Truth and Proof, The Platonism of Mathematics - William W. Tait
Truth and Proof, The Platonism of Mathematics - William W. Tait
Truth and Proof, The Platonism of Mathematics - William W. Tait
TAIT
One may feel that the crucial difference between (1) and (2) is this:
in the former case, proving is inextricably bound up with what I have
been trained to do; whereas in the latter case, the role of training is
confined to language learning and this consists simply in learning to
put the right (conventional) names to things. And, after that, training
plays no further role: I simply read the true proposition off the f a c t as
I observe it.
This view of (2) is in essentials the so-called 'Augustinean' view of
language which, in my opinion, is thoroughly undermined by Witt-
genstein's Investigations, §§1-32. My learning to put names to things
consists in my learning to use and respond, verbally and otherwise, to
expressions involving these names. For example, how is it that I am
naming the chair as opposed to naming its shape, color, surface,
undetached chair part, temporal slice, etc.? T h e answer is that it is the
way we use the word "chair" that determines this. And the point is not
merely that the act of naming is ambiguous as to which among several
categories it refers. Ambiguity itself presupposes language: to under-
stand words like "shape", "color", etc., is to have a mastery of a
language. My point - or rather, Wittgenstein's point - is that nothing is
established by the act which we call an act of naming, without a
background of language or, at least, without further training in how
the name is to be used. 2 We do not read the grammatical structure of
propositions about sensible objects off the sensible world nor do we
read true propositions about sensibles off prelinguistic 'facts'. Rather,
we master language and, in language, we apprehend the structure of
the sensible world and facts. T o apprehend the fact that A is simply to
apprehend that A. And this apprehension presupposes language mas-
tery.
So, if A is a proposition about the sensible world of rooms and
chairs, then it is true if and only if it holds in that world. But we
sometimes count what we experience as verification for A. And why
should these two things, what holds in the world of rooms and chairs
and what we experience, have anything to do with each other? Note
that it is not sufficient to point out that verification is not conclusive in
the way that the existence of a proof is, since the question is why
verification should have anything to do with what holds in the world of
rooms and chairs.
Thus, I see nothing special to mathematics about the Truth/Proof
problem. We have described a Truth/Verification problem which is its
THE PLATONISM OF MATHEMATICS 345
analogue in the case of the sensible world. Moreover, the latter is not
really a new argument but, in essentials, has been a standard part of
the sceptics armory. It is perhaps this analogy that G6del has in mind
when he wrote (1964, p. 470) that "the question of the objective
existence of the objects of mathematical i n t u i t i o n . . , is the exact
replica of the question of the objective existence of the outer world".
At any rate, I know of no argument against the existence of mathe-
matical objects which does not have a replica in the case of sensible
objects. For example, some writers argue against Platonism that, if
there is a system of numbers, then why shouldn't there be more than
one of them, all indistinguishable - how would we distinguish them?
And why should our theorems refer to one such system rather than
another? Answer: why shouldn't there be more than one physical
world, all indistinguishable from one another and such that my 'seeing
a chair' is a seeing a chair in all of them? Why should (2) be about one
of these worlds rather than another? If you answer that it is about the
world you inhabit, then I shall ask: which you?, etc. Sceptics about
mathematical objects should be sceptics about physical objects too.
Of course, scepticism about either is misplaced, and both the
Truth/Proof and the Truth/Verification problems are consequences of
confusion and are not real problems.
Perhaps this becomes more evident when we note that, in both
cases, the problem purports to challenge our canons of warrant (i.e.,
proof and verification, respectively); but carried to its logical con-
clusion, it also challenges our canons of meaningfulness. Why should
the structure of reality be what is presupposed by the grammatical
structure of our language as we have learned it? For example, the
meaningfulness of a sentence involving " + " presupposes the truth of
the sentence which expresses that " + " is well defined in the numbers.
So scepticism about truth will already imply scepticism about
meaning.
