1 William James, The Principles of Psychology and Experimental Psychology
1 William James, The Principles of Psychology and Experimental Psychology
1 William James, The Principles of Psychology and Experimental Psychology
Source: The American Journal of Psychology, Vol. 103, No. 4 (Winter, 1990), pp.
433-447
Published by: University of Illinois Press
REFERENCES
Linked references are available on JSTOR for this article:
http://www.jstor.org/stable/14233177?seq=1&cid=pdf-reference#references_tab_
contents
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions
of Use, available at http://www jstor.org/page/
info/about/policies/terms jsp
http://www jstor.org
This content downloaded from 132.174.255.116 on Fri, 23 Oct 2015 12:30:31 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
AMERICAN SCIENCE SERIES--ADVANCED COURSE
THE PRINCIPLES
OF
PSYCHOLOGY
BY
WILLIAM JAMES
PROFESSOR OF PSYCHOLOGY IN HARVARD UNIVERSITY
IN TWO VOLUMES
VOL. 1
NEW YORK
HENRY HOLT AND COMPANY
This content downloaded from 132.174.255.116 on Fri, 23 Oct 2015 12:30:31 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
William James, The Principles of
Psychology, and experimental
psychology
RAND B. EVANS
East Carolina University
So much has been published about James and his Principles in recent
years and so much more will emerge from the numerous symposia
and memorial publications to mark the centennial, that it is difficult
to find a topic not already worn thin by much handling. A significant
area that still requires explication, however, is James's relationship to
experimental psychology.
Yet, as early as 1895, when James was at the height of his psycho-
logical activity—the period of the Principles and its abbreviated ver-
sion, the Briefer Course (James, 1892)— James was accused of being
an “armchair” psychologist, the ultimate deprecatory label for a non-
experimental, philosophical psychologist of the “old school” (Hall,
1895). Then we also have James's own writings, in the Principles and
elsewhere, in which he criticizes and even denigrates the experimental
endeavor. The present article explores some of these issues to deter-
mine whether a clearer picture of James's attitude toward the ex-
perimental psychology of his day can be ascertained and how James
relates to the experimental tradition.
This content downloaded from 132.174.255.116 on Fri, 23 Oct 2015 12:30:31 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
434 EVANS
This method taxes patience to the utmost and could hardly have arisen
in a country whose natives could be bored. Such Germans as Weber,
Fechner, Vierordt, and Wundt obviously cannot; and their success has
This content downloaded from 132.174.255.116 on Fri, 23 Oct 2015 12:30:31 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
JAMES AND EXPERIMENTAL PSYCHOLOGY 435
James took his position in the Principles not with experimental psy-
chology but with what he called “introspective observation.” That
term should not be confused with the analytical introspection used
by Wilhelm Wundt and particularly developed later by E. B. Titchener.
James meant by introspective observation, “the looking into our own
minds and reporting what we there discover” (James, 1890, 1:185).
What James found there, of course, were states of consciousness. His
was a phenomenological description rather than an analytical descrip-
tion as was used by Wundt and Titchener. James's notions of psycho-
logical description were based on the fundamental precept that “all
people unhesitatingly believe that they feel themselves thinking, and
that they distinguish the mental state as an inward activity or passion”
(James, 1890, 1:185).
This content downloaded from 132.174.255.116 on Fri, 23 Oct 2015 12:30:31 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
436 EVANS
This led to an angry response from James and a demand for Hall’s
public recognition of the precedence of James's early laboratory at
Harvard and of his own lectures at Johns Hopkins on experimental
psychology as marking the beginning of an epoch (James, 1895). Still,
it is clear that the rise of experimental psychology moved the field
away from the path James would like to have seen it take.
This is the same William James who champed at the bit in the 1870s
This content downloaded from 132.174.255.116 on Fri, 23 Oct 2015 12:30:31 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
JAMES AND EXPERIMENTAL PSYCHOLOGY 437
One reason given for James's inability to spend the long hours
required for laboratory work was his health (Perry, 1935, 2:24).
Whether his health problems were real or imagined, it is clear by
looking through James’s life that he went through periods when he
had little physical stamina (see Evans, 1990; Feinstein, 1984; H. James,
1920; Perry, 1935).
James’s early education had contained very little science and little
if any experimental chemistry. Charles Eliot, later president of Har-
vard but in the early 1860s James’s chemistry professor, noted that
James’s educational preparation “did not conform to the Boston and
Cambridge traditional method.” What little science James had was
largely biological and ““in a large proportion observational” (Perry,
1935, 1:207).
This content downloaded from 132.174.255.116 on Fri, 23 Oct 2015 12:30:31 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
438 EVANS
James found, at last, that his ardor for the field of experimental
chemistry had “somewhat dulled” (H. James, 1920, 1:43). It may be
that James's later praise for the ‘generally understandable” chemistry
of Lavoisier derived from his negative experience with experimental
chemistry.
