Homosexuality and The Constitution
Homosexuality and The Constitution
Homosexuality and The Constitution
Winter 1994
Part of the Civil Rights and Discrimination Commons, and the Sexuality and the Law Commons
Recommended Citation
Sunstein, Cass R. (1994) "Homosexuality and the Constitution," Indiana Law Journal: Vol. 70: Iss. 1, Article
1.
Available at: https://www.repository.law.indiana.edu/ilj/vol70/iss1/1
INTRODUCTION
sensitive an area. I therefore argue for the narrowest and most incremental of
the judicial possibilities. In all likelihood, laws against homosexual orientation
and behavior will soon come to be seen as products of unfounded prejudice
and hostility, and private prejudice and hostility will themselves recede.
Courts should play a limited if perhaps catalytic role in this process.
This Article consists of three parts. Part I discusses a wide range of
constitutional claims in the context of homosexuality. Part II sets out an
anticaste principle, designed to help explain why and when sex discrimination
is constitutionally illegitimate. I spend a fair amount of space on the
appropriate conception of sex discrimination. This subject is both of
considerable interest in its own right and of great importance to an under-
standing of the issue of sexual orientation. Part III then connects the legal
attack on gender caste with the issue of same-sex relations. Here, I explore
the possibility that bans on same-sex relations are a form of sex discrimina-
tion and therefore constitutionally unacceptable. Part IV discusses the properly
limited role of courts under the Constitution and indicates how judicial
limitations might bear on the judicial role with respect to laws that disadvan-
tage homosexuals. It also suggests that these limitations apply, though to a
lesser degree, to the President and all others charged with constitutional
interpretation.
My conclusion is that it is important both to have a firm sense of the
constitutional principle that dooms discrimination on the basis of sexual
orientation, and to insist on that principle. But in the implementation of the
principle, it is necessary for courts to be cautious and selective. Caution about
issues of implementation should not be taken to suggest ambivalence about
the principle itself. Abraham Lincoln's approach to the issue of slavery
provides a model in this regard.
I. CONSTITUTIONAL POSSIBILITIES
A. Privacy
1. Equality in General
4. See Cass R. Sunstein, Sexual Orientationand the Constitution: A Note on the Relationship
Between Due Process and Equal Protection, 55 U. C. L. REv. 1161, 1170-74 (1988).
5. Id. at 1170.
6. See id at 1174-75.
7. There is some dispute, however, about the depth and length of the roots. See generallyJOHN
BoswELL, CHRISrIANITY, SOCIAL TOLERANCE AND SExUALITY (1980); JOHN BOSWELT, SAME-SEX
UNIONS IN PREMODERN EUROPE (1994); K.J. DOVER, GREEK HOMOSEXUALITY, (Harv. Univ. Press
1989) (1978).
INDIANA LAWJOURNAL [Vol. 70:1
Under the Equal Protection Clause, the Supreme Court has invalidated
certain forms of discrimination on the ground that they are irrational or
unconnected with any legitimate public purpose. 8 This idea is connected with
an interesting conception of democracy: the distribution of benefits or the
imposition of burdens must reflect a conception of the public good. The Court
has also disqualified, as justifications of legislation, certain ideas on the
ground that they reflect "prejudice" or "hostility." A statute based on
"prejudice" cannot qualify as rational.9
We should think of the category of "prejudice" as a placeholder for a
complex moral argument; the term is usually a conclusion masquerading as
an analytic device. But in some important cases, lower federal courts have
said that discrimination on the basis of sexual orientation can indeed be
irrational because it is a simple product of prejudice or irrational fear. Thus,
for example, some courts have said that the exclusion from the military of
people with homosexual "orientation"-unaccompanied by homosexual
acts-is irrational and therefore unconstitutional under the Equal Protection
Clause. '
In the important ruling in Steffan v. Aspin," the Court of Appeals for the
District of Columbia Circuit held that it was irrational to exclude from
military service people of homosexual orientation, short of a demonstration
of homosexual conduct. In the court's view, homosexual orientation alone was
not a legitimate basis for discharge because it was unconnected with any
plausible government interest. The court did not address the question whether
homosexual conduct could be a basis for discharge. Two district courts
reached the same conclusion, finding exclusion from the military to be
unconnected with any legitimate public goal."
These cases represent an unusual step in the law. The legislature is usually
given the benefit of every doubt against claims of irrationality because judges
lack factfinding capacity and a democratic pedigree."3 Moreover, discrimina-
tion on the basis of sexual orientation is based on widespread moral
convictions and debated empirical claims. Some people think that homosexual
conduct is immoral, though it is not clear what status this argument should
have. Others think that sexual orientation is often chosen, not a product of
genetics or early family influence, and that the state can therefore channel
people toward heterosexuality.
In part because of its modesty, the use of rationality review is quite
promising, even if it is inventive. I cannot fully resolve the rationality issue
here but must restrict myself to three notes. First, the Supreme Court has been
8. See, e.g., Cleburne v. Cleburne Living Ctr., 473 U.S. 432, 440 (1985).
9. See id. at 450.
10. E.g., Steffan v. Aspin, 8 F.3d 57, 70 (D.C. Cir. 1993), vacated, 1994 U.S. App. LEXIS 9977
(D.C. Cir. Jan. 7, 1994); Dahl v. Secretary of the United States Navy, 830 F. Supp. 1319, 1337 (E.D.
