Bertrand Russell - The Problems of Philosophy
Bertrand Russell - The Problems of Philosophy
Bertrand Russell - The Problems of Philosophy
f^.eSi'SEH-lo
Walsh
Philosophy
Collection
PRESENTED /ortf
LIBRARIES of the
UNIVERSITY o/TORONTO
^.^L^^ut^^C^ /Tt^AX^^"^^
LMAn^i/^"^^^ oJc
"J
HOME UNIVERSITY LIBRARY
OF MODERN KNOWLEDGE
No. S6
Editors :
BERTRAND RUSSELL
M.A., F.R.8.
NEW YORK
HENRY HOLT AND COMPANY
LONDON
WILLIAMS AND N ORG ATE
PREFACE
In the following pages, I have confined
myself in the main to those problems of
philosophy in regard to which I thought
it possible to say something positive and
constructive, since merely negative criticism
seemed out of place. For
this reason, theory
of knowledge occupies a larger space than
metaphysics in the present volume, and some
topics much discussed by philosophers are
treated very briefly, all.
if at
I have derived valuable assistance from
IV IDEALISM 58
VI ON INDUCTION ..... 93
Vn ON OUR
PRINCIPLES .....
KNOWLEDGE OF GENERAL
109
Xin KNOWLEDGE,
OPINION .....
ERROR, AND PROBABLE
204
INDEX 253
THE
PROBLEMS OF PHILOSOPHY
CHAPTER I
wholly true.
To make our difficulties plain, let us con-
centrate attention on the table. the eye To
it is oblong, brown and shiny, to the touch
it issmooth and cool and hard when I ;
favouritism, we
are compelled to deny that,
in itself, the table has any one particular
colour.
The same thing applies to the texture.
With the naked eye one can see the grain,
but otherwise the table looks smooth and
even. If we looked at it through a micro-
be?
It will help us in considering these questions
to have a few simple terms of which the
—
mind not necessarily the mind of God,
but more often the whole collective mind of
the universe. This they hold, as Berkeley
does, chiefly because they think there can
be —
nothing real or at any rate nothing
—
known to be real except minds and their
thoughts and feelings. We might state the
argument by which they support their view
"
in some such way as this Whatever:
it do not put it so
shortly or so crudely. But
whether valid or not, the argument has been
very widely advanced in one form or another ;
daily life.
CHAPTER II
frightened by absurdities.
One great reason why it is felt that we must
secure a physical object in addition to the
sense-data, is that we want the same object
for different people. When ten people are
sittinground a dinner-table, it seems pre-
posterous to maintain that they are not
32 THE PROBLEMS OF PHILOSOPHY
seeing the same tablecloth, the same knives
and forks and spoons and glasses. But the
sense-data are private to each separate person ;
what is immediately present to the sight
of one not immediately present to the
is
B
34 THE PROBLEMS OF PHILOSOPHY
consists of sense-data, and does not reveal
other people's experiences unless our own
sense-data are signs of things existing inde-
oendently of us. We must therefore, if
ball.
to
arguments, and it is therefore worth while
THE EXISTENCE OF MATTER 39
instinctively.
Philosophy should show us the hierarchy
of our instinctive beliefs, beginning with
those we hold most strongly, and presenting
each as much isolated and as free from irrele-
1
motion according to the laws of motion.
Science does not deny that it may have other
properties ; but if so, such other properties
are not useful to the man of science, and in
no way assist him in explaining the pheno-
mena.
It is sometimes said that " light is a form
of wave-motion," but this is misleading, for
the light which we immediately see, which
we know directly by means of our senses,
is not a form of wave-motion, but some-
sight.
requires investigation.
We agreed provisionally that physical
objects cannot be quite like our sense-data,
but may be regarded as causing our sen-
sations. These physical objects are in the
space of science, which we may call " physi-
"
cal space. It is important to notice that,
if our sensations are to be caused by phy-
sical objects, there must be a physical space
IDEALISM
" "
The word idealism is used by different
philosophers in somewhat different senses,.
opinion.
The grounds on which ideahsm is advocated
are generally grounds derived from the theory
of knowledge, that is to say, from a discussion
of the conditions which things must satisfy
in order that we may be able to know them.
The first serious attempt to establish idealism
on such grounds was that of Bishop Berkeley.
He proved first, by arguments which were
largely valid, that our sense-data cannot be
supposed to have an existence independent
" "
of us,but must be, in part at least, in
"
We can never truly judge that something
with which we are not acquainted exists."
This is by no means a truism, but on the
contrary a palpable falsehood, I have not
the honour to be acquainted with the Emperor
of Russia, but I truly judge that he exists.
knowledge by description.
All our knowledge, both knowledge of,
*' "
my desiring food an object with which
is
" "
of the form the so-and-so (in the singular)
" "
I shall call a definite description. Thus
"
a man " is an ambiguous description, and
" "
the man with the iron mask is a definite
description. There are various problems con-
nected with ambiguous descriptions, but I
pass them by, since they do not directly con-
cern the matter we are discussing, which is the
nature of our knowledge concerning objects
in cases where we know that there is an object
description
"
when we know that it is " the
so-and-so," i.e. when we know that there is
ACQUAINTANCE AND DESCRIPTION 88
\
88 THE PROBLEMS OF PHILOSOPHY
we convey to others, apart from the fact about
the actual Bismarck, which gives importance
to our judgment, the thought we really have
contains the one or more particulars involved,
and otherwise consists wholly of concepts.