I take it that we have only one such account [of truth], Tarski's, and that its essential
feature is to define truth in terms of reference (or satisfaction) on the basis of a
particular kind of syntactico-semantical analysis of the language, and thus that any
putative analysis of mathematical truth must be an analysis of a concept which is a truth
concept at least in Tarski's sense. (p. 667)
THE PLATONISM OF MATHEMATICS 347
To say that we cannot c o m m u n i c a t e our intuition of the natural numbers une qui voc a l l y
by m e a n s of a formal system would be tolerable only if we had some other me a ns to
c o m m u n i c a t e it . . . . W e c a n n o t know that other people unde rs t a nd the notion of all
properties (of some set of individuals) as we do, and hence ha ve the same model of the
natural numb ers as we do.
• . . we arrive at the d i l e m m a that we are unable to be certain w h e t h e r what s ome one else
refers to as the standard model is really isomorphic to the standard mode l we ha ve in
mind.
terms but may not denote. Moreover, and possibly for the same
reason, he was concerned only with the role of names in the context of
declarative sentences and not in other kinds of linguistic expressions.
Finally, his formulation of the principle leaves open the question of the
meaning of sentences. But one nowhere finds him saying that mathe-
matical objects are the references of mathematical terms in answer to
the question of what they are. Rather, he is giving a criterion for the
meaningfulness of terms and he suggests in §60 that the criterion
extends beyond mathematics. And he then says that there is nothing
more to the question of the self-subsistence of numbers than the role
that number words play in propositions. I take this to mean that to say
that a term refers is to say that it is a meaningful term. T h e r e is
certainly no implication here that every mathematical object is the
reference of a term.
One should note that, anyway, Wittgenstein's reformulation of the
context principle, replacing the context of a proposition by the context
of a language (cf. 1953, §10 and the discussion in footnote 2), must,
for Dummett, also tame the same bold thesis. But, if so, Wittgenstein's
argument also tames the bold thesis that there are physical objects.
T h e issue between the Realist and the Idealist of §402 is a non-issue
too. So if abstract objects are not 'as good as' D u m m e t t conceives
concrete objects to be, then neither are concrete objects. Dummett
(1973) wishes to accept Wittgenstein's critique of language to the
extent of accepting the formula that meaning is determined by use as a
rough guide to the analysis of mathematical language. But I think that
the above passage shows that he does not accept the full consequences
of the critique. However, that is already shown by the fact, noted by
Lear (1982), that he adopts the above formula to argue for a re-
visionist view of mathematics contrary to Wittgenstein (1953, §124).
10.
11.
12.
However, the intuitionists also hold that the objects that a proposition
A stands for, the objects of type A , are its proofs; and that I think is
wrong. A proof of A is a presentation or construction of such an
object: A is true when there is an object of type A and we prove A by
constructing such an object.
Here then is the answer to one of our questions: why is proof the
ultimate warrant for truth? T h e answer is of course that the only way
to show that there is an object of type A is to present one. (To prove
that there is an object of type A will mean nothing more than to prove
A, and that means to exhibit an object of type A.)
Consider the equation s = t between closed terms of elementary
number theory. What does this equation mean? We may say that it
expresses something about the system of numbers. That is certainly so,
358 w . w . TAIT
but it is also not to the point until we say what that something is,
without simply repeating the equation in the same or other terms.
T h e intuitionists seem to me very convincing when they say that
what the equation expresses is that there is a certain kind of com-
putation, namely, one which reduces s and t to the same term. For not
only do we initially learn the meaning of such terms and equations by
learning how to compute, but we take the existence of such com-
putations as the ultimate warrant for the equation. Thus, it seems
entirely natural to construe the equation as standing for the existence
of such a computation and to take the equation to be true precisely
when there is one.
Dummett (1973) accepts this analysis of such equations, but Dum-
mett (1967) feels that, in accepting it, one is rejecting the Platonist
point of view. His argument is that once we have accepted it there is
no reason to invoke the notion of truth in the sense of 'holding in the
system of numbers' to account for the meaning of the equation. But,
of course, we are not accounting for its meaning in this way and,
indeed, could not do so without circularity. That it holds in the system
of numbers - in other words, the fact about this system which it
expresses - is that there is such a computation. And we prove the
equation by producing one.
At least part of the reason why Dummett believes that the above
analysis of equations amounts to a rejection of Platonism is that he,
along with the intuitionists, identifies the proofs of the equations, i.e.,
the presentations of the computations, with the computations them-
selves; and when we do that we can no longer account for the
possibility of true but unprovable equations (Dummett 1967, p. 203).
