The Relevance of Romanticism - Essays On German Romantic Philosophy (Dalia Nassar, 2014)
The Relevance of Romanticism - Essays On German Romantic Philosophy (Dalia Nassar, 2014)
The Relevance of Romanticism - Essays On German Romantic Philosophy (Dalia Nassar, 2014)
Title Pages
(p.i) The Relevance of Romanticism (p.ii)
(p.iv)
With offices in
Argentina Austria Brazil Chile Czech Republic France Greece
Guatemala Hungary Italy Japan Poland Portugal Singapore
South Korea Switzerland Thailand Turkey Ukraine Vietnam
Page 1 of 2
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Title Pages
987654321
Printed in the United States of America
on acid-free paper
Page 2 of 2
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Acknowledgments
(p.vii) Acknowledgments
I would like to thank the contributors to this volume, from whose work I have
learned and with whom I have enjoyed working. I would also like to acknowledge
the support of the Australian Research Council Discovery Early Career Research
Award (DE120102402), which enabled me to undertake and complete this
project. Finally, I wish to thank Ryan Feigenbaum for his invaluable help and
editorial work on the manuscript. (p.viii)
Page 1 of 1
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Abbreviations
(p.ix) Abbreviations
Frequently cited works have been identified by the following abbreviations.
GA
Gesamtausgabe der Bayerischen Akademie der Wissenschaften.
Edited by Reinhard Lauth et al. Stuttgart: Frommann-Holzboog,
1962–2012.
FW
Fichtes Werke. Edited by Immanuel Hermann Fichte. Berlin: W. de
Gruyter, 1971.
FA
Sämtliche Werke (Frankfurter Ausgabe). Edited by H. Birus et al.
Frankfurt am Main: Deutscher Klassiker Verlag, 1985–1999.
LA
Die Schriften zur Naturwissenschaft. Edited by D. Kuhn et al.
Weimar: Hermann Bölhaus Nachfolger, 1947.
MA
Sämtliche Werke nach Epochen seines Schaffens (Münchner
Ausgabe). Edited by K. Richter et al. Munich: Carl Hanser, 1985–98.
WA
Goethes Werke (Weimarer Ausgabe). Edited by P. Raabe et al.
Weimar: Hermann Böhlau, 1887–1919.
NS
Page 1 of 3
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Abbreviations
HW
Johann Gottfried Herder: Werke in zehn Bänden. Edited by Ulrich
Gaier et al. Frankfurt am Main: Deutscher Klassiker Verlag, 1985–
2000.
HSW
Hölderlin: Sämtliche Werke (Kleine Stuttgarter Ausgabe). Edited by
Friedrich Beissner. Stuttgart: W. Kohlhammer, 1962.
HFA
Sämtliche Werke. Historisch-kritische Ausgabe (Frankfurter
Ausgabe). Edited by D. E. Sattler. Frankfurt am Main: Stroemfeld/
Roter Stern, 1975–2008.
Immanuel Kant
AA
Gesammelte Schriften. Edited by Preußischen Akademie der
Wissenschaft. Berlin: de Gruyter, 1900–.
HKA
Werke: Historisch-kritische Ausgabe. Edited by H. M. Baumgartner,
W. G. Jacobs, and H. Krings. Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt: Frommann-
Holzboog, 1976–.
SW
Schellings Sämmliche Werke. Edited by K. F. A. Schelling. Stuttgart:
Cotta, 1856–1861.
KA
Kritische Friedrich-Schlegel-Ausgabe. Edited by E. Behler, J. J.
Anstett, and H. Eichner. Paderborn: Schöningh, 1958–.
FSSW
Page 2 of 3
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Abbreviations
All citations will contain volume and page numbers. In cases where there are
separate parts to a volume, the volume number will be followed by a “/” and then
the part number.
Page 3 of 3
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Contributors
(p.xi) Contributors
Karl Ameriks is the McMahon-Hank Professor of Philosophy at the
University of Notre Dame. He is the author of Kant and the Historical
Turn (Oxford, 2006), Kant and the Fate of Autonomy (Cambridge,
2000), and editor of the Cambridge Companion to German Idealism
(Cambridge, 2000). He is a founding coeditor of Internationales
Jahrbuch des Deutschen Idealismus (International Yearbook of
German Idealism), and since 1994 he has served as a coeditor of the
approximately seventy-volume series Cambridge Texts in the History
of Philosophy. Professor Ameriks was elected a fellow of the American
Academy of Arts and Sciences in 2009. He is also the recipient of
several fellowships from the National Endowment for the Humanities,
the Earhart Foundation (most recently in 2010), and an Alexander
von Humboldt Fellowship. He is a former member of the American
Philosophical Association Board of Officers (2003–2005) and past
president of the Central Division of the American Philosophical
Association (2004–2005) and the North American Kant Society (1991–
1994).
Frederick Beiser, one of the world’s leading historians of German
philosophy, is Professor of Philosophy at Syracuse University. He has
also taught at Harvard, Yale, Pennsylvania, Indiana, and Wisconsin.
His book The Fate of Reason: German Philosophy from Kant to Fichte
won the 1987 Thomas J. Wilson Prize for the Best First Book. He is
also the author of German Idealism: The Struggle against
Subjectivism (Harvard, 2002), The Romantic Imperative (Harvard,
2003), and more recently, Schiller: A Re-examination (Oxford, 2008).
Brady Bowman is Assistant Professor of Philosophy at the
Pennsylvania State University. Before coming to Penn State, he was a
research associate in philosophy at the Friedrich Schiller Universität
Page 1 of 5
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Contributors
Page 2 of 5
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Contributors
Page 3 of 5
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Contributors
Page 4 of 5
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Contributors
(p.xvi)
Page 5 of 5
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Introduction
Introduction
Dalia Nassar
DOI:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199976201.003.0001
Page 1 of 12
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Introduction
known as romanticism. Science and art, philosophy and poetry, the romantics
repeatedly proclaimed, should become one. The various disciplines, as Schelling
put it in the introductory remarks to the inaugural edition of his Zeitschrift für
spekulative Physik (1800–1802), must “enter into one another in the most
precise and closest alliance, in order to bring forth the highest, where the
interest of art and poetry with science and vice versa begin to become absolutely
one and the same” (HKA 1/8, 250–51). Hölderlin, Goethe, Novalis, Schelling,
Schlegel, and Schleiermacher each sought to realize this ideal in his practice as
a poet, philosopher, and scientist. Their aim was nothing less than developing a
new way of knowledge and a new compendium of knowledge, a “bible” or an
“encyclopedia,” as Schlegel and Novalis called it, in which the different
disciplines are united by common insights and goals.1
The general historical interest in romanticism is, perhaps, not surprising. After
all, the so-called romantic movement, which began in Germany in the 1790s, has
had a lasting effect on Western culture. Romantic theories of literature, romantic
conceptions of nature, and romantic interest in non-Western culture (especially
Indian culture and language) have played significant roles in shaping both the
nineteenth and twentieth centuries. However, the recent revival does not simply
have to do with a desire to understand the past, or an attempt to grapple with
the “romantic legacy.” For it is a specifically philosophical revival, motivated by
philosophical questions.
Before discussing the reasons behind this philosophical interest, I want to note
that, at least within the Anglophone context, philosophical romanticism has
generally been regarded in the wider sense of the term “romantic.”5 This is in
contrast to the narrower sense that is usually associated with the Jena
romantics, or Frühromantik in Germany, and specifically denotes the circle of
friends and acquaintances in Jena who congregated around Friedrich and
Page 2 of 12
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Introduction
August Wilhelm Schlegel and their journal, the Athenäum.6 The recent
(Anglophone) reception of romanticism almost always includes Hölderlin (who
was only associated with the Jena group indirectly through Schelling and Hegel)
and often includes Schelling,7 as well as figures who were directly connected to
the Jena romantics, but did not contribute to the Athenäum, such as Goethe.8
Thus, the term romantic—at least within the Anglophone context—means
something like an extended family of thinkers rather than a smaller coterie.9
The volume is divided into four parts. The first consists in a debate between
Frank and Beiser, in which they elaborate their differing interpretations of
romantic philosophy and address their disagreement. Frank’s “What Is Early
German Romantic Philosophy?” recounts some of his key claims regarding both
the development and the character of philosophical romanticism, by situating it
within a realist and skeptical critique of Fichtean and Reinholdian
foundationalist philosophy. Frank thus introduces an English-language audience
to his long-held and influential understanding of romanticism as a distinctive
philosophical movement that should not be identified with idealism. In contrast,
Page 3 of 12
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Introduction
Frank contends that romanticism was a realist movement that was opposed to
the view that the “absolute” is knowable or attainable.
Each of the three following parts of the book focuses on a central concern of the
German romantics: Part 2 considers history, culture, and education; Part 3
concerns aesthetics and mythology; and Part 4 investigates science and nature.
As each of the chapters demonstrates, the “romantic imperative” motivates the
romantic project, and guides the romantics’ conceptions of truth and knowledge,
beauty and reality. In every insistence, the romantics insist on uniting a poetic
and philosophical way of knowing, of bringing aesthetic insight into our
understanding of social and natural phenomena, and scientific knowledge into
human life and art.
