2.1 Omari, The Theology of Abu L-Qasim Al-Ka'bi
2.1 Omari, The Theology of Abu L-Qasim Al-Ka'bi
2.1 Omari, The Theology of Abu L-Qasim Al-Ka'bi
By
Racha el Omari
|
Cover illustration: Interior detail; decoration on so t of arch resting on south pillar (8th-9th century
Abbasid Mosque at Balkh) Copyright Horst P. Schastok, image courtesy of Fine Arts Library, Harvard
University.
Want or need Open Access? Brill Open o fers you the choice to make your research freely accessible
online in exchange for a publication charge. Review your various options on brill.com/brill-open.
Typeface for the Latin, Greek, and Cyrillic scripts: “Brill”. See and download: brill.com/brill-typeface.
-
- - - - (hardback)
- - - - (e-book)
The discussion of the attributes in kalām surfaced in the early second/eighth century with
Jahm b. Ṣafwān and Ḍirār b. ʿAmr. See Frank, Beings and Their Attributes, 10; and van Ess,
Theologie, 425–439.
See, for example, Sayyid (ed.), Faḍl al-iʿtizāl, 213; al-Jishumī, al-ʿUyūn fī l-radd, fols. 12b–13b;
and Mānkdīm, al-Taʿlīq, 149–291.
al-Ashʿarī, Maqālāt al-islāmiyyīn, 169–170, 546–547; al-Ashʿarī, Kitāb al-Lumaʿ, 10–14; Ibn
Fūrak, Mujarrad maqālāt, 38–42; al-Bāqillānī, Kitāb al-Tamhīd, 23–25; al-Juwaynī, Kitāb
al-Irshād, 30–34; al-Baghdādī, Kitāb Uṣūl al-dīn, 88–89.
Daniel Gimaret, La Doctrine d’al-Ashʿarī (Paris: Les éditions du Cerf, 1990), 26–27.
This distinction was rst noted by al-Jubbāʾī, and also adopted by al-Kaʿbī: al-Ashʿarī, Maqālāt
al-islāmiyyīn, 527–528; Frank, Beings and Their Attributes, 17–19.
© , , | . / _
conceptual repertoire of the grammarians. He gave attributes the ontological
weight of “an accusative of state” (ḥāl), thereby eliminating the multiplicity
that resulted from speaking of God as having many predications. But Abū
Hāshim’s solution to the problem resided in expanding the aims of the theology
of attributes to ve categories, which he crafted to describe not only God but
all other beings, including the components of those beings, namely “bodies”
(ajsām), “accidents” (aʿrāḍ), and “atoms” (jawāhir).
The rst category of attributes is a rmed for every being, including God,
and it was called the “attribute of the essence” (ṣifat al-dhāt). The second cat-
egory was the “essential attribute” and it derived from the rst category (li-mā
huwa ʿalayhi fī dhātihi). When this second category of attributes is applied to
God, it refers to the attributes: “powerful” (qādiran), “knowing” (ʿāliman), “living”
(ḥayyan), and “existing” (mawjūdan). While God was considered knowing
because His knowledge is derived from the attribute of the essence, a human
being is knowing because of an “entitative determinant” (maʿnā) in him that is
knowledge. An example of such a category of attributes applying to another
being can be seen in the “occupation of space” (taḥayyuz) being an attribute of
the “atom” (jawhar). The only di ference is that in the case of God this category
is always a rmed, while for other beings, that category must be added to
them. Abū Hāshim’s third category of attributes was this latter kind of attri-
bute that derived from an “entitative determinant”; these attributes inhered, in
the majority of cases, in a “substrate” (maḥall). One attribute of God—the
attribute of volition—was included in this category, though it was not consid-
ered to inhere in a substrate. The fourth category applied to attributes derived
from an “agent” (bi-l-fāʿil) and included the attributes of beings created by God,
as well as attributes of God’s acts, such as His bene cence and mercy. The last
category of attributes was one derived neither from the essence nor from an
The extent to which Abū Hāshim’s conceptualization of the attributes consisted of a full-
scale system was recognized and explained by Richard M. Frank. Abū Hāshim’s concept
of ḥāl for an attribute was developed and borrowed from the Basran grammariansʼ inter-
pretation of the accusative predicate of kāna (Frank, Beings and Their Attributes, 20–24).
Frank, Beings and Their Attributes, 19–20, 27; Ibn Mattawayh, Kitāb al-Majmūʿ fī l-muḥīṭ
bi-l-taklīf, 1:97–112.
Frank, Beings and Their Attributes, 53–55.
The attributes of essence are recognized as these four in Mānkdīm, al-Taʿlīq, 182.
Richard Frank, “Attribute, Attribution, and Being: Three Islamic Views,” in Philosophies of
Existence, Ancient and Medieval, ed. P. Morewedge (New York: Fordham University Press,
1982), 268.
Frank, Beings and Their Attributes, 93–111.
Ibid., 135–136.
“entitative determinant” (lā li-dhāt wa-lā li-maʿnā), and to it belonged God’s
attribute of hearing and seeing that in turn derived from the attribute of living,
but is separate from the attribute of knowing.
Al-Kaʿbī’s views on the attributes were, as we see, at least in part, a continu-
ation of earlier Muʿtazilī experiments on the attributes, which were later
eclipsed by Abū Hāshim’s theology of the attributes. Later biographical dic-
tionaries of ḥadīth transmitters especially note al-Kaʿbī’s view of divine voli-
tion for its a front to the doctrine of divine omnipotence. He was described as
maintaining the stance that God’s volition is equivalent to His knowledge.
Similarly, al-Kaʿbī’s denial of the reality of the attributes of hearing and volition
led Abū l-Qāsim Ismāʿīl al-Bustī (d. late fth/eleventh century) to single it out
as an example of doctrinal di ferences serious enough to lead earlier Muʿtazilīs
to accuse its supporters of unbelief.
Al-Bustī and the later biographical dictionaries of ḥadīth transmitters espe-
cially condemn al-Kaʿbī for his view of divine volition. There is also additional
evidence for al-Kaʿbī’s contributions on the subject of volition as a cosmologi-
cal (daqīq or laṭīf al-kalām) question in its own right. Tracing the potential
in uence of these contributions on his doctrine of the divine attributes, how-
ever, remains beyond the scope of the present chapter. Thus, among the extant
titles of al-Kaʿbī’s lost works, two deal with the subject of volition. These are
the correspondences he exchanged with al-Jubbāʾī: Naqḍ kitāb Abī ʿAlī l-Jubbāʾī
fī l-irāda (Refutation of Abū ʿAlī’s book on volition [irāda]), and al-Kitāb
al-thānī ʿalā Abī ʿAlī fī l-[irāda] (The second book in refutation of Abū ʿAlī
on the subject matter of volition [irāda]). Moreover, parts of Abū Rashīd
Ibid., 148–154.
