Al-'Ilm Al-Hudûrî - Conhecimento Por Presença (Inglês) - Volume I
Al-'Ilm Al-Hudûrî - Conhecimento Por Presença (Inglês) - Volume I
Al-'Ilm Al-Hudûrî - Conhecimento Por Presença (Inglês) - Volume I
Knowledge by Presence
Al-`Ilm al-Hudûrî
Knowledge by Presence
The Book: This book explores the issue of knowledge by presence as an epistemological problem in
philosophy. Al-`Ilm al-Huduri (knowledge by presence) deserves as an epistemological bridge
between philosophy and mysticism. This book is a comparative study of the epistemology of
Suhrawardî and Mullâ Sadrâ Shîrâzî, two Muslim thinkers of the 6th/12th and 11th/17th century. It
focuses on two main issues: Illuminative theory of knowledge and, in the framework of this theory,
Mullâ Sadrâ's doctrine of knowledge by presence (al-'ilm al-hudûrî) studied in the context of his
philosophical system (al-hikmah al-muta'âlîyah). Mullâ Sadrâ's doctrine of knowledge by presence is
the corner stone of his epistemological system. In the light of this doctrine, he gives a new definition
of knowledge, an innovative interpretation of its division into al-'ilm al-hudûrî and al-'ilm al-husûlî,
and, finally, a systematic chain of various kinds of knowledge by presence (e.g., self-knowledge,
God's knowledge of His Essence and God's knowledge of things). These three aspects of his doctrine
have been surveyed and, in comparing them with Suhrawardî's theory, evaluated in this book.
The Author: Dr. Sayyed Mohammad Reza Hejazi is Professor of Islamic Philosophy, Mysticism,
Religious Studies and Islamic Theology at I.M. Seminary, Director of the Islamic Studies and Research
Academy (ISRA), California, USA, Chairman of A.B.A. Assembly of North America, and a founder
member and a Trustee of the Ibn Sina Health Foundation of North America (ISHFNA). He has also
served as Director at the I.E.C., Washington D.C. and was a Chairman at the I.I.N.Y., New York, USA.
He holds a Master of Arts degree in Islamic Jurisprudence from Elmiyeh Seminary of Qom, a
doctorate in Islamic Philosophy from B.U.C. Institute of Qom, a second Master of Arts degree in
Epistemology and Islamic Mysticism from McGill University, Montreal, Canada; and a second
doctorate in Philosophy of Ethics from Catholic University of America, Washington D.C., USA. Dr.
Hejazi has published 22 books in Arabic, Persian and English. He has also published more than 18
articles in different languages and participated in about 28 international and inter-disciplinary
Seminars, Conferences and Academic Workshops. In addition to his teaching and writing, Dr. Hejazi
serves as a consultant in the fields of education, morality, religion and philosophy.
INTODUCTION …………………………………………………………………… 15
I. General ………………………………………………………………. 17
II. The philosophy of Mullâ Sadrâ …………….…………….. 19
III. This study and its methodology ………………………… 23
PART I
Knowledge, Definition and Division
CHAPTER 1 The Definition of Knowledge ……………..…….…. 33
I. General ………………………………………………..….………. 33
II. The concept and the nature of knowledge ………. 34
III. The definition of knowledge ………………………..….. 37
PART II
Knowledge by Presence ( al-‘ilm al-hudûrî )
Introduction …………………………………………………….………………… 99
CONSONANTS
ء ‘ ‘ ص S S
ب B B ض D Z
پ - P ط T T
ت T T ظ Z Z
ث TH TH ع ‘ ‘
ج J J غ GH GH
چ - CH ف F F
ح H H ق Q Q
خ KH KH ک K K
د D D گ - G
ذ DH DH ل L L
ر R R م M M
ز Z Z ن N N
س S S ه H H
ش SH SH ى Y Y
VOWELS
long ا ā
آ Ā
و ū
ي ī
Diphthongs و au or aw
ى ai or ay
Short –َ- a
–ُ- u
–ِ- i
Notes on technicalities
I. General
1
The two Arabic words al-‘ilm and al-ma‘rifa mean knowledge. The usage
of these two terms, as well as other words such as al-‘irfân, al-shu‘ûr
and al-'idrâk, in various Islamic fields (e.g., philosophy, theology,
26 Introduction
al-Dîn Shîrâzî and his Transcendent Theosophy (Tehran, 1978), pp. 55-
60.
30
For instance, in Asfâr, Mullâ Sadrâ usually employs an especial method in
which he has first discussed the views of various schools and then
synthesized the different doctrines into a unity which seeks to
encompass them.
PART ONE
Knowledge
Definition and Division
CHAPTER 1
The Definition of Knowledge
I. General
1
D. W. Hamlyn, "History of Epistemology," in Encyclopedia of Philosophy
(New York: Macmillan, 1967), vol. 3, p. 10.
2
For instance, in the Muslim world, at least for Fârâbî (d. 339/950) and his
successors, knowledge and a theory of knowledge was both possible
and necessary. For more information see: I. R. Netton, Al-Fârâbî and His
School, (London, New York: Rouledge, 1992), p. 88.
3
"This problem occupies an important place in most major philosophical
systems whether philosophy is conceived as an ontological undertaking
or a critical inquiry. In modern philosophy in the widest sense of the
phrase–i.e., philosophy since the Renaissance– theory of knowledge has
usually been the primary field of philosophy." Anthony Quinton,
"Knowledge and Belief," in Encyclopedia of Philosophy (New York:
Macmillan, 1967), vol. 4, p. 345.
4
The fact that most, if not all, Muslim theologians have notably discussed
diverse aspects of knowledge in their works is obvious from the
following passage: "These discussions occupy a position in Islamic
Al-‘Ilm al-Hudûrî (Knowledge by Presence) 42
Ibn Sînâ also, in some of his works, gives us the same statement. See
Ibn Sinâ, Al-Ta‘lîqât (p. 82).
18
Sharh Hikmat al-Ishrâq, pp. 38-9. For a full discussion of Suhrawardî’s
examination of the problem “definition” see: H. Ziai, Knowledge and
Illumination (Atlanta, Ga.: Scholars Press, 1990), pp. 77-135.
19
al-Jurjânî (d. 808/1405) quotes several definition under the title of al-‘ilm
(knowledge) and states his own selected definition as following: "
knowledge is a certain belief which corresponds to the reality." Al-
Ta‘rîfât (Beirut: Maktaba Lubnân, 1990), p. 160. Among theologians, al-
`Ijî (d. 756/1355), on definition of knowledge, mentions several
impressions some of which are: 1. al-Râzî's opinion: knowledge is
necessary, darûrî (therefore, it doesn't need any definition). 2. al-
Juvainî's and al-Ghazzâlî's point of view: knowledge is not necessary, but
its definition is very difficult. 3. For the rest of Muslim thinkers it is
speculative, nazarî or acquired, muktasab. Then he quotes different
definitions and, finally, selects his accepted one. Al-Mawâqif, pp. 9-11.
20
Muhammad ibn ‘Omar Fakhr al-Dîn al-Râzî is one of the most important
Ash‘arite theologians who was among the first to systematize Islamic
theology on a philosophical basis. Fazlur Rahman asserts that al-Râzî,
being Mullâ Sadrâ's most persistent target, wielded great influence on
the subsequent philosophical tradition in Islam. F. Rahman, The
Philosophy of Mullâ Sadrâ, p. 8.
