Fundamentals - of - Historical - Materialism Lorimer
Fundamentals - of - Historical - Materialism Lorimer
of Historical
Materialism
The Marxist View
of History & Politics
Doug Lorimer
2 Fundamentals of Historical Materialism
Introduction .......................................................................................... 5
1. Bourgeois science & reductionism ................................................................. 6
2. Dialectics & reductionism ............................................................................... 8
3. Motion & contradiction ................................................................................. 11
4. Human history & natural history .................................................................. 15
1. Historical Materialism as a Science ........................................ 19
1. The emergence of historical materialism ......................................................19
2. The subject-matter of historical materialism ...............................................22
3. The objective character of the laws of social development ..........................26
4. People’s conscious activity & its role in history .............................................30
2. Social Being & Social Consciousness ................................... 35
1. Social consciousness as the reflection of social being ...................................35
2. The concept of intellectual culture ................................................................37
3. Social psychology & ideology .........................................................................39
4. The relative independence of social consciousness. Connection &
mutual influence of its forms ........................................................................42
5. The correlation between social & individual consciousness .........................45
3. Forms of Social Consciousness & Their
Social Function ........................................................................... 48
1. Political & legal consciousness .......................................................................49
2. Moral consciousness & ethics ........................................................................50
3. Aesthetic consciousness & art ........................................................................53
4. Religion ...........................................................................................................57
5. Science ............................................................................................................60
6. Philosophy ......................................................................................................66
4. Material Production: The Basis of Social Life ...................... 70
1. Society & nature, their interaction .................................................................70
2. The productive forces of society ...................................................................80
3. Production relations.......................................................................................88
4 Fundamentals of Historical Materialism
The purpose of this book is to provide the reader with a general introduction to the
fundamental ideas of historical materialism — the Marxist theory of human history
and society.
For Marxists the study of human history is inseparable from the study of society.
Human beings, Karl Marx and Frederick Engels noted, “can be distinguished from
animals by consciousness, by religion or anything else you like. They themselves begin
to distinguish themselves from animals as soon as they begin to produce their means
of subsistence”.1 That is, what distinguishes humans from other animals is that they
consciously produce their means of subsistence through the use and fabrication of
tools. But in order to do this, they must consciously cooperate with others of their
kind. Society, which involves living and working together as an integrated group, is the
result of labouring to produce food, clothing and shelter. How human beings have
related to each to produce their means of life is the foundation of society and of
human history. The fundamental laws of social life are identical, in the Marxist
conception, with the fundamental laws that govern human history.
This approach stands in sharp contrast to the dominant approach of bourgeois
social “science”, as studied and taught in bourgeois academic institutions. The latter
compartmentalises the study of social life into a number of unconnected disciplines
such as archaeology, social anthropology, economics, political science, history, and
sociology. Within these disciplines further compartmentalisation occurs. Thus “history”
is divided into ancient, medieval and modern and into all kinds of history, for example,
political history, economic history, cultural history, urban history, agrarian history,
etc. Sociology, defined by bourgeois academics as the “study of the origin, development,
organisation, and functioning of human society” and as “the science of the fundamental
laws of social relations”,2 is divided into dozens of specialised branches none of which
is concerned with actually uncovering the fundamental laws which govern the origin,
development and organisation of human society.
6 Fundamentals of Historical Materialism
1. Bourgeois science & reductionism
Bourgeois social “science” is incapable of fulfilling the task of a genuine science of
society, i.e., to provide an integral theory of society by revealing the general laws that
govern its origin, organisation and development. Indeed, the dominant schools of
bourgeois social theory since the beginning of the 20th century have argued that it is
fruitless to even attempt to create such a general theory of social development because,
they claim, society is simply an accidental collection of atomic individuals and history is
nothing more than a record of accidental, unique events. If everything in social life and
history is individual and unique then, of course, it would be pointless to even conceive
of a science of society and history. The bourgeois atomistic view of society inevitably
leads not to scientific explanation, but to mere description, to the ordering and
classification of empirical facts on the basis of the subjective likes and dislikes of the
individual historian or social commentator.
Contemporary bourgeois thought has lost its earlier confidence in the capacity of
human reason to uncover the objective, material causes of social phenomena. Such
agnosticism in social theory has an inner connection with the irrationalism that is
generated in bourgeois thought by the decay of the capitalist social system, with its
deepening spiral of economic chaos, wars and social crises.
The atomistic view of society arises from one side of the contradictory nature of
the capitalist social system. Capitalism separates and pits people against one another
through the generalised commodification of the means of production and labour-
power. Frederick Engels noted this when he described the crowds in the London
streets in his first major work, The Condition of the Working Class in England:
This isolation of the individual, this narrow self-seeking, is the fundamental principle
of our society everywhere … The dissolution of mankind into monads, of which each
one has a separate principle and separate purpose, the world of atoms, is here carried out
to its utmost extreme.3
This atomisation of social life under capitalism gives rise among its intellectual elite to
a reductionist approach to the conception of all phenomena, both natural and social.
This reductionist approach is characterised by four basic assumptions:
1. There is a natural set of units or parts of which any object of study is made.
2. These units are homogeneous within themselves, at least as they affect the
object of which they are the parts.
3. The parts are ontologically prior to the whole. That is, the parts exist in isolation
and come together to make wholes. The parts have intrinsic properties, which they
possess in isolation and which they lend to the whole. In the simplest cases the whole
is nothing but the sum of its parts; more complex cases allow for interactions of the
Introduction 7
parts to produce added properties of the whole.
4. Causes are separate from effects, causes being the properties of subjects, and
effects the properties of objects. While causes may respond to information coming
from effects (so-called “feedback loops”), there is no ambiguity about which is the
causing subject and which is the caused object.
This is the conception of the natural world and social life which permeates bourgeois
science. It views parts as separate from wholes and reifies parts as isolated things in
themselves, as causes separated from effects, as subjects separated from objects. It is
an intellectual conception that has been generated by bourgeois social relations.
Beginning with the first stirrings of merchant entrepreneurship in 13th century
Europe, and culminating in the bourgeois revolutions of the 17th and 18th centuries,
bourgeois social relations have emphasised the isolated, commodity-owning individual
as the primary social actor. By successive acts of enclosure, the mass of the population
was separated from the means of production of life’s necessities and reduced to “social
atoms”, colliding in the marketplace, each with his or her special interests and properties
intrinsic to their role in society.
No individual person, however, is confined to a single role in bourgeois society.
The same people are both consumers and producers, both owners and renters. Yet
bourgeois social theory sees society as constructed of homogeneous individual parts,
each with only one particular interest. The mass of “consumers” have their interest,
“labour” its interest, “capital” its interest, with the whole of capitalist society taking a
shape determined by the action of these categories on each other.
The claim that the capitalist social order is the “natural” result of the adjustment of
demands and interests of competing interest groups is an ideological formulation
meant to make the structure seem inevitable, but it also reflects the social reality that
has been constructed. Workers as individuals do compete with each other to sell the
only commodity they own, their labour-power, in a market whose terms have been
made by struggles between workers and capitalist employers. Consumers do have an
interest in the commodities offered to them that is antagonistic to the interest of the
producers. But these interest groups have been created by the very system of social
relations of which they are said to be the basis.
The reductionist method views the properties of any object of study as reducible to
the individual properties of its structural elements, which are regarded as at base
homogeneous. Hence an attempt is made to isolate these parts as completely as possible
and to study these parts. This underestimates the importance of interaction not only of
the parts of the object of study, but of the object of study with all other objects.
The faith in the atomistic nature of the world that lies at the basis of the reductionist
8 Fundamentals of Historical Materialism
approach of bourgeois science makes the allocation of relative weights to separate
causes the main aim of science, making it more difficult to study the nature of
interconnections. Where simple behaviours emerge out of complex interactions,
reductionism takes that simplicity to deny complexity; where the behaviour is
bewilderingly complex, it reifies its own confusion into a denial of lawful regularity.
The fundamental error of reductionism as a general point of view is that it supposes
that the complex object is somehow “composed” of simple, homogeneous “natural”
parts, which exist prior to and in isolation from the object. From this conception of the
world, the aim of science is to find those smallest units that are internally homogeneous,
the “natural” units of which the world is “composed”.