Cal. 1993); Meinhold v. United States Dep't of Defense, 808 F. Supp. 1453, 1455 (C.D. Cal. 1993).
11. Steffan, 8 F.3d 57.
12. Dahl, 830 F. Supp. 1319; Meinhold, 808 F. Supp. 1453.
13. See Dahl, 830 F. Supp. at 1326.
1994] HOMOSEXUALITY AND THE CONSTITUTION
14. Steffan was probably an egregious case since it involved orientation alone.
INDIANA LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 70:1
15. See THOMAS J. PHILIPPSON & RICHARD A. POSNER, PRIVATE CHOICES, PUBLIC HEALTH 150
(1993).
16. Bowers, 478 U.S. 186, 196 (1986).
19941 HOMOSEXUALITY AND THE CONSTITUTION
17. 759 F. Supp. 1543, 1551 (D. Kan. 1991), rev d on other grounds, 976 F.2d 623 (10th Cir.
1992).
18. Watkins v. United States Army, 847 F.2d 1329, 1349 (9th Cir. 1988), withdrawn, 875 F.2d 699
(9th Cir. 1989), cert. denied, 498 U.S. 957 (1990).
19. See, e.g., City of Richmond v. J.A. Croson, Co., 488 U.S. 469 (1989); Cleburne v. Cleburne
Living Ctr., 473 U.S. 432, 440 (1985); Craig v. Boren, 429 U.S. 190 (1976).
20. See Cleburne, 473 U.S. at 442-45.
21. See, e.g., Cleburne, 473 U.S. at 440 (mentally retarded persons), Jimenez v. Weinberger, 417
U.S. 628 (1974) (illegitimate children); Frontiero v. Richardson, 411 U.S. 677 (1973) (women); Graham
v. Richardson, 403 U.S. 365 (1971) (aliens).
INDIANA LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 70:1
It seems clear too, that homosexuals have been and continue to be subject
to public and private discrimination. For most of American history, disclosure
of a homosexual orientation was grounds for inflicting serious social harms.
Even today, homosexuals must often keep their orientation secret in order to
be free from discrimination and even violence. In many sectors of the
economy, homosexuals cannot easily obtain jobs if their sexual orientation is
disclosed.22
Homosexuals may well be politically powerless in the constitutionally
relevant sense. They often have difficulty in making alliances with other
groups by virtue of the existence of widespread prejudice and hostility
directed against them. Precisely because they are often anonymous (that is,
not known to be homosexual) and diffuse (that is, not tightly organized), they
face large barriers to exerting adequate political influence.23 For this reason,
it is probably not decisive that homosexuality-unlike race and gender-can
be concealed. The ability to conceal can actually make things worse from the
standpoint of exercising political power. This problem, severe in itself, is
heightened by the fact that people who challenge discrimination on the basis
of sexual orientation are often "accused" of being homosexual themselves,
which may have harmful consequences for their reputations.24 The existence
of widespread hostility against homosexuals can thus make it difficult for
homosexuals and heterosexuals alike to speak out against this form of
discrimination.
All of these arguments seem to fit both the facts and the law, but there are
some real complexities here. One problem with the issue of "political
powerlessness" is that relevant judgments are based not simply on facts about
political influence, but also depend on some controversial and usually
unarticulated claims about how much political power is appropriate for the
group in question, and about the legitimacy of the usual bases for legislative
judgments on matters affecting the group. The claim that a group is politically
weak in the constitutional test is thus a product of some controversial, value-
laden claims, which are not always brought to the surface.
For example, it might be thought that homosexuals have a good deal of
political power, for they can influence elections, even elections of the
President. But the same is true of blacks and women, both of whom can
influence elections a great deal. The potentially large electoral influence of
both of these groups does not exclude them from the category of groups
entitled to particular protection against discrimination. The reason is that even
if political influence can be wielded, prejudice in the constitutionally relevant
sense is likely to operate in the political process against both blacks and
22. See LESBIANS, GAY MEN, AND THE LAW, 243-48 (William B. Rubenstein ed., 1993).
23. See Bruce A. Ackerman, Beyond CaroleneProducts, 98 HARV. L. REV. 713, 729-30 (1985).
24. I know of no study of this phenomenon, but substantial evidence suggests that it is widespread.
Consider the fact that there has been serious debate over whether "marching in a gay parade" should
be taken as evidence of homosexuality. See 139 CoNG. REC. S6691, S6692 (daily ed. May 27, 1993)
(remarks of Sen. Nunn) (regarding Representative Frank's proposal concerning gay men and women in
the armed forces); id. at S11211 (daily ed. Sept. 9, 1993) (committee report).