Part 2 focuses on romantic views of human culture and education. The romantic
conceptions of history, language, and sociability, as well as the idea of Bildung,
are considered in light of contemporary social and political thought. Karl
Ameriks’s “History, Succession, and German Romanticism” investigates the
romantic notion of a “progressive universal poetry” and argues that it provides a
useful framework for defining a distinctively romantic conception of history, one
that is all at once political, philosophical, and aesthetic in a broadly (p.4)
religious sense. Ameriks contends that, especially for our late modern age, this
early German romantic conception has advantages over merely linear, circular,
or chaotic conceptions. By situating the romantic model in the context of
debates about the teleological and providential nature of history, as understood
by Kant, Reinhold, and Hegel, and comparing it with views developed in later
antiteleological writings by figures such as Burckhardt, Nietzsche, and
Heidegger, Ameriks illustrates the ways in which the romantic model remains
the most promising.
Page 4 of 12
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Introduction
Jane Kneller’s “Sociability and the Conduct of Philosophy: What We Can Learn
from Early German Romanticism,” describes the model of sociability developed
by the early German romantics with the aim of showing its relevance to
academic discourses that seek to be more diverse and inclusive. Kneller begins
by linking the early romantics’ conception of “symphilosophizing” to the art of
“reciprocal communication” hinted at by Kant at the end of the “Critique (p.5)
of Aesthetic Judgment” and to the transformation of academic discourse in Jena
during that period. She goes on to discuss the ways in which the work of three of
the central figures of early German romanticism—Friedrich Schlegel, Novalis,
and Friedrich Schleiermacher—developed Kant’s notion of a “sociability that
befits our humanity” by socializing Kant’s account of genius, thereby giving rise
to a theory of genial conversation that is still worthy of study and emulation.
Page 5 of 12
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Introduction
sense and this poetology are enacted in Hölderlin’s late, major fragment
“Rousseau.”
Brady Bowman’s “On the Defense of Literary Value: From Early German
Romanticism to Analytic Philosophy of Literature” argues that doubts about
literature’s cognitive relevance are shaped today in part by the institutional fate
and ambivalent legacy of early German romanticism. While the romantics
succeeded in bringing modern literature to the university as an academic
discipline, their attempt to revolutionize traditional scientific cognition failed,
rendering literary studies a conceptual orphan within the university. Bowman
contends that German romanticism has generated two competing views of the
relation between literature and the overtly truth-seeking disciplines. The
Schlegelian legacy of skepticism, antirealism, and antifoundationalism, still vital
to poststructuralist thought, he argues, is powerless to give a positive account of
literary value; it offers no principled justification of the institutions on which it
nevertheless depends. In contrast, Bowman locates a complementarist legacy
associated with figures like Schiller and Schelling, which emphasizes literature’s
cognitive priority to discursive knowledge and its role as the cognitive fulfillment
of such knowledge. This tradition, Bowman maintains, offers important
resources to aesthetic cognitivism for articulating and defending the value of
literature and the institutions that support it. Drawing on John Gibson’s 2007
work Fiction and the Weave of Life, he goes on to argue that the expanded
romantic space of cognition is best understood in terms of a complementarity
between propositional knowledge and Cavellian “acknowledgment.” When
viewed in these terms, Bowman concludes, German romantic theories (p.6) of
aesthetic experience can provide systematic orientation for current analytic
philosophy of literature.
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Introduction
object of the past, but a picture that is still shaping a central strand in the
contemporary debate in philosophical aesthetics on our emotional responses to
fiction. Although she does not use Schlegel’s approach to argue against this view
directly, Gorodeisky suggests that his philosophical method offers resources for
unraveling a central confusion in this contemporary debate.
Page 7 of 12
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Introduction
The final two chapters of the volume focus on what the authors have called
“romantic empiricism,” which, as Amanda Jo Goldstein puts it, emphasizes “the
scene of empirical observation.” In her “Irritable Figures: Herder’s Poetic
Empiricism,” Goldstein challenges the “two culture” framework that has shaped
the pursuit of knowledge over the last two centuries, and argues for a
reappraisal of romantic philosophy of science, as developed by Johann Gottfried
Herder. Goldstein begins by tracing the development of Herder’s philosophy of
science, its relation to the legacies of New Scientific experimentalism and
classical empiricist psychology, and its engagement with the emergent sciences
of life. She then elucidates Herder’s account of perception and cognition, which
Page 8 of 12
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Introduction
Notes:
(1) . Schlegel writes that “the encyclopedia must be constructed out of a
synthesis of the science of knowledge [Wissenschaft] and the science of art
[Kunstlehre]” (KA 18, 374, no. 652). Novalis describes the encyclopedia as “the
book of all books” and as “producing a living scientific organon” (NS 3, 558, no.
21; NS 4, 263).
(2) . Two recent articles enumerate this (to many, surprising) course of events.
See Elizabeth Millán-Zaibert, “The Revival of Frühromantik in the Anglophone
World,” and more recently Peter Thielke, “Recent Work on Early German
Idealism 1781–1801).” Although Thielke’s article looks at new work on German
idealism, he devotes several pages to detailing the rise of interest in
romanticism within the Anglophone context and recognizes that many of the
Page 9 of 12
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Introduction
(3) . The reasons why the romantics have been long overlooked by philosophers
have been elaborated at length by Beiser, “Introduction: Romanticism Now and
Then,” in The Romantic Imperative, 1–5.
(4) . See Robert Richards, The Romantic Conception of Life (2002) for views of
science and nature; Richard Eldridge, Leading a Human Life (1997) and The
Persistence of Romanticism (2011), on the significance of romantic thought for
epistemology; Michael Forster, German Philosophy of Language (2011) and
Kristin Gjesdal, Gadamer and the Legacy of Idealism (2009), for hermeneutics;
Paolo Diego Bubbio and Paul Redding, ed., Religion after Kant (2012) and John
H. Smith, Dialogues between Faith and Reason (2011) on romantic religion; Jane
Kneller, Kant and the Power of Imagination (2007) on theories of imagination and
their significance for social thought.
(5) . The meaning of “romantic” has long been contested. Arthur Lovejoy was
one of the first to challenge the notion that the word represents a specific
movement: “the word ‘romantic’ has come to mean so many things that, by itself,
it means nothing” (Arthur Lovejoy, “On the Discrimination of Romanticism,” in
Essays in the History of Ideas, 235). Beiser offers an account of the various
responses to Lovejoy, and also his own response in “The Meaning of ‘Romantic
Poetry,’” in The Romantic Imperative, 6–22. For the variety of meanings of the
word in the German context (and its various historical sources), see Hans
Eichner, “Germany / Romantisch—Romantik—Romantiker,” in ‘Romantic’ and its
Cognates.
(6) . Philippe Lacoue-Labarthe and Jean-Luc Nancy claim that the “romantic
period” can only be identified by a place—Jena—and a journal—the Athenäum
(The Literary Absolute, 12). Although Frank does not explicitly identify
romanticism with Jena and the late 1790s, he excludes Schleiermacher (who was
in Berlin) and Hölderlin (in Tübingen) from his major examinations of
romanticism, Einführung in die frühromantische Ästhetik and Unendliche
Annäherung. However, as he argues in Chapter 1 of this volume, Frühromantik
encompasses a large number of (lesser known) figures, and should be grasped in
terms of its questions and concerns, rather than in terms of its location.
Page 10 of 12
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Introduction
(8) . Goethe did, however, have editorial input on the journal. See Nicholas
Boyle, Goethe, the Poet and the Age, vol. 2, 646ff. In the German context, the
time period which in English is often described as “romantic” is identified as the
Goethezeit, the time of Goethe. This more inclusive term might be a better
translation of the Anglophone use of romantic than Frühromantik, which is much
more limited. For recent investigations into Goethe’s philosophical contributions
and his relationship to romanticism and idealism, see the special edition of the
Goethe Yearbook (vol. 18; 2011), co-edited by Elizabeth Millán and John H.
Smith, Goethe and German Idealism, and Nassar, The Romantic Absolute. Finally,
Herder has also received more attention in the context of romanticism in the
Anglophone context. See Michael Forster, After Herder and German Philosophy
of Language, and Amanda Jo Goldstein’s contribution to this volume, Chapter 15.
(10) . See Frank, Das individuelle Allgemeine; Das Sagbare und das Unsagbare;
Selbstgefühl: eine historisch-theoretische Erkundung. Beiser’s interests,
although primarily historical, nonetheless affirm the relevance of romanticism.
Page 11 of 12
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Introduction
Page 12 of 12
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
What Is Early German Romantic Philosophy?
DOI:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199976201.003.0002
Page 1 of 16
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
What Is Early German Romantic Philosophy?
What do the dates 1789 and 1796 refer to? They demarcate a space of thought
(“Denkraum”) that Konstellationsforschung has been studying in detail with
hitherto unknown precision and thoroughness. The beginning of this epoch is
marked at one end by Reinhold’s Essay towards a New Theory of the Human
Faculty of Representation (Versuch einer neuen Theorie des menschlichen
Vorstellungsvermögens) and by the second (and considerably reworked) edition
of Jacobi’s Letters on Spinoza’s Doctrine (Briefe über die Lehre Spinozas). At the
other end, the years 1795/96 mark the time in which Hölderlin developed his
important sketch “Judgment and Being” (Urtheil und Seyn), Novalis completed
his “Fichte Studies” (Fichte-Studien), and Friedrich Schlegel began his
“Philosophical Apprenticeship” (Philosophische Lehrjahre). These various
writings considered Fichte’s approach in the “Science of
Knowledge” (Wissenschaftslehre) to have been superseded. The intervening
years between 1789 and 1795/96 were molded by long disputes with the legacy
of orthodox theology, by Kant’s revolutionary spark in Tübingen, by Reinhold’s
attempts to systemize Kantian philosophy, and by the first emergence of doubt in
Jena and Klagenfurt concerning the feasibility of a philosophy that pretends to
derive and develop its whole content from and out of a single first principle. This
type of philosophical project was introduced by Reinhold’s “Elementary
Philosophy” (Elementarphilosophie) and by Fichte, who soon joined him and
adopted the programmatic label.