The history of classical chemistry and physics is the epitome of this bourgeois,
atomistic view of the world. In classical chemistry microscopic objects were composed
of molecules, each of which was homogeneous within itself. With the development of
the atomic theory of matter, these molecules were seen as composed of atoms of
different kinds, so the molecules were then seen as internally heterogeneous. Then it
appeared that the very atoms defied their name (atomos, indivisible), because they too
were internally heterogeneous, being composed of elementary particles — neutrons,
protons and elections. But even that homogeneity has disappeared, and the number
of “elementary” particles has multiplied with each creation of a more powerful particle
accelerator.
à à à
All things that are distinctive about humans, from tool-making, speech and thinking to
the latest triumphs of art, science and technology, are products of our collective activity
over the past several million years. What humans are is the product of human history,
of what humans have made and how they have made it. This is what Marx meant
when he wrote that the “human essence is no abstraction inherent in each single
individual” but the “ensemble of social relations”, i.e., the totality of social practice.6
Never before in history have human beings been so interdependent upon each
other, upon their collective labour activities. Capitalism has socialised the labour process
and welded the whole world into one interdependent productive system. This has
been the progressive side of capitalism. It has laid the material social foundations for
the free association of all humanity, while at the same time accentuating “dog-eat-
dog” competition of each against all by making every human need a commodity in a
worldwide market dominated by the drive for private enrichment by a tiny minority of
super-rich families.
The social environment is the product of collective human action. It can therefore
be changed by the collective action of the working people in order to create a social
environment suited to the fundamentally cooperative nature of human social life, a
social environment suited to the full satisfaction of the material needs and unhampered
cultivation of the physical and mental capabilities of every person. But in order to do
this, working people need a scientific understanding of the laws that govern and shape
social life. That is what historical materialism provides.n
1. Historical Materialism as a
Science
Historical materialism is a science concerned with the general laws and motive forces
of the development of human society. Like all other sciences, historical materialism
seeks to reveal the essence of the object of its study by uncovering the material relations
that are at the foundation of the surface phenomena of its object of study.
The great 20th century physicist Albert Einstein observed: “The belief in an external
world independent of the perceiving subject is the basis of all natural science.”1 This
belief is the cornerstone of the materialist world outlook. But pre-Marxist materialists
were inconsistent and limited. They were unable to apply the principles of philosophical
materialism to the study of social life and history and in this field held idealist views.2
The great contribution of Marx and Engels to the development of scientific thought
was that they completed the half-built edifice of materialism, that is, extended it to the
study of society, thanks to which the materialist world outlook became for the first
time comprehensive and fully consistent and effective.
In complete accord with the materialist world outlook, historical materialism proceeds
from the proposition that social being is primary in relation to social consciousness, to
“public opinion”.
à à à
We have stressed that social consciousness is dependent upon social being and that
different products of social consciousness are, to one extent or another, reflections of
social being. However, it would be wrong to conclude from this that social consciousness
reflects social being like a mirror reflects objects placed in front of it. Precisely such a
position on the passive nature of social consciousness, of the intellectual life of society,
has been ascribed to Marxism by bourgeois ideologists. By establishing the fact that
social consciousness depends on social being, that social consciousness reflects social
being, Marxist social theory in no way belittles the significance of social consciousness.
Having given a correct, scientific, definition of social consciousness and its relation
to social being, historical materialism also indicates its place in the life of society. One
cannot transform society by transforming ideas alone. To make society better, to
make life truly worthy of human beings, it is necessary to reorganise social being. And
social consciousness plays a highly important part in this. Marxist theory, which itself
is part of social consciousness, gives people knowledge of the methods to transform
their social life. When assimilated by the majority of the working class, Marxist theory
stimulates them to work for the revolutionary transformation of social being. That is
why Marx himself stated that “theory … becomes a material force as soon as it has
gripped the masses”.10n
48 Fundamentals of Historical Materialism
In class society social consciousness assumes various forms: socio-political and legal
theories and beliefs, philosophy, morals, aesthetics, religion and science. Each of these
forms, in reflecting social being and actively influencing it, has its own particular object
and mode of reflection, influences social being and people’s consciousness in its own
particular way and is characterised by its specific role in the ideological and political
struggle between classes.
At the early stages of development of society, social consciousness was not broken
down into separate forms. The harsh existence of hunter-gatherer societies with their
extremely low level of material production had its correspondingly primitive and
undifferentiated consciousness. Mental work had not yet been separated from manual
labour, and people’s consciousness was “directly interwoven with the material activity
and the material intercourse of men, the language of real life”.1 But the rudiments of
such forms of social consciousness as aesthetics, morality and religion are to be found
at certain stages of development of labour activity even in pre-class society.
With further division of labour, the appearance of private property, classes and
the state, social life became much more complex, and so did social consciousness. The
division of labour into physical and mental, and the monopolisation of the latter by the
ruling class, signified an increasing separation of consciousness from people’s material
practice. Consciousness became relatively independent of social being. It could now be
regarded as completely independent of being and even primary in relation to being, it
could “proceed to the formation of ‘pure’ theory, theology, philosophy, ethics, etc”.2 In
reality all these “pure” forms of consciousness in some way or other expressed the real
conditions or relationships of class society and acted as the ideological reflection of the
interests of certain classes.
We shall now briefly examine the separate forms of social consciousness, their
specific features and functions, in connection with the historical conditions and social
needs that brought them into existence.
Forms of Social Consciousness & Their Social Function 49
1. Political & legal consciousness
Political consciousness is the system of ideas and attitudes, sentiments and objectives
of classes concerning the political organisation of society, the forms and uses of state
power. It can be considered on the plane of ideology and/or social psychology.
Political psychology is: the feeling of class solidarity or hatred, pessimism or
optimism, patriotism or internationalism, political illusions etc. Political ideology is the
most concentrated expression of the interests and objectives of a social class. It is the
systematised theoretical expression of the interests of a definite class in relation to other
classes and in relation to the state, the class struggle and social revolution. It is a vital
weapon in the struggle for political power, in the establishment, defence, substantiation
and reinforcement of a definite political order and its economic foundation.
Closely connected with political consciousness is legal consciousness, since it originates
together with the state and law. Law is created and enforced by the state and is therefore
binding upon the entire community under the given state’s control. In the Communist
Manifesto Marx and Engels characterise bourgeois law as follows: “…Your
jurisprudence is but the will of your class made into a law for all, a will whose essential
character and direction are determined by the economical conditions of existence of
your class”.3
Legal ideology is the systematic, theoretical expression of the interests of a class in
relation to the nature and purpose of legal relationships, norms and institutions,
questions of legislation, the courts and so on.
The legal principles and theories of the ruling class seek to legitimise its social
system. Law imparts a legal character — “lawfulness” — to the dominant relations of
production that exist within a given socioeconomic formation. Second, legal principles
and theories propose and justify legal institutions, standards and forms best
corresponding to the given socioeconomic system and the dominant form of ownership
of the means of production.
Like any form of theoretical consciousness, political and legal ideologies express
their propositions in logical form and rely on the previous development of the given
branch of knowledge. They are expressed in specialised works on the theory of state
and law. But in dealing with the political consciousness, we are concerned not only with
political doctrines and theories, but also with political programs and platforms, with
political strategy and tactics. Their essence is most clearly demonstrated by the example
of the activity of the Marxist party. Its program, based on the theory of scientific
socialism, shows the ultimate aim of the working-class movement and maps out the
line of march and basic tasks to be followed to achieve it. Its strategy sets out the basic
means to implement its program, while its tactical orientation provides a definite line
50 Fundamentals of Historical Materialism
of conduct for the specific situation it faces.
French aristocratic women in the 18th century can be linked with production activities
because they engaged in none.
To be able to understand what the Aboriginal dance was about, it is enough to
know what role herb-gathering played in the life of an Aboriginal clan. But to see what
the minuet is about, it is not enough to be familiar with the 18th century French
economy. The minuet is one of the art forms expressive of the social psychology of the
idle rich. This psychology underlies most of the customs and “polite manners” of
aristocratic “high society”. At first sight economic life, social relations of production,
seem to be ousted in this case by purely psychological factors. That, however, would
be a superficial judgment, for it must not be forgotten that the very existence of a
strata of idle rich within the ruling class of a society is the result of its economic
development.
The dependence of art and aesthetic views on social conditions is thus highly
complex. There are many intermediate links between the situation and the interests of
a given class and their artistic reflection.* The social and political struggle and its
reflection in various forms of consciousness and also the psychology of certain sections
of society play a tremendous role in this respect. The artistic reproduction of reality is
also greatly influenced by the personality of the artist, his or her talent and skill, his or
her world outlook and the school of art to which he or she belongs, his or her links with
certain traditions etc.