1994] HOMOSEXUALITY AND THE CONSTITUTION
it is not clear that it would be too broad. In fact, the Colorado Supreme Court
relied on a United States Supreme Court case suggesting that special barriers
are permissible when an "identifiable group" is not involved.33 Perhaps we
can read "identifiable group" to include not simply blacks but any group
defined in terms of some characteristic that is not ordinarily a legitimate basis
for the allocation of political authority. Perhaps the Court could say that,
without reaching the question of whether discrimination against homosexuals
is suspect and without saying that such discrimination is generally irrational,
it will require powerful justifications for any law that imposes special
democratic barriers to legislation protecting homosexuals from discrimina-
tion.34
This is not a simple test; it remains to say exactly what sorts of democratic
barriers are constitutionally suspect. But the test would have the beneficial
characteristic of narrowness. Without deciding that discrimination on the basis
of sexual orientation is generally suspect, or generally irrational, courts might
well conclude that no state may impose special barriers to democratic
deliberation about this subject. I suggest that though the precedents do not
require this result, the Equal Protection Clause should forbid special
constitutional barriers to laws that prohibit discrimination on the basis of
sexual orientation.
33. Evans, 854 P.2d at 1282 (citing Gordon v. Lance, 403 U.S. 1, 7 (1981)).
34. Cf Plyler v. Doe, 457 U.S. 202 (1982) (finding that Texas' reasons for controlling resources
were not substantial enough to sustain a law that would harm illegal aliens).
35. Bowers v. Hardwick, 478 U.S. 186, 197 (1986) (Burger, CJ., concurring) (quoting 4 WILLIAM
BLAcKsToNE, CoMMENTAmiEs *215).
36. 388 U.S. 1 (1967).
INDIANA LAWJOURNAL [Vol. 70:1
to say this is to get a bit ahead of the story. Let me turn more generally, then,
to the equality principle of the Fourteenth Amendment.
A. In General
At the origin, the central target of the Fourteenth Amendment was not
irrational distinctions on the basis of race, but the system of racial caste."7
For those who ratified the Civil War Amendments, the problem was that the
law had contributed to a system of caste based on race, thought to be a
morally irrelevant characteristic. Those who framed and ratified these
amendments were aware that the system of racial hierarchy had often been
attributed to nature. Thus, in the aftermath of the American Civil War, it was
expressly urged, "God himself has set His seal of distinctive difference
between the two races, and no human legislation can overrule the Divine
decree."3" In the same period, anti-discrimination law was thus challenged
squarely on the ground that it put the two races in "unnaturalrelation ... to
each other." 9 The Civil War Amendments were based on a wholesale
rejection of the supposed naturalness of racial hierarchy. The hierarchy was
thought to be a function not of natural difference but of law, most notably the
law of slavery and the various measures that grew up in the aftermath of
abolition. The animating purpose of the Civil War Amendments was an attack
on racial caste.
We might similarly understand the problem of sex discrimination, to the
extent that it is troublesome, as amounting to the creation of something like
a system of caste, based on gender and often operating through law. That
system, like the racial caste system and others as well, is often attributed to
"nature" and "natural differences." Consider here John Stuart Mill's remarks:
But was there any domination which did not appear natural to those who
possessed it? ... So true is it that unnatural generally means only
uncustomary, and that everything which is usual appears natural. The
subjection of women to men being a universal custom, any departure from
it quite naturally appears unnatural.4"
37. See Akhil R, Amar, The Case of the Missing Amendments: LA.V. v. City of St. Paul, 106
HARV. L. REv. 124 (1992).
38. 2 CONG. REC. app. 3 (1874) (statement of Rep. Southard).
39. 3 CONG. REc. 983 (1875) (statement of Rep. Eldredge) (emphasis in original).
40. JOHN STUART MILL, THE SUBJECTION OF WOMEN, 13-14 (MIT Press 1970) (1869).
Compare this description of attitudes in prerevolutionary America:
So distinctive and so separated was the aristocracy from ordinary folk that many still thought
the two groups represented two orders of being.... Ordinary people were thought to be
different physically, and because of varying diets and living conditions, no doubt in many cases
they were different. People often assumed that a handsome child, though apparently a
commoner, had to be some gentleman's bastard offspring.
GORDON S. WOOD, THE RADICALISM OF THE AMERICAN REVOLUTION 27 (1991).
1994] HOMOSEXUALITY AND THE CONSTITUTION
A principal feature of the caste system based on gender consists of law and
social practices that translate women's sexual and reproductive capacities into
a source of second-class citizenship.
In these circumstances, I suggest that building on the racial analogue, the
appropriate equality principle in the area of sex equality is an opposition to
caste. The legal objection should be understood as an effort to eliminate, in
places large and small, the caste system rooted in gender. A law is therefore
objectionable on grounds of sex equality if it contributes to a caste system in
this way. The controlling principle to be vindicated through law is not that
women must be treated "the same" as men, but that women must not be
second-class citizens. As discussed below, there are important differences
between the two points.
The concept of caste is by no means self-defining. I will have to offer a
brief and inadequate account here, one that is designed to provide a preface
to the discussion of discrimination on the basis of sexual orientation." Of
course, I do not suggest that the caste-like features of all societies containing
sex inequality are the same. Certainly the American system of sex discrimina-
tion is far less oppressive than most systems of racial and gender caste. But
I do claim that the caste-like features are what justify social and legal
concern.