Aḥmad b. Muḥammad Ibn Khallikān, Wafayāt al-aʿyān, 3:45. Ibn Shākir al-Kutubī includes
Ibn Abī l-Damm’s report, ʿUyūn al-tawārīkh, Micro lm A 408 (American University in
Beirut: Jafet Library), fol. 28a. Al-Dhahabī explained that al-Kaʿbī limited God’s volition to
nothing other than His knowledge (al-Dhahabī, Taʾrīkh al-Islām wa-wafayāt al-mashāhīr
wa-l-aʿlām, ed. ʿUmar ʿAbd al-Salām al-Tadmurī (Beirut: Dār al-Kitāb al-ʿArabī, 1987)),
23:584–585.
al-Bustī, Kitāb al-Baḥth, 24. Al-Bustī also included the attribute of aversion (kārihan) that
is not noted in other sources (see Table 1). Al-Bustī’s nal verdict was that, if unbelief were
based on the serious doctrines he listed, most Muʿtazilīs would be deemed unbelievers.
Hence, he concluded that accusations of unbelief based on grave disagreements in doc-
trine and the conclusions of these earlier Muʿtazilīs should be abandoned (Madelung and
Schmidtke, “Introduction,” Kitāb al-Baḥth, iv–v). Regardless of al-Bustī’s softer position
regarding accusations of unbelief, he listed al-Kaʿbī’s stance on the attributes of volition,
hearing, and seeing as among the doctrines of earlier Muʿtazilīs that warrant a declara-
tion of unbelief (takfīr).
al-Nīsābūrī’s al-Masāʾil fī l-khilāf document al-Kaʿbī’s views on volition from his
work, ʿUyūn al-masāʾil.
al-Naẓẓām
Where the sources highlight in uences on al-Kaʿbī’s views of the attributes, it is
mostly of al-Naẓẓām’s in uence that they speak. In some cases, Baghdadis, who
remain unidenti ed, were also linked to al-Naẓẓām’s doctrine of the attributes.
Although the sources do not describe them as in uences, there are also cases
where the in uence of al-Naẓẓām on al-Kaʿbī is apparent through kindred ten-
dencies that are outlined here. Al-Naẓẓām’s understanding of the divine attri-
butes had an apophatic character that was often presented as a response to
Abū l-Hudhayl’s formulation. The latter a rmed the reality of independent
attributes but simultaneously reduced them to only a rmations of God; Abū
l-Hudhayl depicted God as “knowing with a knowledge that is He, powerful
with a power that is He, living with a life that is He.” In response, al-Naẓẓām
acknowledged the eternity of the attributes, but used only participles and not
nouns that would imply their existence as independent and separate entities.
He pronounced that they exist only as a rmations of God’s “essence” (bi-nafsihi).
Al-Naẓẓām described God as “eternally (lam yazal) knowing, living, powerful,
hearing, and seeing by His essence (bi-nafsihi) and not by the existence of the
While for al-Naẓẓām scripture dictated that the attributes of knowledge and
power should have a less apophatic exposition than other attributes, al-Naẓẓām
claimed that it was also scripture that informed his treatment of “volition”
(irāda) as not actually an attribute, but only a metaphor. Volition is, thus, not
separable from God’s acts and commands: God’s willing of creation (takwīn) is
His creation, and His willing of human acts is His command of human acts.
Ibid., 486.
Ibid., 166–167, 178.
Ibid., 167. In the second part of the same work (486–487), al-Ashʿarī attacked al-Naẓẓām,
stating: “you only a rm God’s essence” (anta lā tuthbitu illā l-dhāt).
Ibid., 187–188. Again in the second part of that work, al-Naẓẓām was quoted as specifying
that God spoke of the attribute of power and knowledge in an absolute manner (aṭlaq), in
contrast to the attributes of hearing (samʿ) and seeing (baṣar), 487.
But, al-Naẓẓām maintained the distinction between the command and the
object of the command.
God’s volition is only (innamā) His act, or His command (amruh), or His
decree (ḥukm). This is [so] because this is the meaning of volition accord-
ing to Arabic usage (fī l-lugha), either it is a secret thought (ḍamīr), or
shows a thing’s position in relation to something else. This [usage can be
observed] in His saying, He is exalted, “a wall that is on the verge of falling
[literally that wishes to fall] but he [al-Khiḍr] erected it.” Since a secret
thought (ḍamīr) cannot be applicable (yastaḥīl ʿalā) to God, the meaning
of His volition has to be what we mentioned. He [al-Naẓẓām] also noted
that the object of volition (al-murād) is designated as volition (irāda) in
Arabic usage (fī l-lugha). Thus it is said: “Bring me my wish (irādatī),
meaning the object of my volition (murādī).” He [al-Naẓẓām] also says:
“God willed judgment day to take place, meaning that He decreed it.”
Clearly scripture did not compel al-Naẓẓām to take a literalist position along
the lines of the “without how” principle (bi-lā kayfa) that was adopted to vary-
ing degrees of exigency by proto-Sunnī and Sunnī mutakallimūn. Indeed, the
attributes of face and hand are not real (fī l-ḥaqīqa) for al-Naẓẓām. They are,
instead, simply expressions, that the hand of God is His blessing (niʿma), and
His face meant that He perdures (yabqā). They are to be understood as meta-
phorical expressions precisely because Arabic usage in the Qurʾān treats them
as such. To regard these descriptions of God as real would be a breach of that
usage.
Among al-Naẓẓām’s views surveyed here, explicit textual support that
al-Kaʿbī followed al-Naẓẓām exists only for al-Naẓẓām’s stance regarding God’s
Qurʾān 18:77.
ʿAbd al-Jabbār, al-Mughnī: al-Irāda, 6/2:3–4. This doctrine is noted in al-Ashʿarī’s Maqālāt
al-islāmiyyīn (190–191) with the added mention that the Baghdadis (who remained
unidenti ed) agreed with al-Naẓẓām on this. See also van Ess, Theologie, 3:401–403, 6:154.