It may be taken as a general law of the development of art that the most significant
works of art, which form part of the golden treasury of human culture, have been
artistic embodiments of living truth, of the progressive ideals and aspirations of the
people of a certain epoch.
Art that is bound up with the life of the common people is a powerful factor in
social progress. It performs its function through artistic perception of the world, through
the satisfaction of people’s aesthetic needs. It reflects reality in artistic images and
through them influences the thoughts and feelings of people, their aspirations, actions
and behaviour. Since they are expressed by certain material means, works of art are
passed on from one generation to another and serve both as a means of knowing
social life and as a means of the ideological, aesthetic and moral education of young
generations.
* To this must be added that the connection of various forms of art with social life is not always
the same. Music is connected with society and classes by far more complex relations than, for
example, literary fiction or painting. But in all its forms art cannot be profoundly understood
without a scientific analysis of the whole structure of social relations in their interaction.
56 Fundamentals of Historical Materialism
In aesthetic thought there have existed and continue to exist theories that reject
the social role of art and regard it as an end in itself. Such theories usually express a
maladjustment of the artist to his or her social environment and lead the artist, under
certain conditions, to depart from any social commitment and become involved in a
one-sided enthusiasm for formalistic experimentation and the like.
The subject of artistic expression is for the most part the life of society, particularly
the sphere of personal relations. Art also portrays nature. But even such portrayal
always implies certain human feelings, emotions, moods and so on. This demand is all
the more true of the portrayal of people, their inner world and social interaction.
The portrayal of the ugly and beautiful, the tragic and the comic, the heroic and the
trivial in the life of society and the individual presupposes a profound knowledge of
social reality, its development and meaning. The aesthetic “yardstick” that the artist
uses to measure reality is not simply a manifestation of his or her subjective will. It is
molded in the process of the whole socio-historical practice of humanity.
Thus the cognitive (and also the political, moral, educational, etc.) significance of
art must be considered in connection with its ideological and aesthetic function. When
the artist reproduces reality in the form of images, he or she makes an ideological and
aesthetic evaluation of reality, that is, the artist expresses his or her attitude to it in
accordance with his or her aesthetic ideal, his or her notions of the beautiful. This
shows how important it is that these notions should correspond to the objective
qualities of reality and be based on a correct understanding of the paths of its
development and transformation. The artist is “tendentious” even in his or her selection
of material for a work of art, not to mention the fact that he or she pronounces
judgment upon phenomena of social life, advocates one thing and condemns another,
awakens certain feelings and aspirations.
The artist seeks to give a generalised reflection of life, to show the essential,
important aspects of reality (people, their relationships). The difference between the
artistic image and the scientific concept is that the generalisation of reality in the image
is given as a living and concrete whole that can be perceived by the senses. In a scientific
work on political economy, for instance, the capitalist is but the personification of
capital, his or her personal features are of no importance. In the artistic work the
capitalist is a generalised but also individualised, sensually perceptible image, a definite
personality with his or her inner world and concretely manifested deeds and actions.
From what has been said we may define art as a specific form of social consciousness
reflecting reality in aesthetic terms. Art has the special property of giving aesthetic
pleasure, of “infecting” people with lofty ideas, feelings and emotions.
Art that is linked with the interests of the working people and socialism seeks to
Forms of Social Consciousness & Their Social Function 57
fulfil such a mission. Though it is far from imposing on the artist any strict demands
that would limit the range of his or her thought or imagination, it sees its task in serving
the millions of people who are fighting for a better future. Herein lies the partisanship
of art and its true freedom. Such art cannot be adapted either to the tastes of a handful
of snobs or to primitive tastes. The working people, said Lenin, have gained the right
to a real and great art.
Although works of literature, music, painting, etc., have no direct utilitarian
significance, certain forms of art (for example, architecture, the decorative arts, modern
industrial design, etc.) combine a utilitarian purpose with aesthetic notions.
4. Religion
Marx and Engels regarded religion and philosophy — the forms of social
consciousness that express people’s world outlook — as the most remote from the
economic basis.
Religion is of more ancient origin than philosophy. Its emergence in pre-class
society was conditioned by the lack of development of production and production
relations. As Marx wrote, primitive social relations “are conditioned by a low stage of
development of the productive powers and corresponding limited relations between
men in the process of creating and reproducing their material life, hence also limited
relations between man and nature. These real limitations are reflected in the ancient
worship of nature, and in other elements of tribal religions”.6
The early forms of religion are connected with the deification of natural forces,
plants and animals. Vestiges of these forms (animism, totemism) survive even in later
religions. Thus the Egyptian god Horus (whose earthly representative was the pharaoh)
had a human body and the head of a falcon. The ancient Greek god Zeus, although
endowed with human features, could turn into a bull, an eagle or a swan.
The spontaneously formed social relations, which were the product of people’s
own material and mental activity, acquired a special power over people as the division
of labour, private property and classes appeared. Consequently, the deification and
worship of the phenomena of nature were replaced by the deification of social forces,
and this accordingly produced a change in religious notions. The supernatural forces
that were conceived to dominate people’s lives were given human form, i.e., became
gods, ruling over both nature and social life. In the ancient Greek religion, for example,
Mars was at first the god of vegetation, and afterwards became the god of war, while
Hephaestos was at first the god of fire and later became the god of the blacksmith’s
trade.
The history of religion also shows that among no people did religion ever begin
58 Fundamentals of Historical Materialism
with monotheism, with the doctrine of one universal god, as is maintained by certain
theologists; on the contrary, monotheism was preceded by polytheism, involving the
worship of several gods.
In wars between peoples, the gods of the conquered yielded place to the gods of
the conquerors, who often assumed some of the features of the gods of the vanquished
people; the uniting of tribes and communities brought about combinations or even
the merging of gods and other objects of worship. When large monarchical states
were formed, the multiplicity of religious faiths that had been characteristic of tribal
unions and the early type of state (where one supreme deity usually emerged from a
number of deities) was replaced by the worship of one, almighty god which assumed
the attributes of all the other gods.
While all other forms of social consciousness reflect reality more or less adequately,
religion alone is the form of social consciousness which gives a distorted, fantastic picture
of the external world. Marx said that religion “is the fantastic realisation of the human
essence”, of social reality.7 Concerning the peculiar quality of religion as a distorted
view of the world, Engels wrote: “All religion … is nothing but a fantastic reflection in
men’s minds of those external forces which control their daily life, a reflection in which
the terrestrial forces assume the form of supernatural forces”.8
Religion should not be conceived of merely as some kind of belief in the world
being built upon a certain pattern and being ruled by gods and other supernatural
forces. Religion is not just a definite interpretation of reality, however much distorted.
If that were so, it would have been shattered long ago, for it would be easy to prove
that this conception of the world has no foundation in experience and to replace these
fantastic notions by a scientific conception of the world.
In addition to its highly distorted interpretation of reality, religion comprises an
emotional element, an emotional attitude to the world. A person who has a religious
view of the world conceives of himself or herself as part of this fantastic world with
which he or she associates certain hopes and expectations. This complex of feelings
bred by religion makes the latter extremely tenacious.
Religious sentiments refer to religious psychology, which is of a dual nature, being an
expression of helplessness, weakness and fear on the one hand, and of hope on the other,
which sometimes grows over into religious protest, ecstasy and fanaticism. Writing of this
level of religious consciousness, Marx underlined that “religious distress is at the same
time the expression of real distress and also the protest against real distress”.9
Thus in Marxist theory two levels of religious consciousness are differentiated, i.e.,
the world-view level and the emotional level. Religions notions and ideas constitute
the “mythological” (world-view) element of religion — a body of myths dealing with
Forms of Social Consciousness & Their Social Function 59
gods and other supernatural forces and with their relation to the world and to humanity.
The emotional level of religion — just as its world-view level — represents a twisted,
distorted level of human consciousness. Religion distorts not only people’s world
outlook, but their feelings, their emotional responses to reality as well.
It would, however, not be enough to dwell on these two levels of religious
consciousness alone. After all, we have stated that forms of social consciousness influence
and shape human conduct. The distorted conception of the world inherent in religion
as a form of social consciousness compels believers to behave in a similarly distorted
manner, manifested in religious worship. This consists of the performance of certain
rites, offering sacrifices and prayers to their deity. These rites have their origin in
primitive magic. Just as primitive communities tried to make natural forces fulfil their
desires and intentions by the performance of magical ceremonies (invocations, sacrifices
etc.), so do religious people today seek help from a god by means of certain rites and
by obeying certain prohibitions laid down by the modern religions.