21
F. Razî, al-Mabâhith al-Mashriqîyah (Beirut: Dâr al-Kitâb al-‘Arabî, 9110),
pp. 450-3.
22
Mullâ Sadrâ, Asfâr, I/3, p. 278.
23
Sabzavârî has paid attention to this point in his commentary on Mullâ
Sadrâ's Asfâr, I/3, p.278.
24
Asfâr, I/1, p.116; part 3, pp. 286,297,354; Mafâtîh al-Ghaib, p. 108. It
could be mentioned here that the propositions which are offered as the
definitions of knowledge are not logically the definitions of knowledge,
for it has been cited that, on the one hand, the logical definition consists
of genus and species and, on the other hand, there is no genus and
species for the nature of “knowledge.” Hence, these propositions seem
to be merely as sharh-ul-ism; or, as Mullâ Sadrâ mentions, these are
propounded as the admonitions and explanations implying clarity and
plainness. Asfâr, I/3, p. 278.
50 Chapter One: The Definition of Knowledge
25
Asfâr, I/3, pp. 278-99; Mafâtîh al-Ghaib, (Tehran: Mu`ssasa Mutâli‘ât wa
Tahqîqât-i Farhangî, 1986), pp. 108-110. See also F. Rahman, The
Philosophy of Mullâ Sadrâ, pp. 210-220.
26
Asfâr, I/3, pp. 286,289. For Suhrawardî's objection to this definition see:
Hikmat al-Ishrâq, p.151. All references here, for Suhrawardî's works
such as Hikmat al-Ishrâq, al-Talvîhât, al-Mashâri‘ wa al-Mutârihât, and
al-Muqâwimât are to the collection under the title of Opera
metaphysica et mystica, vol. I & II, ed. Henricus Corbin (Istanbul: Maarif
Matbaasi, 1945, 1954).
27
Asfâr, I/3, pp. 288-9.
28
Suhrawardî, Hikmat al-Ishrâq, p. 111. Elsewhere, he remarks that:
"perception (idrâk) occurs when the idea or form (mithâl) of the reality
(haqîqa) of the thing is obtained by the person, i.e., in the knowing
subject." Hikmat al-Ishrâq, p. 15 [trans. H. Ziai, Knowledge and
Illumination (Atlanta, Ga.: Scholars Press, 1990), p. 140].
29
Mullâ Sadrâ, Risâla al-Tasawwur wa al-Tasdîq [ed. in al-Jawhar al-Nadîd
(Qum: Intishârât-i Bîdâr, 1984) p. 307.
30
I shall attempt to examine his propositions in the following chapter.
31
The term manifest as a translation for the technical term zâhir has been
used by some contemporary writers like J. Walbridge in The Science of
Mystic Light (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1992).
32
Opera II, Hikmat al-Ishrâq, p.113.
33
Ibid., pp. 106-8,117.
34
Ibid., pp. 97-100; al-Mutârihât, p. 486. In this regard, Ziai concludes as
following: "For Suhrawardî, one does not proceed to know a thing by
analyzing it, but by having an intuitive grasp of its total reality and then
analyzing the intuition." Knowledge and Illumination (Atlanta, Ga.:
Scholars Press, 1990), p. 130.
35
Asfâr, I/3, p.291.
36
Mullâ Sadrâ, Ta‘lîqât on Sharh Hikmat al-Ishrâq (Tehran: Chap-i Sangî,
1913), pp. 270-274; al-‘Arshîya, p. 237 [trans. by J. W. Morris, The
Wisdom of The Throne (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press,
1981) pp. 136].
Al-‘Ilm al-Hudûrî (Knowledge by Presence) 29
37
Asfâr, I/3, pp. 291-2; Ta‘lîqât on Sharh Hikmat al-Ishrâq, pp. 268-274; al-
‘Arshîyah, p. 225.
38
al-‘Arshîyah, p. 225 (trans. by J. W. Morris, The Wisdom of The Throne
(Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1981) pp. 107-8).
39
Ibid., p. 237. Morris here declares that, “Sadra’s primary concern here is
to clarify the ontological implication of Suhrawardî’s theory with regard
to the true nature of soul; he does not claim to outline an adequate
alternative account of vision (or any other sense) on the level of physical
or psychological theory.” (P. 936, n. 83). However, it might be said that,
although Mullâ Sadrâ here does not offer the alternative theory of
vision, he demonstrates his own account in several places of his works.
We shall examine Mullâ Sadrâ’s theory, as well as his criticizing
Suhrawardî’s doctrine, in the following chapter.
40
Asfâr, I/3, p. 297 [trans. by F. Rahman in The Philosophy of Mullâ Sadrâ
(Albany: SUNY Press, 1975), p. 213].
41
F. Rahman, The Philosophy of Mullâ Sadrâ (Albany: SUNY Press, 1975), p.
32.
42
For Mullâ Sadrâ’s interpretation of Suhrawardî’s concept see: Asfâr, I/1,
pp. 38-45; Ta‘lîqât on Sharh Hikmat al-Ishrâq, pp. 182-192; al-Mashâ‘ir,
trans. and ed. P. Morewedge (New York: SSIPS, 1992), pp. 22-33. For
Suhrawardî’s own idea see: Opera II, Hikmat al-Ishrâq, pp. 64-6; Opera I,
al-Talwîhât, pp. 22-3.
43
Mullâ Sadrâ, in his major work, has devoted four chapters to the
discussion of the principiality of existence. He mentions some views,
their objections, and answers one by one. Finally, he demonstrates his
own doctrine by several arguments. Asfâr, I/1, pp. 38-74.
44
Mullâ Sadrâ, al-Mashâ‘ir, trans. and ed. P. Morewedge (New York: SSIPS,
1992), p.43.
45
See above, n. 16.
46
al-Mashâ‘ir, pp. 30,43,63. Although the same theory had a background in
the illuminative doctrine of Suhrawardî.
47
Mullâ Sadrâ, al-Mashâ‘ir, p. 12.
52 Chapter One: The Definition of Knowledge
48
Ibn Sînâ (d. 428/1037) somewhere describes knowledge as relational
quality, and elsewhere, as spiritual quality or simple relation. al-Ishârât,
vol. 2, pp. 319-24, 334-62; vol. 4, pp. 710-16.
CHAPTER 2
The Division of Knowledge
Al-‘ilm al-husûlî & Al-‘ilm al-hudûrî
I. Al-‘ilm al-husûlî
perception in the subject (i.e. the ‘idea’) and the object, which
is not the case of knowledge by presence (al-‘ilm al-hudûrî).