Richard Frank, “Elements in the Development of the Teaching of al-Ashʿarī,” and “The
Science of kalām,” Arabic Sciences and Philosophy 2 (1992): 7–37.
al-Ashʿarī, Maqālāt al-islāmiyyīn, 167. Regarding how to render the attribute of God’s face
(wajh), the Baghdadis and most of the Basrans followed al-Naẓẓām: “The term wajh is
used in the broadest sense (tawassuʿan). We a rm a face that is He (nuthbit wajhan huwa
huwa). This position is justi ed in the linguistic usage of the term face (wajh) in lieu of the
thing itself. Such as someone saying, ‘Had it not been for your face I would have not done
such and such’.” (Ibid., 189).
Ibid.
volition. In al-Naẓẓām’s scripturalist stance there is a signi cant precedence
for al-Kaʿbī’s choice. But the linguistic arguments that al-Naẓẓām invoked for
his position on the attribute of volition and how he formulated the attributes
of knowledge and power were never attributed to al-Kaʿbī, nor was al-Kaʿbī’s
scripturalist stance explicitly tied to al-Naẓẓām. Furthermore, al-Naẓẓām’s
in uence on al-Kaʿbī may have been even more pervasive than indicated by
the speci c similarities of doctrines just reviewed. The similarity and possibil-
ity of al-Naẓẓāmʼs in uence on the Baghdadis is likely, though individual pro-
ponents remain unidenti able, as we see in what follows.
Baghdadi Predecessors
Like other early Muʿtazilīs, the Baghdadis also distinguished between the
attributes of essence and of act. One group relegated God’s volition of cre-
ation to an attribute of act, while the attributes of knowledge, power, life,
hearing, and seeing were deemed attributes of essence. Moreover, their
disagreement in de ning the attributes of act was documented, speci cally
those related to the attribute of generosity. The challenge in determining
the doctrines of the early Baghdadi precursors of al-Kaʿbī on the attributes is
not only that the information is fragmentary, but also that it is sometimes
only identi ed as being that of the general category of Baghdadis.
A work of al-Khayyāṭ on the subject of the “seen” (shāhid) and “unseen”
(ghāʾib) seems to address the methodological concerns underlying his discus-
sion of the attributes. As for al-Khayyāṭ’s views on the attribute of volition,
the available evidence remains inconclusive.
On the formulation of the attribute of essence, the Baghdadis seemed to
agree in principle with al-Naẓẓām in considering the attributes of essence, in the
Ibid., 505.
There are two positions recorded on the Baghdadisʼ understanding of whether jūd (gener-
ous giving) was an attribute of act. ʿĪsā l-Ṣūfī held that His generosity was an attribute of
act but refused to answer the question whether God could be eternally (lam yazal) non-
generous (ghayr karīm). Al-Iskāfī, however, distinguished two kinds of attributes in gen-
erosity, one an attribute of act, when generosity (karam) is generous giving (jūd) and the
other an attribute of essence designating the Being as elevated above other things (ibid.,
178, 506).
See for example, ibid., 504, 508.
Ibn Mattawayh, Kitāb al-Majmūʿ, 165; Madelung, “ʿAbd al-Raḥīm b. Moḥammad b. ʿOṯmān
al-Ḵayyāṭ,” Encycolopedia Iranica, 1:143–144.
Al-Nasafī reports that al-Khayyāṭ agreed with al-Kaʿbī’s doctrine on divine volition, but
the content of al-Kaʿbī’s doctrine that he reports is not accurate, as God’s volition is
described as the absence of God’s forgetfulness (al-Nasafī, Tabṣirat al-adilla, 1:374–375).
form of participles, as eternal attributes. The de nition available was terse and
focused on the negative theology they upheld: “They deny the existence of any
attribute of essence and [they] state that the Maker (al-bāriʾ) is a thing unlike
other things.” In another context, some Baghdadis agreed with al-Naẓẓāmʼs
special treatment of the attributes of power and knowledge, to the exclusion of
the attributes of hearing, seeing, and living because of the way these attributes
appear in scripture. Again, while it is tempting to see this as the position of
al-Kaʿbī, there is no direct evidence to support this identi cation.
Although the early Baghdadis disagreed among themselves about how to
de ne God’s volition, they shared a common concern for separating God’s voli-
tion from His servant’s act and volition. It seems that all Baghdadi and other
Muʿtazilī de nitions of this attribute were in part anchored to theodicean pre-
occupations. The majority of the Muʿtazilīs deemed the attribute of volition as
an attribute of act. Bishr b. al-Muʿtamir alone held that God’s volition was an
attribute of essence, albeit only when the objects of Godʼs volition did not
include evil deeds: “He is eternally willing the [servants’] acts of obedience to
the exclusion of the [servants’] acts of disobedience” (lam yazal murīdan
li-ṭāʿatihi dūna maʿṣiyatih). Bishr postulated two volitions for God, the one
just noted and another as an attribute of act (hiya ʿl min afʿālihi). His signa-
ture “two volitions” spoke of his preoccupation with preserving the integrity of
God’s agency and His servant’s freedom of action.
Other Baghdadi Muʿtazilīs did not opt for Bishr’s concept of two volitions,
but they were equally concerned with de ning God’s volition without compro-
mising Him by association with evil acts. Abū Mūsā l-Murdār (d. 226/841) under-
stood God’s willing of “the servants’ acts of disobedience” (maʿāṣī l-ʿibād) to
Ibid., 190.
Ibid., 512.
Ibid., 191, 513–514. As to the identi cation of God’s volition and creation (makhlūq), it is
not found in al-Murdār, ibid., 190.
Ibid., 173–174.
Ibid., 175.
al-Ashʿarī, Maqālāt al-islāmiyyīn, 506.
Certain cosmological considerations were taking center stage in Muʿtazilī theology at the
time, and these underlay the choices of al-Iskāfī and other Muʿtazilīs when they spoke
about the objects of God’s knowledge. The most important detail to note is al-Kaʿbīʼs dis-
agreement with al-Khayyāṭ’s controversial view that the non-existent (al-maʿdūm) is not
only a thing (shayʾ) but also a body (jism). Al-Khayyāṭʼs view was universally opposed by
promoting the view that God’s attribute of life is His power; this was also widely
followed by the Baghdadis who remain unnamed and who seem to have held a
variety of opinions on the exact relationship between the attributes of knowl-
edge and power. Al-Kaʿbī did not, however, follow this position of al-Iskāfī.