Religious activity is not, however, confined to worship. Groups, associations and
organisations of believers adopt a definite attitude towards society and social issues,
participating in the life of society, social conflicts, the class struggle etc. These activities
are marked by the religious conception and attitude toward the world.
Sorcerers, witch-doctors etc. were the intermediaries between people and the
spirits which people in primitive societies believed animated the natural forces around
them. Class society brings into being a special professional group of servants of religion
— priests. The priesthood acquires great power over people’s minds. Its ideological
influence is reinforced by its connection with the state and by the establishment of a
given faith as a state religion. Religious worship is further developed, and the ceremonial
of religious services involving music and song plays an important part in fostering
religious feelings and strengthening the faith.
The three elements of religion — (1) religious notions, (2) religious feelings and (3)
worship and ritual — vary in importance depending on the social conditions.
Religion is the most conservative ideological form in that it perpetuates its precepts
in the name of a supernatural, all-powerful being. At the same time history shows us
that under the influence of great social upheavals some religions are supplanted by
others. The ancient religions in the Roman empire were conquered by Christianity in
the period of the decline of slave society. Moreover, Christianity inherited certain
definite features from the old religions, for example, recognition of the Old Testament
of Judaism, and the myths of the peoples of Mesopotamia, concerning the suffering,
death and resurrection of the gods, all this being rolled into one with vulgarised versions
of Greek philosophy, particularly that of the Stoics.
60 Fundamentals of Historical Materialism
Having emerged in the Roman empire as the religion of the poor and oppressed
masses, Christianity subsequently became the official ideology of the ruling classes
and lost many of the essential features of early Christianity: its democratic spirit, its
disapproval of rites and ceremony. With the development of feudalism “Christianity
grew into the religious counterpart to it, with a corresponding feudal hierarchy”.10
In the 16th century, on the basis of the growth and consolidation of the bourgeoisie,
Protestantism with its idea of immediate communion between God and the individual
(thus eliminating the need for an expensive, parasitic priesthood), its appeal to individual
conscience and action, its preaching of such virtues as thrift and diligence, broke away
from the feudal-Christian Catholic Church. The development of capitalism compelled
Catholicism, while preserving its dogma, to adapt itself to the new conditions and
evolve its own social doctrine designed to reconcile labour and capital, justify
colonialism and so on.
What has been said does not by any means contradict the fact that at certain
periods, for example in the Middle Ages, the revolutionary masses gave their demands
a religious form: “ … the sentiments of the masses were fed with religion to the
exclusion of all else; it was therefore necessary to put forward their own interests in the
religious guise in order to produce an impetuous movement”.11
But the positive social content that in certain historical periods took the form of
religious consciousness does not negate the basic proposition that religious
consciousness is a retrograde consciousness, and for this reason religion can never be
an adequate form of expression of the essential interests of the masses and the meaning
of human life. It always was and always will be “the opium of the people”, a means of
reconciling working people to oppressive social relations by offering them an illusory
happiness in an “afterlife”.
Marxism took up the banner of militant atheism from the old materialists and
developed their criticism of religion on the basis of the latest discoveries of natural and
social science. It revealed the social roots of religion in class society and showed that
the struggle against religion is not merely a matter of educating the masses, as was
assumed by the early materialists. It must be, above all, a struggle against the oppressive
social conditions that engender or maintain religion. Only on this basis can there be
really fruitful atheistic enlightenment, which is an inseparable part of the work of
building a scientific world outlook.
5. Science
Science comes into being only when society achieves a certain stage of maturity, and
the state of science is one of the basic indicators of social progress.
Forms of Social Consciousness & Their Social Function 61
Primitive society possessed only the rudiments of scientific knowledge. Scientific
knowledge involves the separation of intellectual labour from physical labour, and the
appearance of a written language, which makes it possible to record knowledge, preserve
it and pass it on to succeeding generations.
The rudiments of science arose as a direct response to practical needs confronting
the ruling classes of the earliest civilisations. Empirical inquiry into such fields as
astronomy, mathematics and mechanics were called into being by the needs of large-
scale irrigation, and the building of great public works such as canals, temples and
aqueducts.
The second stage in the history of science begins at the end of the 15th century with
the emergence in Europe of modern experimental natural sciences and the
simultaneous vigorous growth of the social and political sciences and philosophy. The
basic cause of this breakthrough was the emergence of the new, bourgeois social
structure within the womb of feudal society. “If, after the dark night of the Middle
Ages was over, the sciences suddenly arose anew with undreamt-of force, developing
at a miraculous rate, once again we owe this miracle to production”, wrote Engels.12
The growth of scientific knowledge, particularly in mechanics and mathematics in
the 16th, 17th and 18th centuries, was directly connected with the needs of developing
production, navigation and trade, and paved the way for the Industrial Revolution in
England at the end of the 18th century. In its turn, the transition to machine production
gave science a new technical base and powerful stimulus for development.
Summing up the history of science, Marx observed that “along with capitalist
production the scientific factor is for the first time consciously developed, applied and
created on a scale of which previous epochs had not the slightest conception”.13 We see
this most fully in late monopoly capitalism, where the development of scientific
knowledge becomes the point of departure for the revolutionising of production, for
creating whole new branches of industry.
But what is science? There is no one answer to this question, because science is a
many-sided social phenomenon combining both intellectual and material factors.
Nevertheless, the usual definition of science as a system of knowledge of the world
gives us a starting point.
All knowledge, including scientific knowledge, must be regarded as reflection of
nature and social being. All processes of nature and social life, without exception, can
form the subject-matter of scientific inquiry. This is one of the things that distinguishes
science from such forms of social consciousness as political or legal ideology or morality,
which reflect only social relations.
The interrelationship between science and religion has a different structure. These
62 Fundamentals of Historical Materialism
are essentially opposed phenomena. Religion gives a false and distorted reflection of
reality, whereas science, taken as a whole, provides a true reflection of nature and
society. The mistaken hypotheses and theories that arise in the process of development
of science do not alter the substance of the point, because error in science is either the
result of the pressure of reactionary ideology or a by-product of the quest for truth.
Religion is hostile to reason, whereas science is the highest achievement of human
reason, the embodiment of its strength and effectiveness.
Religion appeared before science, at an extremely low level of practical achievement,
when people were totally dominated by natural and social forces and were quite
unable to understand and bend them to their will. The birth of science, on the other
hand, is a direct result of humanity’s increased practical power. The development of
science and the increasing dominion of humanity over the spontaneous forces of
nature and society are interconnected. As Engels observed, “ … it is in the measure
that man has learnt to change nature that his intelligence has increased”.14 Thus, taking
into consideration the opposition between science and religion, we can begin to define
science as a system of objectively true knowledge generalising practice, from which it is
acquired and by which it is tested. But to go any further than this we must bear in mind
also the distinction between science and ordinary everyday knowledge, and the
distinction between science and art.
Everyday, empirical knowledge acquired directly from practice can exist without
science and apart from it. The people of ancient times, for instance, were aware that
day regularly follows night, that iron is heavier than wood, and so on. Even in our days,
the peasant or the craftsworker in small-scale production in the economically backward
countries makes do with the empirical knowledge that has been handed down from
generation to generation. Such knowledge also plays a considerable part in everyday
life. For example, a mother knows that her child is ill if the child starts shivering.
The thing that distinguishes science from such prescientific empirical knowledge is
that science not only provides knowledge of the individual aspects of objects and the
external connections between them, but above all tells us the laws that govern nature
and society. The knowledge that iron is heavier than wood may indeed be acquired
without science, but the concept of specific gravity, not to mention the reason for the
greater specific gravity of iron, compared with wood, is a matter for physics and
chemistry. Awareness of the fact that day follows night is instilled in our consciousness
by empirical observation, but we could never explain the causes of the succession of
day and night and the periodic lengthening and shortening of the days in the course of
the year without astronomy. Fever as a sign of illness can be detected without the help
of science, but a correct diagnosis and prescription of the necessary medicines can be
Forms of Social Consciousness & Their Social Function 63
made only by medical science based on biology and chemistry.