Suhrawardî’s view of intuitive knowledge indicates that the
subject’s immediate experience of the “presence” of the object
determines the validity of knowledge itself; therefore, in
knowledge by presence (al-‘ilm al-hudûrî), there is no absence
between subject and object.22
Mullâ Sadrâ, following the traditional doctrines, namely
Peripatetic and illuminational views, primarily divides
knowledge, as it was mentioned above, into al-‘ilm al-husûlî
and al-‘ilm al-hudûrî. He indicates that, in al-‘ilm al-husûlî, the
reality of the external object of knowledge is absent from the
subject and, in its place, a mental existent is at the presence of
the subject, known by it directly23. Then he states that the
mental existence (al-wujûd al-dhihnî) of the direct object is
thoroughly corresponding with the external existence (al-
wujûd al-khârijî) of the “absent” object. There isn’t any
essential difference between these two kinds of something’s
existence. The only difference is that one existence is mental,
and the other is external.24
As we have seen, both Suhrawardî and Mullâ Sadrâ
declare that, in this kind of knowledge (al-‘ilm al-husûlî), the
form or concept which is known by the mind should be
conformable to the real object, i.e., the external reality. They,
however, don’t elucidate, so far as I could find, the problem
that, in the light of their epistemological system, how they can
prove the conformity of a mental form with its external
existence. The thesis I am putting forward is that although they
Al-‘Ilm al-Hudûrî (Knowledge by Presence) 21
1
For instance, Sabzavârî mentions several divisions of knowledge such as:
"Knowledge is either husûlî (empirical) or hudûrî (intuitive); and it is
either mufrad (separative) or murakkab (collective); and it is either fi‘lî
(active) or infi‘âlî (passive). The Metaphysics of Sabzavari, trans. and
eds. M. Mohaghegh and T. Izutsu (New York: Caravan Books, 1977), pp.
212-13.
2
Asfâr, I, 3, pp. 382-4, 500-507.
3
Ibid., p. 382.
4
In the following pages, I shall attempt to clarify the technical term al-‘ilm
al-husûlî.
5
Asfâr, I/1, pp. 272-86, 309; Risâla al-tasawwur wa al-tasdîq, p. 307.
6
H.A.Ghaffar Khan, “Shâh Walî Allâh: on the nature, origin, definition, and
classification of knowledge,” Journal of Islamic Studies, vol. 3, no. 2
(1992), Oxford, pp. 210-11.
7
This term is also used in Suhrawardian epistemological language. Ziai
alleges that the term idrâk as used by Suhrawardî is like a genus that
covers a number of species, such as ‘ilm, ma‘rifa, hiss, etc. Knowledge
and Illumination (Atlanta, Ga.: Scholars Press, 1990), p. 141 (note no. 1).
8
Asfâr, I/3, pp. 293,382-3. Idrâk has been divided into several divisions in
recent Persian philosophy for which see: A. M. Mishkât al-Dînî, Tahqîq
dar Haqîqat-i ‘ilm (Tehran: Châpkhân-i Dânishgâh-i Tehran, 1965), pp.
2ff.
9
Ibn Sînâ, al-Ishârât wa al-Tanbîhât (Tehran: Matba‘a Heidarî, 9128), vol. 2,
al-namat 3, pp. 343-7.
10
Ibid., pp. 334-342.
11
Al-‘ilm al-husûlî can be translated as sensory, empirical, conceptual,
formative, and a posteriori knowledge. It is called empirical or
observational because observation and practical experience are its
prerequisites. It is called formative because the form of the known
object is the central point where the activity of the perception becomes
knowledge. And it is called a posteriori because knowledge in this case
comes after the experience and observation. S. J. Sajjadi, Farhang-i
70 Chapter Two: The Division of Knowledge
19
Ibn Sînâ, al-Ishârât., vol. 2, al-namat 3, pp. 334-342.
20
Ibid., p. 334 (trans. by A. Al-Oraibi in Shî‘î Renaissance, Ph.D. thesis,
McGill University, 1992).
21
Suhrawardî, Hikmat al-Ishrâq, p. 15.
22
Ibid., pp. 111-116.
23
Mullâ Sadrâ, Asfâr, I/3, pp. 280-84, 298.
24
The division of existence into mental existence (al-wujûd al-dhihnî) and
external existence (al-wujûd al-khârijî) has been discussed in several
philosophical and theological works so far. Mullâ Sadrâ earmarks one
part of the first book of his Asfâr (about 64 pages) to the discussion of
mental existence (al-wujûd al-dhihnî) and its ontological and
epistemological characters. Asfâr, I/1, pp. 263-326.
25
Ibid., pp. 297-99, Mafâtîh al-Ghaib (Tehran: Muassasa Mutâli‘ât wa
Tahqîqât-i Farhangî, 1984), p. 109; al-‘Arshîya, p. 32.
26
F. E. Peters, Greek Philosophical Terms (New York: New York University
Press, 1967), p. 127.
27
According to some of Sufis' idea, namely Shâh Walî Allâh’s, the notion of
al-‘ilm al-hudûrî is slightly different from that of Suhrawardî. This
understanding is that “it is a direct fayd (emanation) from al-Rahmân,
not from the person who is receiving intuition or illumination. According
to him, the Gnostic is in a passive state. It is al-Rahmân who induces
intuitive knowledge in the heart of the mystic in an indescribable way.”
H. A. Ghaffar Khan, “Shâh Walî Allâh.,” Journal of Islamic Studies, 3:2
(1992), p. 211.
28
S. J. Sajjadi, op. cit. 170.
29
Qutb al-Dîn Shîrâzî was one of the pupils of Nasîr al-Dîn Tûsî, and one of
the famous astronomers and philosophers. In the field of Peripatetic
philosophy, he left a remarkable work, written in Persian, entitled
Durrat al-Tâj. He was one of the popular expositors of Suhrawardî’s
illuminationist philosophy. In his commentary on Suhrawardî’s Hikmat
al-Ishrâq, Qutb al-Dîn Shîrâzî explains and elucidates the whole idea of
the illuminative system.
30
Q. Shîrâzî, Sharh Hikmat al-Ishrâq ‘Commentary on The Philosophy of
Illumination’ (Tehrân: Châp-i Sangî, 1913) pp. 38-39.
72 Chapter Two: The Division of Knowledge
31
H. Ziai, Knowledge And Illumination (Atlanta, Ga.: Scholars Press, 1990), p.
135.
32
Suhrawardî, Hikmat al-Ishrâq, p. 15.
33
Qutb al-Dîn Shîrâzî, Sharh., p. 39.
34
In this regard, Ziai, the author of knowledge and Illumination, asserts and
explains the idea of Suhrawardî, as well as Shîrâzî- the commentator of
Hikmat al-Ishrâq. Unfortunately, he doesn’t clarify the main difference
between the knowledge which is obtained through an ‘idea’ (mithal)
and the knowledge which is obtained by presence. It is clear that,
according to Suhrawardî, the technical terms such as ‘presence’ (al-
hudûr), ‘illuminationist relation’ (al-idâfa al-ishrâqîya), and ‘knowledge
based on illumination and presence’ (al-‘ilm al-ishrâqî al-hudûrî) refer
only to the latter. The commentator, Qutb al-Dîn Shîrâzî -in his Sharh, p.
39- explicitly elucidates the distinction between these two kinds of
knowledge, with regard to the view point of Suhrawardî. On this point
see: H. Ziai, Knowledge and Illumination (Atlanta, Ga.: Scholars Press,
1990), pp. 140-3.
35
Q. Shîrâzî, Sharh., p. 38.
36
In Hikmat al-Ishrâq, pp. 97-103, Suhrawardî mentions several viewpoints
and rejects all one by one. thereafter, he explains his own idea.
37
Mullâ Sadrâ notably has a discussion about the issue, “ittihâd al-‘aql wa
al-‘âqil wa al-ma‘qûl”. Having remarked and evaluated several notions,
he finally demonstrates his theory of unification (al-ittihâd). In this
regard see: Asfâr, I/3, pp. 312-44; F. Rahman, The Philosophy of Mullâ
Sadrâ (Albany: SUNY Press, 1976), p. 239.