Page 2 of 16
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
What Is Early German Romantic Philosophy?
Von Herbert left space at the end of the letter, in order to invite Johann Benjamin
Erhard (1766–1826), the leading intellectual figure of the Reinhold circle, to add
some personal remarks. A few years later, in 1797, Novalis described Erhard as
“the only true friend” of the Reinhold circle (NS 4, 202). Erhard agrees with
Herbert’s portrait of the situation and specifies the shared anti-Fichtean
conviction it expresses:
From one point of view Herbert’s position regarding the one principle is
justified. A philosophy that starts out with one principle and pretends to
deduce everything from it will always be nothing more than a piece of
sophistry; only that philosophy which is capable of climbing to the highest
principle and manages to show how everything stands in harmony with
that principle without being deduced from it, only that philosophy is the
true one.4
It is not difficult to see how in this letter Erhard already starts the move,
motivated by the sterility of Elementary Philosophy, that will lead him to a
reaffiliation with the Kantian theory of ideas and the systematic use of
teleological principles embedded within it.
Page 3 of 16
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
What Is Early German Romantic Philosophy?
As a lawyer and liberal enemy of Fichte, another one of Reinhold’s pupils, Paul
Johann Anselm Feuerbach (the father of the famous philosopher Ludwig
Feuerbach and a fellow lodger with Friedrich Schlegel), spoke of the
“impossibility of a first absolute philosophical principle.”5 Friedrich Carl
Forberg, another former pupil of Reinhold’s and a dear friend of Novalis’s, who
later became the catalyst and then, alongside Fichte, the victim of the Atheism
Controversy in 1798, similarly proclaimed the impossibility of philosophical
foundations.6 Both Novalis’s “Fichte Studies” and Feuerbach’s text were most
likely requested by Niethammer as contributions to his journal, to which
Schlegel also contributed.7 It was essential for the newly founded Philosophical
Journal (Philosophisches Journal) to serve as a forum for discussing the
legitimacy or futility of a philosophy starting from a first principle.
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
What Is Early German Romantic Philosophy?
Absolute is transformed into an idea in the Kantian sense of the term. In what
follows I will show that Novalis and Friedrich Schlegel were quickly driven from
the first to the second consequence. But to begin with, I will consider the first
consequence.
With respect to the latter: in the play of appearance and reflection, self-
consciousness manifests an identity that it cannot represent as such. In Novalis’s
words: the bipartite form of judgment denies the monadic content. The
nominalized reflexive pronoun “self” stands for this detour or indirect
representation: “We abandon the identical,” writes Novalis in September 1795,
“in order to represent it” (NS 2, 104, no. 1). Hence self-consciousness is the
representation of something that is in itself nonpresentable. He writes,
In the expression reflection there is another layer of meaning which was already
prefigured in Novalis’s notion of an “illusory proposition.” Even if consciousness
emerges only through reflection, it is only a perverted and apparent one. The
Page 5 of 16
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
What Is Early German Romantic Philosophy?
reason for this view becomes clear when we take into account the fact that
Novalis thinks of consciousness as an “image” or “sign” of “Being” that
transforms Being into appearance. Indeed, another meaning of “reflection” is an
inverted mirroring (verkehrende Spiegelung). Our original consciousness—
Novalis speaks of a “self-feeling” or “sense of self”—stands in an inverted
position to reality. It is inverted because by reaching from out of itself,
consciousness encounters the (p.20) world secundo loco, as something
secondary. “Our theory has to proceed from the conditioned,” Novalis writes,
and not, as is the case with Fichte’s philosophy, from the unconditioned (NS 2,
147, no. 86). That which depends on Being, namely, consciousness, is not itself
that of which it is conscious (namely Being), but only copies or “represents” it
through a “sign” (NS 2, 106). Nonetheless, consciousness detects in itself the
means by which to correct this inversion by a second inversion (“ordine
inverso”) (NS 2, 127f., 131ff.). “There is always an alteration between image and
Being. The image is always the inversion of Being. What is located to the right of
the person appears in the image on the left” (NS 142, no. 63; cf. 114ff.). The
reflected mirror image or the self-reflection restores the original order, so that
the I becomes conscious of its ontological dependence on Being.9 Fichte,
according to Novalis, did not perform this self-reflection and consequently, in a
Berkeleyean vein, conceived Being as something dependent on a thematizing
consciousness or rather as some kind of inert condensation of an antecedent act.
Consequently, for the idealist, Being is neither understood as something positive
nor as a Kantian “absolute position,” but rather as a “negative concept” that only
demarcates itself against the truly positive concept of conscious action (GA 1/1,
498f.). But Novalis did not want to be an idealist.
Page 6 of 16
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
What Is Early German Romantic Philosophy?
But what is a self-feeling? The insight that Novalis achieves in a few steps leads
from the presupposition of an absolute identity to the presupposition of Being,
and, in so doing, to a second concept, whose meaning we have yet to clarify.
Hölderlin and Novalis are directly referring to Jacobi, and indirectly referring to
Kant and his famous thesis on Being.
Kant first presented this thesis in his early text The Only Possible Argument in
Support of a Demonstration of the Existence of God (1763). The indeterminate
verb “being” has a “completely simple” meaning, namely, position (“Position”)
(AA 2, 73; see also 70). Kant’s thesis resounds in Hölderlin’s discussion of
“Being, in the only sense of the word.”11 Position is nearly the name of the genus
or class “Being,” which is—Kant maintains—conceptually almost irresolvable or
unanalyzable (“unauflöslich”) (AA 2, 73). Almost unanalyzable because there is
nonetheless a double specification we can wrench from it, which distinguishes
relative and absolute positing. The relative position of a concept is one that
poses a general term in relation to a subject. This is the case in usual predicative
sentences. A concept is posited absolutely, by contrast, when something general
corresponds to it, and when the concept’s class of reference is not empty, as in
the following nonpredicative sentences: “There is a God” or “I am.” Strictly
speaking, the meaning of “Being” (qua existence) is restricted to the meaning of
the absolute position.
But how are Being and predication connected? What makes them conceivable as
varieties of position or positing? The synthesis in judgment (the “relative
position”) must be grasped as an inferior type of what Kant calls “absolute
Page 7 of 16
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
What Is Early German Romantic Philosophy?
Being—expresses the union of subject and object... Judgment. is... that kind
of separation by which object and subject become possible, the primordial
division [Seyn—drükt die Verbindung des Subjects und Objects aus.... (p.
22) Urtheil. ist... diejenige Trennung, wodurch Object und Subject
möglich wird, die Ur-theilung].
In exactly the same way, Novalis conceives of the manner in which existential
Being—embedded in the form of a judgment—mediates itself to consciousness,
as Pseudo-Being, or, as he drastically puts it, as “improper Being,” adding that
“improper Being [unrechtes Seyn] is an image of Being” (NS 2, 106, no. 2). In
the language of Kant: the relative position, which is constitutive for
consciousness, displays the absolute position in the form of judgment.
One might have noticed that Hölderlin and Novalis articulate the primordial
division in both semantic and epistemological terminology; they use “subject”
and “predicate” as well as “subject” of consciousness and its “object” in parallel
to “predicate” which is singular. This has to be seen in light of the fact that this
generation (unlike Kant) interprets the predicative “is” as an indication of
identity. In so doing they follow the Leibnizean thesis that all true judgments
consist in an analysis of what is comprehended in the subject term:
“praedicatum inest subjecto.” Moreover, the group operating in Tübingen was
influenced by the view, espoused by the logician and metaphysician Gottfried
Ploucquet, that predication is a statement of identity. Ploucquet’s writings were
canonical in the Tübingen Seminary and for a long time served as the basis for
the theses and dissertations produced there.12 If we want to bring this view (of
predication as identity) to some kind of convergence with the Kantian one, then
predication simply consists in a relative identification, while Being is an absolute
identification. By superimposing Kant’s famous thesis on Being and the
conception of predication as a statement of identity, a distinctive view emerges—
one that was shared by both Hölderlin and Novalis, and incidentally also by
Schelling—namely, the notion of the essence of absolute identity as enclosing a
ground that repels all consciousness. Being, the late Schelling will say, is prior to
thought (“unvordenklich”). In other words, there is no thought—no real
predicate—that can be inserted or presupposed in order to function as a ground
for deducing or grasping existence (SW 2/3, 227f., see also 262).
Now that the nexus between Being and identity has become clearer, we can take
the next step and ask: how can Being refer to a specific feeling, as Novalis
maintains? Again, the decisive inspiration stems directly from Jacobi, and
indirectly from Kant. It was Jacobi who, with the term “feeling,” moved the focus
Page 8 of 16
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
What Is Early German Romantic Philosophy?
The highest principle must not at all be something given, but something
freely produced, something fabricated [Erdichtetes], devised [Erdachtes],
in order to lay down the foundations for a general metaphysics.
(NS 2, 273)
This not only offers a strong response to the foundationalist context of absolute
idealism, but also illustrates the will to radically break with a philosophy based
on first principles and demonstrates an unexpected high regard for poetry.
But let us proceed step by step. The early romantic definition of philosophy as
“yearning for infinity” emphasizes the nonpossession, the lack, of a principle.18
If there is no safe foundation that presents itself to our consciousness as evident,
Page 9 of 16
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
What Is Early German Romantic Philosophy?
then it is possible to doubt each of our beliefs: “the clinging, the being glued to
the finite,” maintains Schlegel, “is the true character of dogmatism” (KA 12, 51).
So-called romantic irony allows for that; it is not a particular feature of the (p.
24) content, but a trait of the style of speech. Something is uttered ironically
when the way of saying it neutralizes the determinateness of the content, brings
it into suspense, or sets in motion a withdrawal from it in favor of an infinity of
options that might as well have been uttered in its place. Ironic speech keeps
open the irrepresentable location of the infinite by permanently discrediting the
finite as that which is not intended.
One of the deep convictions of the young intellectuals, who were later called the
Jena romantics, was that beliefs cannot be ultimately justified, but—as Schlegel
ironically puts it—“are eternally valid only for the time being” (KA 2, 179, no.
95).19 Like Reinhold’s students, the Jena romantics dismissed epistemological
foundationalism as the Scylla, without throwing themselves into the arms of the
Charybdis of skepticism, or “intellectual anarchism” as they also called it (NS 2,
288–89, no. 648).20 At the beginning of July 1796, during a visit with his former
fellow student Forberg,21 Novalis again takes up the question that marks the
beginning of his “Fichte Studies.”22 He writes, “What do I do when I
philosophize? I reflect on a ground...All philosophizing must result in such an
absolute ground” (NS 2, 269, no. 366).
What would it be like if this absolute, all-embracing ground were not given,
if this concept contained an impossibility: the drive to philosophize would
be an infinite activity—and therefore without end, because an eternal need
for an absolute ground would exist, which can only be partially sated—and
therefore would never cease.
Page 10 of 16
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
What Is Early German Romantic Philosophy?
I shall forgo the details of this claim and only anticipate the conclusion at which
Novalis arrives. Searching for an ultimate concept from which all the others can
be derived, he claims, is “nonsense” and leads us into the “areas of nonsense.”
“Representation” (Vorstellung) is the highest mental concept (i.e., concept
concerning mental entities). However, it is—just like all other concepts—
achieved through comparison between and abstraction from singular mental
acts and experiences. This means that if it is derived from these mental
operations, it cannot be their source. In other words, the pretension of
Page 11 of 16
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
What Is Early German Romantic Philosophy?
In light of the comfortable Fichtean liquidation of the external world and the
thing-in-itself, which Forberg had witnessed in Jena, he wrote in his Fragments
from my Papers that in the presence of Fichte he had “not felt differently than in
the company of a conjurer,” adding that he only begs God to save Kant from his
self-declared friends, since “as far as his enemies are concerned he probably will
be aware of them personally.”31 Like many of Reinhold’s (p.27) pupils, Forberg
stuck to the motto: Better to fail with Kant, than to win with Fichte.
Page 12 of 16
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
What Is Early German Romantic Philosophy?
Did Kant not emphasize with all the desirable clarity that, according to his
theory, “representation in itself does not produce its object in so far as existence
is concerned,” but ought to receive it from the world (KrV A125)? Novalis simply
offers a twist to this when he writes, “consciousness is a Being outside of Being
within Being.” He continues:
Being outside Being must not be proper Being [kein rechtes Sein].
The highest-ranking works of art are absolutely unobliging. They are ideals
that can—and should—please us only approximately: aesthetic imperatives.
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
What Is Early German Romantic Philosophy?
Around the time that Novalis was jotting down his thoughts about infinity, or
rather about the impossibility of philosophy as a search for knowledge, he
received a visit from Forberg in Jena, who, as Novalis remembers, “after a
longer interruption of our friendship showed...a heart full of tenderness toward
me” (NS 4, 187). As previously mentioned, Forberg had studied with Novalis (p.
28) under Reinhold. Apparently Forberg was so taken by Novalis’s views,
quoted above, that a year later, in his Letters on the Newest Philosophy, he
wrote:
Nothing else would follow than this: that the demand of reason could never
be completely met—that reason would have to continue its investigations
into the infinite, without bringing them to an end even into eternity. The
absolute thus would be nothing more than the idea of an impossibility.
But: is a goal that is unattainable less of a goal? Is the view towards the
sky less enchanting, only because once and forever it remains a VIEW?32
Notes:
(1) . Manfred Frank and Gerhard Kurz, eds., Materialien zu Schellings
philosophischen Anfängen (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1975), 122.
(3) . Ibid., 75f. The letter from von Herbert to Niethammer is dated May 6, 1794.
(5) . This is the title of his 1795 essay, which appeared in the Philosophisches
Journal 2, no. 2 (1795): 306–22.
(8) . Hölderlin’s “Urtheil und Seyn” (“Judgment and Being”) appeared in HSW 4,
226–7. Schlegel’s “Philosophische Lehrjahre” (“Philosophical Apprenticeship”)
appeared in KA 18. Novalis’s “Fichte-Studien” (“Fichte Studies”) is in NS 2, 104–
296.
(9) . See also Schelling for a similar conception: SW I/4, 85ff.; SW I/9, 230ff.
Page 14 of 16
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
What Is Early German Romantic Philosophy?
(12) . See Manfred Frank, Auswege aus dem deutschen Idealismus (Frankfurt am
Main: Suhrkamp, 2007), 13–14; Gottfried Ploucquet, Logik, trans. and ed.
Michael Franz (Hildesheim: Olms, 2006), xxxff.
(13) . Jacobi, Ueber die Lehre des Spinoza in Briefen an Herrn Moses
Mendelssohn. Neue vermehrte Auflage (Breslau: Löwe, 1789), 193f. The new
critical edition reference is Friedrich Heinrich Jacobi, Werke, vols. 1/1 and 1/2,
Schriften zum Spinozastreit, ed. Klaus Hammacher and Irmgard-Maria Piske
(Hamburg and Stuttgart-Bad Cannstadt: Meiner and Frommann-Holzboog,
1989). The old pagination is provided in the margins of the new critical edition.
(14) . Jacobi, Briefe (1789), 109; cf. Manfred Frank, Selbstgefühl. Eine historisch-
systematische Erkundung (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 2002).
(18) . See for instance KA 12, 7, 51; KA 18, 418, no. 1168; KA 18, 420, no. 1200.
Page 15 of 16
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
What Is Early German Romantic Philosophy?
(26) . Schmid, Empirische Psychologie (Jena: Cröker, 1791), 57f.; cf. Dieter
Henrich, Grundlegung aus dem Ich. Untersuchungen zur Vorgeschichte des
Idealismus Tübingen-Jena (1790–1794) (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 2004),
316; 600ff.; Immanuel Carl Diez, Briefwechsel und Kantische Schriften.
Wissensbegründung in der Glaubenskrise Tübingen-Jena (1790–1792), ed. Dieter
Henrich (Stuttgart: Klett-Cotta, 1997), 912 (from a report from Reinhold to
Erhard dated June 18, 1792).
(30) . Ibid., 59; cf. his argument against Fichte: Schmid, “Bruchstücke aus einer
Schrift über die Philosophie und ihre Principien,” Philosophisches Journal So the
Journal was quoted earlier and later. 3, no. 2 (1795): 95–132; here: 101.
(31) . Forberg, Fragmente aus meinen Papieren (Jena: J. G. Voigt, 1796), 74, 42.
Page 16 of 16
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Romanticism and Idealism
DOI:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199976201.003.0003
Keywords: German idealism, German romanticism, Manfred Frank, Frederick Beiser, foundationalism,
antifoundationalism, subjective idealism, absolute idealism
Page 1 of 15
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Romanticism and Idealism
to find, therefore, that the relationship between them has been so understudied.
What they have in common, and how they differ, is still very obscure. They are
indeed so obscure that some scholars have begun to dispute their proper
relationship.
Two such scholars are myself and Manfred Frank. Over the years we have
formed antithetical conceptions of the relationship between idealism and
romanticism. In his Unendliche Annäherung Frank has seen the early romantic
movement as fundamentally opposed to idealism.1 He has stressed the
opposition between these movements for two reasons: the romantics were
realist in their ontology, and they were antifoundationalist in their epistemology,
unlike the idealists, who were foundationalists. In my German Idealism and
Romantic Imperative I have placed the early romantic movement within German
idealism,2 which Frank and others see as a terrible mistake because it seems to
attribute Fichtean idealism and foundationalist concerns to the early romantics.
Recently, Frank has declared our differences on this score in a prominent (p.31)
place,3 and so it is imperative that I try to clarify the issues. The point of this
article will be to do just that.