One might object that the Platonist need not account for this pos-
sibility providing he can account for there being some true but
unprovable propositions. But the identification of computation with
proof is a special case of the intuitionistic identification of the object
with its construction in general. I do not believe that this identification
is ultimately intelligible; but one sees that, in accepting it, there is in
general no possibility of true but unprovable propositions.
However, it seems to me that, even in the case of the above sort of
equations, the intuitionists are wrong and that one should not identify
computations with proofs. For example, we easily prove 101° -- (105) 2
as an instance of a more general theorem; but in the canonical
notation 0, SO, SS0 . . . . for numbers, I shall be unable to explicitly
THE PLATONISM OF MATHEMATICS 359
compute 101° and, even for terms with much shorter computations,
the chance of my computing accurately is very small. D u m m e t t (1977)
makes the distinction here between 'canonical proofs', which in the
present context are the explicitly presented computations, and the sort
of proof one obtains from proofs of more general propositions, which
are shorthand descriptions of canonical proofs. But when we know
that the computation is longer than human beings, individually or
collectively, are able to preform, we must ask the question: canonical
proof for whom? T o answer this by reference to an 'ideal computer'
seems highly unsatisfactory. In the first place, proof is a human
activity - and this would seem especially important to an intuitionist.
But secondly, I am unable to see a significant difference between
referring to an ideal computer who can compute f ( n ) for each n and
one who can compute it for all n and hence can decide whether
f ( n ) = O for all n or not. I don't mean that there isn't a formal
difference, but rather that it is hard to see why the one idealization is
legitimate and the other not. Yet the intuitionists reject the latter one,
which would lead to the law of excluded middle for arithmetic pro-
positions.
Computations are mathematical objects, forming a mathematical
system like the system of numbers. One may object to the use of the
term " c o m p u t a t i o n " here, because of its association with computing as
a human activity. But the term is also used in my sense, for example in
the mathematical theory of computability. T h e ease with which one
can confuse the two senses may contribute to the apparent plausibility
of the intuitionistic identification of the computation with its presen-
tation.
13.
Vx:A. ckx
is the type of all functions f defined on A such that fx : dpx for all x : A,
360 w . w . TA~T
and
3x: A . 4~x
is the type of all pairs (x, y) such that x : A and y : ~bx. These defini-
tions of the quantifiers are essentially forced on us by the propositions
as types conception. 8 T h e remaining logical constants are definable
from the quantifiers, the null type 0 and the two-element type 2, whose
objects we denote by T and _1_.Thus, if we identify the t y p e / 3 with the
constant function ~b - B, then implication and negation are defined by
A---~B=Vx:A.B ~A=A--~O
and, if tot = A and tO& = B, then
AAB=Vx:2.tox AvB=3x:2.tox
Again, these definitions are essentially forced on us. 9
In this way, the logical operations appear as operations for con-
structing types and the laws of logic as principles for constructing
objects of given types. In this respect, there is no essential difference
between constructing a number or set of numbers and proving a
proposition. As Brouwer insisted should be the case, the logic of
mathematics becomes part of mathematics and not a postulate about
some transcendent model. However, Brouwer's view that the objects
of mathematics be mental objects does not seem to me coherent. And
the intuitionists' view that, for example, when we construct a number,
we should be able to determine its place in the sequence 0, 1, 2 , . . .
ignores the difficulty that we cannot in any case do this for sufficiently
complex constructions. Anyway, it is a restriction on ordinary
mathematical practice that is inessential to the conception of pro-
positions as types. T h e law of excluded middle amounts to admitting
objects of types A v ~ A which we may not otherwise be able to
construct; and this does indeed lead to the construction of numbers
whose positions in the above sequence are not computable. But it is
not essential to our conception that they should be.
An object of an V-type is a function and I have argued elsewhere
(cf. Tait, 1983) that, even in the case of constructive mathematics, one
must distinguish between a function and a presentation of it, by a rule
of computation or otherwise. I shall assume that, in the case of
nonconstructive mathematics, no argument is needed for this and,
THE PLATONISM OF MATHEMATICS 361
14.
