them
that liberalism inherits its character as a series of denials.
From this negative character derives both the virtue and the
vice of liberalism. The virtue resides in the affirmation of the
values of toleration and of freedom of expression; on this matter
I stand squarely with the liberal values and against Wolff. But I
have argued that case elsewhere and will not repeat it here. 1 The
vice of liberalism derives from the continuous refusal of liberals
to recognize the negative and incomplete character of their
liberalism. The precepts of liberalism enjoin upon us certain
constraints on our political activities; but they set before us no
ends to pursue, no ideal or vision to confer significance upon our
political action. They never tell us what to do. Hence no institution,
no social practice can be inspired solely or even mainly by
liberalism; and every institution or social practice that claims to be
so inspired-such as the "liberal" university or the "liberal"
state-is always a fraud.
Why do liberals fail to recognize this? Part of the answer is
that there is another constant element in liberalism, a way of
envisaging the social world and men's place in it, which is often
assumed at so deep a level that it is not identified as a contingently
alterable way of seeing the world, but is instead naively envisaged
as the way the world is. What are the key features of this ideolo-
gically distorted and distorting vision ?
There is first of all an abstract moralism, an appeal to very
general principles on very concrete issues. Liberalism lacks what
the scholastics called "middle axioms," methods of interpreting
and meditating the application of first principles. Hence morality
is always being adduced, and liberals tend to be moral exhibitionists
with all the unsavoriness that attaches to the habitual use of a high
moral tone. Closely allied to this is a view of the individual as the
fount of all value and the locus of all value. The individual
confronts a realm of determinate facts with the value judgments
which he has chosen. Fact is one thing, value another, and even if
the individual commits himself to the values of community, as
Wolff wishes him to do and T. H. Green wished him to do, it is the
autonomy of the individual in judging which is of the essence of
morality. We can indeed understand the power of this liberal
picture of the relationship of individual choice, fact and value when
we notice how T. H. Green, whose philosophy was in some
1 Cf. Alasdair MacIntyre, Herbert Marcuse : An Exposition and A
Polemic (New York: Viking; London: Collins, 1970).
Against the Self-Images of the Age
fundamental respects at odds with it, did in fact have to com-
promise with it.
Thirdly, there is a consequent view of politics as the offering
of alternatives to rational individuals who then make choices for
which they are morally responsible. Right politics is offering the
right values to individuals and if they reject them, then we are
entitled to condemn them unless they were disabled by invincible
ignorance. So the liberal view of politics is indeed precisely
ideological in that it conceals from view all those social facts which
have to do with ideology. It turns out to be no accident that liberals
should turn to something like the end-of-ideology thesis.
On these three points I wish to make two comments. The first
is that all these characteristically liberal positions turn up in
Wolff's book as Wolff's own positions which, so he appears to
believe, belong to a position to be sharply distinguished from
Wolff's own liberalism. Why is this? Wolff himself argues, and
rightly, that American conservatism and American liberalism
are conceptually entangled in such a way that they have more in
common than the adherents of either would like to believe. I
take Wolff's own adherence to liberal positions in his book to
be evidence that the same is also true of American liberalism
and American radicalism. Engels once complained that England
had a bourgeois proletariat and a bourgeois aristocracy as well as a
bourgeois bourgeoisie; we may well complain that America has
liberal conservatives and liberal radicals as well as liberal liberals.
In the case of conservatism, the moralistic stance is apparent.
Liberalism-as contrasted with conservatism and socialism-in
European contexts has been unique in its purely negative attitude
to tradition, a negativism grounded in its general negativism.
But American conservatism has no tradition, no past to repossess,
except a liberal past ; and the sermonizing tone of the abstract
moralist is the dominant tone of modern American conservatism.
Radicalism in America too is essentially yet another liberalism,
a liberalism that has lost its temper with social reality for being so
irremedially resistent to liberalism and that therefore turns, as
Wolff turns, to blaming "the people." To free ourselves from
liberalism therefore radicalism is the wrong remedy. Marx
already saw this when he castigated the Young Hegelian radicals;
and, if Marxism today will not do for us the work of providing us
with a fundamental critique of liberal society and liberal thought
that we need in order to transform society radically, we can at
least learn from it where not to begin.

You might also like