Muʿtazilīs, because it could lead to the conclusion that bodies are co-eternal with God
(al-Ashʿarī, Maqālāt al-islāmiyyīn, 504; al-Shahrastānī, Kitāb al-Milal wa-l-niḥal, 53).
Instead al-Kaʿbī understood the non-existent (al-maʿdūm) to be a thing (shayʾ), but nei-
ther an atom (juzʾ) nor an accident (ʿaraḍ) (Abū Rashīd al-Nīsābūrī, al-Masāʾil fī l-khilāf,
37–38). In this al-Kaʿbī still held a minority position, as the majority of Basrans, starting
with al-Shaḥḥām, thought that things, bodies, and accidents are only known by God
before their existence (al-Ashʿarī, Maqālāt al-islāmiyyīn, 162). These cosmological discus-
sions had an immediate in uence on the doctrine of the attributes. For example, al-Jubbāʾī
accepted hearing and seeing as eternal attributes (lam yazal) distinct from knowledge,
but denied them their transitive quality, it seems, to accommodate al-Shaḥḥāmʼs view,
which he followed. That is, al-Jubbāʾī did not deem God to be samīʿan, mubṣiran, because
this would have required the eternity of the objects of hearing and seeing with God (ibid.,
175–176, also 492–493). On the analysis of the non-existent (maʿdūm) as a discussion of
the ontology of the possible, see Richard M. Frank, “The Non-Existent, the Existent, and
the Possible in the Teaching of Abū Hāshim and his Followers,” Mélanges de l’Institut
Dominicain d’Etudes Orientales du Caire 14 (1980): 185–209.
al-Ashʿarī, Maqālāt al-islāmiyyīn, 168.
Ibid., 176–177. The equation of God’s knowledge with God’s power is in some instances
misattributed to al-Kaʿbī (see below).
al-Māturīdī, Kitāb al-Tawḥīd, 78; al-Nasafῑ, Tabṣirat al-adilla, 1:225.
al-Ashʿarī, Maqālāt al-islāmiyyīn, 178, 506.
al-Jishumī, Sharḥ ʿUyūn al-masāʾil, vol. 1, fol. 171b; al-Nasafī, Tabṣirat al-adilla, 1:225.
of essence as “because of His essence” (li-nafsihi) must be rejected. Al-Kaʿbī
characterized the attributes of essence as those attributes whose opposite is
impossible. This is documented by al-Jishumī, al-Nasafī, and al-Māturīdī; this
is a distinction that had been used by earlier Muʿtazilīs to de ne God’s attributes
of essence. However, in al-Māturīdī we nd an additional argument for the
attribute of essence ascribed to al-Kaʿbī, one that is not attested elsewhere.
Al-Māturīdī cites an unnamed work of al-Kaʿbī directly. But al-Māturīdīʼs state-
ment, as promising as it is indicative of a distinct line of argumentation, cannot
be accepted without reservation because, on occasion, al-Māturīdī cites al-Kaʿbī
as a spokesperson of shared Muʿtazilī stances. Below I analyze al-Māturīdīʼs
statements in tandem with accounts of al-Kaʿbīʼs other arguments proposed by
earlier Muʿtazilīs and given by al-Nasafī and al-Jishumī.
al-Jishumī, ʿUyūn al-masāʾil, fols. 21a–21b; Sharḥ ʿUyūn al-masāʾil, vol. 1, fol. 148b; al-Mufīd,
Awāʾil al-maqālāt, 13; Mānkdīm, al-Taʿlῑq, 168; Ibn al-Malāḥimī, Kitāb al-Fāʾiq, 36–37;
al-Shahrastānī, Kitāb Nihāyat al-iqdām, 341; al-Bāqillānī, Kitāb al-Tamḥῑd, 253; al-Ashʿarī
Maqālāt al-islāmiyyīn, 175.
al-Ashʿarī, Maqālāt al-islāmiyyīn, 175.
Ibn al-Malāḥimī, Kitāb al-Fāʾiq, 36–37.
al-Juwaynī, Kitāb al-Irshād, 176.
al-Shahrastānī, Kitāb Nihāyat al-iqdām, 341.
al-Jishumī, Sharḥ ʿUyūn al-masāʾil, vol. 2, fol. 191a; al-Mufīd, Awāʾil al-maqālāt, 13; al-Ashʿarī,
Maqālāt al-islāmiyyīn, 509–510.
al-Bāqillānī, Kitāb al-Tamhīd, 252; Ibn Fūrak, Mujarrad maqālāt, 76; al-Baghdādī, Kitāb
Uṣūl al-dīn, 91.
al-Ashʿarī, Maqālāt al-islāmiyyīn, 509–510.
Ibn al-Malāḥimῑ, Kitāb al-Fāʾiq, 42.
In the second recension (Table 1: 5B) al-Kaʿbī understands God’s volition
to mean His knowledge—and in one single statement, His power. This
recension must be treated as indicative of later developments in the recep-
tion of al-Kaʿbī’s doctrine because this statement that Godʼs volition is His
knowledge veers from al-Kaʿbī’s article that God’s volition is His act or His
command, an article whose ascription to al-Kaʿbī is validated by the agree-
ment of all the testimonies. It should also be treated as a later development
because the arguments reported in this second recension include signi -
cant divergences among themselves. Indeed the statements of this recen-
sion all derive from late Ashʿarī sources. But the reports of this recension
also include one veri ed component of al-Kaʿbī’s theology, namely one
inherited from al-Naẓẓām which states that the meaning of divine volition
is His act and His command. Because of this component, this recension
can be read as consisting of a late “reception” of al-Kaʿbī’s doctrine on the
attributes.
A third recension includes the most strongly and consistently docu-
mented stance attributed to al-Kaʿbī, namely that God’s volition is His act
and command (Table 1: 5C), but this recension simultaneously mixes this
with other theologiansʼ doctrines that do not agree with al-Kaʿbī. Thus the
statements of Mānkdīm and al-Nasafī allege that al-Kaʿbī held that God’s
volition means “the absence of His forgetfulness (sahw),” and this was a doc-
trine of al-Najjār. Fakhr al-Dīn al-Rāzī cites two mixed reports indepen-
dently from one another. In both reports al-Kaʿbī is linked through hybrid
articles to other gures, namely al-Jāḥiẓ and Abū l-Ḥudhayl, though he has
little in common with them on the doctrine of volition. The fourth and
last recension (Table 1: 5D) is also mixed: al-Ījīʼs statement links al-Kaʿbī
with al-Jāḥiẓ and Abū l-Huhdayl. Clearly these mixed recensions cannot
be used to reconstruct al-Kaʿbī’s theology, rather they re ect Ashʿarī theo-
logical concerns in the course of the sixth/twelfth to eighth/fourteenth
centuries.
al-Shahrastānī, Kitāb Nihāyat al-iqdām, 238; al-Shahrastānī, Kitāb al-Milal wa-l-niḥal, 43–
44; al-Juwaynī, Kitāb al-Irshād, 63–66; al-Zabīdī, Itḥāf al-sāda, 2:141; Ibn al-Malāḥimī,
Kitāb al-Fāʾiq, 42.