Of course, we have not really specified the types 0 and 2 nor the
operations V and 3 until we have specified the principles of con-
struction or proof associated with them. A brief discussion of this
occurs in Tait (1983) (though the treatment of equations there is
inadequate) and a fuller treatment is in preparation. These principles
underlie mathematical practice in the sense that arguments that can-
not be reduced to them are as a matter of fact regarded as invalid.
Questions about the legitimacy of principles of construction or
proof are not, in my opinion, questions of fact. For mathematics
presupposes a c o m m o n mathematical practice and it is this that such
principles codify. Without agreement about these principles and their
application, there are no mathematical 'facts' (cf. note 8). Of course,
many factors, including the requirement of logical consistency, would
be involved in explaining why our mathematics takes the form it does;
but the view that there is some underlying reality which is independent
of our practice and which adjudicates its correctness seems to me
ultimately unintelligible. 1°
In this respect, the controversy between constructivists and non-
constructivists is similar to controversies about what is good or just
between people of different moral or political outlook. In the latter
case, one may ask what precisely is the issue. Why not simply use the
terms 'just1' and 'just2'? It seems to me that the answer is that there is
agreement about what I shall call the normative content of the term
'just' (or 'good'). Namely, to hold an action X to be just is to be
disposed to act in certain ways. A n d I am not referring here entirely to
linguistic acts such as affirming that one ought to do X. Rather, I have
in mind Aristotle's practical syllogism: to hold that X is just is to be
disposed to do X . If there were no agreement about this normative
content of the term 'just', then there would be no point in disputing its
material content, i.e., the question of what acts are to count as just.
But the latter sort of dispute seems to me not necessarily to involve
matters of fact, in as much as there may not be a sufficient basis of
ethical agreement to decide the issue.
In the same way, there is a normative content of the term 'valid'. T o
362 w . w . TAIT
15.
basis of what we now accept, but are provable by means that we would
accept. When I Speak here of new means of proof, I do not of course
mean the acceptence of new logical principles concerning 0, 2, V, 3,
inductive definitions, etc., but rather the introduction of further types
to which we can apply these principles. For example, by the intro-
duction of new types we may construct numerical functions, i.e.
'proofs' of N---~ N, which we cannot otherwise construct.
It is, incidently, this open-endedness of mathematics with respect to
the introduction of new types of objects that refutes the formalistic
conception of mathematics, even if we leave aside the fact that
mathematical concepts such as the number concept have a wider
meaning than that given by their role in mathematics itself. T h e
formalists seem to me right - in any case, we have not one example to
refute them - that the above type-forming operations are completely
determined in mathematics by the principles of inference we as a
matter of fact associate with them. T h e incompleteness of formal
systems such as elementary number theory is best seen as an in-
completeness with respect to what can be expressed in the system
rather than with respect to the rules of inference. For example,
G6del's undecidable proposition for elementary arithmetic can indeed
be proved by induction; but the induction must be applied to a
property not expressed in the system itself.
NOTES
* Earlier versions of this paper were presented to the Philosophy Department of the
University of Wisconsin at Madison in the Winter of 1984, at the Tarski Memorial
Conference at Ohio State in the spring of 1984 and at the Pacific Division meeting of
the A P A in the spring of 1985. I received many valuable comments on all of these
occasions and, in particular, from Paul Benacerraf and Clifton Mclntosh, who com-
mented on my paper at the A P A meeting. I should also like to thank Michael Friedman
for his comments on an earlier version and for our many discussions of its subject
matter.