38
Mullâ Sadrâ, Mafâtîh al-Ghaib (Tehran: Muassasa Mutâli‘ât wa Tahqîqât-i
Farhangî, 1984), pp. 108-110.
39
Mullâ Sadrâ, Asfâr, I/1, pp. 282-296, 308-309.
40
Mullâ Sadrâ, al-‘Arshîya, p. 32 (trans. by J. W. Morris in The Wisdom of
the Throne, p. 159).
41
The great contemporary Muslim philosopher, ‘Allâma Sayyed
Muhammad Husayn Tabâtabâ`î (1321-1402/1902-1983) is the author of
some philosophical works such as Nihâyat al-Hikmah, and Usûl Falsafa
wa Ravish realism (The principles of philosophy and the Method of
Al-‘Ilm al-Hudûrî (Knowledge by Presence) 23
56
Mullâ Sadrâ, al-‘Arshîya, p. 225. Mullâ Sadrâ here argues that any
material thing is absent from itself by itself.
57
The discussion and the arguments of the nature of knowledge by
presence, as well as of its restriction to the immaterial things will be
pointed out in the following chapter.
58
M. Ha`irî Yazdî, The Principles., p. 45. The parentheses are mine.
59
In the very beginning of his Hikmat al-Ishrâq (p. 10), Suhrawardî asserts
that there is no doubt in this kind of illuminative understanding. Mullâ
Sadrâ also confirms the same statement in his work Al-Mashâ‘ir, p. 30.
60
Mullâ Sadrâ, Mafâtîh al-Ghaib, p. 109; Tabâtabâ`î, Bidâyat al-Hikmah
(Beirut: Dâr al-Mustafâ, 1982), p. 164.
61
Mullâ Sadrâ, Mafâtîh al-Ghaib, pp. 108-110.
62
Mullâ Sadrâ, al-Mashâ‘ir, p. 30 (trans. by P.Morewedge in the same
page).
CHAPTER 3
Immateriality and “knowledge by presence”
I. Tajarrud (Immateriality) 1
a: Immateriality of “knowledge”
Both Suhrawardî and Mullâ Sadrâ maintain that
“knowledge” (al-‘ilm) is “free from matter” (mujarrad). Their
80 Chapter Three: Immateriality and Knowledge
b: Immateriality of “knower”
On the immateriality of the human soul (as a knower),
there is an accepted theory among the Muslim philosophers,
namely Fârâbî, Ibn Sînâ, Tûsî, Suhrawardî and Mullâ Sadrâ. By
different methods and distinct backgrounds, they have
demonstrated the immateriality of the human soul, confirming
the fact that “nafs” (the human soul) is ultimately capable of
existing independently of the body.23 In order to prove that
“self” (al-nafs) is an immaterial spiritual substance, Ibn Sînâ
has recourse to his famous argument that a person, under
certain suppositions, can affirm his own “self” (dhâtihî) without
affirming the existence of his body.24
In a number of his works,25 Suhrawardî holds that the
human soul “self” (nafs) is separated from the body since, he
argues, the body is in a continuous state of change. But, it is
not possible for humans to undergo so much change and yet
remain the same. There must be an immaterial substance,
mind or self (nafs), separate from body. The nature of this
substance or entity cannot be material since all material things
undergo change and therefore cannot remain the same.
Consequently, this “self” (nafs) has to be immaterial. In this
regard Suhrawardî states:
All the parts of the body change and if your “self”
consisted of these parts of the body, they would also be
in a continuous state of change. (Thus) your self
yesterday would not be the same “self” as today, but
each day your self would be other than itself and this
obviously is not the case. And since your knowledge is
Al-‘Ilm al-Hudûrî (Knowledge by Presence) 83
that the soul is bodily in its origin but spiritual in its survival
(jismânîyat al-hudûth, rûhânîyat al-baqâ`).31
Yet Mullâ Sadrâ maintains that the human soul is free
from matter and hence capable of existence independently of
the body. The reason for this doctrine, in part, is to prove that
simple human souls which possess hardly any intellective
activity, but simply work with imagination also survive. For,
Mullâ Sadrâ absolutely holds that a being endowed with
imagination is independent of natural matter even though it is
not independent of a certain kind of extension and quantity
(miqdâr) which, however, is not material. This view, in turn,
rests on his doctrine of the ‘Alam al-Mithâl (World of Images),
according to which, an image, although not spiritual, is not
material either, is not directly subject to substantive change as
the world of physical forms and, therefore, exists by itself
independent of matter.32
Further, to prove that the human soul is separate from
the body, Mullâ Sadrâ applies the philosophers’ argument33
from self-knowledge. The human’s self-knowledge is direct,
continuous, and independent of its knowledge of the external
object. Hence the human soul is independent of the material
body. Again, he argues that the immateriality of “knowledge”
also postulates the immateriality of the soul. Apprehension of
knowledge means the reception of the known by the knower,
and the apprehension of a thing and its presence is nothing
except its existence, that existence itself. The immediacy of the
known requires that the knower acquiring its knowledge be in
act, non-deficient in any respect arising from association with
Al-‘Ilm al-Hudûrî (Knowledge by Presence) 82
in seeing something, it is not the case that the subject sees the
external object but that it is the presence of the inner object to
be seen that allows for the very act of seeing to take place.45
According to Mullâ Sadrâ, the act of seeing (or any kind
of sensitive perception) takes place when an interaction
happens between the soul (as a knower) and the external
world (as a known). The external world, on the one hand,
prepares some necessary conditions of the act of seeing, and
the soul, on the other hand, makes an immaterial form
corresponding to the external object.
Consequently, the existence of the form (in any sort of
perception), being at the presence of the soul, is directly
perceived by the soul.46 Mullâ Sadrâ contends that this
relation between the soul and the immaterial form is due to be
called “illuminative relation” (al-idâfah al-ishrâqîyah).47
What seems plausible, on the ground of our discussion,
to be concluded here is that Mullâ Sadrâ reached much the
same epistemological conclusion as Suhrawardî, although by a
very different route. Having recourse to their illuminative
principles, both Suhrawardî and Mullâ Sadrâ have been
ultimately led to the inference that, in the act of vision, the
only way through which the external thing could be known is
knowledge by presence.
The process of “knowledge by presence,” according to
Suhrawardî, happens directly between the soul (nafs) and the
external object. But, according to Mullâ Sadrâ, since the
process of “knowledge by presence” cannot be applicable
directly between knower and any material object, as we have
90 Chapter Three: Immateriality and Knowledge
1
“separation from matter,” “noncorporeality” or “immateriality” are the
usual translations of “tajarrud.”
2
mâdda, translated here as “matter,” often refers simply to the elements
of corporeal being, and in those cases is close in meaning to jism,
“body.” According to the definition of “jism” that Mullâ Sadrâ gives us
here the term “jism or jismânî” is preferably, in contrast with
“mujarrad,” applied in place of “mâdda or mâddî.” Asfâr, I/2, p. 94.
3
J. Sajjâdî, Farhang-i ‘Ulûm-i ‘Aqlî (Tehran: Kitâbkhâni Ibn Sînâ, 1962), p.
192.
4
Mullâ Sadrâ, Asfâr, I/3, p. 313 (trans. by M.Hâ`irî as stated in The Principle
of Epistemology in Islamic Philosophy, p. 35).
5
Ibid., p. 313.
6
Ibn Sînâ, known to the West as Avicenna, lived from 980-1037 A.D. For
further information on his life see: William E. Gohlman, The life of Ibn
Sînâ (Albany: SUNY Press, 1974).
