0% found this document useful (0 votes)
20 views32 pages

Chapter 5 Utility Function

The document discusses utility theory, which allows individuals to incorporate risk preferences into decision making. It introduces the concept of a utility function, which assigns a numerical value to outcomes based on an individual's preferences. This accounts for the fact that additional utility decreases as wealth increases. Von Neumann-Morgenstern axioms are presented to define a rational utility function. A risk-averse individual has a concave utility function, while a risk-seeking individual has a convex utility function. The shape of the utility function determines the individual's attitude toward risk.

Uploaded by

Nermine Limeme
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
20 views32 pages

Chapter 5 Utility Function

The document discusses utility theory, which allows individuals to incorporate risk preferences into decision making. It introduces the concept of a utility function, which assigns a numerical value to outcomes based on an individual's preferences. This accounts for the fact that additional utility decreases as wealth increases. Von Neumann-Morgenstern axioms are presented to define a rational utility function. A risk-averse individual has a concave utility function, while a risk-seeking individual has a convex utility function. The shape of the utility function determines the individual's attitude toward risk.

Uploaded by

Nermine Limeme
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 32

Decision & Game Theory

Chapter 5: Utility Functions

Sonia REBAI
Tunis Business School
University of Tunis
Introduction
²The expected value criterion offers an advantage of simplicity by
summarizing all the available information on a one score.

²However, this advantage represents as well his main weakness. In fact, by


summarizing the information, the criterion loses much of it, which can
make its application dangerous.

²The paradox of St. Petersbug, analyzed in the 18th century by Niclas


Bernoulli, displays this phenomenon.
² Consider the following game: Toss repeatedly a fair coin and obtain a profit
2n if head appears on the nth trial. As soon as head appears, the game is
completed. How much are you willing to pay for this game?
² Based on expected value criterion, to access the game we need to pay an
amount equal to the expectation of winning. The expected payoff of the
game is k
k =¥
kæ 1 ö
VE = å 2 ç ÷ = 1+1+! = ¥
k =1 è2ø

² Even if the expected payoff is infinite, still many people would not pay more
than few amount of money.
0

Not 1/2 2
TH 1/22 22
.
.
∞ .
T……TH 1/2n
play 2n
.
.
.
1/2∞
2∞
² The EV criterion is not adequate to approach such situations.

² In addition, several real situations require the consideration of intangible


factors that are difficult to express by a simple measure of the EV.

² Suppose you have a choice between the following two options:

§ Toss a coin and win 1000 TD if head and zero if tail

§ or accept the sum of 600 TD.


1
0.75

0.5

0.25

0
X* X0.75 X0.5 X0
X0.25 0.5
X0.5
X0.25 ⋍
0.5 X0

U(X0.75)= 0.5U(X*)+0.5U(X0.5) =0.5 +0.5*0.5


² We are interested in a measure that takes into consideration any
qualitative or quantitative objective .
² We need to use a new measure taking into account the risk factor and
reflecting the preferences of the DM (his attitude towards risk).
² How can we model a DM’s preferences?
² We introduce in the following an approach called utility theory that
allows us to incorporate the riskiness of an alternative when deciding on
the best course of action.
² The theory of utility allows individuals to have different attitudes towards
money and against hazards.
² Also, it takes into consideration the fact that the utility of any additional
monetary unit decreases with the increase of capital.

² The utility function is an ordinal concept (as opposed to a cardinal


concept).

² It permits to assign a value to each choice according to the preferences


of the decision maker.

² Such a measure must satisfy a number of axioms of rationality


Von Neumann-Morgestern axioms
Notations & Terminology

²A lottery L is any uncertain event having random outcomes.

²Consider two lotteries L and L’, then

§ L is more preferred than L’ is denoted by: L ! L’

§ L is less preferred to L’ is denoted by L ≺ L’

§ L is equally preferred to L’ is denoted by L » L’


Von Neumann and Morgenstern (1944) were the first to establish
the axiomatic theory of the rule of expected utility.

Total Ordering Axiom

Consider two lotteries L and L’, then exactly one of the following
types of preferences must hold:

L ! L’, L’ !"L, or L » L’

Transitivity Axiom

For all lotteries L, L’, L”, If L≻L' and L'≻L'' Then L≻L''
Independence Axiom

For all lotteries L, L’, and L’’, for all p Î [0,1], we have that

L ≻ L' ⇔ pL +(1− p)L'' ≻ pL' +(1− p)L''

Continuity Axiom
For all lotteries L, L’, and L’’
If L ≻ L' ≻ L'' ⇒ there is p ∈ [0,1] such that
L' = pL + (1− p)L''
An agent accepting all four axioms above is called Von Neumann-
Morgestern rational or just VNM-rational.
Von Neumann-Morgenstern Theorem

There exists a utility function U so that for any lotteries L and L’ such that
L ≻ L' if and only if U(L) ≥ U(L') (1)

How to develop a utility function?

²Set the utility of the best outcome (denoted by x*) to be 1 and that of

the worst (denoted by x0) to be 0.

U(x*) =1 and U(x0) =0


²Let x be an intermediate outcome and let p a probability in [0,1]. Then,
ask the DM whether he prefers x with certainty or the lottery, L, leading
to x* with probability p and x0 with probability 1-p.
²By trial & error find p so that the DM becomes indifferent between both
lotteries.
²Set U(x) = p. x is called the certainty equivalent of the lottery L, denoted
by CE(L).
²Take other intermediate values of x and find their corresponding p.
²Fit the curve (x, u(x)).
²It is important to note that x is not necessarily a monetary value. It can
even be a qualitative attribute.

An alternative approach: Keeney & Raiffa 5-points procedure.

²It is often difficult for DM to manipulate probabilities. However, they feel


more comfortable playing with 50-50 lotteries.

²With this approach, we proceed as follows:

§ U(x*) = 1 and U(x0) = 0.


§ Then, the DM is asked to determine CE(L), where L(x*, 0.5; x0, 0.5),
denoted x0.5. It is obvious that U(x0.5)= 0.5.

§ Next, find the CE of the lottery L(x*, 0.5; x0.5 , 0.5) denoted x0.75, with
U(x0.75) = 0.75.

§ Next, find the CE of the lottery (x0.5, 0.5; x0, 0.5) denoted x0.25, with
U(x0.25) = 0.25.

§ Fit the curve passing through (x*,1); (x0.75,0.75); (x0.5,0.5); (x0.25,0.25); and
(x0,0).
DM attitudes toward risk

²A DM is averse to risk if for any lottery L, the certainty equivalent of L is

worst than the expected value of the lottery L. In profit case, we have

E(L) > CE(L)

§ The difference RP(L) = E(L)-CE(L) > 0 is called the risk premium of L.

§ RP(L) is the amount of money the DM is willing to pay to avoid risk.


²A DM is risk-neutral if for any lottery L, the certainty equivalent

of L is equal to the expected value of L

E(L) = CE(L)

§ Therefore, the risk premium is zero

RP(L) = E(L)-CE(L) = 0
²A DM is prone to risk, risk seeker, or risk taker if for any lottery L,

the certainty equivalent of L is better than the expected value of

the lottery L. In profit case we have E(L) < CE(L)

§ The risk premium of L, RP(L)=E(L)-CE(L) < 0

§ RP(L) is the amount of money the DM is willing to receive in

addition to the expected value of the lottery to give up risk.


Profit case
Convexity/Concavity and Attitude toward risk

²A function f(x) is said to be convex if

" x, y; "α Î [0, 1]; f(αx+(1-α)y) ≤ αf(x)+(1-α)f(y)

²If f is differentiable, then f is convex if its derivative is an increasing


function

²If f is twice differentiable, then it is convex if its second derivative is


non-negative: f”(x)≥0.
Convex Function
²A function f(x) is said to be concave if –f is convex.

"x, y,"αÎ [0,1], f(αx+(1-α)y) ≥ αf(x)+(1-α)f(y)

²If f is differentiable, then f is concave if its derivative is a decreasing


function

²If f is twice differentiable, then it is concave if its second derivative is


non-positive: f”(x)≤0.
Concave Function
Interpretation

²Let the lottery L have values x with probability p and y with probability 1-p.

²If the DM is neutral to risk, he would accept the expected value criterion.

²Therefore, he will be indifferent between the average z with certainty and

the risky lottery L. (z = E(L) = (px+(1-p)y))

²That is, u(z)=u(px+(1-p)y) = u(E(L)) = E(u(L)).


Cost case
That is,
u(E(L))=u(px+(1-p)y) = E(u(L))
U(x)

U(z)= U(E(L))
= pU(x)+(1-p)U(y)

U(y)

x z y
²If the DM is risk-averse, then the
certain situation, z, is preferred to
U(x)
the lottery L
U(z)
U(L)=
pU(x)+(1-p)U(y) ²z=px+(1- p)y
U(y)
²U(z)=U(E(L))≥E(U(L)).
x Z y

²The utility function is concave


²If the DM is risk-seeker, the
U(x)
lottery L is preferred to the
U(L)=
pU(x)+(1-p)U(y)
certain situation z (px+(1-p)y)
U(z)
²U(z) = U(E(L))≤E(U(L))
U(y)
²The utility function is convex
x z y
Theorem

² A DM is risk-averse if and only if his utility function is concave.

² A DM is risk-neutral if and only if his utility function is linear.

² A DM is risk-seeker if and only if his utility function is a convex


function
U(M) U(M) U(M)

M M M
Risk Averse Risk prone Risk Neutral

²The higher the curvature the more averse or seeker the DM.
²The same DM may have different risk attitudes based on the
problem situation or the values considered.
Example
An individual owns a house with a value of 150,000 TND. The risk to lose his

house from fire or other catastrophic event is 0.1% each year. His utility

function for the house is of the form:

U (x) = ax + b

How much he is willing to pay for an insurance company to preserve the value

of his asset? What is the corresponding risk premium?


Solution
Let u be the utility function of the loss of the asset of the DM, where u(0)
=1 and u(150,000)=0. Then, b=1 and a=-1/150,000. That is,

1
u(x)= − x +1
150,000

Consider now the lottery L: [(0; 0.999), (150,000; 0.001)]. Then, E(u(L))=
0.999.
Let us find x, such that U(x) = 0.999; or the certainty equivalent of L, CE(L).

Then solving
1
0.999 = − x +1
150,000

yields x = 299.850 = 300 TND

The risk premium RP(L) = 300 -150,000*0.001 = 150 TD


That is the DM is willing to pay 150 TD to avoid losing his asset.

You might also like