For example, compare the arguments in al-Shahrastānī, Kitāb al-Milal wa-l-niḥal, 43–44 to
al-Zabīdī, Itḥāf al-sāda, 2:141.
For example, al-Shahrastānī, Kitāb al-Milal wa-l-niḥal, 43–44.
ʿAbd al-Jabbār, al-Mughnī: al-Irāda, 6/2:5.
al-Rāzī, al-Maṭālib al-ʿāliya, 3:179; al-Rāzī, Kitāb al-Arbaʿīn, 147.
al-Ashʿarī, Maqālāt al-islāmiyyīn, 189–190, 363–364, 510.
God’s Speech and God’s Relation to Place
While Muʿtazilīs stipulated that God’s speech is created, there were some dis-
agreements on where the accident of speech took place. Al-Kaʿbī followed an
earlier Baghdadi Muʿtazilī stance promulgated by Jaʿfar b. Ḥarb and Jaʿfar b.
Mubashshir (d. 234/849) that stipulates that the Qurʾān as a created accident
could not exist in more than one place. It only exists in the eternal tablet. All
other manifestations of the Qurʾān, meaning its recitation, writing, and hear-
ing, were only imitations (ḥikāya) of the letters created on the tablet, the object
of imitation (maḥkī). In this al-Kaʿbī followed the earlier Muʿtazilī position of
Jaʿfar b. Ḥarb and Jaʿfar b. Mubashshir, and he disagreed with al-Iskāfī’s posi-
tion that was subsequently followed by al-Jubbāʾī. The latter understood the
Qurʾān as an accident that exists in more than one place at the same time.
Thus al-Jubbāʾī, following al-Iskāfī, also thought that each recitation is identi-
cal with the created accident of the Qurʾān. This is documented by al-Nasafī,
whose statement allows for the identi cation of a similar statement in
al-Ashʿarī’s Maqālāt al-islāmiyyīn.
In another recorded position on the attributes, al-Kaʿbī also favored an ear-
lier Muʿtazilī stance. He followed the minority position of Hishām b. ʿAmr
al-Fuwaṭī and his student ʿAbbād b. Sulaymān al-Ṣaymarī (d. c. 250/864) in
believing that God is not constituted spatially. In this al-Kaʿbī disagreed with
the position of earlier Baghdadi Muʿtazilīs, including the two Jaʿfars, and
al-Iskāfī, as well as the Basrans Abū l-Hudhayl and al-Jubbāʾī, who both consid-
ered God to be in every place in the sense that He is “managing” (mudabbir)
every place. It is al-Māturīdī who allows us to identify al-Kaʿbī among the
group of unidenti ed Muʿtazilīs noted in Maqālāt al-islāmiyyīn who, in this
regard, are believed to have followed this minority position. Moreover,
al-Māturīdī’s statement added one further detail to al-Kaʿbī’s endorsement of
this position, al-Kaʿbī explained God’s relation to place as one of “knowing it”
(ʿalā maʿnā annahu ʿālim) and “preserving it” (ḥā ẓ lahu). This relationship was
comparable to the role of a person in relation to the building of a house, in the
A perfect (muḥkam) and sound (mutqan) act proves (yadullu) that its
agent (fāʿiluh) is knowing and powerful only (faḥasb). Then we apply
rational inquiry (naẓar) to [the result of the earlier proof], [if we nd]
that ignorance (jahl) and incapacity (ʿajz) are admissible to [describe]
the agent, [we learn] that He is knowing with a knowledge (ʿālim bi-ʿilm)
and powerful with power (qādir bi-qudra). If [we nd that] ignorance
and incapacity and all the contraries of knowledge and power are inad-
missible for him (istaḥāla ʿalayhi), He is [proven to be] knowing by His
essence (bi-nafsihi), powerful by His essence (bi-nafsihi).
Thus a perfect act is the starting point for the proof that knowledge constitutes
its agent’s attribute of essence. The agent of this perfect act is then subjected to
rational inquiry to examine if the contrary of knowledge and power can char-
acterize him. When the result of this examination is positive, then the agent is
declared as having an essence according to an entitative determinant, be it
knowledge or power. But when the result of the examination is negative—that
is, when the agent cannot be characterized by the opposite of the attributes of
knowledge and power—He is then declared to be knowing and powerful by
His essence (bi-nafsihi). This is how al-Kaʿbī arrived at the conclusion that
God’s attributes of essence are those that cannot tolerate their opposite.
For al-Jubbāʾī, God’s knowledge was distinguished from that of other agents
in the sense that while they know because of an “entitative determinant”
(maʿnā) of knowledge, God knows “because of His essence” (li-nafsihi).
Abū Hāshim, and those who followed him, upheld the view that knowl-
edge of His being knowing, powerful, and living is neither derived from
(yataʿallaq bi) His essence only, nor from an entitative determinant that
is other than Him, but rather it is correlated to His essence in a state (bi
dhātihi ʿalā ḥālatin) … Abū ʿAlī [al-Jubbāʾī] upheld this position in [some]
instances. However, though he upheld the term ḥāl (lafẓ al-ḥāl) in his
[work] Jawāb al-Khurāsāniyya [Response to the Khurāsānīs], he men-
tions a divergent term (bi-khilāf dhālik) in other instances. Abū l-Qāsim
[al-Kaʿbī] held that [knowledge of His being knowing, powerful, and liv-
ing] is knowledge by His essence (ʿilm bi-dhātihi).
Ibid.
Daniel Gimaret, “Matériaux pour une bibliographie des Jubbāʾī: note complémentaire,” in
Islamic Theology and Philosophy, Studies in Honor of G.F. Hourani, ed. M.E. Marmura
(Albany: State University of New York Press, 1984), 33.
al-Jishumī, Sharḥ ʿUyūn al-masāʾil, vol. 1, fol. 171b.