The motivating idea behind an anticaste principle, broadly speaking
Rawlsian in character, is that without very good reasons, social and legal
structures ought not to turn differences that are irrelevant from the moral
point of view into social disadvantages. They certainly should not be
permitted to do so if the disadvantage is systemic. A difference is morally
irrelevant if it has no relationship to individual entitlement or desert. Race and
sex are certainly morally irrelevant characteristics in the sense that, in general,
skin color and gender are not appropriate grounds for the distribution of social
benefits and burdens. A systemic disadvantage is one that operates along
standard and predictable lines in many important spheres of life and applies
in realms that relate to basic participation as a citizen in a democracy. The
anticaste principle means that, with respect to basic human capabilities and
functionings, one group ought not to be systematically below another.42
Self-respect and its social bases ought not to be distributed along the lines
of race and gender. 43 An important aspect of a system of caste is that social
practices produce a range of obstacles to the development of self-respect,
41. See generally CASS P- SUNSTEIN, THE PARTIAL CONSTITUTION ch. 11 (1993) [hereinafter
SUNsTEN, PARTIAL CONSTITUTION]; Cass R. Sunstein, The Anticaste Principle,92 MICH. L. REv. 2410
(1994).
42. On capabilities and functioning, see generally AMARTYA SEN, COMMODITIES AND CAPABILITIES
(1985); AMARTYA SEN, INEQUALITY REEXAMINED (1992); Martha Nussbaum, Aristotelian Social
Democracy,in LIBERALISM AND THE GOOD 203 (R. Bruce Douglass et al. eds., 1990). I am adding to
these discussions (1) a suggestion that in the context of gender, the problem lies in the particular fact
that one group is systematically below another along the relevant dimensions, and (2) an explanation
of how this situation is produced by social practices and law.
43. See JOHN RAWLS, POLITICAL LIBERALISM 82, 180 (1993).
INDIANA LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 70:1
44. See generally JONI SEAGER & ANN OLSON, WOMEN IN THE WORLD: AN INTERNATIONAL ATLAS
(1986); DEBBIE TAYLOR ET AL., WOMEN: A WORLD REPORT (1985).
45. For a recent example, see RICHARD A. EPSTEIN, FORBIDDEN GROuNDS 269-82 (1992).
46. On how these questions are at work in American law, see generally CATHARINE A.
MACKINNON, FEMINISM UNMODIFIED (1987) [hereinafter MAcKiNNON, FEMINISM UNMODIFIED];
CATHARINE A. MAcKINNON, TOWARD A FEMINIST THEORY OF THE STATE (1989) [hereinafter
MACKINNON, TOWARD A FEMINIST THEORY OF THE STATE].
1994] HOMOSEXUALITY AND THE CONSTITUTION
social, these practices might be altered even if the differences remain. In any
case, inequality is not justified by the brute fact of difference.
An analogy may be helpful here. The problems faced by disabled people are
not a function of disability "alone" (an almost impenetrable idea-what would
current disabilities even mean in an entirely different world?) but instead
result from the interaction between physical and mental capacities on the one
hand and a set of human obstacles made by and for the able-bodied on the
other. It is those obstacles, rather than the capacities taken as brute facts, that
create a large part of what it means, socially speaking, to be disabled.
"Nature" is quite irrelevant. It would be implausible, for example, to defend
the construction of a building with stairs, and without means of access for
those in wheelchairs, on the ground that those who need wheelchairs are
"different." The question is whether it is acceptable, or just, to construct a
building that excludes people who need another means of entry. That question
may not be a simple one, but it cannot be answered simply by pointing to a
difference. The same is true for sex.
We can go further. Differences between men and women-especially those
involving sexuality and reproduction-are often said to explain sex inequality,
indeed to be the origin of inequality. But it might be better to think that at
least some such differences are an outcome of inequality or its product.47
Certainly some and perhaps many of the relevant "real differences" between
men and women exist only because of sex inequality. Differences in physical
strength, for example, would certainly exist without inequality, but such
differences as there now are undoubtedly have a good deal to do with
differences in expectations, nutrition, and training. These differences cannot
solely be attributed to women's sexual and reproductive capacities. Indeed, the
degree of difference between men and women is notoriously variable across
time and space. These variations are sufficient to show that what society
attributes to nature is often a social product.
Even differences in desires, preferences, aspirations, and values are in
significant part a function of society and even law-in particular of what
these institutions do with sexuality and reproduction. Preferences are often
adaptive to the status quo, and a status quo containing caste-like features
based on sex will predictably affect the preferences of men and women in
different ways. It will lead to distinctive processes of preference formation,
inclining men and women in different directions in both the public and private
spheres.
This point suggests that it is wrong to base sex discrimination policy only
on what women currently "want."48 Existing preferences may well be at least
47. See MAcKINqON, FEMINISM UNMODIFIED, supra note 46, at 32-45. 1 phrase the point tentatively
because ultimately this is a historical question on which there is now insufficient evidence for firm
judgments.
48. In the context of sex discrimination, see MILL, supranote 40, and MARY WOLSTONECRAFT, A
VINDICAnON OF THE RIGHTS OF WOMAN, (Carol H. Poston ed., 1975). See generally Martha Craven
Nussbaum, Shame, Separateness,and PoliticalUnity, in ESSAYS ON ARISTOTLE'S ETHICS 395 (Am61ia
Oksenberg Rorty ed., 1980); Amartya Sen, Rational Fools, 6 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 317 (1977); Cass R.
Sunstein, Preferences and Politics, 20 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 3 (1991).
INDIANA LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 70:1
A. A True Story"
In 1958, Richard Loving, a white man, and Mildred Jeter, a black woman,
were married in the District of Columbia.52 Soon thereafter, they returned to
their home in Virginia and were promptly indicted. Their crime was to have
married in violation of Virginia's prohibition on interracial marriage. They
pleaded guilty to the charge and were sentenced to a year in jail. The trial
judge suspended the sentence on the condition that the Lovings leave Virginia
and not return for twenty-five years. The judge said: "Almighty God creates
the races white, black, yellow, malay and red, and he placed them on separate
49. See generally Andrew Koppelman, The Miscegenation Analogy, 98 YALE L.J. 145 (1988);
Sylvia A. Law, Homosexuality and the Social Meaning of Gender, 1988 WIs. L REV. 187; Adrienne
Rich, Compulsory Heterosexualityand Lesbian Existence, in BLOOD, BREAD, AND POETRY 23 (1986).
50. See discussion infra part HLA.
51. See Koppelman, supra note 49.
52. The idea that there is an analogy between the Loving case and cases involving the ban on same-
sex relations has been well-discussed elsewhere. Versions of the argument are made in Koppelman,
supra note 49 and Law, supra note 49. I am much indebted to those treatments here.
1994] HOMOSEXUALITY AND THE CONSTITUTION
continents. And but for the interference with his arrangement there would be
no cause for such marriages. The fact that 53
he separated the races shows that
he did not intend for the races to mix.
The Lovings challenged the anti-miscegenation law on constitutional
grounds, claiming that the law deprived them of the "equal protection of the
laws. 54 Thus was born the most aptly titled case in the entire history of
American law, Loving v. Virginia.
The legal issues before the United States Supreme Court in Loving were
relatively straightforward. In 1954, the Court had decided Brown v. Board of
Education." There, the Court emphasized that racial discrimination is
56
constitutionally unacceptable and that "separate but equal" is not equal.
The Brown Court held that under the Constitution, the government could not
discriminate against blacks. This was the issue in Loving: Was the ban on
racial intermarriage a form of discrimination in the relevant sense?57 On this
question, there was sharp dispute. Virginia thought that the answer was
"Clearly not."
Virginia's lawyers argued that anti-miscegenation laws punished whites and
blacks equally. They claimed that there was no discrimination against blacks.
The only relevant discrimination was against people who sought to participate
in mixed marriages, and such people were racially diverse. Unlike in Brown,
where racial separation marked racial inequality, here separation was truly
equal. Discrimination against people who seek to participate in mixed
marriages is not "racial discrimination" at all. It does not draw a line between
blacks and whites. It is a form of discrimination to be sure-but not the form
that justifies special judicial skepticism under the Constitution. Because blacks
and whites were treated exactly alike, that kind of skepticism was unwar-
ranted.
From the standpoint of the 1990's, the argument may seem odd, even
otherworldly. But if we linger over it, we will see that its logic is straight-
forward and even plausible. It is true that in an important way, laws
forbidding interracial marriages treat blacks and whites alike. How did the
Supreme Court respond? The key sentence in Loving says that "the racial
classifications [at issue] must stand on their own justification, as measures
designed to maintain White Supremacy."5 8 This striking reference to White
Supremacy-by a unanimous Court, capitalizing both words and speaking in
these terms for the only time in the nation's history-was designed to get at
B. A Hypothetical Story
Now let us imagine a hypothetical case. Two women seek to marry. They
are prevented from doing so by a law forbidding same-sex marriage. They
argue first that the relevant law violates their right to be free from sex
discrimination. This seems to be a good strategic choice on their part. It is of
course well-established that laws discriminating on the basis of sex will be
subject to careful judicial scrutiny and will generally be invalidated.59 By
contrast, it also seems clear-at least for the time being-that laws discrimi-
nating on the basis of sexual orientation will be subject to deferential judicial
scrutiny and will generally be validated.60
Our hypothetical couple would therefore do very well to argue that they are
subject to discrimination on the basis of sex, not sexual orientation. They
might try to establish this argument by saying what seems clearly true, that
if one of them were a man, there would be no barrier to the marriage. The
law therefore seems to contain explicit discrimination on the basis of sex. It
treats one person differently from another simply because of gender. It is
therefore a form of sex discrimination.
This argument appears straightforward. Laws forbidding same-sex relations
do involve an explicit gender classification. Under current law, however, the
argument gets nowhere. 6' The prohibition on same-sex marriage, it is said,
59. See, e.g., Mississippi Univ. for Women v. Hogan, 458 U.S. 718, 723-27 (1982).
60. The Court has not yet resolved this issue, however. Lower courts generally, though not
unanimously, apply "rational basis" review of laws discriminating on the basis of sexual orientation.
61. This is true at least at the federal level. With respect to application of the argument at the state
level, see Baehr v. Lewin, 852 P.2d 144 (Haw. 1993).
1994] HOMOSEXUALITY AND THE CONSTITUTION
discriminates on the basis of sexual orientation rather than on the basis of sex.
There is no sex discrimination because women and men are treated exactly the
same. If a man wants to marry a man, he is barred; a woman seeking to marry
a woman is barred in precisely the same way. For this reason, women and
men are not treated differently. From this we see that the complaint in our
hypothetical case is really about discrimination on the basis of sexual
orientation, not about discrimination on the basis of sex. To the extent that
discrimination on the basis of sexual orientation is subject to highly
deferential "rational basis" review, resulting in the validation of most
classifications, the barrier to same-sex marriages and relations is constitution-
ally acceptable.
This is indeed the answer offered by current constitutional law. Thus
concluded the Supreme Court of Missouri as against an argument of this kind.
According to the court:
The State concedes that the statute prohibits men from doing what women
may do, namely, engage in sexual activity with men. However, the State
argues that it likewise prohibits women from doing something which men
can do: engage in sexual activity with women. We believe it applies
equally to men and women because it prohibits both classes from engaging
in sexual activity with members of their own sex. Thus, there is no denial
of equal protection on that basis.62
It will readily appear that this response is the same answer offered by the
State of Virginia in the Loving case.63 To the extent that Loving is now
believed inapposite, it is because a law forbidding racial intermarriage is now
seen as an effort to promote White Supremacy. The separation of the races,
especially in matters of sexuality and marriage, was part and parcel of the
subordination of blacks to whites. Undoubtedly, this separation was part of the
creation of a fixed category of racial differences. No one really denies this.
It seems clear that if racial mixing were common, no one would know who
is black and white; indeed the categories would lose much of their meaning.
(It even seems reasonably clear that issues of sex discrimination are at work
in this context, since the availability of black women to white men was
common, and since the miscegenation laws seem especially inspired by the
effort to prevent black men from having relations with white women.) The
effort to promote "white purity" was conspicuously intended to prevent the
various results that would come about from racial mixing. The Supreme
Court's reference to "White Supremacy" was thus both necessary and
sufficient to defeat Virginia's argument, and it was readily shown that the
miscegenation laws were connected to that constitutionally unacceptable social
institution."
For participants in the current legal system, it is much harder to say that
bans on same-sex relations are connected to a similarly unacceptable social
62. State v. Walsh, 713 S.W.2d 508, 510 (Mo. 1986) (en banc).
63. See Koppelman, supra note 49, at 149-50.
64. Loving v. Virginia, 388 U.S. 1, 7 (1967).
INDIANA LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 70:1
65. Note also that miscegenation laws attempt to keep blacks and whites apart, while bans on same-
sex relations attempt to keep men and women together. If the argument below is correct, however, this
difference does not make a difference, since the effort to keep blacks and whites apart was an effort to
maintain a caste system based on race, just as the effort to keep men and women together is-by
preventing same-sex relations-part of a system of sex-role stereotyping.
1994] HOMOSEXUALITY AND THE CONSTITUTION
banned because they complicate traditional gender thinking, showing that the
division of human beings into two simple kinds is part of sex-role stereo-
typing, however true it is that women and men are "different."
This is not merely a philosophical or sociological observation. It is highly
relevant to the legal argument. It suggests that, like the ban on racial
intermarriage, the ban on same-sex marriages may well be doomed by a
constitutionally illegitimate purpose. The ban has everything to do with
constitutionally unacceptable stereotypes about the appropriate roles of men
and women.
Moreover, the ban may well have constitutionally unacceptable effects. It
is part of a system of sex-role stereotyping that is damaging to men and
women, heterosexual and homosexual alike, though in quite different ways.
Indeed, one of the most interesting issues has to do with the distinctive ways
in which the ban differentially harms heterosexual men, gay men, heterosexual
women, and lesbians."
In this space, I will not be able fully to defend this thesis, on which much
work remains to be done. Certainly the thesis is not belied by the fact that
some "macho" cultures do not stigmatize male homosexuality as much as
(say) the United States.67 Even in such cultures, a sharp distinction is drawn
between passivity and activity in sexual relations, and cultural understandings
of passive and active operate in gendered terms." Thus, the passive role is
both stigmatized and identified with femininity, whereas the active role is
socially respectable and identified with masculinity. In such cultures, sex-role
distinctions have somewhat different manifestations, but sex discrimination is 69
fully operative in thinking both about men and women and about sexuality.
My claim about the reasons behind the ban on same-sex marriages is in part
an empirical one; and it has suggestive empirical support in psychological
studies. For example, one social psychologist, capturing much of the general
view, finds that "a major determinant of negative attitudes toward homosexu-
ality is the need to keep males masculine and females feminine, that is, to
avoid sex-role confusion. ' 7' The evidence taken as a whole suggests that the
prohibition on homosexual relations is best seen as an effort to insist on and
to rigidify so-called natural difference, in part by crisply separating gender
roles. 71 This occurs largely by ensuring that there are firm and clear lines,
66. Cf Rich, supra note 49 (arguing that anti-lesbian views not only stigmatize lesbians apart from
other homosexuals but harm heterosexual women as well).