All names of —
places London, England,
Europe, the Earth, the Solar System simi,- —
larly involve, when used, descriptions which
start from some one or more particulars with
which we are acquainted. I suspect that even
the Universe, as considered by metaphysics,
involves such a connection with particulars.
In logic, on the contrary, where we are
concerned not merely with what does exist,
but with whatever might or could exist or
be, no reference to actual particulars is
involved.
would seem that, when we make a
It
statement about something only known by
description, we often intend to make our
statement, not in the form involving the
description, but about the actual thing de-
scribed. That is to say, when we say any-
thing about Bismarck, we should like, if we
could, to make the judgment which Bismarck
ACQUAINTANCE AND DESCRIPTION 89
by an appeal to experience.
The inductive principle, however, is equally
incapable of being proved by an appeal to
experience. Experience might conceivably
confirm the inductive principle as regards the
cases that have been already examined ; but
as regards unexamined cases, it is the in-
ductive principle alone that can justify any
inference from what has been examined to
what has not been examined. All arguments
1
of our expectations about the future. If the
principle is assumed.
Thus all knowledge which, on a basis of
108 THE PROBLEMS OF PHILOSOPHY
experience, tells us something about what is
not experienced, is based upon a belief which
experience can neither confirm nor confute,
yet which, at least in its more concrete appli-
cations, appears to be as firmly rooted in us
as many the facts of experience. The
of
existence and justification of such beliefs —
for the inductive principle, as we shall see,
is not the only example
— raises some of the
most difficult and most debated problems of
philosophy. We will, in the next chapter,
consider briefly what may be said to account
for such knowledge, and what is its scope and
its degree of certainty.
CHAPTER VII
"
Suppose it known that if this is true, then
that is true. Suppose it also known that this
is true, then it follows that that is true."
When it is the case that if this is true, that
" "
is true, we shall say that this implies that,
"
and that that " follows from this. Thus
our principle states that if this implies that,
and this is true, then that is true. In other
112 THE PROBLEMS OF PHILOSOPHY
"
words, anything implied by a true pro-
"
position is true," or whatever follows from
a true proposition is true."
This principle is really involved —at least,
concrete instances of it are involved— in all
demonstrations. Whenever one thing which
we believe is used to prove something else,
is."
"
(2) The law of contradiction : Nothing
can both be and not be."
"
(3) The law of excluded middle Every-
:
ceding chapter.
One of the great historic controversies in
philosophy is the controversy between the
two schools called respectively "empiricists "
and
"
rationalists." The empiricists who —
are best represented by the British philo-
sophers, Locke, Berkeley, and Hume main-
—
tained that all our knowledge is derived from
experience ;
—
the rationalists who are repre-
sented by the Continental philosophers of the
seventeenth century, especially Descartes and
—
Leibniz maintained that, in addition to
what we know by experience, there are certain
** " "
innate ideas and innate principles,"
GENERAL PRINCIPLES 115
disproved by experience.
All pure mathematics
a priori, like logic.
is
* Mathematics
Cf. A. N. Whitehead, Introduction to
"
"
two and two are four," and empirical
"
generalisations such as all men are mortal."
portant.
CHAPTER VIII
knowledge.
Hume(1711-1776), who preceded Kant,
accepting the usual view as to what makes
knowledge a priori, discovered that, in many
cases which had previously been supposed
analytic, and notably in the case of cause and
effect, the connection was really synthetic.
Before Hume, rationalists at least had
supposed that the effect could be logically
deduced from the cause, if only we had
sufficient knowledge. Hume
argued cor- —
rectly, as would now be generally admitted
—that this could not be done. Hence he
inferred the far more doubtful proposition
that nothing could be known a priori about
130 THE PROBLEMS OF PHILOSOPHY
the connection of cause and effect. Kant,
who had been educated in the rationahst
tradition, was much perturbed by Hume's
142
THE WORLD OF UNIVERSALS 143
possible.
The first of these views, which was advo-
cated by Spinoza, and is held in our own day
by Mr. Bradley and many other philosophers,
is called monism ; the second, which was
advocated by Leibniz, but is not very common
nowadays, is called monadism, because each
of the isolated things is called a monad. Both
these opposing philosophies, interesting as
they are, result, in my opinion, from an undue
attention to one sort of universals, namely the
sort represented by adjectives and substan-
THE WORLD OF UNI VERS ALS 149
quainted.
Another relation with which we become
acquainted in much the same way is resem-
blance. If I see simultaneously two shades
of green, I can see that they resemble each
other ; if I also see a shade of red at the same
ON KNOWLEDGE OF UNIVERSALS 161
couple.
Thus the statement " two and two are four **
deals exclusively with universals, and therefore
,
If the above account is correct, all our know-
If
demonstrations ;
but they themselves, or at
least some of them, are incapable of
demonstration.