Ibid., vol. 1, fols. 171b–172a.
essence amounts to not really knowing anything about God. Al-Jishumī
explained that there are two conditions that remain unmet in such a scheme.
First, knowledge of two separate things cannot be identical. Second, speci c
and general knowledge are distinct from one another. If knowledge of God’s
essence is tied to (mutaʿalliq) knowledge of His attributes, then this is the same
as maintaining that knowledge of God’s existence is equal to knowledge of His
attributes. This was unacceptable to al-Jishumī because these are two separate
types of knowledge, namely speci c versus general knowledge about God.
Al-Jishumī thought that al-Kaʿbī’s formulation of knowledge of the attribute of
the essence did not lead to any speci c knowledge about God, other than that
He is an unknowable essence.
Al-Māturīdī provides a more detailed account of al-Kaʿbī’s understanding of
the attributes of essence, starting with his account of how an attribute of
essence is di ferent from an attribute of act. An attribute of act—as opposed to
an attribute of essence—is characterized by three features. First is its tolerance
of discord, such as the attribute that God is “compassionate” (raḥmān), or
“sustaining” (rāziq). God could be compassionate in one case and not com-
passionate in another; He could sustain one servant but not another. Both
examples of the attributes of act express “discord” (ikhtilāf), the rst spelled out
as “discord in state (ḥāl),” meaning in God’s state, and the second as discord in
relation to the person to whom God’s attribute is directed. Second, an attribute
of act is dominated by God’s power: God could speak in one instance and not in
another. He is not necessarily held to be speaking all the time. The third fea-
ture of al-Kaʿbī’s understanding of the attribute of act is the existence of its
opposite, such as the opposite of the attribute of mercy. The attributes of act are
external to God, they are derived from His power and can be opposed to one
another, discordant with one another.
“Discord” is the criterion that de nes the attributes of act, while its oppo-
site, harmony, which remains unnamed but implied in this passage, de nes
the attributes of essence:
Finally, al-Kaʿbī spelled out the principle of the “absence of discord” as a prin-
ciple of “internal necessity” that persists for as long as His essence endures.
“Since His essence (dhāt) is not discordant, discord is not possible as long as
His essence (nafs) lasts, just as a thing (shayʾ) is necessary because of a cause
that endures as long as it [a thing] lasts.” Al-Kaʿbī compared the relationship
of the necessity of a thing (shayʾ) to an internal cause, which persists for as
long as that thing exists, to the relationship of lack of discord with God’s
essence. The comparison implied that lack of discord was due to an internal
cause that continues for as long as He exists. While the function of the “absence
of discord” was explained through this comparison as a necessary internal
cause, it was not identi ed categorically.
This necessary internal cause rst described as “absence of discord” appears
again in al-Māturīdī’s statement of al-Kaʿbī’s explanation of the attribute of
Ibid.
Ibid.
Ibid. [emphasis added].
essence. This time, however, the “absence of discord” is worded in a rmative
language. It is an internal necessary cause, and attributions are derived from it.
Of course, like other Muʿtazilīs, for al-Kaʿbī the attributes and names were
words, attribution (waṣf) or (tasmiya), and not attributes (ṣifa). These attri-
butes, speci cally those of essence, derived from “that in which harmony
exists” (mā fīhi al-wifāq). Just as the “absence of discord” was not recognized as
a category, though its function was, the same was true in the case of “that in
which harmony exists.” Indeed, aside from being described as “an internal nec-
essary cause,” the ontological status of “that in which harmony exists” cannot
be uncovered from these passages.
Al-Naẓẓām and other early Muʿtazilīs had already spoken of the attribute of
essence as negating its opposite and a rming the essence of God. But none
of their descriptions attest to the mention of “necessity” when describing the
attribute of essence, and most importantly there was no mention of a principle
of harmony or absence of discord. As for his Basran counterparts, both
al-Jubbāʾī and Abū Hāshim found fault in al-Kaʿbīʼs formulation of the attri-
butes of essence as by His essence (fī nafsihi), and thus could not have favored
his explanations of what it was. With the little information available about the
arguments used by early Muʿtazilīs for understanding the attribute of essence,
al-Māturīdī’s statement cannot be taken as nal evidence for the uniqueness
of al-Kaʿbī’s use of the notion of an “internal necessary cause” to de ne the
attribute of essence.
Notwithstanding that al-Kaʿbī’s sources remain unknown and that his ter-
minology here must be documented further, what is attributed to al-Kaʿbī by
Robert Wisnovsky, “One Aspect of the Avicennian Turn in Sunnī Theology,” Arabic
Sciences and Philosophy 14 (2004), 88.
Peter Adamson, al-Kindī (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007), 172.
Ibid., 162.
Ibid., 163.
Frank, Beings and Their Attributes, 15. For a discussion of al-Jubbāʾī’s adoption of reason as
su cient for knowing the attributes, and its in uence on Abū Hāshim’s stance that the
origin of language is convention (muwāḍaʿa) and not revelation (tawqīf), see Sophia
Vasalou, “Their Intention was Shown by Their Bodily Movements,” Journal of the History
of Philosophy 47 (2009): 201–221.
not exist separately from words, or that a particular meaning could only be
expressed in one word. Rather it was based on the view that God’s names must
only be determined by scripture. Indeed al-Kaʿbī upheld the same view of lan-
guage, as known by convention (muwāḍaʿa), that al-Jubbāʾī upheld, but he
stopped short of applying this rule to God’s names speci cally.
Al-Jubbāʾī held that reason should su ce for knowing a given name of God and that God’s
names could not be known by scriptural postulation (talqīb). This is based on al-Jubbāʾī’s
stance that any given meaning was independent of the word that represented it, with
only human convention tying them together (al-Ashʿarī, Maqālāt al-islāmiyyīn, 525).
See Table 1: 3A1, where this position is identi ed as al-Kaʿbī’s.
al-Ashʿarī, Maqālāt al-islāmiyyīn, 525.
al-Jishumī, Sharḥ ʿUyūn al-masāʾil, vol. 1, fol. 177a.
al-Jishumī’s report, al-Kaʿbī or his followers’ potential retort to this view was
never disclosed.