7
Ibn Sînâ, Dânishnâmah ‘Alâ`î, Ilâhîyât, p. 36 (trans. by S. H. Nasr in An
Introduction to Islamic Cosmological Doctrines, p. 200). See also F.
Al-‘Ilm al-Hudûrî (Knowledge by Presence) 13
20
Ibid., pp. 297-8 (trans. by F. Rahman in The Philosophy of Mullâ Sadrâ, p.
213).
21
M. H. Tabâtabâ`î, Bidâyat al-Hikma (Beirut: Dâr al-Mustafâ, 1982), pp.
148-9.
22
Mullâ Sadrâ, al-Mabda` wa al-Ma‘âd, p. 79.
23
For Fârâbî’s point of view see: al-Rasâ`il, Risâlat fî Ithbât al-Mufâriqât, pp.
3,5,7; al-Ta‘lîqât, pp. 10,12-13; al-Madîna al-Fâdila, p. 23; for Ibn Sînâ’s
theory see: al-Shifâ`, al-Nafs, chapter 6, al-Ishârât, vol. 2, pp. 319-24,
334-42; for Tûsî’s doctrine see: his notes on Ibn Sînâ’s al-Ishârât., vol. 2,
pp. 319-24, 334-42. In this connection, for more details see: F. Rahman,
Avicenna’s Psychology, pp. 50-53; Prophecy in Islam (London: Allen &
Unwin, 1958), Chapter I, Section 1,2.
24
Ibn Sînâ, al-Ishârât., vol. 2, al-namat 3, pp. 319-323; al-Najât, pp. 174-8.
See also Davidson, Alfarabi, Avicenna, and Averroes, on Intellect (New
York: Oxford University Press, 1992), p. 106.
25
Suhrawardî, Opera I, al-Talvîhât, pp. 68-74,79-81, al-Mashâri‘, pp. 496-7;
Partaw Nâmah, chapter 4, pp. 23-24.
26
Suhrawardî, Partaw Nâmah, chapter 4, pp. 23-24 (trans. by M.
Aminrazavi, in Suhrawardî’s Theory of Knowledge, p. 127). For another
argumentation of Suhrawardî, see p. 76 in the following chapter.
27
Opera I, al-Talvîhât, pp. 68-74,79-81, al-Mashâri‘, pp. 496-7.
28
Suhrawardî, Opera II, Hikmat al-Ishrâq, pp. 116.
29
Mullâ Sadrâ, Asfâr, IV/1, pp. 325-27, ‘Arshîya, p. 19.
30
Asfâr, IV/1, pp. 260-322.
31
Ibid., p. 347.
32
Mullâ Sadrâ, Asfâr, IV/1, pp. 42-44, 278, 294-6.
33
For Fârâbî’s demonstrations that the human soul is immaterial see:
Risâlat fî Ithbât al-Mufâriqât, p. 2; and for Ibn Sînâ’s argumentation see:
al-Shifâ`, al-Nafs, pp. 187-96; al-Najât, pp. 210-20; see also F. Rahman,
Avicenna’s Psychology (London: Oxford University Press, 1952), pp. 41-
54.
34
Mullâ Sadrâ, Asfâr, IV/1, pp. 43, 294-6.
Al-‘Ilm al-Hudûrî (Knowledge by Presence) 12
35
For Suhrawardî’s view see: Opera II, Hikmat al-Ishrâq, p. 134; for Sadrian
theory see: Asfâr, IV/1, pp. 178-183.
36
Opera II, Hikmat al-Ishrâq, p. 134.
37
Suhrawardî, Opera II, Hikmat al-Ishrâq, pp. 150, 152-153.
38
Ibid., pp. 134-5, 213-216.
39
H. Zia`i, Knowledge and Illumination (Atlanta, Ga.: Scholars Press, 1990),
p. 161.
40
For a more complete discussion on this problem see: M. Aminrazavi,
Suhrawardî’s Theory of Knowledge (Ph. D. Thesis, Temple University,
1989), pp. 234-237.
41
Mullâ Sadrâ, Asfâr, IV/1, p. 182.
42
Mullâ Sadrâ, al-‘Arshîyah, p. 225 (Trans. J.W. Morris in The Wisdom of
the Throne, pp. 107-108).
43
Ibid., p. 237 (Trans. J.W. Morris in The Wisdom of the Throne, p. 136).
44
Ibid., p. 237 (Trans. J.W. Morris in The Wisdom of the Throne, pp. 136-
137).
45
M. H. Tabâtabâ`î, n. 1, Asfâr, I/1, p. 286.
46
Mullâ Sadrâ, Ta‘lîqa ‘alâ Sharh-i Hikmat al-Ishrâq, p. 454.
47
Mullâ Sadrâ, Asfâr, IV/1, p. 182, al-‘Arshîyah, p. 21.
48
Mullâ Sadrâ, al-‘Arshîya, p. 227 (Trans. J. W. Morris in The Wisdom of the
Throne, p. 114).
49
Sabzavârî, n. 1, Asfâr, IV/1, pp. 179-81 (n. 1). See also his notes on Mullâ
Sadrâ’s Asfâr, III/1, pp.164-166 (n. 3).
50
M. Mesbâh Yazdî, Ta‘lîqa., pp. 205, 256-7. This issue and the Sadrian
theory of vision (concerning the problem of God’s knowledge) will be
discussed in chapter 5.
51
It seems that Suhrawardî, in his Hikmat al-Ishrâq, maintains this kind of
relationship between a special kind of human being and the external
world. For more details see: Opera II, Hikmat al-Ishrâq, pp. 213-215.
PART TWO
Knowledge by Presence
(al-‘ilm al-hudûrî )
Introduction
1
In chapter 4, I shall attempt to give a detailed account of this kind of
knowledge by presence, namely self-knowledge.
2
For instance see: Fârâbî, al-Rasâ`il, Risâlat fî Ithbât al-Mufâraqât, pp.
3,5,7; al-Ta‘lîqât, pp. 10,12-13; Ibn Sînâ, al-Shifâ`, al-Nafs, pp. 212-213;
al-Ishârât, vol. 2, pp. 319-24, 334-42, vol. 3, p. 481, vol. 4, p. 709; al-
Najât, p. 99; al-Ta‘lîqât, pp. 77-81, 160-62; Fakhr al-Râzî, al-Mabâhith
al-Mashriqîya, pp. 459-463; Tûsî, Sharh Mas‘alat al-‘ilm, pp. 28,34.
Although, in the case of the former philosophers such as Fârâbî or Ibn
Sînâ, we don’t find the exact term “al-‘ilm al-hudûrî” in their works, the
104 PART TWO: Introduction
I. “Self” (al-dhât)
1
In this regard, there are some technical Arabic terms such as nafs, rûh,
dhât which are interchangeably used by Muslim thinkers. In the case of
the identity of a person, these terms are represented to the term ana ( I
).
2
For Fârâbî’s point of view see: al-Rasâ`il, Risâla fî Ithbât al-Mufâraqât, pp.
3,5,7; al-Ta‘lîqât, pp. 10,12-13; al-Madîna al-Fâdila, p. 23; for Ibn Sînâ’s
theory see: al-Shifâ`, al-Nafs, chapter 6, al-Ishârât, vol. 2, pp. 319-24,
334-42. In this connection, for more details see: F. Rahman, Avicenna’s
Psychology, pp. 24-68; Prophecy in Islam (London: Allen & Unwin, 1958),
Chapter I, Section 1,2.