Scientific laws express the necessary connections between natural or social
phenomena. As such they also reveal the essence of these phenomena. Thus, for
example, chemistry has established that water is a specific unity of the chemical elements
hydrogen and oxygen, H2O. This statement is true of necessity, not by virtue of any
“logical” or “conceptual” connections, but by virtue of the real nature or essence of
water. Any chemical substance that is not H2O in its essential composition is not and
cannot be water, however much it may resemble water in its appearance. Human
beings did not always know this; it was a discovery people made about the essence of
water. Real natures or essences do not lie around on the surface for our immediate
appropriation. They have to be uncovered by investigation, observation and theory.
To acquire such knowledge is the essential task of science. As Aristotle observed:
“There is scientific knowledge of a thing only when we know its essence”.15
Art, like science, also plays a cognitive role in respect of the phenomena of social
life. Realistic art, like science, can tell us about deep-going social processes and the
psychology of a particular class. But unlike art, which always expresses the general
through the individual, the concrete, science presents it in the form of abstract logic, by
means of concepts and categories.
To sum up, the specific nature of science lies in the fact that it is the highest
generalisation of practice capable of embracing all phenomena of reality, and provides
true knowledge of the essence of phenomena and processes, the laws of nature and society
in an abstract, logical form.
The structure of science is extremely complex, but it can be reduced to three basic
interacting components.
First, science includes empirical knowledge, and not only the knowledge which is
borrowed from ordinary consciousness for the purpose of analysis and generalisation,
but also the knowledge obtained through experiments and observation. New theoretical
fields in natural science are usually opened by the experimental discovery of new facts
that refuse to “fit” into the framework of the existing theories and for some time may
defy a satisfactory theoretical explanation. This was the case with the discovery of
radioactivity at the end of the 19th century; not until 20 years later was it explained as
the conversion of chemical elements. Thus, new facts provide a stimulus to the
development of theory.
Second, science is a sphere of theoretical knowledge. It is the business of theory to
explain facts in their totality, to discover the operation of laws in empirical material
and to bring these laws together in a unified system. In every field of science the
process of accumulation of facts sooner or later leads to the creation of a theory as a
64 Fundamentals of Historical Materialism
system of knowledge, and this is a sure sign that the given field of knowledge is becoming
a science in the true sense of the term. The study of mechanics became a science thanks
to Isaac Newton, who at the end of the 17th century discovered the basic laws of the
mechanical motion of bodies and built them into a system. The study of biological
organisms became a genuine science only with Darwin’s theory of evolution of species
according to natural selection. In the second half of the last century the study of
electricity became a genuine science only when James Maxwell produced a consistent
theory of the electromagnetic field. The same period saw the great work performed by
Marx and Engels transforming the study of society into a science with the development
of the materialist theory of history, and of political economy into a science with the
development of a consistent labour theory of value.
The essence of science as a theoretical system is its laws, which reflect the objectively
necessary, essential connections of phenomena in one or another sphere. The laws of
science may be truly understood only if we take into consideration their interconnection
as an essential part of the system of scientific knowledge. Another part of theoretical
science consists of hypotheses, without which science cannot develop and which in the
course of practical testing are either rejected or else corrected, cleansed of error and
become theories.
Third and last, an inseparable part of science is its philosophical foundations and
conclusions, in which theory finds its direct continuation and culmination. Scientific
theory may have varying degrees of universality, and the greater the degree of
universality, the nearer the given theory comes to philosophy. It is not surprising
therefore that the most important synthetic theories of natural science are distinctly
philosophical in character. For example, the interpretation of the law of the conservation
and conversion of energy and the law of entropy that forms the basis of thermodynamics
would be impossible without an elucidation of the philosophical questions of the
eternity and infinity of matter and motion, their quantitative and qualitative
indestructibility. The theory of relativity establishes the connection between space,
time and matter; the quantum theory reveals the interrelation between continuity and
discontinuity at the level of interactions of sub-atomic objects. These are not only
physical but also philosophical problems.
What has been said above refers also to the generalising theories in biology and
astronomy, and even more so to the social sciences.
In the social sciences ideological factors play a part in the interpretation of facts,
that is, at the level of theory,` whereas in the natural sciences they usually function at
the level of philosophical interpretation of theories. For this reason the absolute
opposition of science to ideology, which is so characteristic of contemporary bourgeois
Forms of Social Consciousness & Their Social Function 65
philosophy and sociology, does not stand up to criticism. Nevertheless bourgeois
ideologists make a great fuss about the necessity of “cleansing” science of ideology,
their principal intention being to “cleanse” the social sciences of Marxism and completely
subordinate them to bourgeois ideology.
As for natural science, both positivism and religious philosophy insist on its complete
“deideologisation”, although from different standpoints. In their speeches at the 14th
International Philosophical Congress in Vienna (September 1968), during the debate
on the problem of “Philosophy and Natural Science” the neopositivist A.J. Ayer and
the neo-Thomist16 Joseph Meurers agreed that natural science can “only measure
quantities”. For Ayer this is the end of cognition in general, but for Meurers the
essence of the phenomena of nature can be known only by religion, so natural science
can and should be “liberated” from materialist philosophy. In this way both philosophers
impoverish natural science and limit its scope. In actual fact, science is penetrating ever
deeper into the essence of phenomena and processes and embracing an ever wider
picture of the world, and for this reason its philosophical content is steadily increasing.
While it remains a phenomenon of the intellectual life of society, science is at the
same time embodied in the sphere of its material life. It is a special field of human
activity, both theoretical and practical. At the earliest stages of scientific development,
scientists not only contemplated nature, they also acted; they invented instruments,
carried out observations, made experiments and thus gathered new facts for science.
Take for example, the ancient astronomical instrument known as the gnomon, invented
by the ancient Greeks. This was a vertical pole on a horizontal plane which they used to
determine not only the altitude of the sun above the horizon but also geographical
latitude.
In modern times such forms of scientific practice as instrumental observation, and
particularly experiment, have been rapidly developed, and today there is not a single
science that can do without a solid experimental base. In many branches of science this
base demands tremendous expenditure and is technologically far more complex than
any form of production.
The division between theory and practice in many branches of science has
demanded a division of labour between scientists. For example, experimental physicists
conduct experiments, control instruments and provide the first generalisation of the
data received, while theoretical physicists devote themselves entirely to generalising
experimental data and developing theory.
The main distinguishing feature of practical activity in science is that it is
subordinated to the work of acquiring knowledge, of developing theory. The material
and mental factors are interwoven not only in science but in any field of human
66 Fundamentals of Historical Materialism
endeavour, and the dialectics of the interaction of these factors must be taken into
account when considering either of them. Whereas material production and work
cannot exist without the intellectual element, no form of social consciousness can exist
without the material element. This is particularly true of science, which presupposes a
number of special forms of practical activity (experiment, observation), which are
often known as “practical science”. The existence of “practical science” should not,
however, be taken as an argument against regarding science as primarily a phenomenon
of the intellectual life of society, a special form of social consciousness.
6. Philosophy
There exist a wide range of vitally important questions that are not dealt with by the
specialised sciences, e.g., what is the essential nature of the world around us? Or, to put
it differently, what is the relationship between matter and consciousness? Do our
perceptions and thoughts about the world around us correspond to the reality of the
external world? What is the nature of humanity and what is its place in the world?
These and similar questions make up the content of a special form of social
consciousness, philosophy.
Philosophy is a world outlook with its own specific content and form, a world
outlook which offers theoretical grounds for its principles and conclusions. This is
what distinguishes philosophy from the unscientific, religious world outlook, which is
based on faith in the supernatural and reflects reality in forms conjured up by the
imagination and emotions.
A philosophical world outlook is a system of highly generalised theoretical views of
nature and society. Philosophy seeks to substantiate a definite orientation in political,
scientific, moral, aesthetic and other spheres of social life.
Everybody forms his or her own particular view of the surrounding world, but this
view often consists of no more than fragments of various contradictory ideas without
any theoretical basis. The philosophical world outlook, on the other hand, is not
merely the sum total but a system of ideas, opinions and conceptions of nature,
society, the individual human being and his or her place in the world. It does not
merely proclaim its principles and try to make people believe in them; it gives logical
arguments for these principles.
By no means every theoretically substantiated world outlook is scientific in character.