Moreover, al-Kaʿbī was accused of inconsistency because he deemed reason
su cient to rule out what could not be considered divine attributes. He was
also accused of inconsistency when he accepted the Basran linguistic principle
that meaning could be expressed in di ferent words and that meaning was
apprehended through reason, yet he did not apply these two principles to
scripture. Al-Kaʿbī also shared with the Basrans the principle that language
is known by convention (muwāḍaʿa), but refrained from applying it in the case
of the divine names. What is framed as inconsistency by al-Jishumī only illus-
trates how far al-Kaʿbī’s scripturalism went: he made exceptions to divine
names over other linguistic matters.
The Basran claimed that God’s names (asmāʾ Allāh) are derived from
usage (iṣṭilāḥ) and analogy (qiyās). The consensus of the ahl al-sunna is
that God’s names are derived from revelation (tawqīf) and that it is not
possible to name God by a name based on analogy (min jihat al-qiyās),
rather He is named by that which appears in the book (al-kitāb),
Al-Jishumī understood that even the names by which God is described in ritual prayers
can also be known by reason.
al-Jishumī, Sharḥ ʿUyūn al-masāʾil, vol. 1, fols. 176b–177a.
the correct sunna, or the consensus of the community. Al-Kaʿbī
followed them [the ahl al-sunna] in this matter.
But al-Baghdādī’s claim about the meaning of scripture for al-Kaʿbī cannot be
accepted without contradicting what is known about the limits of al-Kaʿbī’s
toleration of consensus and the sunna, and the limits he put on the Qurʾān as
the basis for theological knowledge. Furthermore, al-Mufīd, who associ-
ated the majority of Baghdadis with other groups (such as the Zaydīs, Murjiʾīs,
and the ahl al-ḥadīth), gives no details on what scripture meant for the
Baghdadis when they accepted scripture as a source for knowing the attri-
butes. Al-Kaʿbī’s scripturalism, as attested by al-Jishumī and the Maqālāt
al-islāmiyyīn, invites parallels between him and the ahl al-sunna. But
al-Baghdādī’s claim that al-Kaʿbī’s position on scripture for knowing God’s
names is equal to that of the ahl al-sunna is ultimately misleading, as it entails
many contradictions of al-Kaʿbīʼs theological commitments that are known to
us with certainty.
For al-Kaʿbī, the ears and eyes were only media (wasāʾiṭ) that mediated the
production of objects of knowledge; they did not apprehend the end result of
their toil. Their products—what al-Kaʿbī refers to as the objects of seeing and
hearing—are seated in the heart and in reason. This description of knowledge
implies that both a nal seat and a medium of production are required, and
that these two are distinct from one other.
Once he had established the distinction between the medium and the seat for
the production of knowledge, al-Kaʿbī provided a more speci c account of the
mechanism of human knowledge, in order to preface its distinction from divine
knowledge. A human being is in need of the speci c medium of hearing and see-
ing to attain the object of knowledge, even when that object can only be appre-
hended by reason and the heart. “Because knowledge is not realized (yaḥṣulu
lahu) for the human being except by means of his sight, the latter was labeled a
[separate] sense (ḥāssa). Otherwise, the perceiver (al-mudrik) is the knower
(al-ʿālim) and his perception is not additional to his knowledge.” Just as hearing
and seeing are media (wasāʾiṭ) for attaining knowledge, there are also other
media for attaining knowledge. These media do not, however, a fect the quality of
knowledge, which a knowing person would nd in himself (yajiduhu fī nafsihi).
The proof for this [that di ferent media of knowledge do not a fect the
nal result of knowledge] is that whoever knows something by means of
a report then sees it with the eyes discovers a di ferentiation (tafriqa)
between the two states [yielded by the two media of knowledge]. Except
that this di ferentiation is not one of class (jins) or species (nawʿ) but
rather one between the general (jumla) and the speci c (tafṣīl), univer-
sality (ʿumūm) and particularity (khuṣūṣ), and the absolute (iṭlāq) and
concrete particular (taʿyīn). Otherwise the state of the soul (nafs) is iden-
tical in both cases (ḥālatayn).
Knowledge remains the same even when the medium is di ferent; it consists of
the same class (jins) or species (nawʿ) regardless of its medium. There are,
Ibid.
Ibid.
Ibid.
however, quantitative di ferences in knowledge generated by di fering media.
These non-qualitative di ferences pertain to the order of the general versus the
speci c. An example of this is transmitted knowledge yielded by a report: this
was deemed equal to knowledge yielded by other media in what pertained to
class, but not in what pertained to the general and the speci c.
Al-Shahrastānī noted another of al-Kaʿbīʼs arguments in support of the
independence of the object of knowledge from the medium of hearing and
seeing. Al-Kaʿbī argued that if objects of hearing and seeing result from the
existence of hearing and seeing as independent attributes, an illogical result
would ensue. This illogical result would be that each time a person knows
something—in other words each time knowledge is produced—what was
simply an instrument of this knowledge would have to be produced along with
the knowledge itself. Because the medium of the production of an object of
knowledge was not always present with its object, al-Kaʿbī concluded that
hearing and seeing did not really exist; they were just media of knowledge.
[Al-Kaʿbī added] that should the perceiver perceive with perception [i.e.,
not with knowledge as al-Kaʿbī upheld] a musical instrument being
played, freely moving animals, drummed drums, and blown (tunfakh)
images would have to be present by means of an intact sense (al-ḥāssa
al-salīma) in the perceiver, but [we know that] he [the perceiver] does
not see them or hear them, for God did not create these perceptions for
him. In the same way, [should the perceiver perceive with perception],
it would have been possible [for the perceiver] to see a person in the dis-
tance and not see someone who is close because the perception of
distance was created for him while [the creation of the close person] was
not. We already know by necessity (ʿalimnā ḍarūratan) that the truth of
the matter (amr) is contrary to this [hypothesis].
This passage invokes the idea that knowledge can be attained by di ferent
means, and this supports al-Kaʿbī’s position that Godʼs hearing and seeing are
means of knowledge, and not separate attributes. Moreover, this view that
knowledge can be attained by di ferent means is a central tenet of al-Kaʿbī’s
epistemology, and led him to tolerate imitation (taqlīd) as a means for attain-
ing knowledge.
Ibid.
Ibid., 344.
See Chapter 4.
Divine Volition
Al-Kaʿbī adopted al-Naẓẓām’s view that God has no volition in reality, that His
volition means His act and His command of His servant’s act. Yet, the premise
that God’s volition is His knowledge (and is sometimes described as from eter-
nity) is a late addition and thus a late Ashʿarī reception and interpretation of
al-Kaʿbī’s original article.