Many other contemporary authors could of course have been cited for essentially the
same point. I shall focus primarily on Benacerraf (1973) and D u m m e t t (1967, 1973) in
citing the literature because these seem to me to represent most clearly and fully the two
most important formulations of difficulties with Platonism. Benacerraf's paper is
frequently cited as grounds for revisionist foundations of mathematics - e.g., in Field
(1980, 1981), Kitcher (1978, 1983) and Steiner (1975). It consists in arguing that, in the
context of mathematics, there is an apparent conflict between our best theory of truth,
which is Tarski's, and our best theory of knowledge, which is causal, because we do not
364 W.W. TAIT
But, despite their remoteness from sense experience, we do have something like a
perception also of the objects of set theory, as is seen from the fact that the axioms
force themselves Ul~Onus as being true. (pp. 483-84)
Many authors regard G6del as an archetypal Platonist and this passage as a bold
statement of what every Platonist must hold if he is to account for mathematical
knowledge. In the words of Benacerraf (1973) (who, incidently, inadvertently left out
the words "something like" in quoting the above passage):
[Gtdel] sees, I think, that something must be said to bridge the chasm, created by his
realistic and platonistic interpretation of mathematical propositions, between the
entities that form the subject matter of mathematics and the human knower . . . . he
postulates a special faculty through which we "interact with these objects. (p. 675)
But I don't think that this is a fair reading of G-tdel's remark. To understand what he
means by "something like perception", one should look at his argument for it: "the
axioms force themselves upon us as being true." One should also look at the paragraph
immediately following the quoted one:
It should be noted that mathematical intuition need not be conceived of as a faculty
giving an immediate knowledge of the objects concerned. Rather it seems that, as in
the case of physical experience, we .form our ideas also of those objects on the basis of
something else which is immediately given. Only this something else here is not, or
not primarily, the sensations. That something besides the sensations actually is
immediately given follows (independently of mathematics) from the fact that even our
ideas referring to physical objects contain constituents qualitatively different from
sensations or mere combinations of sensations, e.g., the idea of object itself, whereas,
THE PLATONISM OF MATHEMATICS 365
on the other hand, by our thinking we cannot create any qualitatively new elements,
but only reproduce and combine those that are given. Evidently the "given" underly-
ing mathematics is closely related to the abstract elements contained in our empirical
ideas. It by no means follows, however, that the data of the second kind, because they
cannot be associated with actions of certain things upon our sense organs, are
something purely subjective, as Kant asserted. Rather they, too, may represent an
aspect of objective reality, but, as opposed to the sensations, their presence in us may
be due to another kind of relationship between ourselves and reality.
If anything is being 'postulated' here it is this other kind of relationship, not a faculty.
This relationship is to account for the objective validity, not only of the 'something like
a perception' of mathematical objects, but also of our ideas referring to physical objects.
For it concerns the 'given' underlying mathematics, which are closely related to the
abstract elements contained in our empirical ideas - e.g., the elements giving rise to our
idea of an object (cf. Theaetetus 184d-186). That G6del intends this relationship to be
necessary for the objective validity of empirical as well as mathematical knowledge is
indicated by the first sentence of the next paragraph, which I have already partially
quoted, indicating that the question of the objective existence of mathematical objects is
the exact replica of that concerning the objective existence of the outer world.
But he writes that the former question "is not decisive for the problem under
discussion here. The mere psychological fact of the existence of an intuition which is
sufficiently clear to produce the axioms of set theory and an open series of extensions of
them suffices to give meaning to the truth or falsity of propositions like Cantor's
continuum hypothesis." The point seems clear: the 'something like a perception',
namely, mathematical intuition, is not what bestows objective validity on our theorems,
any more than the perceptions of the Brain-in-the-Vat bestow objective validity on its
assertions about the physical world. Yet, the Brain-in-the-Vat will have grounds for
asserting (2); and, in the same way, mathematical intuition yields grounds for asserting
(1). Thus, the 'something like a perception' is not the 'another kind of relationship
between ourselves and reality' to which G6del refers.
I do not entirely agree with G6del here. What is objective about the existence of
mathematical or empirical objects is that we speak in a common language about them -
and this includes our agreement about what counts as warrant for what we say. And this
view guides my estimation, stated above, of the role of mathematical intuition vis-a-vis
grounds for asserting mathematical propositions. I cannot make the distinction G6del
seems to want to make between subjective validity, founded on our intuition, and
objective validity. But it is worthwhile to point out that G6del's 'something like a
perception' is not a 'special faculty through which we interact with [mathematical]
objects.' Indeed, he was far less naive about the role of ordinary sense perception in
empirical knowledge than the many writers who have focused on the passage in question
as the Achilles heel of Platonism.