But before I go into details, it is necessary to clarify the main issue. Someone
might object, quite understandably, that the quarrel between Frank and myself
is a storm in a teacup, a mere dispute about words. Why not just declare with
Humpty Dumpty that words mean what we want them to mean, so that Humpty
(Beiser) gets to call romanticism one thing and Dumpty (Frank) gets to call it
another? The relationship between romanticism and idealism is understudied
and disputed, the objector will say, for the simple reason that the terms
“romanticism” and “idealism” have no definite meaning. Since they have no
precise meaning, there is no such thing as a fixed or definite relationship
between romanticism and idealism. What relationships scholars find just
depends on the meanings they give the terms. And so it seems the better half of
prudence to regard the whole question as a purely verbal one, a trap for
scholars unwary and naive. It was on just these grounds that, nearly a century
ago, Arthur Lovejoy bid us to abandon the very concept of romanticism.4 That
concept had been given so many different, even opposing, definitions, Lovejoy
complained, that it was better to talk about “romanticisms” in the plural than
“romanticism” in the singular. Since idealism is in no better shape than
romanticism, perhaps we should abandon that concept too, and so drop the
whole question about its relationship with romanticism?
Such advice has its point, of course. There is a real danger that discussion of the
relationship between romanticism and idealism gets bogged down in mere
words. Some of the dispute between Frank and myself, I have to confess, is
verbal, revolving around the different meanings of the term “idealism.” Still, it is
a mistake to think that the issue is entirely verbal, as if there were no
substantive issues at stake. The fact of the matter is that the denotation or
Page 2 of 15
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Romanticism and Idealism
So, given that the old theory has collapsed, it is necessary to rethink the whole
question of the relationship between idealism and romanticism. There are two
ways of going forward. One would be to stress the difference between idealism
Page 3 of 15
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Romanticism and Idealism
and romanticism, to make a sharp distinction between them. The other would be
to continue to emphasize the affinity between them but to hold that Fichtean
idealism is only one part or aspect of idealism in general. Manfred Frank has
gone down the first path; I have gone down the second. Over the years I have
tried to convince Frank to go down the path of salvation and righteousness, but
he has stubbornly resisted. Rather than recanting and renouncing the error of
his ways, he has challenged me in public. And so he has, in effect, thrown down
his gauntlet. In full recognition of such a worthy opponent, who has taught me
so much over the years, I now pick it up and prepare to joust.
Page 4 of 15
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Romanticism and Idealism
such general terms, it should be clear that these forms of idealism are
conceptually distinct. A subjective idealist need not hold that everything in
experience is an appearance of some ideal or archetype; for he might be a
nominalist who denies the reality of archetypes and who affirms that everything
that exists is particular. An objective idealist need not claim that those particular
things that embody or instantiate the archetypical are perceived by or exist for
some self-conscious subject; for they could still be embodiments or instantiations
of the ideal even if no self-conscious subject existed to perceive them.
(p.34) Any adequate account of the German idealist tradition has to be broad
enough to accommodate both these senses. A narrow univocal account will not
work if only because the paradigmatic thinkers that we place in this tradition—
Kant, Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel—use “idealism” in both these senses. As all
students of the tradition know, there was a fundamental break around 1800
between the “subjective idealism” of Kant and Fichte and the “objective
idealism” of Schelling and Hegel. That break appears in Schelling’s
correspondence with Fichte, and then in Hegel’s Differenzschrift, which defends
Schelling’s break with Fichte. Schelling and Hegel argued that their “objective
idealism” is superior to the subjective idealism of Kant and Fichte because it
accommodates the independent reality of nature and because it does not reduce
nature down to the experience of the self-conscious subject alone. That was, as I
read it, the point behind Schelling’s famous Durchbruch zur Realität, which he
makes in his 1799 Allgemeine Deduktion des dynamischen Prozesses.9
Given that subjective and objective idealism have such different senses, and
given that there was such a deep and self-conscious break between its chief
protagonists, one might well ask why or how there is one idealist tradition at all.
Why not speak of two traditions, or “idealisms” in the plural, as Lovejoy advises
us to do with “romanticism”? I would do so if it were not for the fact that a hard
and fast distinction between these idealisms, as if they have nothing in common,
is equally problematic. There is still one general sense of “idealism” common to
both strands of the tradition insofar as both regard the realm of thought or the
ideal as the key to understanding experience or reality, and insofar as both
oppose materialism. The basic difference between these strands is simply
whether we attach or detach the ideal—the realm of thought or meaning—from
the self-conscious subject: subjective idealists attach it, objective idealists
detach it. What the common principle of these idealism might be is a difficult
question that I cannot pursue here. But, quite apart from how we formulate that
principle, there is still another reason to write of a single tradition from Kant to
Hegel. Namely, Schelling and Hegel themselves self-consciously continued to
place themselves within the Kantian-Fichtean tradition. It is noteworthy, for
example, that Hegel, in his Differenzschrift, still sees himself as completing the
Kantian revolution in philosophy.10 No account of German idealism is complete
or adequate, I believe, unless it can explain this apparent paradox: that
Page 5 of 15
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Romanticism and Idealism
Schelling and Hegel broke with Kant’s and Fichte’s idealism yet both placed
themselves within the Kantian-Fichtean tradition.
Now my major difference with Frank regarding the concept of “idealism” is that
he narrows its meaning down to subjective idealism alone. According to his
definition in Unendliche Annäherung, “idealism,” “crudely put” (grob gesagt),
denotes the view that “the basic givens of reality are mental [geistige] entities or
can be reduced down to them.”11 This is a passable definition for (p.35)
subjective idealism all right; but it does not work at all for objective idealism,
which does not hold that the basic givens of reality are mental. If we were to
adopt Frank’s definition for the idealist tradition as a whole, we would have to
limit it down to Kant and Fichte and leave aside Schelling and Hegel. It would
become impossible to make any sense of “objective idealism,” not to mention
Schelling’s and Hegel’s break with Fichte and their advocacy of an idealism that
takes into account the independent reality of nature. There are passages in
Unendliche Annäherung where Frank does talk about “absolute idealism,” a
synonym for “objective idealism,” which he defines in terms of the doctrine that
an absolute ego creates all of reality.12 But this is still “subjective idealism” in
my terms because it does not matter whether the realm of consciousness
belongs to a transcendental or empirical, universal or particular, subject. In any
case, absolute idealism in this sense—a supersubject creating the entire world of
empirical reality—is not a useful term to describe anyone in the idealist
tradition. It is an old misconception that is better laid to rest.13
The different meanings Frank and I attribute to idealism are decisive for the
dispute between us. Because he defines the concept in subjective terms, he
distinguishes it from early romanticism; because I define it more broadly, not
only in subjective but also objective terms, I place it under the general heading
of idealism. But in an important sense Frank and I agree. Namely, if one were to
define idealism in the subjective sense, then the romantics are not idealists, and
they were indeed opposed to it. It was this narrow subjective sense behind the
old Fichtean interpretation of early romanticism, which Frank and I both reject.
Furthermore, Frank and I are at one regarding the realism of early romanticism.
In Unendliche Annäherung Frank argues that the romantics were not idealists
but realists in holding that the realm of being exists independent of the self-
conscious subject. After Fred Rush complained about the vagueness of Frank’s
use of “realism,”14 Frank made some fine distinctions in Auswege aus dem
deutschen Idealismus.15 We need not pursue these distinctions here, useful
though they are. The relevant sense of realism for the romantics Frank calls
“ontological realism,” according to which “there are things existing independent
of consciousness and whose independence is denoted by the term being.”16
Though it might surprise Frank and others, I have to stress that I agree with him
entirely that the early romantics were committed to just such a realism. It is
important to add that this realism was meant to be full and robust, allowing for
Page 6 of 15
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Romanticism and Idealism
Granted that the romantics aspired to a higher realism, which is indeed the kind
of ontological realism that Frank attributes to them, it is tempting to conclude
that they were opposed to idealism. This is indeed just the inference that Frank
makes. It is misleading, however, because it fails to distinguish between
subjective and objective idealism. While the higher realism is indeed
incompatible with subjective idealism, it is perfectly compatible with objective
idealism, and the whole point of objective idealism is to accommodate that
realism. Even if there were no self-conscious subject, it is still possible to hold
that everything that exists in nature is a manifestation of the ideal, where the
ideal is the archetypical or intelligible.
If we accept that the romantics held such an objective idealism, then it becomes
possible to explain one extraordinary feature of their philosophical language:
namely, their demand for an ontology that is both idealistic and realistic. During
the late 1790s and early 1800s the early romantics would often write of an
“ideal-realism” or “real-idealism.” This was not a deliberately paradoxical or glib
turn of phrase but the expression of a very reasonable philosophical program:
the call for a form of idealism that could do justice to the reality of the external
world. The early romantics were convinced that there should be some middle
path between a complete materialism on the one hand and a total subjective
idealism on the other hand. That middle path was their objective idealism. It
alone could interpret the world as a manifestation of the ideal—and so avoid
materialism—but it could also allow the world to exist independent of the subject
—and so escape subjective idealism.
Realizing that the early romantics are objective idealists in this sense also makes
it possible to stress a side of early romanticism that has been underplayed by
Frank but that has been rightly emphasized by some older commentators.18 This
is the Platonic dimension. All the early romantics—Friedrich Schlegel,
Schleiermacher, Hölderlin, Novalis, and Schelling—were profoundly influenced
by Plato in their youth, and this had a pervasive impact on all their thinking.
Oskar Walzel was entirely correct, I believe, when he wrote, nearly a century
ago, that romanticism was the greatest revival of Platonism since the
Renaissance.19 The Platonic dimension of the romantics’ idealism appears in
Page 7 of 15
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Romanticism and Idealism
their identification of the absolute with reason or logos or idea. I will have to
forgo here marshalling and citing all the evidence for this interpretation, a task I
have executed elsewhere.20 Assuming, however, that we adopt this Platonic
interpretation, the consequences for our general interpretation of romanticism
are weighty. For it means that we have to reject the pervasive and popular (p.