3
Suhrawardî’s view on the existence of a self in his Persian works can be
found in the following works: Hayâkil al-Nûr, pp. 4-92; al-Alwâh al-
‘Imâdîyah, pp. 116-165; Bustân al-Qulûb, pp. 342-387; and Yazdân
Shinâkht, pp. 412-444. In his Arabic works, he discusses the issue in the
al-Talwîhât, pp. 68,81,82. Suhrawardî in Partaw-Nâmah (Opera III, pp.
23-24) offers several arguments for the existence of a “self” (nafs) and
Al-‘Ilm al-Hudûrî (Knowledge by Presence) 922
its independence of the body. Mullâ Sadrâ also allocated one part of his
major work Asfâr to the issue. Asfâr, IV/1.
4
Fârâbî, al-Rasâ`il, Risâlat fî Ithbât al-Mufâraqât, pp. 3,5,7; al-Ta‘lîqât, pp.
10,12-13; al-Madîna al-Fâdila, p. 53; Ibn Sînâ, al-Shifâ`, al-Nafs, chapter
6, al-Ishârât, vol. 2, pp. 319-24, 334-42.
5
Ibn Sînâ, al-Ishârât., vol. 2, al-namat 3, pp. 319-323. See also F. Rahman,
Avicenna’s Psychology (London: Oxford University Press, 1952), pp. 50-
62.
6
Opera III, Partaw-nâma, pp. 23-4 (trans. by M. Aminrazavi in Suhrawardî’s
Theory of Knowledge, p. 124). For another argumentation of
Suhrawardî, see p. 58 in the preceding chapter.
7
Ibid., pp. 25-6 (trans. by M. Aminrazavi in Suhrawardî’s Theory of
Knowledge, p. 125).
8
Suhrawardî, Opera I,al-Talwîhât,p.115.
9
Mullâ Sadrâ, in his major work Asfâr has devoted four chapters to the
discussion of the principiality of existence (asâlat al-wujûd). He
mentions some views, as well as their objections, and answers one by
one. Finally, he demonstrates his own doctrine by several arguments.
Asfâr, I/1, pp. 38-74.
10
Mullâ Sadrâ, Asfâr, IV/1, pp. 11-14.
11
Mullâ Sadrâ,al-Mashâ‘ir,p.30. al-Mashâ‘ir is one of the famous works of
Mullâ Sadrâ in Metaphysics. It has been edited and translated into
French by Henry Corbin entitled as Le Livre des pénétrations
métaphysiques (Paris and Tehran, 1965), and into English by Parviz
Morewedge entitled as The Metaphysics of Mullâ Sadrâ (New York:
SSIPS, 1992).
12
Asfâr, IV/1, pp. 47-8.
13
See above, n. 8.
128 Chapter Four: The Human Soul and Knowledge
14
Ibid., pp. 11-23.
15
Ibid., pp. 326-7, 347.
16
Ibid., pp. 51, 121-3, 134-6.
17
Ibid., pp. 47-8.
18
Suhrawardî, Opera II, Hikmat al-Ishrâq, pp. 110-111. It should be noted
that sometimes Suhrawardî uses the term “wujûd” (existence) in his
examination of self-experience. See above, n. 8.
19
Mullâ Sadrâ, Asfâr, IV/1, p. 47. However, we have seen before, in chapter
1 (p. 23), that Mullâ Sadrâ has interpreted the illuminative term “nûr” in
his own terminology as “wujûd.”
20
The problem of God’s knowledge of His Essence (al-‘ilm bi-dhâtihî) will be
examined in the following chapter.
21
Suhrawardî, Opera I, al-Talwîhât, p. 116.
22
Fârâbî, Risâlat fî Ithbât al-Mufâriqât, pp. 3, 7.
23
Ibn Sînâ, al-Ishârât., vol. 2, al-namat 3, pp. 319-323.
24
Ibn Sînâ, al-Ta‘lîqât, pp. 79,80,82.
25
Sabzavârî, Sharh Manzûma, p. 185.
26
See above, pp. 70-74.
27
Suhrawardî, Opera I, al-Talwîhât, pp. 69-75; al-Mashâri’, pp. 484-489;
Opera II, Hikmat al-Ishrâq, pp. 110-116
28
Opera, II, Hikmat al-Ishrâq, p. 110.
29
Ibid., pp. 110-111 (trans. by M. Ha`irî, as stated in The principle of
Epistemology in Islamic Philosophy, p. 72).
30
Ibid., p. 112.
31
Suhrawardî, Opera I, al-Talwîhât, pp. 70-74. For more explanation, see M.
Ha`irî, Knowledge by Presence, pp. 121-165.
32
Suhrawardî, Opera I, al-Mashâri‘, p. 484.
33
Suhrawardî, Opera I, al-Talwîhât, p.70.
Al-‘Ilm al-Hudûrî (Knowledge by Presence) 921
34
H. Landolt, “Suhrawardî’s “Tales of initiation,” Journal of The American
Oriental Society, vol. 107, no. 3 (July-September, 1987), p. 480.
35
Opera I, al-Talwîhât, p. 70 (trans. by M. Ha`irî as stated in Knowledge by
Presence, pp. 329-330).
36
Ibid., pp. 70-4.
37
Mullâ Sadrâ, Asfâr, I/1, pp. 38-74.
38
al-Mashâ‘ir, p. 30.
39
Asfâr, IV/1, pp. 47-8.
40
Ibid., III/1, pp. 156-7.
41
Ibn Sînâ, al-Ta‘lîqât, pp. 79,160,161,162.
42
For Suhrawardî see: Opera II, Hikmat al-Ishrâq, pp. 111-113; for Mullâ
Sadrâ see: al-Mabda` wa al-Ma‘âd, pp. 80-83.
43
See F. Rahman, Avicenna’s Psychology (London: Oxford University Press,
1952), pp. 25-40.
44
Opera I, al-Talwîhât, pp. 71-3.
45
Ibid., pp. 71-3; al-Mashâri‘, pp. 484-5.
46
Opera I, al-Mashâri‘, p.484-5. (trans. by M. Hâ`irî as stated in The principle
of Epistemology in Islamic Philosophy, p. 94-95).
47
The translator, M. Hâ`irî, here prefers the word “reality” as the more
suitable translation of dhât.
48
Opera I, al-Mashâri‘, p.485. (trans. by M. Hâ`irî as stated in The principle
of Epistemology in Islamic Philosophy, p. 94-95).
49
The important thirteenth century philosopher, scientist, and Shî‘îte
theologian Nasîr al-Dîn al-Tûsî was a great follower of Ibn Sînâ, and one
of the most important commentator on his al-Ishârât. He was, however,
influenced by certain views of the Illuminationist philosophers, although
the exact extent and nature of this influence still needs to be closely
determined.
50
Tûsî, in his notes on Ibn Sînâ’s al-Ishârât wa al-Tanbîhât, vol. 3, al-namat
7, pp. 714-92 (trans. by N. Heer in his translation of Jâmî’s al-Durra al-
Fâkhira, p. 46).
130 Chapter Four: The Human Soul and Knowledge
51
Ibid., pp. 714-715.
52
Tûsî, Sharh-i Mas`alat al-‘ilm (Mashhad: Matba‘a Jâmi‘a, 9162), p. 32.
53
Mullâ Sadrâ, Asfâr, IV/1, pp. 12-14. See above, p. 78.
54
The doctrine of “substantial movement” has been considered as a novel
theory demonstrated by Mullâ Sadrâ Shîrâzî. He has discussed the issue
and its related problems in detail in Asfâr, I/3, pp. 80-113. For more
explanation, see F. Rahman, The Philosophy of Mullâ Sadrâ (Albany:
SUNY Press, 1975), pp. 94-124.
55
Asfâr, IV/1, pp. 16-17.
56
Ibid., p. 51, 120-123, 133-5, 221-230.
57
Ibid., pp. 133-6.
58
Mullâ Sadrâ, Ta‘lîqa ‘alâ Sharh-i Hikmat al-Ishrâq, p. 454.
59
Mullâ Sadrâ, al-‘Arshîya, pp. 237-8 (trans. by J.W. Morris as stated in The
Wisdom of the Throne, p. 138).
60
A very similar idea has been already held by Suhrawardî. In his Hikmat al-
Ishrâq (p.213).
61
Mullâ Sadrâ, Asfâr, IV/1, pp. 51-2, 73-77, 133-6.
62
Ibid., p. 121.
63
Mullâ Sadrâ, al-‘Arshîya, p. 228 (trans. by J.W. Morris as stated in The
Wisdom of the Throne, p. 115).
64
Mullâ Sadrâ, Asfâr, III/1, pp. 157-164.
65
Mullâ Sadrâ, al-‘Arshîya, p. 236 (trans. by J.W. Morris as stated in The
Wisdom of the Throne, p. 134).
66
Mullâ Sadrâ, Asfâr, III/1, pp. 157-9; al-Mabda` wa al-Ma‘âd, pp. 80-1.
67
Ibid., p. 161; al-Mabda` wa al-Ma‘âd, p. 81.
68
Asfâr, IV/1, p. 140-142.
CHAPTER 5
God and “Knowledge by presence”
external object and him who sees. In other words, the act of
vision happens when the object is at the presence of the
subject. The knowledge of God (Nûr al-Anwâr, literally, the
Light of Lights), is of this kind, that is, a kind of presence, which
infers a direct, illuminational relationship between God and
things. Since all things are in the presence of the Light of
Lights, all things are manifest (zâhir) to it; hence the Light of
Light knows all things by presence. Therefore, God’s vision and
knowledge are the same.30 Consequently, God knows things
directly because of this relationship of ishrâq (illumination) and
does not need any intermediate cognitive forms.31
In this regard, Tûsî’s consideration of God’s knowledge
may be accounted as that of a follower or supporter of
Suhrawardî’s idea. To examine this, let us have a glance at
Tûsî’s argumentation. Rejecting Ibn Sînâ’s doctrine of forms in
God’s mind, Tûsî, in this sense, departs from the traditional
peripatetic view. His profound examination of the issue will
throw light on our survey of the fact that the epistemological
relation between God and His effects happens by virtue of
knowledge by presence. He argues that just as the soul knows
such imaginative and intellective forms as it itself creates
directly, not through any preceding forms, but because it is
their creator, so does God know things directly because they
flow from Him as His creations, not through any preceding
cognitive forms.32 The affinity of this view with that of
Suhrawardî in certain essential respects is obvious: both deny
Ibn Sînâ’s cognitive forms and identify God’s knowledge of
things with the fact that things flow from God, viz., a direct
knowledge based upon God’s creative activity.
142 Chapter Five: God and Knowledge by Presence
1
Fârâbî, al-Ta‘lîqât, pp. 8, 12; Kitâb al-Fusûs, p. 18, 20-21; Ibn Sînâ, al-
Ishârât., vol. 4, al-namat 7, pp. 708-9; al-Najât, pp. 99-100, 102-3; al-
Ta‘lîqât, pp. 78-9, 81, 97; Ghazzâlî, al-Iqtisâd fi al-I‘tiqâd, pp. 99-100;
Tahâfut al-Falâsifa, pp. 188-201; al-Râzî, al-Mabâhith al-Mashriqîya, vol.
1, pp. 491-5; Suhrawardî, Opera II, Hikmat al-Ishrâq, pp. 150-153; Tûsî,
Sharh Mas`alat al-‘Ilm, pp. 38-44; Ibn Rushd, Tahâfut al-Tahâfut, pp.
Al-‘Ilm al-Hudûrî (Knowledge by Presence) 929
Suhrawardî, al-Mutârahât, pp. 377-9; Mullâ Sadrâ, Asfâr, I/2, pp. 127-
130; F. Rahman, The Philosophy of Mullâ Sadrâ, pp. 74-81.
17
Ibn Sînâ, al-Rasâ`il, Risâla al-Hudûd, p. 117; Bahmanyâr, al-Tahsîl, p. 519;
Mîr Dâmâd, al-Qabasât, p. 53; Suhrawardî, Hikmat al-Ishrâq, p. 62; al-
Mutârihât, pp. 376-7; Mullâ Sadrâ, Asfâr, I/2, p. 127. In Hikmat al-Ishrâq
(p. 62).
18
Mullâ Sadrâ, al-Mashâ‘ir, p. 66.
19
Fârâbî, al-Ta‘lîqât, pp. 8, 12; Kitâb al-Fusûs, p. 18, 20-21; Ibn Sînâ, al-
Ishârât., vol. 4, al-namat 7, pp. 708-9; al-Najât, pp. 99-100, 102-3; al-
Ta‘lîqât, pp. 78-9, 81, 97; Ghazzâlî, al-Iqtisâd fi al-I‘tiqâd, pp. 99-100;
Tahâfut al-Falâsifa, pp. 188-201; al-Râzî, al-Mabâhith al-Mashriqîya, vol.
1, pp. 491-5; Suhrawardî, Opera II, Hikmat al-Ishrâq, pp. 150-153; Tûsî,
Sharh Mas`alat al-‘Ilm, pp. 38-44; Ibn Rushd, Tahâfut al-Tahâfut, pp.
447-468; Jâmî, al-Durrat al-Fâkhira, pp. 14-24.
The problem of God's knowledge, particularly His knowledge of things,
has been assumed as a main part of Christian theology as well. Thomas
Aquinas (1225-1274) has asserted:
"The forms of all things occur in the essence of God, so He, at
first, apprehends these forms by presence, not through other
forms but rather through those identical forms."
P.K. Meagher, Encyclopedic Dictionary of Religion (Washington, D. C.:
Corpus, 1979), p. 1826.
20
It has been said that this issue is one of the most difficult of all
philosophical questions in which some great sages, in spite of their
sagacity and sharp-sightedness, have committed some blunders. Mullâ
Sadrâ, al-Mabda` wa al-Ma‘âd, p. 90.
21
Mullâ Sadrâ, Asfâr, III/1, pp. 180-2; al-Mabda` wa al-Ma‘âd, pp. 90-91;
Sabzavârî, Asrâr al-Hikam, pp. 67-68; Tabâtabâ`î, Nihâya al-Hikma
(Tehran: Intishârât-i al-Zahrâ, 1984), pp. 326-9.
22
Ibn Sînâ, al-Ishârât wa al-Tanbîhât, vol. 3, al-Namat 7, pp. 712-14; al-
Ta‘lîqât, p. 82.
23
Ibn Sînâ, al-Najât, pp. 102-5; Ibn Rushd, Tahâfut al-Tahâfut, 447-468.