The actual content of a philosophical world outlook may be scientific or unscientific or
even anti-scientific. Only the world outlook that bases its conclusions on the findings
of contemporary science, that uses scientific method in its thinking and allows no place
for various kinds of anti-scientific, mystical and religious views and superstitions may
Forms of Social Consciousness & Their Social Function 67
be considered scientific. Of course, the very idea of scientificality must be considered
historically. For example, the world outlook of the French materialists of the 18th
century was scientific because in addition to the historically transient element in their
teaching there was something that proved to be historically intransient, and this has
been inherited by modern materialism. There were also scientific ideas and propositions
in the great idealist philosophical systems (for example, in Descartes, Leibnitz, Kant,
Fichte and Hegel) to the extent that they had a true grasp of ideal relationships and
connections.
The subject matter of philosophy has changed historically in close connection with
the development of all aspects of humanity’s intellectual life, with the development of
science and philosophical thought itself.
Philosophy first arose in the commercially oriented city-states of ancient Greece.
The most ancient form of world view, which immediately preceded philosophy in
history, was religion. In religious mythology with its belief in imaginary spirits and
gods as the creators and rulers of the world, great importance was attached to questions
of the origin and essence of the world. Philosophy grew out of the myth-steeped
religious consciousness, while simultaneously fighting it, and thus took shape in its
struggle to furnish a naturalistic, as opposed to a supernatural, explanation of the
world. The emergence of philosophy coincides historically with the beginnings of
scientific knowledge, with the need for theoretical inquiry. In fact, philosophy was the
first historical form of theoretical knowledge, of science.
Initially, philosophy tried to answer the questions that had already been posed by
the religious-mythological view of the world. But philosophy had a different way of
tackling these questions. It based itself on a theoretical analysis that was in accord with
logic and practical experience.
The early Greek philosophers (Thales, Anaximenes, Anaximander, Parmenides,
Heraclitus and others) were mainly interested in understanding the origin of the diverse
phenomena of nature. Natural philosophy (philosophical doctrine concerning nature)
was the first historical form of philosophical thought.
As specialised scientific knowledge was accumulated and thinkers began to develop
specific methods of research and notions about the laws prevailing in various realms
of nature, a process of differentiation of the hitherto undivided body of theoretical
knowledge occurred, and mathematics, medicine, astronomy and other disciplines
broke away and formed separate sciences. But this process was not one-sided. As the
range of problems studied by philosophy diminished, there was a corresponding
development, deepening and enrichment of the purely philosophical notions, and
various philosophical theories and schools emerged. Such philosophical disciplines
68 Fundamentals of Historical Materialism
were formed as ontology — the study of being, or the essence of all that exists;
epistemology — the theory of knowledge; logic — the science of the forms of correct,
that is to say, consistent, argued thinking; the philosophy of history, ethics, aesthetics,
and later, philosophy itself.
The age of the Renaissance, and particularly the 17th and 18th centuries, accelerated
the process of differentiation. Mechanics, physics, chemistry, biology, jurisprudence,
and political economy became independent branches of scientific knowledge. This
progressive division of labour in the sphere of scientific knowledge brought about a
qualitative change in the goal of philosophy, its place in the system of knowledge and
its relationship to the specialised sciences. Philosophy was no longer able to devote
itself to solving the special problems of mechanics, physics, astronomy, chemistry,
biology, law, history and so on, though it was still better equipped to deal with general
scientific questions, with questions of world outlook, which are often implied in the
work of the specialised sciences, but which cannot be solved within their terms of
reference and by their specialised methods.
We know from history that the interrelationships between philosophy and the
specialised sciences have been extremely complex and contradictory in character, since
the specialised sciences (with the exception of mathematics and mechanics) were for a
long time restricted mainly to empirical research, while the general theoretical questions
concerning these sciences were dealt with by philosophy. But philosophical inquiry
into the theoretical problems of the specialised sciences was not based on sufficient
factual material (as a rule such material had not been accumulated); such inquiry was
therefore abstract and speculative, and its results often conflicted with the latest facts
discovered by science. This was where the opposition arose between philosophy and
the specialised sciences, which assumed a particularly acute form in those philosophical
doctrines that were connected with religion and sought to provide a justification for
the religious world outlook, which is incompatible with science.
Some philosophers created encyclopaedic philosophical systems designed to
counterpose the philosophy of nature to natural science, the philosophy of history to
history as a science, or the philosophy of law to the science of law. These philosophers
usually assumed that philosophy was able to go beyond the bounds of experience, to
provide “superscientific” knowledge. Such illusions were exploded by the development
of the specialised sciences, which proved that physical problems can be solved only by
physics, chemical problems by chemistry and so on.
At the same time, the opposite tendency, the reduction of philosophy to the status
of a specialised science, was to be observed in a number of philosophical doctrines.
The successes of the specialised sciences, particularly mathematics and mechanics,
Forms of Social Consciousness & Their Social Function 69
prompted philosophers to study the methods by which these successes had been
obtained, so that they could find out whether these methods could be used in
philosophy. Philosophers often attempted to apply, for example, the axiomatic method
of mathematics for building up philosophical systems; attempts were also made to
universalise the principles of classical mechanics, so that, basing itself on these principles,
philosophy could explain not only the phenomena of inanimate nature, but also
biological and even social processes.
The development of the specialised sciences demonstrated, however, that there
are problems that can be dealt with by philosophy as well as by the sciences. In fact,
such problems can be solved only by their joint efforts. There are also some specific
philosophical problems that philosophy alone can solve, but even here a solution can
be obtained only if philosophy relies on the sum-total of the scientific data and advanced
social practice.
But philosophy that relies upon scientific data begins to loose its character as
“philosophy”, as explanations about the world relying simply upon pure thought. It
was in this sense that Engels declared that with the development of the dialectical
materialist conception of nature and of human history, philosophy is reduced to study
of the “realm of pure thought”, to the “theory of the laws of the thought process itself,
logic and dialectics”. In the realm of the study of nature and human history, philosophy
as such “becomes unnecessary and impossible” since in these spheres of knowledge, it
“is no longer a question anywhere of inventing interconnections from out of our
brains, but of discovering them in the facts” of material reality.17 n
70 Fundamentals of Historical Materialism
4. Material Production:
The Basis of Social Life
The subject matter of historical materialism is human society and the most general
laws of its development. The first step towards discovering these laws was to establish
the role of material production in the life of society. It will easily be understood that
society cannot exist without producing the material goods needed for human life. This
proposition is obvious and had been recognised even before the time of Marx and
Engels. But Marx and Engels did not stop there; they established the law-governed
dependence of all social relations on the relations people enter into to produce material
goods.
In the process of production people do not only create material products; production
does not only provide people with means of existence. In producing material goods
people produce and reproduce their own social relations. The study of social production,
its structure, its constituent elements and their interconnections, therefore, makes it
possible to penetrate into the essence of the historical process, to reveal the deep-
going social mechanisms that operate in the life of society.
3. Production relations
Production has always been and remains social. In creating material, goods people
enter into various relations with one another, and only within the bounds of these
relations does their relation to nature exist.
People have never produced anything purely as individuals in complete isolation
from one another. The idea of anybody being able to produce in absolute isolation,
outside society, is a pure figment of the imagination. As we have said already, humans
emerged from the animal world and developed only in society, in intercourse with
others of their own kind. In the first stages of the development of society, production
was collective in the direct sense of the term. When it lost its collective character and
was carried on by separate families, the production relations between people did not
disappear. They were retained and afterwards extended along with the development
of the social division of labour and the growth of commodity production and exchange.
As the division of labour developed, every producer became increasingly dependent
on the others, inasmuch as he or she obtained from them his or her raw materials and
implements and sold them his or her products. Finally, with the appearance of large-
scale machine production, these interconnections between producers became even
more organic, as expressed in the extensive socialisation of the process of labour.
Various relations are formed between people in the production process. There
are, for example, relations conditioned by the technical division of labour between
various specialised trades. These are relations between workshops of a factory, between
the workers performing certain interrelated production operations, and so on. They
may be described as the work (production-technical) relations, or more accurately, the
division of labour within a production unit. They are conditioned by the instruments
of labour available to the producers and their technical knowledge and skills. The
division of labour, the technical cooperation necessary for production, involved with a
specific technology is both a force and a relation of production.
Social production (economic) relations are a different matter. Their character
depends on how the means of production are distributed in a society or, in other
words, how the problem of the ownership of the basic means of production has been
Material Production: The Basis of Social Life 89
solved in that society.