It seems to me that perhaps the time has come for psychology to begin
to be a science—some measurements have already been made in the
region lying between the physical changes in the nerves and the ap-
pearance of consciousness-at (in the shape of sense perceptions), and
more may come of it. I am going on to study what is already known,
and perhaps may be able to do some work at it. Helmholtz and a2 man
named Wundt at Heidelberg are working at it, and I hope I live through
this winter to go to them in the summer. (H. James, 1920, 1:118-119)
This content downloaded from 132.174.255.116 on Fri, 23 Oct 2015 12:30:31 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
JAMES AND EXPERIMENTAL PSYCHOLOGY 439
James had high praise for the scientific work he saw in Berlin: “The
general level of thoroughness and exactness in scientific work here is
beyond praise.” James wrote to Henry Bowditch that “it seems to me
that the fact of so many American students being here of late
years . . . ought to have a good influence on the training of the suc-
ceeding generation with us” (H. James, 1920, 1:121). Although James
found the opportunities for study in Berlin “superb,” he was, himself,
unable to work in the laboratories because of his lack of energy. He
was able to go to Heidelberg in the spring and appears to have
attended some lectures given by Helmholtz. Most of the time that he
was supposed to have been studying physiology, however, he spent
convalescing at a spa. He apparently never did any of the laboratory
work available for him, although he expressed great admiration for
the laboratories at Berlin: “The physiological laboratory, with its end-
less array of machinery, frogs, dogs, etc., etc., almost ‘burst my gizzard,
when I go by it, with vexation” (H. James, 1920, 1:121).
This content downloaded from 132.174.255.116 on Fri, 23 Oct 2015 12:30:31 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
440 EVANS
James did conduct some experiments. His primary work was done
on dizziness in which he used not only questionnaires collected from
physicians and other medical workers, but also the examination of
nearly 200 Harvard students and faculty (James, 1880, 1881, 1882;
Perry, 1935, 2:23). It does not appear to have been a satisfying pursuit.
Another reason that James may have been led to reject experimental
psychology had to do with his conception of the relationship between
experimentation and elementism. He noted this relationship as early
as 1873 when he wrote, “For the empiricist the only order which has
any objective existence is the elementary order—the dynamic laws
by which elements and their properties are associated” (Perry, 1935,
1:497). Much later, James would define empiricism as “the tendency
which lays most stress on the part, the element, the individual, treats
the whole as a collection, and calls the universal an abstraction” (Perry,
1935, 2:380).
This content downloaded from 132.174.255.116 on Fri, 23 Oct 2015 12:30:31 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
JAMES AND EXPERIMENTAL PSYCHOLOGY 441
The problem James had with most laboratory research was that
when the experimenter manipulated some variables while holding
others constant, there was the general assumption that the phenom-
enon under study was made up of component parts. Analysis pre-
supposes wholes made up of parts. Thus Wundt and Titchener could
easily experiment with sensations using their analytical introspection,
perhaps manipulating qualities of the sensation while holding intensity
constant and vice versa. James could not do the same within the
context of his stream-of-thought metaphor. Cutting a cross section of
the stream and determining the constituents of the stream at that
instant, which is what the elementists were doing, did not relate to
the ongoing processes of the thoughts that make up the stream.
This content downloaded from 132.174.255.116 on Fri, 23 Oct 2015 12:30:31 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
442 EVANS
Why did James not do research using the models available to him?
Perhaps, in the end, James’s avoidance of experimentation came down
to the simple matter that James was interested in mental life in its
broad strokes, in its great significances, but found the details tedious.
Problems dealing with more specific subjects, such as the ease of
remembering differing stimulus types or studies of the perception of
octaves, were not the sort that could hold the attention of someone
like William James. With his leanings and interests, it is doubtful that
James would have been involved in psychological research even if an
experimental methodology congenial to his holistic and functional
notions had been dominant in his time. He was, at heart, a philosopher,
not an experimental scientist. James admitted to his confidant, Stumpf:
This content downloaded from 132.174.255.116 on Fri, 23 Oct 2015 12:30:31 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
JAMES AND EXPERIMENTAL PSYCHOLOGY 443
This content downloaded from 132.174.255.116 on Fri, 23 Oct 2015 12:30:31 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
444 EVANS
This content downloaded from 132.174.255.116 on Fri, 23 Oct 2015 12:30:31 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
JAMES AND EXPERIMENTAL PSYCHOLOGY 445
spectable lineage of the older and becomes a sorting out and confir-
mation of the older. Where the newer finds the older in error, there
is status gained by disproving the great authority of the past, thus
taking on some of the luster of the older without really diminishing
the older’s authority. James has served this purpose for generations
of experimental psychologists, as has Ebbinghaus. The profusion of
ideas in James’s Principles has been the source of many research ideas
using experimental methods. Thus, a wealth of experimental research
was stimulated by James’s interesting observations and his often ten-
uous explanations. How many experimental research lines can be
traced directly or indirectly to some flash of insight or speculation in
one of James's writings? James believed that these uneven trails, these
loose ends, this “unfinished-seeming front” was the “best mark of
health that a science can show” (James, 1890, I:vii).
This content downloaded from 132.174.255.116 on Fri, 23 Oct 2015 12:30:31 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
446 EVANS
Notes
2. Cattell also mentioned G. Stanley Hall, but pointed out that Hall was
still a student in Germany.
References
Beecher, H. K., & Altschule, M. (1967). Medicine at Harvard: The first three
hundred years. Hanover, NH: University Press of New England.
James, H. (1920). The letiers of William James (2 vols.). Boston: Atlantic Monthly
Press.
This content downloaded from 132.174.255.116 on Fri, 23 Oct 2015 12:30:31 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
JAMES AND EXPERIMENTAL PSYCHOLOGY 447
James, W. (1890). The principles of psychology (Harvard ed., 2 vols.). New York:
Holt.
James, W. (1895). Letter to G. S. Hall, Oct. 12, 1895. Hall Papers, Clark
University Archives, Worcester, MA.
Perry, R. B. (1935). The thought and character of William James (2 vols.). Boston:
Little, Brown.
Taylor, E. (in press). New light on the origin of William James’s experimental
psychology. In M. G. Johnson & T. B. Henley (Eds.), William James: The
Principles at 100. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
This content downloaded from 132.174.255.116 on Fri, 23 Oct 2015 12:30:31 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions