Plato's Republic

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 12

Plato

The Republic
By Nickolas Pappas, City College of New York
___________________________________________________________________________

Learning objectives
1. To gain a sense of how the disparate parts of the Republic constitute an argument.
2. To grasp how the overall argument answers the threat of immorality or nihilism.
3. To appreciate the Republic as a portrayal of philosophy, as philosophy seeks to inform
governance, and as it differs from general rationality.
4. To understand the parallel approaches to justice in the Republic, as a characteristic of
constitutions and as a virtue grounded in a person’s psychic balance.
5. To attain an overview of Platonic metaphysics and the dualism of ‘Plato’s two worlds.’

Commentary

Introduction
Philosophy, famously impractical, brought to the cynical practicalities of politics: Plato’s Republic
assigns itself this task in a bid to reimagine philosophy so that it engages with politics, and also to
reimagine politics in a way that opens it to such engagement.
The dialogue’s ambition, together with its capacious inclusivity of topics, have made it
always one of Plato’s central works. (Books on the Republic include Annas 1981, Blackburn 2006,
Brown 2017, Cross and Woozley 1964, Ferrari 2007, McPherran 2010a, Reeve 1988, Santas 2006,
2010.)
As most Platonic works do the Republic takes the form of a conversation (Hyland 1968,
Patterson 1982). Socrates dominates. But readers should distinguish this character from the
historical figure who lived in ancient Athens (Kahn 1981). There was such a person, from all the
evidence a provocative thinker and personally an eccentric, who cross-examined expertly, focusing
on what words meant (Benson 1992, Vlastos 1991). Did he teach, though? – and what, and to
whom? The consensus is that he offered no lessons, although he set an example that inspired others
to philosophize (Blank 1985, Nehamas 1992). He showed little interest in theories about nature, but
as the sophists did he addressed matters of politics and value.
Unlike Socrates, the sophists offered formal instruction. They taught many subjects, but
came to be identified with persuasive speaking. Sometimes mistaken for a sophist, Socrates
investigated questions of value as if they had answers. He asked about courage, friendship, and
justice, trusting that inquiry could lead to precise accounts. The sophists hid in thickets of ambiguous
language; Socrates cleared thickets away.
A jury sentenced Socrates to death in 399 BCE, partly because he had made enemies by
interrogating prominent Athenians, but mainly because he was suspected of having undermined
democracy. Some of his associates aided Sparta, enemy of Athens, during the war between the
cities. Others overthrew the democracy and ruled in a Spartan puppet regime. It did not help that
Socrates sympathized with Sparta and challenged the wisdom of collective decision-making.
Plato was young when he met Socrates, probably through relatives who had conspired
against democracy. Plato kept himself aloof from politics, in this respect emulating Socrates, who
despite his sympathies remained uninvolved with public life. Probably after Socrates’ death, Plato
joined the numerous associates who had written dialogues portraying Socratic conversations (Boys-
Stones and Rowe 2013). Some scholars believe that the short, inconclusive pieces he wrote –

Information Classification: General


Euthyphro, Laches, and others – depict a Socrates like the one who really lived, whereas longer
works ascribe theories to him unknown to the historical figure; but such hypotheses are risky.
Regarding politics, the Republic’s ‘Socrates’ voices suspicions about democracy that
harmonize with what we think the real Socrates said. Moreover the historical Socrates’ proposal that
one follow an expert, where experts are available, appears in the Republic’s plan for a
knowledgeable ruling class. Yet even here a difference appears between Plato’s character and
Plato’s friend. Faced with the divide between philosophy and politics, Socrates declined political
involvement in favour of free private thinking. The Republic pictures him questioning that divide.
Must one live either politically or ethically, or might there be an ethical polity?

Outline of the Republic


The Republic is accessible even for those new to philosophy. It does cover many topics, but it
possesses a clear structure (Barney 2010). First, Books 1 and 10 (following an ancient division,
though not Plato’s own) should be set aside as ancillary to the main argument. The remainder is
guided by an analogy: The virtue called justice in a human soul resembles the desirable constitutional
trait known as justice in a state, and is to be preferred over injustice in either city or state (Blössner
2007, Cooper 1977, Ferrari 2005, Neu 1971). Books 2-9 devote themselves to explicating and
justifying this claim, digressing from the main argument to support claims about psychology,
education, poetry and the arts, feminism, and ontology. The overall argument goes:
➢ Justice in soul and city. Books 2-3-4.
o Digression to the distinctly political appearance of justice. Books 5-6-7.
▪ Digression from the digression. Forms and the Form of the Good.
➢ Injustice in soul and city, always worse than justice. Books 8-9.
The linked ethical and political inquiries are introduced by a gripping but inconclusive opening
discussion that seeks to define justice in traditional fashion. Book 10 then returns first to the topic of
poetry and art and subsequently to the life after death that souls experience.
Along the way, the Republic discusses education twice, and speaks twice of poetry and art.
These repetitions obscure the argumentative structure but are not gratuitous. Education comes up
twice because Socrates twice defines the city’s governing class, describing first the military and then
a cadre within that military, and both definitions imply contradictions. To prevent possible
contradictions from undermining the political theory, Socrates details what the ‘guardians’ will learn
and how. The tensions reveal something essential about philosophers, thus both illuminating and
threatening the Republic’s ‘philosophicalization’ of politics.
Poetry and art meanwhile come up initially in the context of the first passage on pedagogy,
which examines poetry from a ruler’s perspective – politically – then again when the Republic
grounds those earlier criticisms in a theory of the soul’s inner order: psychologically.

What is justice? Book 1


Of Book 1, as of many sections of the Republic, you may say that it contributes to the whole but also
exceeds the demands of its contributory function.
Book 1 stands apart stylistically from what follows (Kahn 1993, Lycos 1987, Sesonske 1961).
Many Platonic dialogues establish scene and character in detail. In others the characters are mere
names, the setting rudimentary. The Republic takes both approaches. Whereas Books 2-10 mainly
contain the first-person voice of Socrates detailing arguments with complaisant replies from Glaucon
and Adeimantus, Book 1 spells out where the conversation is taking place, and when, and in what
company. It resembles those short dialogues that end in confusion.
Polemarchus, his father Cephalus, and the rhetorician Thrasymachus seek to explain
dikaiosunê ‘justice,’ the virtue pertaining to interactions among people. After some exploratory
definitions (Joseph 1966), Thrasymachus declares that justice, ‘the advantage of the stronger,’ never
benefits the just (338c). At worst, moral language is hijacked by those in power to extol the

Information Classification: General


behaviour that benefits them (338d-339a). Or else ‘justice’ describes something real, but the
behaviour it prescribes is unprofitable (343c-344c).
Socrates silences Thrasymachus by seizing on inconsistencies in his overstated claims. Then
he introduces ‘soul’ in a defence of justice as soul’s well-being (352d-354a). But Thrasymachus’s
attack lingers. Why obey moral precepts when they bring no benefit (Barney 2006, Boter 1986,
Gotoff 1980, Reeve 1985, Sparshott 1966)?

Justice in city and soul: Books 2-4


The Republic follows Book 1 with a systematic introduction to the questions it will address and the
terms in which it will answer them (Ferrari 2010, Weiss 2007).
This reiteration exemplifies a presentational strategy of this dialogue. A point is made, then
argued for or illustrated a second time. Often Glaucon hears the abstruse idea and Adeimantus has it
spelled out to him; but the reiteration takes other forms too.
As Book 2 begins, Glaucon and Adeimantus urge Socrates to produce a better defence for
justice. He silenced an immoralist without refuting immoralism (358b). But people resent the
demands of justice. Human beings worked out rules of society in order to live together, so those
rules have force only insofar as people enforce them (358e-359b). Anyone freed from social
sanctions by magical invisibility would commit atrocities (359c-360c). An unjust person with a
reputation for justice would be as happy as a just person believed to be unjust is miserable (360c-
362c). Therefore, even when they praise justice, people do so cynically, with an eye to social
consequences distinct from the virtue itself (362e-363a). Virtue needs a defence that shows justice
in the soul (see Psychê) conferring benefits on the just (366e; Lycos 1987).
Socrates announces his analogy. Because both cities and souls can possess justice, the city’s
may be thought of as a soul-justice more easily analysed. They should look at elements of a city’s
constitution and ascertain how those elements reveal the justice or injustice in that city. If the soul
contains comparable elements, we can define its justice (368c-369a). Not incidentally, the analogy
lets philosophy address questions considered unphilosophical. The city, ostensibly mere picture of
the soul, becomes the dialogue’s main subject. The manifestly philosophical task of understanding
soul permits philosophizing about politics.
Socrates sketches a simple community, based on axioms that will guide later steps in the
argument. A1. In every society, a plurality joins together (369b). A2. Social organization entails the
coordination of specialized activities (370a). No need for social contracts where natural forces
organize society.
A1 and A2 identify the unity and division of labour found in all societies. Socrates will justify
aspects of his political proposals that we call communistic by saying they foster unity (462a-b). He
defends the segmentation of the population as division of labour (434a-b). The Republic’s definition
of city-justice combines the axioms when it describes a city unified in its acceptance of its class
differences (433a-b).
First, anyway, Socrates conceives a town that provides sustainable happiness (370c-371e).
Glaucon prefers something resembling the Athens he knows (372c-d), so Socrates steers away from
utopia to ask how one might begin with a complex city and create the conditions for justice there
(372e-373c). Philosophy remains among practicalities. Interpreters who take Plato to demean the
inquiry into the unhealthy city miss this point. The great accomplishment for philosophy is to change
the existing world, not to dream up a different one (Bobonich 2002, Klosko 1981, Lane 1999).
Thus, for one thing, complex societies will experience wars. Appealing to A2, Socrates
proposes a standing army, the city’s phulakes ‘guards’ or ‘guardians’ (374b-e). (One translation
emphasizes that this class watches the population, the other that it watches over them.) The
phulakes function as combined military and police, being therefore ferocious in battle but gentle at
home (375b-c) – a contradiction, unless they are trained right (376c-e). Hence the first account of
education.

Information Classification: General


The army’s schooling draws on tradition in that it incorporates poetry, music (Fitzpatrick
2021, Schofield 2010), and physical exercise, but each of these will need to be transformed, poetry
especially (Belfiore 1985, Havelock 1966, Partee 1970). Homer and the tragedians slander gods and
heroes (377d). The city will banish all stories from mythology that represent divinities as deceitful,
lustful, or otherwise lacking virtue (377e-383c), and stories about unvirtuous heroes (386a-391e).
The very form of much poetry is dangerous, when it is performed with any enactment of
characters (393b-d). Playing someone temperate would be all right; more often performers emulate
cowardice or uncontrolled desire (395c-396e). The city ought to shield its fighters from the
corrupting effect of such playacting.
The Republic’s insistence on special training seeks to reconcile natural differences in
strength and aggressivity with the demands of civilized society. It may ameliorate the impression of a
caste structure (Annas 1981). Plato does assume that the gifted will largely be found among children
of the gifted (415b). But the pains taken to redesign the culture one grows up in ought to indicate
how much more than innate traits go into making a ruler. To the same point the Republic compares
its guardians to dogs (e.g. 495a-b), conjuring up the effect of domestication.

City and soul as articulated wholes


Socrates complicates the class organization he proposed and uses it to define the constitution’s
justice. He discerns motives that work within an individual as the city’s classes work in the society.
On the political side of the argument, one detail stands out: Socrates divides the guardians
into the army and its commanders, who govern the entire city (413c-414b). These rulers form a
separate group. The argument’s focus shifts so decisively to this cadre that Socrates designates them
the true guardians, the army now ‘auxiliaries.’
A proposal about enacting the new city also stands out: the ‘noble lie’ (414d-e). Citizens will
be taught that the founding generation gestated underground and contained metals of different
values – gold, silver, bronze, iron – which the founders of the new order used in sorting this
generation into classes (Lear 2006). Whatever crisis in fact goes into transforming an existing city
into the new one is veiled behind this lie, because of which all history before the revolution
disappears, together with any suspicion that government is an artifice (Pappas 2021).
The class structure lets the Republic define a state’s virtues in terms of citizens’ virtues. The
city enacts its courage in battle, hence by possessing a brave army. Wise rulers make it a wise city
(see Wisdom). Less specifically, moderation (sôphrosunê) too is defined with reference to class
membership (428a-432a).
These subsidiary virtues have justice as their common feature. Each class performs its
function, and justice means ‘doing one’s own thing,’ inasmuch as your civic business is what your
class determines it to be (433a-b). Justice combines the axioms describing human society, for this
separate performance of the class function (A2) serves the purpose of the larger entity’s unity (A1).

Psychology
Socrates finds analogues of ruler, army, and productive labourer in the soul, mainly through
examples of inner conflict. The examples reveal two impulses distinguishable from reason: desire
(Lorenz 2006), which includes hunger and sexual appetite (437b-e); and ‘spiritedness,’ the thumos
(Brennan 2012), source of non-rational emotions associated with shame and anger (439e-440a).
Advancing beyond dualistic psychodynamics – reason contra unreason – this account distinguishes
an impulsive non-rational element from one susceptible to guidance. Now the drives of appetite can
be contained by the non-rational power of shame and indignation. Justice consists in this internal
harmony, rather than in any particular actions.
Some commentators debate whether Plato can produce a workable theory of soul without
reifying the three motive-types into independent subjects (Bobonich 2002, Price 2009, Shields 2010).
But on any interpretation, the soul contains a governance and hierarchy. In a just soul every motive
stays within its bounds, reason governing (Cooper 1984, Vasiliou 2012).

Information Classification: General


Digression. Political specifics
The Republic will clinch its case by surveying all constitutional forms that differ from the best city,
and all souls other than the just, and showing that each one is worse than the just. Plato defers that
comparison to Book 8, staging an interruption by interlocutors who want to hear more about the
new city – not how the city parallels the soul, but the opposite. What can Socrates say about the city
considered as a city (449c-d)?
Having lost control of the argument (Ferrari 2010), Socrates spells out life under the new
constitution. Women will be equal to men (451d-456a; Bluestone 1987, Santas 2010). The rulers will
arrange ‘marriages,’ now understood as temporary procreative couplings, to breed the best
guardians. Guardian children grow up not knowing whom they are related to (460b-d). The
guardians will live communistically and not even touching money (463c-464d; see 416d-417a).
Sometimes these details are read as generating a new politics different from what preceded; but on
most interpretations they amend and explain the constitution already established.
Pressed to explain how such changes might come about, Socrates reveals his most radical
proposal. Philosophers will govern (473c-d). That specific impossibility lets the hugely impossible city
exist.
Philosopher-kings and –queens embody the Republic’s enterprise of bringing philosophizing
into politics. Immoralists (Thrasymachus) detect only manipulative power in justice. The ‘social
contract’ with which Glaucon explains society comes from jaded sophists, grounding morality in
shrewdness. But where others found self-interest and truthless persuasion, philosophy sees principle
rooted in natural order. If A1 and A2 describe necessary conditions for all societies, all cities should
divide up civic functions and coordinate the classes performing them. And now, with these
philosopher-royals, philosophy can inform day-to-day governance.
For exemplars of reason to rule, reason must be expanded. Thus far in the dialogue it has
been the faculty controlling other motives. Analogously the city’s ruling class oversees what the
other classes do and believe. Now, being philosophers, rulers will additionally want to contemplate
abstract truths. Human reason goes from only guiding other impulses to also following its desire for
knowledge.
In a city premised on the division of labour, the innovation that makes the plan possible
threatens A2. Philosophers live two vocations. This logical pressure on the argument inspires a
second educational theory (489a, 504c-d), seeking to describe philosophical knowledge that is both
the study of being and a moral inquiry guiding the rulers’ judgment (Sedley 2007).
By knowing the Forms, objects of greater reality than those seen, philosophers compare
with non-philosophical people as those awake with dreamers, for they have knowledge not mere
opinion (476c-d, 477a-b; Fine 1993, Silverman 2014). In Plato’s dialogues Socrates typically speaks of
Forms as ideal versions of what is perceived (see Forms, Platonic). They are sometimes versions of
objects (the Form of tree) more often of relational properties (largeness, doubleness), and
paradigmatically evaluative properties (justice and beauty).
Objects of experience hold their properties equivocally, Socrates says now. Beautiful things
contain ugly components, look ugly in other contexts or to other observers, are uglified over time
(479a-c). Thus F things both are and are not F (Malcolm 1991, Nehamas 1979, Rickless 2007). The
Form of F however is F (always, everywhere, throughout) and so is absolutely where perceptible
things somewhat are (Kahn 2009). In a word: A Form bears its property yet is not identical to any
ordinary bearer of that same property.
If Forms do not exist, no properties can be known. The perceived world lacks intelligibility. It
follows that if some intelligible world did exist, one would know more insofar as one inquired into
that world’s elements. One would know things better by knowing better things (Ferejohn 2006).
The educational theory that creates these philosophers comes in Book 7 (521c-541b). It also
includes a sketch of philosophy’s highest goal (505a-520e).

Information Classification: General


Forms and the Good
The simile of the sun, the divided line, and the allegory of the cave illustrate Platonic metaphysics.
The sun (505a-509d) gives a point to the parallel between what can be seen and what can be
thought. The sun causes the existence of visible living things, which we see thanks to light from the
sun. Objects of thought owe their existence to the Good (Form of the Good), but the Good also gives
forth the truth thanks to which as thinking beings we can know those things (Denyer 2007, Santas
1983).
How the Good generates Forms or enables knowledge is unclear. It can’t be a Form of
Forms, because objects are said to ‘share’ in a Form’s property, and although Forms are
characterized as all possessing being, the Good is ‘beyond being’ (509b). Forms can’t get their being
from it.
The divided line (509d-511e) amplifies the comparison between visible and intelligible.
Divide a line unequally. Divide each resultant segment in the same ratio. The first division sets the
intelligible realm apart from the visible. The subdivision within the visible realm distinguishes objects
from shadows and reflections; within the intelligible realm we get Forms and mathematical objects.
The intelligible domain is more real than the visible, as a tree is than its reflection (Benson 2010,
Denyer 2007, Smith 1996).
The less that eyesight is involved in an experience, the better the knowledge. Reflections
and shadows are nothing but appearance; regular objects have an appearance but are more than
that; appearance triggers thoughts of unseen mathematical objects, as when a drawn circle invites
geometers to demonstrate properties of circles (510c-e). Only regarding Forms does one think from
start to finish free from sight. Thus Forms are known with complete understanding, while about
shadows there is nothing to know. Highest of all is again the Good, the progress towards which can
be read as aiming either at axiomatic certainty (what is most true) or definitional clarity (what is best
understood).
The line leaves unsettled the question whether each kind of object determines a distinct
type of cognition. Does what you inquire into establish how well you inquire; or does how one thinks
determine what one thinks about (Silverman 2014)?
The line’s layout of beings maps onto the next image (514a-515c). Picture the sun as Good,
shining on plants and animals (Forms), which are also visible as reflections in still water
(mathematical objects). People live as prisoners chained down inside a cave, seeing only shadows
(empty talk) cast on the cave wall by cutout shapes (physical objects) carried past a fire (sun).
Now picture one prisoner liberated, turned around to see how the cave works, and dragged
to the world outside. One gets accustomed to things’ reflections, then can look at things themselves,
sometimes glimpsing the sun. Upon returning to the cave unimpressed by its shadow plays, the
liberated prisoner describes the world outside the cave, only to be met with jeers and threats (515b-
517a).
Such is life. But whereas those in existing cities who escape cave living refuse to re-engage
with it, the newly constituted city will send its philosophers back underground to rule (519d-520d).
The allegorical escapee’s reluctance to return indicates the conflict within philosophical
rulers (Brown 2000, Mahoney 1992, Smith 2010). One trusts them because they have something
better to do than govern (521a). But how can the philosopher’s training reveal the unity of higher
thought with governance if it produces people who find governing insufficiently philosophical? It is in
such places that ‘philosophy’ appears ambiguous, meaning sometimes sound executive thinking and
sometimes thought about distinct objects. And if the demand that philosophers govern is just
(520e), how can people as splendid as philosophers resent it? Justice, which was to mean happiness
in the soul, evidently feels burdensome even to the just.
Another problem: The prisoners’ jeers imply that the public even under a new regime will
mistrust enlightened rule. This is not the concord promised elsewhere (Kamtekar 2004).
Socrates has steered back to governance. He now details what the new city’s philosophers
will learn (Burnyeat 2000), before returning to the main argument. Mathematics and other

Information Classification: General


theoretical subjects join music and gymnastics, for rather than putting content into the soul
education is now seen as turning the soul’s eye around (518c; Reeve 2010). The stimulation of
thought must not go too far, though. Bright young students exposed early to dialectical
argumentation risk being corrupted by it (537c-539d). Making good rulers takes more delicacy than
training a militia.

Unjust cities and souls


Existing cities prove the desirability of the new order. The constitutions under which people live
contain undesirable qualities, and instabilities that send those constitutions degenerating into worse
ones (Hitz 2010).
Book 8 arranges constitutions in a depressing chronology. Despite its best efforts the
philosophical city will become a Spartan-style military society (547b-c). That degrades into oligarchy
(550d-551b), oligarchy into relativistic democracy (555b-557a). The pursuit of wealth and the
liquidation of real property create economic conditions for these transformations. Then democracy
ends when one figure appeals to the poor for support and establishes tyranny (565d-566d).
Why does the Republic present these transformations as a history (Frede 1996)? The
comparative argument does not require these constitutions to arise consecutively. It does not even
require this ranking. As long as every other constitution can be seen as inferior to the best, they may
be as good as one another and arise in any sequence. The chronological arrangement does however
underscore the need for a well-run city, because every other constitution gets caught up in the laws
of worsening history, and because only the Republic’s city separates power from the wealth that
corrupts every other order.
(As it happens Athenian history had moved oppositely, from tyranny into democracy, which
in Plato’s adolescence became an oligarchy, in his adulthood a junta declaring Spartan ideals. Plato is
not observing history but inverting it.)
The ranking and sequence let the Republic indict democracy. Athens hated tyranny; so does
the Republic; but whereas in Athenian discourse tyranny was cast as opposite to democracy, the
Republic’s history resituates democracy at tyranny’s threshold (Arruzza 2019). At the same time
however democracy contains the makings of the philosophers’ city (557d). It is the crisis-constitution
poised to change to either better or worse.
Souls decline as cities do. A man with an oligarchical soul has a democratically-souled son
(559d-e). His son has a constitution resembling tyranny (572d-573b). Books 8-9 supplement the
psychological theory developed earlier, so that the three parts of the soul generate five types. The
additional complexity derives from the variety in desire. At its most organized, being the desire for
money, it dominates in the oligarch’s thrifty personality. In a democratic soul all desires flower. Then
importunate lust emerges (571c-573a). Sexually deviant, fed by simulacra (586b-c, 587c-d), the soul
putatively driven by pleasure is the unhappiest (Parry 2007), as seen through contrasts between it
and the just soul (580a-587e). Note that the just soul is now understood as the philosopher’s (581b;
Brown 2017, Russell 2007). Again the philosopher’s reason comprises both ordinary reasonableness
and the special pursuit of metaphysics (Nussbaum 1986).

Book 10. Book 10 enlarges and reinforces earlier points, beginning with poetry and painting (595a-
608a; Burnyeat 1999, Halliwell 2002). Continuing the theme of souls that take in likenesses, Socrates
argues that mimetic poetry consists in such likenesses (see Mimêsis).
Poetry that represents human beings resembles painting in presenting appearance without
reality (596e, 600e). Born from ignorance (598d-600c), it is show alone. It evidently appeals to the
worst part of the soul (602c-603b; Moss 2007, Nehamas 1982).
Socrates does not explain why tragedy’s apparitions have a pernicious effect not found in
shadows. Poetry must contain some entrancement (598d, 607c, 608a) that makes its audience
prefer artistic ignorance over philosophical insight. Book 10 explores that charm, diagnosing the
emotional experience of tragedy. Spectators sympathize with the sight of a hero overcome by

Information Classification: General


misery; their capacity for lamentation increases (603d-606c). As Book 3 said, one must ban mimetic
poetry (Pappas 2020).
The Republic has argued that justice is better for the soul throughout life than injustice. It
concludes by extending that assertion beyond life. The soul is immortal (608d-610d) (see Immortality
in ancient philosophy). The myth of Er reveals the rewards and punishments awaiting after death
(Annas 1982), first for a millennium of afterlife, then as souls select the lives they’ll be reincarnated
into (614b-621d).
The myth revisits the ambiguity that reason acquired when rulers became philosophers, and
rationality expanded from executive ordering to contemplation. In the process virtue came to mean
more too. Thus the myth awards a heavenly millennium to any orderly soul that obeys just
principles. When souls select their next lives, those narcotized by heavenly reward will choose
carelessly; they’ll be born fated to vice then punishment (619d-e). In the very long run, just
behaviour does not suffice (McPherran 2010b). Philosophers, being obedient and congenitally
thoughtful, pick good lives every time (618b-c, 619d-e). Philosophical justice prevails.

Questions for review


1. The allegory of the cave tells of hostility exhibited toward the released prisoner who returns
to the cave. Does this imply that human beings will always reject philosophy, even in a well-
run city? What contrary evidence does the Republic provide that the populace might accept
and value governance by philosophers, and how compelling is that evidence?
2. Do the “parts of the soul” that appear in the Republic’s analysis of motivation need to be
distinct entities for Plato’s psychological theory to work? Will they be like little selves inside
the big self? What naturalistic sense can we make of the distinctions that Socrates draws
among human motives, without feeling as though the distinctions generate a mythology of
the human interior?
3. In what respects does Plato undervalue poetry and the arts? In what respects does he over-
value them? How does the Republic’s assessment of literary writing and drama compare
with modern assessments, from the point of view of how much truth a work might contain,
how much knowledge goes into it, how much can be learned by studying it, how strongly it
affects the mind, and how slyly it subverts a culture’s values?
4. According to the Republic, does the level of reality or being of the objects one studies
determine the cognitive level of the thinking one does about such objects? If so, does it
follow that one can never be wrong about the Forms? Does that make it impossible for two
people who think in different ways (one philosophically, one empirically) to look at one
object and understand it differently? But if the objects studied do not determine the level of
thought about those objects, what becomes of the advantage to a city to have its rulers
study philosophy? The subject seems not guaranteed to improve their minds.

Bibliography

Annas, J. 1981. An Introduction to Plato’s Republic. Oxford, Oxford University Press.

Annas, J. 1982. ‘Plato's myths of judgment,’ Phronesis 27: 119-43.

Arruzza, C. 2019. A Wolf in the City: Tyranny and the Tyrant in Plato’s Republic. Oxford, Oxford
University Press.

Barney, R. 2006. ‘Socrates’ Refutation of Thrasymachus,’ in Santas (ed.) Blackwell Guide to Plato’s
Republic, pp. 44-62.

Information Classification: General


Barney, R. 2010. ‘Platonic Ring-Composition and Republic 10,’ in McPherran (ed.) Plato’s Republic,
pp. 32-51.

Belfiore, E. 1985. ‘“Lies Unlike the Truth”: Plato on Hesiod, Theogony 27,’ Transactions of the
American Philological Association 115: 47-57.

Benson, H. H., ed. 1992. Essays on the Philosophy of Socrates. Oxford, Oxford University Press.

Benson, H. H. 2010. ‘Plato’s philosophical method in the Republic: the Divided Line (510b-511d),’ in
McPherran (ed.), Plato’s Republic, pp. 188-208.

Blackburn, S. 2006. Plato’s Republic: A Biography. London, Atlantic Books.

Blank, D. 1985. ‘Socrates vs. Sophists on Payment for Teaching,’ California Studies in Classical
Philology 48: 1-49.

Blössner, N. 2007. ‘The City-Soul Analogy,’ trans. G. Ferrari, in Ferrari (ed.) Cambridge Companion to
Plato’s Republic, pp. 345-85.

Bluestone, N. H. 1987. Women and the Ideal Society: Plato’s Republic and Modern Myths of Gender.
Amherst, University of Massachusetts Press.

Bobonich, C. 2002. Plato’s Utopia Recast. Oxford, Oxford University Press.

Boter, G. J. 1986. ‘Thrasymachus and Pleonexia,’ Mnemosyne 39: 261-81.

Boys-Stones, G. and C. Rowe. 2013. The Circle of Socrates: Readings in the First-Generation Socratics.
Indianapolis, Hackett Publishing Company.

Brennan, T. 2012. ‘The Nature of the Spirited Part of the Soul and its Object,’ in R. Barney, T.
Brennan, and C. Brittain (eds.) Plato and the Divided Self. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press,
pp. 102-127.

Brown, E. 2000. ‘Justice and Compulsion for Plato’s Philosopher-Rulers,’ Ancient Philosophy 20: 1-17.

Brown, E. 2017. ‘Plato’s Ethics and Politics in the Republic,’ Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy
(http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/plato-ethics-politics/).

Burnyeat, M. F. 1999. ‘Culture and Society in Plato’s Republic,’ The Tanner Lectures on Human Values
20: 217-324.

Burnyeat, M. F. 2000. ‘Plato on Why Mathematics is Good for the Soul,’ Proceedings of the British Academy
103: 1-82.

Cooper, J. 1977. ‘The Psychology of Justice in Plato,' American Philosophical Quarterly 14: 151-7.

Cooper, J. 1984. ‘Plato’s Theory of Human Motivation,’ History of Philosophy Quarterly 1: 3-21.

Cross, R. C. and A. D. Woozley. 1964. Plato's Republic: A Philosophical Commentary. New York, St
Martin's Press.

Denyer, N. 2007. ‘Sun and Line: The Role of the Good,’ in Ferrari (ed) Cambridge Companion to
Plato’s Republic, pp. 284-309.

Information Classification: General


Ferejohn, M. 2006. ‘Knowledge, Recollection, and the Forms in Republic VII,’ in Santas (ed.) Blackwell Guide
to Plato’s Republic, pp. 214-33.

Ferrari, G. 2005. City and Soul in Plato’s Republic. Chicago, University of Chicago Press.

Ferrari, G., ed. 2007. The Cambridge Companion to Plato’s Republic. Cambridge, Cambridge University
Press.

Ferrari, G. 2010. ‘Socrates in the Republic,’ in McPherran (ed.) Plato’s Republic: A Critical Guide, pp.
11-31.

Fine, G. 1993. On Ideas. Oxford, Oxford University Press.

Fitzpatrick, K. 2021. ‘Two Songs in the Kallipolis of Plato’s Republic,’ The Political Science Reviewer
45: 193-219.

Frede, D. 1996. ‘Plato, Popper, and Historicism,’ Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in
Ancient Philosophy 12: 247-76.

Gotoff, H. C. 1980. ‘Thrasymachus of Calchedon and Ciceronian Style,’ Classical Philology 75: 297-
311.

Halliwell, S. 2002. The Aesthetics of Mimesis: Ancient Texts and Modern Problems. Princeton,
Princeton University Press.

Havelock, E. A. 1966. ‘Plato on Poetry,’ in Sesonske (ed.) Plato’s Republic, pp. 116-35.

Hyland, D. 1968. ‘Why Plato Wrote Dialogues,’ Philosophy and Rhetoric 1: 38-50.

Joseph, H. W. B. 1966. ‘Plato's Republic: The Argument with Polemarchus,’ in Sesonske (ed.) Plato's
Republic, pp. 6-16.

Kahn, C. 1981. ‘Did Plato Write Socrates’ Dialogues?’ Classical Quarterly 31: 305-320.

Kahn, C. 1993. ‘Proleptic Composition in the Republic, or Why Book 1 Was Never a Separate
Dialogue,’ Classical Quarterly 43: 131-42.

Kahn, C. 2009. Essays on Being. Oxford, Oxford University Press.

Kamtekar, R. 2004. ‘What’s the Good of Agreeing? Homonoia in Platonic Politics,’ Oxford Studies in
Ancient Philosophy 24: 131-170.

Klosko, G. 1981. ‘Implementing the Ideal State,’ The Journal of Politics 43: 356-89.

Lane, M. 1999. ‘Plato, Popper, Strauss, and Utopianism: Open Secrets?’, History of Philosophy
Quarterly 16: 119-42.

Lear, J. 2006. ‘Allegory and Myth in Plato’s Republic,’ in Santas (ed.) Blackwell Guide to Plato’s
Republic, pp. 25-43.

Lorenz, H. 2006. The Brute Within: Appetitive Desire in Plato and Aristotle. Oxford, Oxford University
Press.

Lycos, K. 1987. Plato on Justice and Power: Reading Book I of Plato’s Republic. Albany. State University of

Information Classification: General


New York Press.

Mahoney, T. 1992. ‘Do Plato’s Philosopher-Rulers Sacrifice Self-interest to Justice?’, Phronesis 38: 265-82.

Malcolm, J. 1991. Plato on the Self-Predication of Forms: Early and Middle Dialogues. Oxford, Clarendon
Press.

McPherran, M., ed. 2010a. Plato’s Republic: A Critical Guide. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.

McPherran, M. 2010b. ‘Virtue, Luck, and Choice at the End of the Republic,’ in McPherran (ed.)
Plato’s Republic, pp. 132-46.