4 The 'external question' of the existence of numbers would seem to presuppose a
univocal and nonquestion begging notion of existence against which to measure
mathematical existence. But what is it? Quine (1953, fn. 1), indeed attempts an
argument to the effect that the desire to distinguish mathematical from spacetime
existence on the grounds that the latter, but not the former, involves empirical
investigation is unfounded. His argument is that showing that there is no ratio between
the number of centaurs and the number of unicorns involves empirical investigation.
366 w.w. WAIT
But the mathematical fact here is that 0 has no reciprocal; and that needs no empirical
investigation.
I think that Carnap (1956) is right that 'external questions' of existence have no prima
facie sense. But his attempt to make an absolute distinction between theoretically
meaningful questions and those without theoretical meaning on the basis of his notion of
a linguistic framework fails. For example, his framework for number theory is a formal
system. But correct and sufficiently expressive formal systems for number theory are
incomplete and, moreover, do not express all the properties of numbers. In later
writings, Carnap attempted to solve the problem of incompleteness by allowing the
system to contain the infinitary oJ-rule. But now the internal question " D o e s there exist
a number n such that ~b(n)" can only mean " D o e s there exist an infinitary deduction of
3x~b(x)?". But this is an external question and may be mathematically nontrivial. But,
anyway, linguistic frameworks are constructed in our everyday language; and it is hard
to see how, lacking a precise notion of theoretical meaningfulness for it, we can
convincingly determine when we have a 'good' framework and when we do not.
5 In the nominalism of Field (1980, 1981), the mathematical model is identified with the
physical world. Thus, spacetime regions become nominalistically acceptable objects and
mathematics is involved only insofar as such objects as numbers, sets and function are.
Regions are real because we causally interact with them or at least can do so with some
of them. This idea is developed in the 1980 book to show how to free Newton's theory
of gravitation of mathematics, to make it a nominalistic theory. Of course, there is a
difficulty in that, for a wide range of phenomena, Newton's theory is inadequate and, if
we replace it by Einstein's theory, for example, the 'nominalization' has yet to be
demonstrated. Moreover, Einstein's theory does not account for other ranges of
phenomena and it is open whether it is compatible with an account of them. Finally,
even if we had a reasonable universal physics, i.e., an account of all known forces, we
should still have to ask (at least if we took Fiel~l's position) whether it was true. Well, let
us suppose that we have such a 'true' universal physics, which is a spacetime physics.
W o n ' t causation be a relation between spacefime points or regions? But, unless some
Supreme Court decisions - made with greater precision than, not only is it accustomed
to, but than it is in principle capable of - are begged, I am not a spacetime region and so
do not causally interact with such things. The world of chairs and rooms and us is
different from the world of mathematical physics. The latter is called an idealization of
the former; and this only means that we can use the mathematical theory in a certain
way.
6 Putnam (1979) also seems confused on this point. He writes that Wittgenstein may
have had in mind the following 'move':
One might hold that it is a presupposition of, say, "2 + 2 = 4," that we shall never
meet a situation that we would count as a counterexample (this is an empirical fact):
and one might claim that the appearance of a "factual" element in the statement
"2 + 2 = 4" arises from confusing the mathematical assertion (which has no factual
content, it is claimed) with the empirical assertion first mentioned,
The 'empirical fact' and 'empirical assertion first mentioned', I assume, is that we shall
never meet a situation that we would count as a counterexample. But this is, for
Wittgenstein and in fact, no more an empirical fact than that we shall never meet, in a
THE PLATONISM OF MATHEMATICS 367
game of chess, a situation which we would count as one in which the king is captured.
Of course, neither of these assertions is a prediction about our future behavior or an
assertion about our past behavior; they are each part of a description of a certain game.
It is indeed an empirical fact that we play the game - that we do mathematics and play
chess - but that is another matter. Putnam goes on:
The answer is simply: yes. But what has this to do with the fact that the mathematical
proposition "2 + 2 = 4" or "Turing machine t with input '111' never halts" is not the
sort of proposition for which the idea of empirical counterexamples makes sense? This
example is no different from our explanation of the motion of a physical object. We
model the behavior of T with t. If it is a good model (and this idea defies precise
analysis), then the fact that t doesn't halt (in the mathematical sense) should lead us to
believe that T doesn't (in the physical sense) halt. But what has this to do with the
conceivability of an empirical counterexample to the statement that t doesn't (in the
mathematical sense) halt? The sense in which it is claimed that "2 + 2 = 4" has no
'factual content' is not intended to imply that it has no empirical applications.
7 Consider systems ~ = (A, a, f), where A is a type of object, a is an object of type
A(a : A) and f is a function from A to A (f: A--~ A). Dedekind (1887) characterized the
system N = (N, 0, S) of numbers as such a system in which 0 ~ Sn for all n : N ,
S m = Sn---~ m = n and, if X is any set of numbers containing 0 and closed under S, then
it is the set of all numbers. There is no question of identifying the system of numbers: it
is, as Dedekind puts it (§73), a 'free creation of the human mind.' We have created it in
the sense that we have specified once and for all its grammar and logic. Moreover, given
any other system ~/satisfying this characterization, the proof that ~/is isomorphic to N
is a triviality and we shall not disagree about that. We might indeed disagree about the
principles used to construct some set P of numbers or some system ~1; but that is a
different matter and, anyway, if we leave aside those who wish to use only constructive
principles, then as a matter of fact, there is no such disagreement (cf. §15). Moreover,
the possibility of this kind of disagreement exists even in constructive mathematics,
which D u m m e t t (1973) is advocating. In that case, Dedekind's characterization should
be replaced by the classically equivalent one essentially given by Lawvere (1964),
namely that X has the property of unique iteration: given any system ~t, the equations
gO = a and gS = fg define a unique function g: N---~ A. But we may still disagree about
when a system ~ / h a s been legitimately introduced.
8 Suppose that we already have that, for any x : A, ~b(x) is already identified with a type
of object. T h e n 3 x : Ack(x) means that, for some x : A, ~b(x), and so that, for some x : A,
368 w.w. TAIT
there is a y:th(x), and so that there is a pair (x, y) of the required type. V x : A t h ( x )
means that ~b(x) for all x : A, and so that, for each x : A, there is a y : ~b(x). So we have
'reduced' the meaning of V to 'for all x, there exists a y.' We avoid an infinite regress
here only by taking the latter to mean that we have a function f which gives us y = fx
for each x. This is, as a matter of fact, the way in which we do reason. The appearance
that it isn't arises from the fact that we often are thinking of the reasoning as taking
place in a model in which no such [ occurs. So Vx : Aep(x) may be true in the model
without there being the required f in the model. But that of course is different from
saying that there is no s u c h / .
Our analysis of the quantifiers yields the Axiom of Choice in the form
V x : A 3 y : B ~ ( x , y) ~ 3 z : A ~ B V x : Ad/(x, zx).
For let f be of the antecedent type. Then for each x : A , fx is of the form (y, u), where u
is of type ff(x,y). Let z:A---->B be defined by z x = y and let v : V x : A ~ ( x , zx) be
defined by vx = u. Then (z, v) is of the type of the conclusion. The argument above for
our analysis of the universal quantifier looks itself like an application of the Axiom of
Choice:
Vx : A 3 y ( y : ~b(x))--~ 3 f V x : A ( f x : d,b(x)).
But there are two respects in which it is different. First, it contains two variables, y and
jr, whose type is unspecified and, secondly, it involves 'propositions' of the form ' u : C'.
Concerning the first point, the notion of a mathematical object in general seems a
problematic notion and certainly is no part of the Platonistic conception that I am
discussing. Concerning the second, ' u : C' is not a mathematical proposition in the sense
that I am discussing. Otherwise, we would have to know what are the objects v of type
u : C, the objects of type v : (u : C), etc., leading to an infinite regress. The fact is that we
have a type C only when we have agreement as to what counts as an object of type C.
Thus, statements such as ' u : C ' are grammatical statements. It is the wrong picture to
think that there is a universe of 'mathematical objects' and then we must determine for
one of them, u, what type it has. (This seems to me to be the view behind Jubien (1977),
where its absurdity is well illustrated.) 0 is a mathematical object because it is a number.
If I have introduced an object u of type C, then either u : C or else I have been
indulging in nonsense.