In principle, in the most general form, this problem may be resolved in two ways:
Either the means of production belong to the whole of society, or they belong to
individuals or a part of society, while the other part of society is barred from any
participation in ownership. In other words, ownership of the means of production
may be social or private. But ownership is not simply the right to something in law, i.e.,
property. Ownership is a real economic relationship between people, mediated by
their indirect relationship to things — to the means of production. The social relations
that people enter into in undertaking production are not the result of any deliberate
act; they come about by an unconscious and spontaneous adaptation to the material
productive forces at their disposal. But in entering into these relations in the process of
production, people become conscious of the need to make them socially recognised
and obligatory. In undertaking production, then, it is necessary for people to socially
regulate their mutual relations to the means of production. This is how property relations
arise.
In social production, the means of production become the property of various
people or groups of people. For in carrying on production and the distribution of the
results of production, it is necessary that some arrangement should be made, binding
on all members of a given society, by which it is known who is entitled to dispose of the
various means of production and of the product which is produced by working with
them. Property relations, therefore, are ways of socially regulating people’s mutual
relationships in the process of utilising the means of production and disposing of the
product, of making the relations of production obligatory relations, binding on society
and all its members.
We can therefore define the social relations of production as the mutual relations
into which people enter in the process of production and disposal of the product, and of
which they become conscious as property relations.
If the means of production are owned by the whole of society, the members of
society stand in an equal relationship to the means of production, and collectivist
relations of cooperation and mutual help are established between them. The forms of
this cooperation, like the forms of social ownership, may differ. For example, in history
social ownership is found in the forms of the property of a clan, tribe or primitive
commune, and the property of the working class as a whole in a post-capitalist society,
held and administered by the workers’ state.
If, on the other hand, the owners of the means of production are individuals, if the
means of production are in the hands of only a part and not the whole of society,
property acquires a private character, people are placed in an unequal relationship to
90 Fundamentals of Historical Materialism
the means of production, and relations of domination and subjection, relations of
exploitation, appear.
What is meant by exploitation? When the instruments of labour are primitive and,
consequently, the productivity of labour is low, only a rudimentary technical-productive
division of labour is possible. All members of the society are compelled to work in
common to survive. This leads to common ownership of the means of production and
the fruits of production, such as they are, are accordingly shared by the whole
community, by the whole clan or tribe. But when the instruments of labour become
more powerful and consequently labour productivity increases, labour produces a
surplus over and above what the producers require to satisfy their own essential
needs. There thus arises the possibility for a minority in society, if they can appropriate
this surplus, to live off the labour of others. This possibility becomes a reality when this
minority appropriates the means of production that the labourers utilise to produce
the surplus, i.e., when the mass of producers are forced to accept these means of
production as the private property of this minority. For the producers, exploitation
therefore means that only a part of their total labour is used to meet their own
requirements, the rest being appropriated and used by another, by virtue of the
latter’s private ownership of some form of means of production. By taking other
people’s surplus labour, the exploiters can live well without having to work.
Exploitation means that some people, the minority of society, by virtue of their
ownership of large-scale property, live without labour off the fruits of the labour of
others, the majority.
In his 1859 preface to A Contribution to a Critique of Political Economy, Marx
defined different basic types of socioeconomic formation based on the exploitation of
labour — Asiatic, slave, feudal and capitalist. At each of these stages of social development
there also existed or exists the small private property of the peasants and craftsmen,
based on personal labour.
The form of property in each of these types of society determines the mode of
exploitation of the producers. The Asiatic mode of production* first appeared in
ancient Iraq and Egypt in the 4th millennium BC, in the Indus river valley in the 3rd
* The fact that this mode of production also arose outside Asia — in ancient Egypt and in
ancient Mexico and Peru — makes the designation “Asiatic” misleading. Marx used this adjective
to designate this mode of production because he first became aware of it during his studies of the
impact of British capitalism on India and China during the 18th and 19th centuries. Since this
mode of production was based upon large-scale irrigation works organised by a despotic state
which extracted suplus labour from village communes as tribute, later Marxists have used a
number of different terms to designate it, e.g., “hydraulic”, “communal” and “tributary”.
Material Production: The Basis of Social Life 91
millennium BC, in northern China in the 2nd millennium BC. This mode of production
arose on the basis of and was dependent upon an agriculture that required large-scale
public works carried out by the community as a whole. The basic means of production
— the land and the water — were the private property of a despotic ruler. The labouring
population — the village communities of craftsmen-peasants — owned their
instruments of labour (tools, oxen) but were dependent upon the ruler and the vast
apparatus of officials he commanded (headed by a priestly and military nobility) for
the organisation of the construction and maintenance of the large-scale irrigation
systems (canals, dykes, reservoirs). The king and the priestly and military nobility
exploited the rural population through the forcible extraction of tribute (in both goods
and labour services).
It is typical of slave production relations, which arose in ancient Greece and Rome,
that not only the means of labour, but also the labourers themselves became the
property of other people, the slave-owners. The latter appropriated to themselves the
whole product of the slave’s labour, allowing the slaves only as much as was necessary
to keep them alive.
The system of feudal relations, which arose in medieval western Europe, was
based on large-scale property in land. The craftsmen-peasants (serfs) were personally
dependent upon the feudal landowner for the provision of a small plot of land on
which to live and make a living. This enabled the feudal lord to exploit the serfs by
requiring them to provide labour services to him free of charge.
The economic structure of capitalism is based on the capitalists’ private ownership
of the basic means of production — the factories, mines etc. — and on free labour, i.e.,
labour that is free of personal dependence, and free of possession of means of
subsistence. Economic necessity compels the worker to sell his or her labour-power as
a commodity to the owner of capital, and only in this form can the worker become
united with the means of labour and begin the process of production. The capitalist
extracts surplus labour from the worker by purchasing his or her labour-power at a
price on the market (the wage rate) that is lower than the value (amount of socially
necessary labour) of the commodities which the worker produces while working for
the capitalist.
Thus property relations have fundamental significance in the history of humanity.
Whole epochs of human history differ from one another depending on the dominant
forms of property. Indeed property relations are always an expression of a definite
system of production relations. The bounds of these relations are determined by the
movement of the material product, which begins in the sphere of material production,
passes through a definite cycle there, and then through exchange and distribution
92 Fundamentals of Historical Materialism
reaches the consumer and ends in the sphere of individual consumption. Consumption
itself depends on production, but at the same time is opposed to it in the sense that it
takes a material product out of the sphere of production relations.
Consequently, production relations imply not only the forms in which the producer
is united with the means of labour in the process of material production, but also the
relations of exchange of activity and the products of activity, and the distribution of the
material goods produced. The need for the exchange of activity and its products stems
from the existence of a social division of labour — the division into craft/industrial and
agricultural, mental and physical labour etc.
The character of distribution — the forms and size of the incomes of various
classes and social groups — also depend on the form of property.
Like the productive forces, relations of production also belong to the material side
of social life. The material character of production relations is expressed in the fact that
they exist objectively, independently of human will and consciousness. Their existence
and character are determined not by people’s wishes, but by the level of production
that has been achieved. Moreover, the production (or economic) relations established
between people are not only not determined by people’s social consciousness; they
are not even completely grasped by it.
The productive forces and relations of production are the two inseparable aspects
of social production. Only in abstraction can the forces of production be considered
without production relations, or vice versa. In reality they are as inseparable from each
other as content and form, if in this case we regard the productive forces as content
and the relations of production as the social form. Just as, in general, content determines
form, so do the productive forces determine production relations. In their turn, the
production relations endow the functioning of the forces of production with a certain
social quality. Although the production relations depend on the state and character of
the productive forces, it is the production relations that determine the social nature of
every mode of production.
* This distinction between the social basis and the social superstructure was misrepresented by
Nikolai Bukharin in his 1921 work Historical Materialism: A System of Sociology. Bukharin
declared that the term “superstructure” included “any type of social phenomena erected on the
economic base … including social psychology … as well as such phenomena as language and
thought”. Thus, social superstructure was equated by Bukharin with social consciousness. Later,
Stalin enshrined this view as part of the canon of official Soviet “historical materialism”. “The
superstructure”, Stalin declared, “consists of the political, legal, artistic and philosophical views
of society and the political, legal, and other institutions corresponding to them” (J. V. Stalin,
Marxism and Linguistics, New York, 1951, p. 9). Marx, however, made a clear distinction
between the “political and legal superstructure” of society and the “definite forms of social
consciousness” which corresponded to the superstructural institutions. Although superstructural
institutions are consciously created by people, this does not mean that their ideas and aims are
part of these institutions, any more than tools consist of both tools and people’s ideas for
making tools. Like tools, the social superstructure is the material realisation of people’s ideas,
not the ideas themselves. The Bukharin-Stalin conception of the superstructure as including
people’s political, legal, religious etc., ideas is a partial revival of the idealist conception espoused
by Aleksandr Bogdanov that equates social being with social consciousness.
110 Fundamentals of Historical Materialism
resist the existing form of management and rule. This is the most immediate and
direct way in which intellectual processes are connected with the economic structure of
a given socioeconomic formation. Most remotely connected with the economic basis,
and more directly related to the existing political conflicts, there arise further intellectual
processes — religious, moral, philosophical, artistic and so on — and institutions
associated with them.
Every socioeconomic formation has its basis and corresponding superstructure.
The superstructure, like the basis, is therefore historically specific in character.
Depending on what kind of economic basis, what classes a given society possesses, it
will be dominated by the corresponding political, legal, religious and philosophical
views and also institutions corresponding to these views. It is quite impossible for the
economy of a country to be dominated by feudal lords or capitalists while in politics, in
the legal system and in intellectual life, the predominant role is played by the working
people. Such an incongruity could not possibly exist for any length of time. The relations
of production in feudal or bourgeois society are class relations. And the class that
holds the dominant position in the given economic structure naturally holds the
dominant position in the ideological sphere, establishes its political domination, creates
and passes laws preserving this economic and political domination, and therefore also
holds the dominating position throughout the superstructure.
The distinction between basis and superstructure is a distinction between two
social processes which are the most obvious and open to investigation, and most
immediately affect the members of society and strike the attention of historians, and
those which are less immediately obvious and the details of which can only be uncovered
by patient researches. What is most obvious is the ideas which people are proclaiming,
the speeches they are making and the epithets they are throwing at each other; the
political, legal, religious, moral, philosophic, aesthetic battles they are fighting; and the
organisations and institutions they have organised to wage these battles. Less obvious
and, as it were, buried beneath all this but nevetheless sustaining it, are the economic
processes and relations of the socioeconomic formation. All the hurly-burly on the
surface is conditioned by the underlying economic relationships, and serves a social
function relative to their development.
According to the idealist conceptions of history the primary, determining factor in
social development is to be found in the ideas of society. According to the idealists,
people first develop certain ideas, then they create organisations corresponding to
those ideas, and on that basis they carry on their economic life.
“The whole previous view of history”, wrote Engels, “was based on the conception
that the ultimate causes of all historical changes are to be looked for in the changing
The Socioeconomic Formation 111
ideas of human beings. . . But the question was not asked as to whence the ideas
come into men’s minds.”3
On the other hand, the process of economic development is self-explanatory. If
you ask “why did certain economic relations arise?” — why did private ownership
come into being, why did products become commodities, why did wage-labour come
into being and so on — then you do not have to look outside the sphere of economic
development itself in order to find the explanation.
And then, having established the trend of economic development and the economic
causes of it, it can be explained why, on the basis of that development, people grew
dissatisfied with some ideas and developed other ones, rebelled against old political
and legal institutions and set up new ones. Engels wrote: “… the economic structure of
society always furnishes the real basis, starting from which we can alone work out the
ultimate explanation of the whole superstructure of juridical and political institutions
as well as of the religious, philosophical, and other ideas of a given historical period”.4
We have considered the dependence of the superstructure on the basis, which is
expressed in the fact that the economic basis determines the content of intellectual processes
of any given society and therefore the content of its superstructure. Changes in the
superstructure occur under the influence of changes in the basis, mediated through
changes in social consciousness. The elimination of the old basis and emergence of a
new one bring about the transformation of the whole enormous superstructure.
At the same time the superstructure possesses a relative independence in relation
to its basis. A social system can never be so rigid and closely determined as a system of
mechanical dependencies. The basis influences the superstructure through the
interlocking economic and political interests of classes, the complex system of
intermediate links between the economy and various forms of social consciousness.
History is made by the people, by social classes. Responding to changes in the economic
basis of society, to the rise of new productive forces, they create new ideas and conduct
an ideological struggle against the old order, carry out a revolution, change the
superstructure, sweep away the old, outmoded property relations — the legal
expression of the old, outmoded production relations — and thus clear the way for the
development of new production relations corresponding to the new productive forces.
The dependence of the superstructure on the basis should not therefore be
oversimplified, understood as a mechanism that operates automatically. It is wrong to
attribute all changes in the superstructure to economic causes. Various interactions
take place within the elements of the superstructure that lead to results which are
sometimes not economically conditioned. It is only in the final analysis that the economy
(the relations of production) determines the social superstructure.
112 Fundamentals of Historical Materialism
The social function of the superstructure is to protect, fortify and develop its basis.
In a class-divided society, the superstructure ensures the political and ideological
supremacy of the class that holds the dominant position in the economy. It does this
not only through ideological means, but also through other forms of social control.
The state, for example, also employs coercion, includes such material factors as army,
police force, courts and prisons. The superstructure is therefore always an active force
influencing all aspects of social life, including its own basis. Thus, for example, from the
economic processes of feudalism in Europe arose not only feudal ideas and a feudal
superstructure, but also ideological controversies and institutional struggles which
reflected the conflict between nascent capitalism and decaying feudalism; great
ideological battles, political upheavals and religious wars took place — all of which
played an indispensable part in the development of the feudal economy itself and in
the economic change from feudal relations of production to capitalist ones.
6. SOCIAL REVOLUTION
In the development of society there occur both gradual evolutionary changes and
leaps in various fields — science and technology, the means of production and
communications, people’s outlook. The most significant of these are termed
“revolutions”. But even significant changes in certain aspects of social life, taken by
themselves, do not yet signify social revolution. Social revolution means a fundamental
change in the whole socioeconomic system.
Qualitative transformations may also occur within one and the same socioeconomic
system, during transition from one phase or stage of its development to another.
Such, for example, is the transition from pre-monopoly capitalism to monopoly
capitalism. But this is not a social revolution because the basic features of capitalism
continue to exist. Social revolution, on the other hand, “is a change which breaks the
old order to its very foundations”.1
Social revolution implies a qualitative leap in the development of society, resulting
in the replacement of one socioeconomic formation by another.
What are social classes? Why do classes exist at certain stages in the development of
society? What place do class relations occupy in social life? The correct answering of
these questions supplies the key to our understanding of the essence of such important
social phenomena of the modern world as the state, political relations and ideological
life. The class approach to the analysis of the life of any society divided into classes is
one of the fundamental methodological principles of Marxism. Explaining the
significance of this principle, Lenin wrote: “People always have been the foolish victims
of deception and self-deception in politics, and they always will be until they have
learnt to seek out the interests of some class or other behind all moral, religious,
political and social phrases, declarations and promises”.1
Classes and class antagonisms complicates the structure of social life. New forms of
social relations, political and legal, arise. Political activity comprises a number of
organisations and institutions that were unknown in pre-class societies. The most
important of them is the state, which is the organisation of political power of the ruling
class. In class society, political parties and other public organisations arise that are
designed to win or maintain political power, to fight for the interests of this or that
class. All these organisations and institutions, taken together, constitute the political
organisation of society. The political organisation of any class society may thus be
defined as a system of institutions and organisations regulating the political relations
between human communities (e.g., nations), classes and states. The political life of society
embraces political institutions and relations, political consciousness and activities.
The way in which people are organised to produce the material goods they need for
their survival is the basis of all social relations. It determines the structure of society,
the types of social groups and the more or less stable historical forms of human
community.
References to the works of Marx and Engels and Lenin in the most frequently quoted
editions have been abbreviated as follows:
Introduction
1 MESW, Vol. 1, p. 20
2 The Macquarie Dictionary (Macquarie Library: Sydney, 1989), p. 381
3 F. Engels, The Condition of the Working Class in England (Progress Publishers: Moscow,
1973), p. 64
4 ibid., pp. 64-65
5 K. Marx, Capital, Vol. 1 (Penguin Books: Harmondsworth, 1976), p. 283
6 MESW, Vol. 1, p. 14
6. Social Revolution
1 LCW, Vol. 33. p. 110
Notes 205
2 LCW, Vol. 13, p. 37
3 LCW, Vol. 23, pp. 238-239; Vol. 29, pp. 157, 203
4 LCW, Vol. 27, p. 89
5 LCW, Vol. 21, pp. 213-14
6 MESW, Vol. 1, p. 193