Moss, J. 2007. ‘What is Imitative Poetry and Why is it Bad?’, in Ferrari (ed) Cambridge Companion to
Plato’s Republic, pp. 415-444.

Nehamas, A. 1979. ‘Self-Predication and Plato's Theory of Forms,’ American Philosophical Quarterly
16 (1979): 93-103.

Nehamas, A. 1982. ‘Plato on Imitation and Poetry,’ in J. Moravcsik and P.Temko (eds.) Plato on Beauty,
Wisdom, and the Arts. Totowa, NJ, pp. 47-78.

Nehamas, A. 1992. ‘What Did Socrates Teach and to Whom Did He Teach It?’ Review of Metaphysics 46: 279-
306.

Neu, J. 1971. ‘Plato's Analogy of State and Individual: The Republic and the Organic Theory of the
State,' Philosophy 46: 238-54.

Nussbaum, M. 1986. ‘The Republic: True Value and the Standpoint of Perfection,’ in The Fragility of
Goodness: Luck and Ethics in Greek Tragedy and Philosophy. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press,
pp. 136-64.

Pappas, N. 2020. ‘Plato’s Aesthetics,’ The Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy, Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL =
<https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2020/entries/plato-aesthetics/>.

Pappas, N. 2021. Plato’s Exceptional City, Love, and Philosopher. London, Routledge.

Parry, R. 2007. ‘The Unhappy Tyrant and the Craft of Inner Rule,’ in Ferrari (ed) Cambridge Companion to
Plato’s Republic, pp. 386-414.

Partee, M. H. 1970. ‘Plato’s Banishment of Poetry,’ The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 29:
209-22.

Patterson, R. 1982. ‘The Platonic Art of Comedy and Tragedy,’ Philosophy and Literature 6: 76-93.

Price, A.W. 2009. ‘Are Plato’s Soul-Parts Psychological Subjects?’, Ancient Philosophy 29: 1-15.

Reeve, C. D. C. 1985. ‘Socrates Meets Thrasymachus,’ Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 67: 246-
65.

Reeve, C. D. C. 1988. Philosopher-Kings: The Argument of Plato’s Republic. Princeton, Princeton


University Press.

Information Classification: General


Reeve, C. D. C. 2010. ‘Blindness and Reorientation: Education and the Acquisition of Knowledge in
the Republic,’ in McPherran (ed.) Plato’s Republic, pp. 209-28.

Rickless, S. 2007. Plato’s Forms in Transition. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.

Russell, D. 2007. Plato on Pleasure and the Good Life. Oxford, Oxford University Press.

Santas, G. 1983. ‘The Form of the Good in Plato's Republic,’ in J. P. Anton and A. Preus (eds.) Essays
in Ancient Greek Philosophy, II, Albany, SUNY Press, pp. 232-63.

Santas, G., ed. 2006. The Blackwell Guide to Plato’s Republic. Malden, Blackwell Publishing.

Santas, G. 2010. Understanding Plato’s Republic. Oxford and New York, Wiley-Blackwell.

Schofield, M. 2010. ‘Music All Pow’rful,’ in McPherran (ed.) Plato’s Republic, pp. 229-48.

Sedley, D. 2007. ‘Philosophy, the Forms, and the Art of Ruling,’ in Ferrari (ed) Cambridge Companion to
Plato’s Republic, pp. 256-83.

Sesonske, A. 1961. ‘Plato's Apology: Republic I,' Phronesis 6: 29-36.

Sesonske, A., ed. 1966. Plato's Republic: Interpretation and Criticism. Belmont, California,
Wadsworth Publishing Company.

Shields, C. 2010. ‘Plato’s Divided Soul,’ in McPherran (ed.) Plato’s Republic, pp. 147-170.

Silverman, A. 2014. ‘Plato's Middle Period Metaphysics and Epistemology,’ The Stanford
Encyclopaedia of Philosophy, Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL =
<https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2014/entries/plato-metaphysics/>.

Smith, N. 1996. ‘Plato’s Divided Line,’ Ancient Philosophy 16: 25-46.

Smith, N. 2010. ‘Return to the Cave,’ in McPherran (ed.) Plato’s Republic, pp. 83-102.

Sparshott, F. E. 1966. ‘Socrates and Thrasymachus,’ Monist 50: 421-59.

Vasiliou, I. 2012. ‘From the Phaedo to the Republic: Plato’s tripartite soul and the possibility of non-
philosophical virtue,’ in R. Barney, T. Brennan, and C. Brittain (eds.) Plato and the Divided Self.
Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, pp. 9-32.

Vlastos, G. 1991. Socrates, Ironist and Moral Philosopher. Ithaca, Cornell University Press.

Weiss, R. 2007. ‘Wise Guys and Smart Alecks in Republic 1 and 2,’ in Ferrari (ed.) Cambridge
Companion to Plato’s Republic, pp. 90-115.

Information Classification: General

You might also like