24
This doctrine of Ibn Sînâ’s was severely criticized by al-Ghazzâlî (d.
505/1111) and al-Râzî (d. 606/1209). In this respect, al-Ghazzâlî has
Al-‘Ilm al-Hudûrî (Knowledge by Presence) 923
38
Asfâr, I/3, pp. 403-407,417.
39
Asfâr, III/1, pp. 180-182; al-Mabda` wa al-Ma‘âd, pp. 91-123. F. Rahman,
The Philosophy of Mullâ Sadrâ, pp. 146-163; See H. Landolt, “Ghazâlî
and Religionswissenschaft,” p. 21, n. 928.
40
The theory of basît al-haqîqa kull al-ashyâ` has been profoundly
considered and also demonstrated by Mullâ Sadrâ in his works. Asfâr,
I/2, pp. 368-72; III/1, pp. 100-104; al-Mabda` wa al-Ma‘âd, pp. 43-6; al-
Mashâ‘ir, pp. 62-3.
41
Al-Mashâ‘ir, p. 59 (trans. by P. Morewedge in the same page ).
42
Asfâr, I/1, pp. 117-8, 276. For the discussion of systematic ambiguity
(tashkîk) of existence, see Mullâ Sadrâ, Asfâr, I/1, pp. ; F. Rahman, The
Philosophy of Mullâ Sadrâ, pp. 34-7.
43
Al-‘Arshîya, p. 224 (trans. by J.W. Morris as stated in The Wisdom of the
Throne, pp. 104-105).
44
Al-Mashâ‘ir, pp. 69-70 (Trans. by P. Morewedge in the same page).
45
Asfâr, I/3, pp. 407, 417.
46
Asfâr, III/1, pp. 164-7, 259-260; al-‘Arshîya, p. 225.
47
For Sabzavârî’s view see his notes on Mullâ Sadrâ’s Asfâr, IV/1, pp. 179-
81 (n. 1); III/1, pp.164-966 (n. 3); for Mesbâh’s opinion see: Ta‘lîqa., pp.
205, 256-7.
48
Asfâr, III/1, p. 176; al-Mabda` wa al-Ma‘âd, pp. 89-90; al-‘Arshîya, p. 224.
49
Mullâ Sadrâ, Risâla fî al-Qadâ` wa al-Qadar, p. 152 [trans. by D. Ede as
stated in Mullâ Sadrâ and the Problem of Freedom and Determinism
(Ph.D. thesis, McGill University, 1978), p. 52].
50
Ibid., p. 152.
51
Mullâ Sadrâ, Risâla fî al-Qadâ` wa al-Qadar, p. 152 [trans. by D. Ede as
stated in Mullâ Sadrâ and the Problem of Freedom and Determinism
(Ph.D. thesis, McGill University, 1978), p. 54].
52
Mullâ Sadrâ, al-Mabda` wa al-Ma‘âd, p. 121-3.
53
F. Rahman, The Philosophy of Mullâ Sadrâ (Albany: SUNY Press, 1976),
pp. 162-3.
CONCLUSION
Conclusion
1
Mullâ Sadrâ, al-Mashâ‘ir (New York: SSIPS, 1992), p.6 (trans. by
P.Morewedge in the same page).
2
Ibid., p. 30.
3
Ibid., p. 63.
4
Suhrawardî, Opera II, Hikmat al-Ishrâq, p. 13 [trans. by M. Aminrazavi in
Suhrawardî’s Theory of Knowledge (Ph. D. Thesis, Temple University,
1989), p. 174].
5
Ibid., p. 106 [trans. by M. Aminrazavi in Suhrawardî’s Theory of
Knowledge (Ph. D. Thesis, Temple University, 1989), p. 175].
6
S.H. Nasr, “Post-Avicenna Islamic Philosophy and the study of Being,” in
Parviz Morewedge (ed.), Philosophy of Existence (New York: Fordham
University Press, 1982), p. 341.
7
F. Rahman, The Philosophy of Mullâ Sadrâ (Albany: SUNY Press, 1975), p.
4.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Bibliography
I. BOOKS
Morewedge, Parviz, A Study in Ibn Sînâ and Sûfîsm, Ph.D. Diss., Los
Angeles: University of California, 1969.
--------, Al-Farabi and His School, London, New York: Routledge, 1992.
Walbridge, John T., The Science of Mystic Lights, Qutb al-Dîn shîrâzî
and the illumination tradition in Islamic Philosophy,
Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1992.
II. ARTICLES
Ghaffar Khan, Hafiz A., "Shah Wali Allah:On The Nature, Origin,
Definition, and Classification of Knowledge," Journal of
Islamic Studies,vol. 3, no. 2 (1992), Oxford: Oxford University
Press, pp. 203-213.
---------, “Sadr dl-Dîn Shîrâzî (Mullâ Sadrâ), His life, Doctrines and
Significance,” Indo-Iranica, vol. XIV, no. 4 (December, 1961),
Calcutta: Iran Society, pp. 6-16.
The Book: This book explores the issue of knowledge by presence as an epistemological problem in
philosophy. Al-`Ilm al-Huduri (knowledge by presence) deserves as an epistemological bridge
between philosophy and mysticism. This book is a comparative study of the epistemology of
Suhrawardî and Mullâ Sadrâ Shîrâzî, two Muslim thinkers of the 6th/12th and 11th/17th century. It
focuses on two main issues: Illuminative theory of knowledge and, in the framework of this theory,
Mullâ Sadrâ's doctrine of knowledge by presence (al-'ilm al-hudûrî) studied in the context of his
philosophical system (al-hikmah al-muta'âlîyah). Mullâ Sadrâ's doctrine of knowledge by presence is
the corner stone of his epistemological system. In the light of this doctrine, he gives a new definition
of knowledge, an innovative interpretation of its division into al-'ilm al-hudûrî and al-'ilm al-husûlî,
and, finally, a systematic chain of various kinds of knowledge by presence (e.g., self-knowledge,
God's knowledge of His Essence and God's knowledge of things). These three aspects of his doctrine
have been surveyed and, in comparing them with Suhrawardî's theory, evaluated in this book.
The Author: Dr. Sayyed Mohammad Reza Hejazi is Professor of Islamic Philosophy, Mysticism,
Religious Studies and Islamic Theology at I.M. Seminary, Director of the Islamic Studies and Research
Academy (ISRA), California, USA, Chairman of A.B.A. Assembly of North America, and a founder
member and a Trustee of the Ibn Sina Health Foundation of North America (ISHFNA). He has also
served as Director at the I.E.C., Washington D.C. and was a Chairman at the I.I.N.Y., New York, USA.
He holds a Master of Arts degree in Islamic Jurisprudence from Elmiyeh Seminary of Qom, a
doctorate in Islamic Philosophy from B.U.C. Institute of Qom, a second Master of Arts degree in
Epistemology and Islamic Mysticism from McGill University, Montreal, Canada; and a second
doctorate in Philosophy of Ethics from Catholic University of America, Washington D.C., USA. Dr.
Hejazi has published 22 books in Arabic, Persian and English. He has also published more than 18
articles in different languages and participated in about 28 international and inter-disciplinary
Seminars, Conferences and Academic Workshops. In addition to his teaching and writing, Dr. Hejazi
serves as a consultant in the fields of education, morality, religion and philosophy.
Al-`Ilm al-Hudûrî
Knowledge by Presence