37) interpretation of romanticism as a form of irrationalism, as a rebellion
against the Aufklärung and as a more radical form of the Sturm und Drang. The
romantic doctrine of the primacy of aesthetic experience over the forms of
discursive thinking was not meant as a rejection or limitation of reason in
general but was intended to elevate intuitive forms of reason over discursive
ones. It was never intended as a rejection of rationality as such.
This objection is partly inspired by and based on the point that the romantics
were opposed to foundationalism, which was part and parcel of the idealist
tradition. This is indeed one of the chief reasons for the distinction between
romanticism and idealism. According to this version of the distinction, the
romantics were fundamentally antifoundationalist, while the idealists were
essentially foundationalist in their epistemology.22 Fichte and the early Schelling
were followers of Reinhold’s foundationalist program—his Elementarphilosophie
—which was basically a revival of the old philosophia prima that we find in
Descartes, Spinoza, and Leibniz. While Hegel rejected the Reinholdian program,
he never abandoned foundationalism but simply pursued it through other means:
his famous dialectic. The early romantics were among those many philosophers
in the Jena Wunderzeit who rejected the Reinholdian program, which was one of
the starting points for their own philosophy. Frank has especially stressed the
antifoundationalism of early romanticism, and his explorations and elaborations
of this theme are, I believe, one of his major contributions to research on early
romanticism. I agree with Frank entirely about the antifoundationalism of early
romanticism, and I have, following in his footsteps, incorporated it into my own
Page 8 of 15
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Romanticism and Idealism
work. Here we have indeed good reason to make a distinction between early
romanticism and idealism, and I do not think I have emphasized that point
enough in my earlier work. (p.38) However, it is necessary to add: the
antifoundationalism of early romanticism does not make it any less idealistic in
the precise sense of idealism I have in mind. There is nothing in the thesis of
objective idealism, as explained above, that commits its adherents to
foundationalism. We can affirm that all reality is a manifestation of the ideal and
deny every form of foundationalism. It is possible to hold the following position:
that we perceive the ideal through intuition or feeling, through the dark glass of
aesthetic experience, and to be critical of all foundationalism. That was indeed,
as I see it, the romantic position.
Before I spur that stubborn beast, let me pause to note the curious tension in
Frank’s position. It is strange that he separates romanticism so firmly (p.39)
from idealism but then stresses the significance of the Kantian Copernican
Page 9 of 15
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Romanticism and Idealism
Here something has to give because Frank cannot have it both ways. And what
does give is Frank’s emphasis on the Copernican Revolution. For in the course of
his Einführung Frank finds himself retracting the importance of the analogy he
first made his guiding theme. He sees, perfectly correctly, that there is
something amiss with the analogy. The problem is this: when the Copernican
doctrine is applied to aesthetics, it leads to the doctrine that aesthetic judgment
is noncognitive. It is no accident that Kant tells us emphatically and explicitly in
the first paragraph of the Kritik der Urteilskraft that aesthetic judgment has
nothing to do with truth, that it does not refer to anything whatsoever in the
object, because it concerns only the feeling of pleasure in the spectator.27 The
Kantian doctrine of the strictly subjective status of pleasure is the immediate
consequence of the Copernican Revolution because it places the standard of
beauty in the faculties of the perceiver rather than in the object itself. Kant saw
the opposing doctrine—the rationalist theory that aesthetic judgment formulates
an intuition of perfection in the object itself—as a relapse into the bad old ways
of metaphysical dogmatism, which placed the standard of beauty in the object
itself, and more specifically in its perfection or unity-in-variety. But it is precisely
Kant’s denial of cognitive status to aesthetic judgment that shows the profound
difference between his Copernican Revolution and the romantics. For the
romantics were, one and all, passionately committed to the doctrine that
aesthetic perception is cognitive, that it does give us insight into truth. Frank
knows this all too well, of course, and it is noteworthy that for this reason he
retracts, qualifies, or fails to follow through with his analogy.28
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Romanticism and Idealism
Now, having made some grand sweeping claims, let me make another, one more
heretical than the preceding. Namely, rather than seeing romantic aesthetics as
built on a Kantian foundation, we should see it as an attempt to rehabilitate
rationalist aesthetics and as a reaction against Kant’s Copernican Revolution.
For the romantics wanted first and foremost to restore the classical doctrine of
the cognitive status of aesthetic judgment against Kant’s subjectivism. The very
doctrine that Kant was intent on burying they were intent on reviving. The
romantic emphasis on the truth behind poetry and art, and their Platonic
heritage, permits no other conclusion.
There is still, of course, a great difference between the romantics and their
rationalist forebears. Namely, the romantics turned the rationalist hierarchy of
knowledge upside down. While the rationalists placed aesthetic experience
below the powers of reason—here understood in the traditional sense as the
powers to conceive, judge, and infer—the romantics placed it above them. It is in
just this respect, of course, that it is fair to stress Kant’s influence on the
romantics, for they did accept some of his critique of traditional metaphysics.
Kant’s attack on the powers of discursive reason was indeed crucial for their
elevation of aesthetic experience over all forms of knowledge. But this point has
been taken too far, as if the break with rationalist metaphysics meant a break
with its aesthetics. That too is a non sequitur.
Although there is a clear affinity between romantic aesthetics and the rationalist
tradition, and although there is a clear tension between romantic aesthetics and
the Kantian tradition, I am not optimistic that scholars will begin to turn their
attention away from Kant and toward the rationalists. The old habits of looking
at Kant as the fount of aesthetic wisdom are simply too hard to break. We
romantics know what the Kantians do when the post coach from Königsberg
breaks down. Rather than going without truth for weeks, they go ferreting into
the more obscure recesses of the Kritik der Urteilskraft to find solace. They
rummage through the text for every trace of evidence for the romantics’
indebtedness to this non plus ultraof the aesthetic universe. And, sure enough,
they find doctrines that seem to anticipate later romantic themes. Thus they
point to Kant’s concept of genius, to his idea of art as a symbol of morality, and
to the paradox of purposiveness without a purpose. All of these ideas might have
been indeed suggestive to the romantics. But the problem with them is that they
are too hedged with regulative qualifications to support the romantic faith in the
cognitive status of art. Kant never permits the artist to (p.41) have insight into
the ideas behind nature for the simple reason that these ideas have for him only
a regulative validity. He permits us to treat nature only as if it were created
Page 11 of 15
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Romanticism and Idealism
according to ideas, but not to assume that it actually is so. The Kantian artist is
still left trapped inside the circle of consciousness of subjective idealism.
Regarding these old Kantian habits, I frankly have to state my incredulity. The
romantics were never fervent admirers of Kant’s Kritik der Urteilskraft, and they
never went poring over the text to find inspiration. What could one say after all
about a text that made the arabesque the height of aesthetic perfection? The
great admirer of the Kritik der Urteilskraft was Schiller, and it seems that Kant’s
influence on Schiller, and Schiller’s influence on the romantics, licenses by
transitivity Kant’s influence on the romantics. But there is a great gap between
Schiller’s Aesthetische Briefe and Hölderlin’s Neue Aesthetische Briefe. The
latter work was meant to vindicate the claim to aesthetic truth undermined by
the former. One reason the alleged affinity between Kant and the romantics
lacks credibility is because it fails to acknowledge, and to see the consequences
of, one basic but simple fact: Kant did not read Greek. Most of the young
romantics were trained in that language from an early age, and it is that which
gave them access to, and a deep appreciation of, Plato’s Timaeus, Symposium,
and Phaedrus. It was Kant’s ignorance of Greek that puts a major cultural
barrier between him and the romantic generation. Let us face it: the stiff and dry
sage of Königsberg had no appreciation of the erotic, and so he would never
have understood the soul of Diotima’s teaching.
In one respect I am willing to concede that the old analogy between Kant’s
Copernican Revolution and romantic aesthetics contains a grain of truth.
Namely, the romantics did stress the creative role of the artist, and they did not
expect the artist simply to replicate the appearances of external nature. But this
point leaves us with a problem, which the protagonists of this analogy do not
recognize. Namely, how could the romantics stress both the creative role of the
artist and the power of art to reveal the truth? It might seem that the artist’s
creativity simply reveals his own feelings and desires rather than anything about
the world outside him. The problem here is how to bring together the romantic
faith in artistic creativity with a doctrine of the imitation of nature, a doctrine
the romantics never really renounced and which is even required by their
ontological realism. The explanation for this apparent paradox, I would suggest
here, lies in the romantics’ general conception of nature, and more specifically,
their conception of nature as an organism. According to that idea, the organic
powers of nature reach their highest organization and development in the
creativity of the subject, so that what he creates is also what nature creates
through him. The artist, through his own creativity, then becomes the instrument
for the (p.42) self-realization and self-revelation of nature herself. The
paradigmatic expression of this idea is in Schelling’s System des
transcendentalen Idealismus. If I am correct that this is the solution to the
paradox, then it shows the importance of romantic Naturphilosophie for their
aesthetics. It is only when we place romantic aesthetics in the context of their
Page 12 of 15
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Romanticism and Idealism
And so there you have it. With that diatribe I have made my last parry in this
tournament. My Rocinante is tired now, as I imagine my spectators are too. I quit
the field not knowing what favors Mathilde might care to bestow upon me.