Self-evidence, however, is not confined to
those among general principles which are
incapable of proof. When a certain number
have been admitted, the
of logical principles
rest can be deduced from them but the ;
that, if we choose
to suppose it false, nothing
will any longer be incoherent with anything
else. Thus the laws of logic supply the
skeleton or framework within which the test
of coherence applies, and they themselves
cannot be established by this test.
TRUTH AND FALSEHOOD 198
a
194 THE PROBLEMS OF PHILOSOPHY
opposition of truth and falsehood, but would
have to be always true. This may be made
clearby examples. Othello believes falsely
that Desdemona loves Cassio. We cannot
say that this belief consists in a relation to a
"
single object, Desdemona's love for Cassio,"
ing fact.
It will be seen that minds do not create
belief.
must be true.
The second sort of self -evidence will be that
KNOWLEDGE AND ERROR 215
intuitive it follows
already.
It follows that we cannot prove that the
universe as a whole forms a single harmonious
system such as Hegel believes that it forms.
And if we cannot prove this, we also cannot
previous chapters.
Most of the great ambitious attempts of
metaphysicians have proceeded by the at-
tempt to prove that such and such apparent
features of the actual world were self-contra-
Formerly it
appeared that experience left
only one kind of space to logic, and logic
showed this one kind to be impossible. Now,
logic presents many kinds of space as possible
apart from experience, and experience only
partially decides between them. Thus, while
our knowledge of what is has become less than
"
kind is unreasonable. Descartes' methodi-
cal doubt," with which modern philosophy
began, is not of this kind, but is rather the
kind of criticism which we are asserting to be
"
the essence of philosophy. His methodical
"
doubt consisted in doubting whatever
seemed doubtful ; in pausing, with each ap-
"
was called the mathematical principles of
natural philosophy." Similarly, the study of
the human mind, which was, until very lately,
a part of philosophy, has now been separated
from philosophy and has become the science
of psychology. Thus, to a great extent, the
uncertainty of philosophy is more apparent
than real those questions which are already
:
to continue
part of the business of philosophy
the consideration of such questions, to make us
aware of their importance, to examine all the
approaches to them, and to keep alive that
speculative interest in the universe
which is
242 THE PROBLEMS OF PHILOSOPHY
apt to be killed by confining ourselves to
definitely ascertainable knowledge.
Many philosophers, it is true, have held that
philosophy could establish the truth of certain
answers to such fundamental questions. They
have supposed that what is of most importance
in religious beliefs could be proved by strict
ledge
— knowledge
as impersonal, as purely
as it is possible for man to
contemplative,
attain. Hence also the free intellect will value
more the abstract and universal knowledge
into which the accidents of private history do
not enter, than the knowledge brought by the
senses, and dependent, as such knowledge
must be,upon an exclusive and personal point
of view and a body whose sense-organs distort
as much as they reveal.
The mind which has become accustomed to
the freedom and impartiality of philosophic
contemplation will preserve something of the
same freedom and impartiality in the world of
action and emotion. It will view its purposes
THE VALUE OF PHILOSOPHY 249
Plato Republic,
:
especially Books VI and VTI. Trans-
lated by Davies and Vauqhan. Golden Treasury
Series.
Descartes : Meditations. Translated by Haldane and
Ross. Cambridge University Press, 1911.
Spinoza : Ethics. Translated by Hale White and
Amelia Stirling.
Leibniz The Monadology.
: Translated by R. Latta.
Oxford, 1898.
Berkeley Three Dialogues between Hylas and Philonous.
:
Hume :
Enquiry concerning Human Understanding.
Kant :
Prolegomena to every Future Metaphysic.
/
251
INDEX
The interrogations indicate places wliere a view is
discussed, not asserted.
by acquaintance and by
Objectof apprehension, 65-'/
description, 70, 72-92, of judgment, 197
170
definition of, 204 fT.
Particular, 145
derivative, 171, 207-9
235 Perception, 177-9, 214
indubitable ? 8,
Phenomena, 134
intuitive, 171, 174-85,
Philosophy, value of, 237-50
210 ff, 232
uncertainty of, 239-44
of futme, 94 ff.
Physical objects, 18, 30 ff.,
of general principles, 53,81, 132, 170
109-26, 131 68
Plato, 142 ff.
of things and of truths,
Principles, general, 109-26
69, 72, 170, 225 i Probable opinion, 217
of universe, 40, 2''0, 241
Probability,96, 102,105, 114
only of mental things ? I
I
Proper names, 84 ff., 145
64 ff.
Propositions, constituents
theory of, "0 of, 90
philosophical, 233, 239
Qualities, 149, 159
Laws, general, 104, 115
Leibniz, 22, 24, 50, 114, 148 Rationalists, 114, 134
INDEX 255
Cloth bound, good paper, clear type, 256 pages, per vol-
ume, bibliographies, indices, also maps or illustrations
where needed. Each complete CA ,r»£3.-r«^ci
and sold separately. Per volume. *^^ CdlLS.
59. DR. JOHNSON AND HIS CIRCLE. By John Bailey. Johnson's life,
authority.
SOCIAL SCIENCE.