9 Cf. Tait (1983). In the case of negation, note that A A B--> 0 should he a requirement
for a negation B of A. But when this holds, B - - ~ - I A ; and so -hA is the weakest
candidate for negation. One may feel, nonetheless, that negation presents a counterex-
ample to the view of propositions as types; since, if ' A is true' is to mean that there is an
object of type A, then ' A is false' ought to mean that there is no such object, and this is
not an existence statement. But if there is no object of type A , then there is an object of
type A---~ 0, namely the null function. But, in any case, there is something deceptive
about the discussion. What does 'not' mean when we say that it is not the case that there
is an object of type A? For this too is a mathematical proposition and, indeed, simply
means 7 A . We should not think that there is a meaning of 'not' that somehow
transcends mathematical practice.
1o The question of the truth of mathematics, as opposed to truth in mathematics has
historically been the concern of many philosophers. In some cases, e.g., Plato and
THE PLATONISM OF MATHEMATICS 369
Leibniz, this question has been distinguished from that of why mathematics applies to
the phenomena and in others, such as Aristotle and Kant, it has not. This latter
question, of why mathematization of the phenomena works, has itself been a source of
anti-Platonism. But, as I have indicated in §7, the only kind of answer to that question
would be in terms of cognitive science and an account of why it is that we have evolved.
E1 Of course, if one is interested only in constructive mathematics, one may diverge
from the classical development of, say, analysis, by choosing concepts more amenable to
constructive treatment than the classical analogues. My point is only that the principles
of construction and reasoning used in the development remain classically valid. Ap-
parent counterexamples such as Brouwer's proof that every real-valued function on the
continuum is continuous are a result of ambiguity, not of using classically invalid
principles.
12 There is another method of obtaining new types which derives from Dedekind (1888)
and which we may refer to as 'Dedekind abstraction.' For example, in set theory we
construct the system (to, th, tr) of finite von Neuman ordinals, where trx = xU{x}. We
may now abstract from the particular nature of these ordinals to obtain the system ~/" of
natural numbers. In other words, we introduce N together with an isomorphism between
the two systems. In the same way we can introduce the continuum, for example, by
Dedekind abstraction from the system of Dedekind cuts. In this way, the arbitrariness of
this or that particular 'construction' of the numbers or the continuum, noted in
connection with the numbers in Benacerraf (1965), is eliminated. It is incidently
remarkable that some authors such as Kitcher (1983) have taken Benacerraf's obser-
vation to be an argument against identifying the natural numbers with sets, but have
been content to identify the real numbers with sets, although there are again various
ways to do that. Kitcher (1978) contains an amazing argument based on Benacerraf's
observation, to the effect that Platonism is false: on grounds of economy, all 'abstract'
objects should be sets. Numbers are abstract. But there is no canonical representation of
the numbers as sets. Therefore, the view that there are such things as numbers is false.
(A person makes up a budget and, on grounds of economy, fails to budget in for food.
But we need to eat. So the notion of a budget is incoherent.)
REFERENCES
Benacerraf, P.: 1965, 'What Numbers Could Not Be', Philosophical Review 74, 47-73.
Benacerraf, P.: 1973, 'Mathematical Truth', The Journal of Philosophy 70, 661-79.
Benacerraf, P. and H. Putnam (eds.): 1984, Philosophy of Mathematics: Selected
Readings, 2nd. edn., Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, Mass.
Carnap, R.: 1956, 'Empiricism, Semantics, and Ontology', Meaning and Necessity, 2nd.
edn., University of Chicago Press, Chicago, reprinted in 3.
Chihara, C.: 1973, Ontology and the Vicious Circle Principle, Cornell University Press,
Ithaca.
Dedekind, R.: 1888, Was sind und was sollen die Zahlend, Brunswick, Vieweg.
Dummett, M.: 1963, 'The Philosophical Significance of GSdel's Theorem', Ratio 5,
140-55, reprinted in 11, page references are to 11.
Dummett, M.: 1963, 'Platonism', first published in 11.
Dummett, M.: 1975, 'The Philosophical Basis of Intuitionistic Logic', H. E. Rose and J.
370 w.w. TAIT
Department of Philosophy
University of Chicago
Chicago, IL 60637
U.S.A.