Whether I or Frank deserves her blue flower I will leave the spectator to judge.
Notes:
(1) . Manfred Frank, Unendliche Annäherung. Die Anfänge der philosophischen
Frühromantik (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1997), 27, 65–66, 663–65, 715.
(3) . See Manfred Frank, Auswege aus dem deutschen Idealismus (Frankfurt am
Main: Suhrkamp, 2007), 16–17. Elizabeth Millán-Zaibert has also taken issue
with my subsumption of the romantics under idealism in her Friedrich Schlegel
and the Emergence of Romantic Philosophy (Albany: State University of New
York, 2007).
(5) . We could, of course, extend the date beyond 1801. But I will leave that aside
here, for the purposes of a more precise comparison with the early romantics.
By 1801 the essentials of Schelling’s and Hegel’s objective or absolute idealism
were formed, and Schelling’s and Hegel’s works only expounded the main ideas
in more systematic detail. I will also leave aside the problem of applying the
term “idealism” solely to the period from Kant and Hegel. This is problematic
because it ignores Lotze and Trendelenburg, two of the most influential thinkers
of the nineteenth century in the idealist tradition.
(6) . Rudolf Haym, Die romantische Schule (Berlin: Gaertner, 1882); H. A. Korff,
Geist der Goethezeit (Leipzig: Koehler und Amelang, 1964), III, 244–52; and
Nicolai Hartmann, Die Philosophie des deutschen Idealismus (Berlin: de Gruyter,
1923), I, 220–33, esp. 221, 224, 226, 228.
Page 13 of 15
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Romanticism and Idealism
(8) . I argue for this distinction in German Idealism, 349–74, 379–91, 418–21,
447–51, 491–505.
(17) . See Schlegel, Philosophische Lehrjahre, in KA 18, 31, no. 134; 38, no. 209;
80, no. 606. Novalis held similar views. See his Allgemeine Brouillon, in NS 3,
382–4, no. 634; 252, no. 69; 382, no. 633; 429, no. 820, and Fragmente und
Studien, NS 3, 671, no. 611.
(18) . The Platonic heritage was stressed by Oskar Walzel, German Romanticism
(New York: Putnam, 1932) and Erwin Kirchner, Philosophie der Romantik (Jena:
Diederichs, 1906), 8–34.
(21) . This is the view of Millán-Zaibert, Friedrich Schlegel and the Emergence of
Romantic Philosophy, 32, 34, 36, 38.
(22) . This conception of the idealist tradition goes back to a forgotten but
venerable source: Jakob Friedrich Fries’s Reinhold, Fichte und Schelling
(Leipzig: Reineicke, 1803). Fries shows how Fichte and Schelling adopt the
foundationalist program of Reinhold, and makes weighty objections against that
Page 14 of 15
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Romanticism and Idealism
program. He makes passing references to Hegel, who would soon become his
nemesis.
(24) . See Hans-Georg Gadamer, Wahrheit und Methode (Tübingen: Mohr, 1990),
93–94. Gadamer says little about the romantics but sees them as part of
Schiller’s program of aesthetic education, which he thinks has subjectivized
aesthetics.
(25) . Jane Kneller, Kant and the Power of Imagination (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2007).
(26) . Kant, Kritik der reinen Vernunft, B xviii. Cf. B xii, xiii.
Page 15 of 15
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
History, Succession, and German Romanticism
DOI:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199976201.003.0004
Page 1 of 21
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
History, Succession, and German Romanticism
circular, linear, or chaotic shape.4 The romantics deserve special credit for
having made prominent a fourth basic option here, namely, that of an elliptical
path.5 The romantic notion of an elliptical path is often shorthand for the
thought of history as kind of gyre, or open-ended rising spiral, such that there is
directionality and progress in a multidimensional fashion, one that requires
repeatedly returning to one’s original place in a way that involves development
through off-center movements with more than one focal point.
Page 2 of 21
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
History, Succession, and German Romanticism
Leaving aside for specialists the factual question of which groups have in fact
been governed by which version of the view, my initial aim here is simply (p.49)
to characterize, through broad conceptual contrasts, the most basic feature of
what I mean by a circular view in general: Although a circular view allows
accumulation of expertise over time, which can be incorporated into the evolving
“second nature” of each successive generation, its defining presumption,
whether simple or complex, is that there are only refinements and no absolutely
fundamental historical developments in philosophical truth itself, especially with
respect to the central issue of what, in the eighteenth century, was called the
“vocation of humanity” (Die Bestimmung des Menschen).
Given this general characterization, one can regard, as a mere complex variation
of the circular view, views of history that include a stress on highly dramatic
quests of various far-ranging types (e.g., the Iliad, the Odyssey, the Republic) but
that still regard progress as largely a matter of reinstating central structures of
an original harmony. Such views can be found in the ancient Western societies
mentioned earlier, as well as in “organic” conceptions of society and history that
arise much later, such as Hegel’s mature notion of “ethical life” and “reason in
history.” Hegel is, of course, well known for his emphasis on the feature of
progress in Western civilization, not only in technological and economic-political
matters but also in terms of the appreciation of the fundamental notions of
philosophy itself. Hegel takes these notions to define not only the concrete
processes of nature, society, and history but also the basic understandings in
terms of which humanity’s “absolute spirit” eventually makes explicit this full
structure.8 Nonetheless, because Hegel’s ultimate position (on traditional
“schoolbook” readings) is that the pure system of his “logic” and related work
prefigures all the most basic forms of progress within human history, it still can
be said that his view on history is a circular one, albeit of a very complex rather
than simple type.9 The “absolute knowledge” of Hegel’s system can be taken, in
its content, as just a reflective formulation of what is implicit from the start
within reason’s “Idea” of a reconciled harmony of object and subject, and so,
despite the dramatic reality of an extensive sequence of quests and necessary
changes within the world of appearance, there remains an underlying and
unchanging philosophical order, one without any fundamental incompleteness.10
This is not to say that the monistic unfolding in time of what Hegel calls the
“absolute,” which is as much “subject” as “substance,” is a matter of a merely
analytic unpacking of isolated terms or entities. The main point, as Hegel insists,
is that, however complex this “development”11 appears to be, it constitutes a
system of reason that is not only necessary and eventually transparent, but also,
from the start, necessarily complete, and hence it has an eternal form that in
Page 3 of 21
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
History, Succession, and German Romanticism
essence preconditions its temporal instantiation. The transitions from era to era
are, to be sure, extraordinarily complex for Hegel, and they involve a necessary
dialectic of “determinate negation” that appears as an unpredictable (p.50)
process. But even though this process can be comprehended only in retrospect,
the main point of Hegel’s system is that in late modernity we finally can
retrospectively comprehend and be satisfied by what is, in a philosophical sense,
an in principle complete course of history. The dynamic complexity of lived
history is thus still consistent with a basically constant and reconciling picture of
humanity’s overall trajectory and its underlying logic. We have moved in three
steps: first, from a stage of relative immediacy, then through the dramatic
appearance of a complete sequence of forms of alienation, and finally into (the
beginning of) a stage of higher immediacy, with an essentially reconciling
harmony of “substance” and “reflection.”
A variant of this linear approach is the complex linear view of mainline versions
of Abrahamic religious traditions that are defined by the confident expectation of
a final phase of radical redemption that is supernaturally generated in a unique
way.13 The end phase that humanity moves toward on this view involves
something like the complexity of Hegel’s circular system insofar as it has as its
crucial precondition the drama of a sequence of dialectical stages within history
that are revolutionary in the limited sense of requiring a reversal of serious
previous shortcomings in our basic attitudes but not a denial of an original
teleological blueprint for existence on the whole. The traditional religious
version of this approach is linear and complex, however, insofar as it emphasizes
the nonnatural feature of absolute free choice in both human and divine agency.
The goal of history is therefore neither, as with strict Hegelianism (and its
complex circular view), metaphysically determined by the eternal necessities of
speculative logic, nor, as with strict naturalism (and its simple linear view), is it
naturally determined by givens of the external world that happen to (p.51)
fulfill us more and more by physical necessity. Instead, “the end of all things” is
Page 4 of 21
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
History, Succession, and German Romanticism
The figures who became most famous by inspiring others to hold a simple
chaotic view of history tended themselves, however, to adopt a complex chaotic
position, one that eschews relativism, as well as nihilism and positivism, and that
adds the wrinkle of stressing that there are key eras, or compartments of life, in
which it is important to appreciate that very significant “developments” of
various overlooked kinds can be, and should be, uncovered. These developments
also involve decline, as in the “death” as well as “birth” of “tragedy,” or the
“event” of “presence” as well as of “being,” or the rise of “the clinic” as well as
of “the care of the self,” followed by a “pandemonium” of consequences. These
processes are thus taken to be limited stages that have no absolutely lasting
trajectory and still fail to show that human life as a whole is heading in a
particular direction with an increasingly positive (or clearly negative) value.
Page 5 of 21
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
History, Succession, and German Romanticism
poetry offers an ideal combination of what is best in each of the three other
views. First, as universal, the romantic view picks up on the attractive broad
scope of the circular view, which consists in being especially open to regarding
the significance of human life as not limited to the circumstance of belonging to
any particular slice of space or time; wherever and whenever ordinary human
beings live, they all can participate in what is said to make life most meaningful.