67. See RICHARD A. POSNER, SEX AND REASON 291 (1990).
68. Id. at 64-66, 157.
69. Id.
70. Koppelman, supra note 49, at 159 n.86 (citing A.P. MacDonald & Richard G. Games, Some
Characteristicsof Those Who Hold Positive and Negative Attitudes Toward Homosexuals, 1 J.
HOMOSEXUALITY 9, 19 (1974)); see also Marc A. Fajer, Can Two Real Men Eat Quiche Together?
Storytelling Gender-Role Stereotypes, and Legal Protectionfor Lesbians and Gay Men, 46 U. MIAMI
L. REv. 511, 617 (1992); Bernard E. Whitley, Jr., The Relationship of Sex-Role Orientation to
Heterosexuals'Attitudes Toward Homosexuals, 17 SEX ROLES 103 (1987) (examining the relationship
between traditional sex-role beliefs, sex-role self-concept, and sex-role behavior pattern on the one hand
and attitudes toward homosexuals on the other).
71. Koppelman, supra note 49, at 159 n.86.
INDIANA LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 70:1
of course in very different ways and to quite different degrees. The distinction
between the rigid categories "male" and "female," with the accompanying
social and sexual traits "active" and "passive," has especially conspicuous
harmful effects for gay men and lesbians. But for all of us, the categories and
the traits are much too crude to account for social and sexual life when both
of these are going well. For heterosexual women as well, the distinction can
be highly damaging because it is rigidly confining and untrue to the
complexity of their experience, even when their sexual attraction is directed
to men. The damage is closely connected to the castelike features of the
current system of gender relations. For heterosexual men, very much the same
is true since a degree of passivity in society and in sexual relations is both an
inevitable and a desirable part of life, and since it is such an unnecessary
burden to be embarrassed by or ashamed of this.
These are speculative and brisk arguments. They might properly be
questioned on the ground that they depend on social and psychological claims
that are not obviously right, that they require far more support than provided
here, or that they are too uncertain to warrant judicial endorsement. Certainly
I have not provided the full defense that would be needed to translate this
argument into constitutional law. But formal sex inequality is an explicit part
of the ban on same-sex relations, and there is good reason to think that formal
inequality stems from impermissible sex-role stereotyping. While judges
should probably not accept this argument today, it may ultimately be
concluded, outside if not inside the courtroom, that the prohibition on same-
sex relations is a form of discrimination on the basis of sex, just as the
prohibition on miscegenation was a form of discrimination on the basis of
race. Both prohibitions are invalid under the Equal Protection Clause.
Abraham Lincoln always insisted that slavery was wrong. On the basic
principle, Lincoln allowed no compromises. No justification was available for
chattel slavery. But on the question of means, Lincoln was quite equivo-
cal-flexible, strategic, open to compromise, aware of doubt. The fact that
slavery was wrong did not mean that it had to be eliminated immediately, or
that blacks and whites had to be placed immediately on a plane of equality.
In Lincoln's view, the feeling of "the great mass of white people" would not
permit this result.80 In his most striking formulation, he declared: "Whether
this feeling accords with justice and sound judgment, is not the sole question,
if indeed, it is any part of it. A universal feeling, whether well or ill-founded,
can not be safely disregarded.""'
79. See generallyALEXANDER M. BICKEL, TE LEAST DANGEROUS BRANCH 64-68 (1962); HARRY
V. JAFFA, CRISIS OF A HOUSE DIVIDED (1959).
80. BICKEL, supra note 79, at 66 (quoting Abraham Lincoln, speech at Peoria, Illinois (Oct. 16,
1854), in 2 THE COLLECTED WORKS OF ABRAHAM LINCOLN 256 (Roy P. Basler ed., 1953)).
81. Id.
INDIANA LAW JOURNVAL [Vol. 70:1
In the area of sex discrimination, such managerial issues are not necessarily
present. Suppose, for example, that the ban on same-sex marriage is
challenged on equal protection grounds. Here, ongoing judicial supervision of
complex institutions is not really at issue. Nonetheless, there is reason for
great caution on the part of the courts. An immediate judicial vindication of
the principle could well jeopardize important interests. It could galvanize
opposition. It could weaken the anti-discrimination movement itself. It could
provoke more hostility and even violence against gays and lesbians. It could
jeopardize the authority of the judiciary. It could well produce calls for a
constitutional amendment to overturn the Supreme Court's decision.85
At a minimum, courts should generally use their discretion over their
dockets in order to limit the nature and the timing of relevant intrusions into
the political process. Courts should also be reluctant to vindicate even good
principles when the vindication would clearly compromise other important
interests, including ultimately the principles themselves.