Al-Shahrastānī argued against this alleged position of al-Kaʿbī as follows:
Since al-Kaʿbī and al-Naẓẓām conceded that volition was a class of accidents
(jins min al-aʿrāḍ) based on the speci cation (ikhtiṣāṣ) of one act in distinction
from another in the seen world (fī l-shāhid), the same distinction should follow
for the unseen world (al-ghāʾib). Al-Kaʿbī hypothetically responded by
explaining that volition is necessary for humans because of the limitations of
human knowledge and power. This is how al-Kaʿbī is cited as describing the
function of volition in the human agent.
In the seen world (shāhid) speci cation (ihktiṣāṣ) is proof for [the exis-
tence of] volition because the agent’s (fāʿil) knowledge neither encom-
passes all the aspects (wujūh) of the act, nor the objects that are unseen,
nor the time (waqt) and amount (miqdār), hence he [the agent] is in
need of intent (qaṣd) and determination (ʿazm) in order to specify [the
choice of] one time (waqt) rather than another, and [one] amount
(miqdār) rather than another.
The elements that are necessary for the realization of an act by a human agent
are speci cation, intent, determination, and the choice of one moment in
time. These same elements have no place for an act of God. This is because His
knowledge and power renders these faculties unnecessary.
This is based on the Ashʿarī principle guiding the relationship between the world of the
seen (shāhid) and the world of the unseen (ghāʾib) (al-Shahrastānī, Kitāb Nihāyat
al-iqdām, 239).
Ibid.
need] for intent (qaṣd) and volition... Thus it is established (taʿayyana)
that the Eternalʼs volition, He is exalted, has no meaning except His
being knowing, powerful, and being an agent ( fāʿilan).
The rst assumption of al-Kaʿbī’s argument in favor of this position is that voli-
tion in the seen world requires intent for speci cation. The second assumption
is that God’s knowledge, by its very nature, makes this intent super uous, since
His knowledge already includes speci cation of time, form, and power. The
premise of the argument rests on the proposition that what God knows exists
by necessity. But how this assumption was justi ed and what its implications
were for al-Kaʿbī’s corollary view that “God’s volition is His knowledge, power,
and act” remain open questions.
Al-Shahrastānī pointed to al-Kaʿbī’s cosmology as the reason for his stance
on the attribute of volition. When al-Shahrastānī repudiated the broadly held
Muʿtazilī position on the attributes, he accused al-Kaʿbī of following the propo-
nents of the doctrine of nature and of denying God’s freedom of choice: “There
is no reason to deny volition as al-Kaʿbī did. He deemed it necessary (li-annahu
yūjib) for the compulsory acts (al-afʿāl ghayr [al-]ikhtiyāriyya) to be similar
(shabīha) to natural acts (al-afʿāl al-ṭabīʿiyya) according to the proponents of
the doctrine of nature (ahl al-ṭabāʾiʿ).”
Al-Shahrastānī does not, however, explain how al-Kaʿbī’s doctrine of nature
in uenced his conception of compulsory actions. This absence of explanation
does not necessarily imply that al-Shahrastānī was merely alluding to the doc-
trine of nature with polemical intent. Indeed, when al-Māturīdī spoke of
al-Kaʿbī’s position on God’s choice in His act as equal to what is naturally deter-
mined (maṭbūʿ) even he alluded to the in uence of the doctrine of nature.
Al-Māturīdī’s discussion, however, remains brief and requires further elucida-
tion before it can be taken as corroborating evidence for al-Shahrastānī’s
statement.
…
Al-Kaʿbī maintained the earlier Muʿtazilī distinction between the attributes of
essence and act. Unlike al-Jubbāʾī and, to a degree like al-Naẓẓām, he saw
The text that records this additional argument attributed to al-Kaʿbī contains many cor-
ruptions and is not fully legible (ibid., 240).
Ibid. [emphasis added].
Ibid., 245.
“God’s acts are by choice because the acts of whatever is naturally disposed (maṭbūʿ) are
one species (nawʿ) only” (al-Māturīdī, Kitāb al-Tawḥīd, 92).
scripture as the only source by which to identify the attributes of God. Following
al-Iskāfī, he understood God’s hearing and seeing, sometimes described as His
perception, to be His knowledge. Following al-Naẓẓām, he deemed God’s voli-
tion to be nothing other than His own act and His command of His servants’
acts. Al-Kaʿbīʼs continuation of earlier views on the attributes, views that his
Basran counterparts rejected, is evidenced in the case of the scriptural basis of
knowing the attributes, and the formulation of the attribute of essence as “by
His essence” (bi- or fī nafsihi) rather than “because of His essence” (li-nafsihi) as
al-Jubbāʾī thought.
One historiographical question, with historical implications, emerges from
these conclusions. Why do the sources single out al-Kaʿbī so emphatically for
doctrines that he did not originate? Do sources associate him with these doc-
trines only because it is convenient: he was the latest representative of these
earlier views? Or did he utilize a new methodology with which he reformulated
them. Based on the evidence examined here I cannot o fer a conclusive answer
to these questions. In the case of his de nition of the attribute of essence, the
likelihood that it was based on his particular ontology is credible but not con-
clusive. The evidence for his de nition of the attribute of essence is found in
al-Māturīdīʼs work. Although there is nothing to contradict this evidence, fur-
ther perspective is needed to contextualize it. Furthermore, al-Shahrastānī
noted the role of al-Kaʿbī’s epistemology in support of his equating the attri-
butes of hearing and seeing with the attribute of knowledge. Al-Shahrastānī
also recounted arguments derived from al-Kaʿbī’s cosmology and epistemology
in support of the latter’s understanding of divine volition. The problem with
al-Shahrastānī’s statement in the case of the attributes of hearing and seeing is
that it is combined with the allegation that al-Kaʿbī initiated this view, when it
was originated by al-Iskāfī. As for al-Shahrastānīʼs statement about al-Kaʿbī’s
reasoning on the attribute of volition, it is harder to accept this without reser-
vation because it is tied to an element that is not corroborated by the majority
of the sources. This uncorroborated element is the claim that al-Kaʿbī under-
stood divine volition to be divine knowledge, a claim that was prevalent in late
Ashʿarī sources and Sunnī biographical dictionaries as well.
Thus, while al-Kaʿbī did not innovate in his formulation of the doctrines of the
attributes, there is preliminary yet signi cant evidence that he sought to re ne
these earlier positions with advances he made in cosmology and epistemology.