Consider, for example, the issue of abortion. Suppose we think that
restrictions on abortion violate the right of privacy or (in an argument more
congenial to that offered here) that such restrictions deny women the right to
equal protection of the laws.86 Is it therefore clear that Roe v. Wade87 was
rightly decided? Surely not. The precipitous vindication of the relevant
principle might well have been a mistake.' Indeed, it is for this reason, and
not because of any supposed abuse of interpretive authority, that Roe may
have been wrong when initially decided.
It seems at least reasonable to think that the Roe decision prematurely
committed the nation to a principle toward which it was in any case steadily
moving, and that the premature judicial decision had a range of harmful
consequences. These included the creation of the Moral Majority, the death
of the Equal Rights Amendment, the galvanizing of general opposition to the
women's movement, the identification of that movement with the single issue
of abortion, the dampening of desirable political activity by women, and the
general transformation of the political landscape in a way deeply damaging
to women's interests. 89 This result suggests that even if discrimination on the
basis of sexual orientation is often a violation of the Equal Protection Clause,
courts should be cautious and selective in vindicating that principle.
In the area of homosexuality, we might make some distinctions. Certain
imaginable rulings would minimally stretch judicial capacities and authority;
other imaginable rulings would pose problems of judicial prudence in their
85. Compare the decision of the Hawaii Supreme Court in Baehr v. Levin, 852 P.2d 144 (Haw.
1993). An advantage of a federal system is that it allows successful experiments in constitutional law
at the state level.
96. See SUNSTEIN, PARTAL CONSrITrION, supra note 41, at 270-85.
87. 410 U.S. 113 (1973).
88. I therefore agree with the controversial remarks on the abortion issue by then-Judge Ginsburg.
See Ruth Bader Ginsburg, Some Thoughts on Autonomy and Equality in Relation to Roe v. Wade, 63
N.C. L REV. 375 (1985).
89. Some of these claims are made in GERALD N. ROSBERo, THE HOLLOW HOPE: CAN COURTS
BRING ABOUT SOCIAL CHANGE? (1992).
INDIANA LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 70:1
most severe form. For example, the argument I have explored here-for the
proposition that same-sex relations and even same-sex marriages may not be
banned consistently with the Equal Protection Clause-is, to say the least,
quite adventurous. If the Supreme Court of the United States accepted the
argument in 1995, or even in 1996 or 1997, it might cause a constitutional
crisis, a weakening of the legitimacy of the Court, an intensifying of
homophobia, a constitutional amendment overturning the Court's decision, and
much more. Any Court, even one committed to the basic principle, should
hesitate in the face of such prospects. It would be far better for the Court to
start cautiously and to proceed incrementally.
The Supreme Court might, for example, accept the most narrow arguments,
and reject or (better) avoid passing on the more general and intrusive ones.
It might conclude that the Equal Protection Clause forbids state constitutional
amendments that interfere with the attempts of ordinary democratic processes
to outlaw discrimination on the basis of sexual orientation. The Court might
say that such amendments do not merely discriminate on the basis of sexual
orientation, but also disfavor a defined group in the political process in a way
that involves issues of political equality.
Alternatively, the Supreme Court might say-as some lower courts have-
that government cannot rationally discriminate against people of homosexual
orientation without showing that those people have engaged in acts that harm
a legitimate government interest. Courts could recognize that discrimination
on the basis of orientation alone has the basic characteristics of a "status
offense" disfavored in American law.90 Despite its problems, "rationality"
review might well be the best route here. Narrow rulings of this sort would
allow room for public discussion and debate before obtaining a centralized
national ruling that preempts ordinary political process over a moral issue
about which society is in a state of evolution.
We can go further. Constitutional law is not only for the courts; it is for all
public officials. The original understanding was that deliberation about the
Constitution's meaning would be part of the function of the President and
legislators as well. There was not supposed to be a judicial monopoly on that
process. 9' The post-Warren Court identification of the Constitution with the
decisions of the Supreme Court has badly disserved the traditional American
commitment to deliberative democracy. In that system, all officials, not only
the judges, have a duty of fidelity to the founding document. And in that
system, elected officials will have a degree of interpretive independence from
the judiciary. They will sometimes fill the institutional gap created by the
courts' lack of factfinding ability and policy-making competence.92 For this
reason, they may conclude that practices are unconstitutional even if the Court
would uphold them, or that practices are valid even if the Court would
invalidate them. Lincoln is an important example here as well. Often, he
CONCLUSION
cases and also invalidate measures that combine restrictions on the democratic
process with discrimination. Broader rulings should be avoided. Elected
officials, including the President, have somewhat more flexibility in carrying
out their own independent constitutional responsibilities.
There is good reason to think that before terribly long, discrimination on the
basis of sexual orientation will be seen as a product of unthinking prejudice
and hostility, much like discrimination on the basis of race and gender. Courts
can play a part in this process, requiring tangible justifications for the
infliction of social harm, fortifying the process of democratic deliberation, and
requiring genuine reason-giving in all cases of discrimination. But the judicial
role, though important, is secondary. If discrimination against homosexuals
is eventually to be seen-as I think that it should-to be inconsistent with
constitutional principles, it will be the result of an extended process of
deliberation, in which courts play an occasionally catalytic but far from
decisive role.