This positive feature of open scope contrasts with both the linear view, which
can make life’s meaning appear to be largely an unfair accident of being exposed
to a particular limited tradition (salvation through local revelation, or a fully
secular but late-blossoming process), and also with the chaotic view, which, at
best, is either relativism or typically limited to an episodic and elitist view of
meaning. In contrast to the circular view, however, the romantic view has the
further, distinctively historical advantage that for it the universal significance of
human life is neither—as on the complex circular view—dependent on a highly
questionable teleology rooted in speculative logic, nor—as on the simple circular
view—regarded as a brute feature of nature’s recurrent patterns that has
nothing essentially to do with what is special about human history as a very
broadly extended project.
Third, as poetry, the romantic view, with its insistence on an open and unclear
future, picks up on the attractive methodological feature of the chaotic view, its
critical attitude in regard to straightforward traditional claims about a fully
established teleological structure to human life. The romantic view’s positive (p.
53) feature of a stress on humanity’s absolutely free16 capacity for creating
highly imaginative initiatives contrasts with the circular view, which overlooks
the value of this capacity, as well as with the linear view, which ultimately
understands progress in terms of externally generated and clearly conclusive
forms of satisfaction and thus discounts the growing uncertainties of late
modernity. That is, both the simple and complex versions of the linear view
neglect the special value of humanity’s ongoing struggle of unsure and
Page 6 of 21
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
History, Succession, and German Romanticism
If this last problem is the only one that remains, however, then the romantics
could still at least deserve credit for having articulated a unique and relevantly
challenging positive conception of our historical situation, even if it may seem
overly optimistic to most secular intellectuals in our era. As Immanuel Kant and
William James argued, and as many contemporary antifoundationalists have
noted,17 there are important situations in which agents should not limit their
options to what is present in the form of evidence, for such a limitation can
undercut not only itself (since it is hardly clear that foundationalism’s own (p.
54) ground, as a principle, is evident) but also the unrefuted possibility of
achieving very significant goals. Moreover, because the romantics typically
present their work—and especially their philosophy of history—in various
“poetic” forms, it is clear from the start that they understand the argumentative
uncertainty of any global view. In particular, they see the need to present any
general position on history not as a demonstrated assertion but as an
imperative, a call to other free individuals to join with them in seeking to make
humanity’s future, despite its dim record and prospects, a process that is “in the
state of becoming ever more universal and progressive.”18
Page 7 of 21
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
History, Succession, and German Romanticism
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
History, Succession, and German Romanticism
Page 9 of 21
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
History, Succession, and German Romanticism
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
History, Succession, and German Romanticism
The original form of this turn has its origins in the mid-1780s, an era dominated
by the conflicting accounts offered by Herder, Reinhold, and Jacobi of the
interlocking trajectories of modern religion, science, and philosophy (after Kant,
Hume, and Spinoza), and then the reaction to these accounts by the young
seminarians of Tübingen—Hölderlin, Hegel, and Schelling—in their movement
toward a “system program” that would combine a “new physics” and “new
mythology” in an at once universal, progressive, and aesthetic philosophy of the
future. The main immediate complication in this era, from Reinhold through
Hegel, is the still influential thought that any philosophy that is genuinely
modern has to be thoroughly systematic and scientific in a sense that can (p.58)
supposedly correspond to and even outdo the power of the new mathematical
sciences.26 Only when the dominance of this presumption finally declines,
toward the end of the eighteenth century, and an alternative is sought for the
overambitious thought of making philosophy absolutely certain and systematic in
a quasi-mathematical sense,27 is the way cleared for the new antifoundationalist
conception of philosophy that the romantics embrace. On this conception,
philosophical writing is not antithetical to science, but it is liberated to be
distinctive by being historically argumentative in form, and thereby largely
interpretative and even poetic in a broad sense—although precisely not as a
matter of mere “artistic” expression or amusement.
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
History, Succession, and German Romanticism
Page 12 of 21
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
History, Succession, and German Romanticism
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
History, Succession, and German Romanticism
a sensitivity for the multiplicity of connected forms that the “spirit” of true peace
appears to take as history proceeds. This pluralism is not a regression to
paganism or relativism but an attempt to enlarge the mainstream heritage of
Hölderlin’s own tradition, that is, to regard the spirit of Christianity as a fruitful
outgrowth of an ancient Greek setting with similar concerns (for example, in
aspects of the Dionysus cult), and as something that can be replanted in new
settings, albeit with increasing difficulty, in later ages.
(p.61) The key to identifying the “prince” of peace, that is, the figure awaited
and celebrated throughout the poem, is to avoid the exclusivist fallacy of
hypothesizing that it is simply Napolean, Jupiter, Jesus, the poet himself, or some
other particular figure such as Dionysus or Heracles. Instead, as Peter Szondi
has pointed out, one should note that Hölderlin uses a long sequence of varied
holy names, names that are not singular but rather descriptive of different
aspects of what we know as best in “spirit.”35 It thus can be argued that it is the
very succession of names, and naming processes, that is the subject of the
“celebration” of peace, and that Hölderlin’s own poem is intended, like the
multiple scriptures of old, to be but one stage in this process—and a reminder of
the importance of maintaining this kind of process as such.36 The poem
celebrates:
For Hölderlin, spirit dwells now neither in a pagan “thunderstorm” age (of mere
naturalism), nor in an orthodox “miracle” age (of mere supernaturalism),38 but
in a late modern age of “hymns” and gatherings for a struggling movement
toward universal progressivism. “All” are to be assembled in a celebrative
process in which they understand themselves as being “present” together
through writings that literally re-collect the past and help forge a “blessed”
future in a creatively extended tradition.
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
History, Succession, and German Romanticism
Page 15 of 21
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
History, Succession, and German Romanticism
Notes:
(1) . Friedrich Schlegel, Athenaeum Fragments, no. 116, in Philosophical
Fragments, trans. Peter Firchow (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press,
1991), 31–32, a volume put together in Jena in 1798 as an act of “sym-
philosophy” by Schlegel and Novalis (Friedrich von Hardenberg). Italics added.
(3) . See my Kant and the Historical Turn: Philosophy as Critical Appropriation
(Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2006).
(4) . This classification contrasts somewhat with Kant’s distinction of three views
(“progressing,” “regressing,” and “standstill”) on the question of whether
“humankind is continually improving,” in The Contest of the Faculties (1798) (AA
8, 81).
(5) . This pattern is also treated by the romantics as an “eccentric path,” and as
highly relevant to individual life as well as history as a whole. See Charles
Larmore, “Hölderlin and Novalis,” in The Cambridge Companion to German
Idealism, ed. Karl Ameriks (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000), 141–
60. It is well known that the value of focusing on elliptical patterns was an
important astronomical insight of Johannes Kepler’s, but it is sometimes
forgotten how Kepler’s general courage to “think outside the box” in this
literally eccentric way made him a hero in Germany on a level with Copernicus
and Galileo. Kant compared his own work to Kepler’s breakthrough (AA 8, 18),
and Hölderlin, who, like Kepler, studied in Tübingen, wrote a noteworthy early
Page 16 of 21
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
History, Succession, and German Romanticism
(7) . See e.g., René Girard, “A Christian conversion is never circular. It never
returns to its point of origin. It is open-ended.” “Conversion in Christianity and
Literature” (1988), in Mimesis & Theory: Essays on Literature and Criticism,
1953–2005, ed. Robert Doran (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2008), 266.
(14) . Among the German idealists, broadly speaking, it is Kant who holds on
most firmly to this libertarian aspect of traditional religion. On divine
concurrence in his notion of the highest good, see e.g., notes from the lectures,
“Ethic Herder” (AA 27, 16). Among the romantics, Hölderlin most fully
appreciates this aspect of Kant’s doctrine of freedom. See his “On the Law of
Freedom” (1794) in Friedrich Hölderlin: Essays and Letters on Theory, ed.
Thomas Pfau (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1988), 33f., and his
Page 17 of 21
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
History, Succession, and German Romanticism
letter to his brother, April 13, 1795, “what is most indispensable here is certainly
freedom of the will,” Essays and Letters, 127–28. Hölderlin also follows Kant,
who follows Rousseau, in attributing contemporary evil primarily to our giving in
to the inherited trappings of luxury and modern culture: “that which was the
general reason for the decline of all peoples, namely that their originality, their
own living nature succumbed to the positive forms, to the luxury which their
fathers had produced, that seems to be our fate as well, only on a larger scale—”
in “The Perspective from Which We Have to Look at Antiquity” (1799), Essays
and Letters, 39.
(15) . One can also add, of course, an account in which our future is taken to be
basically negative rather than positive (see above, note 4), but that is also a kind
of “progression.”
(17) . See Alvin Plantinga and Nicholas Wolterstorff, Faith and Rationality (Notre
Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1983).
(18) . Cf. Simon Critchley, The Faith of the Faithless: Experiments in Political
Theology (New York: Verso, 2012), 251: “what is rather being called for is a
rigorous and activistic conception of faith that proclaims itself into being at each
instant without guarantee or security.”
(19) . In this essay, I directly invoke classic studies by Peter Szondi, Ernst Behler,
Michael Hamburger, Dieter Henrich, Manfred Frank, Charles Larmore, and Alice
Kuzniar; more recently I have also been influenced by Frederick Beiser, Richard
Eldridge, Karsten Harries, Jane Kneller, Elizabeth Millán, Fred Rush, and Eric
Santner. I am also indebted to very helpful comments by the editor of this
volume.
(21) . See above note 18, and Simon Critchley’s recent effort to recapture “for
the left” a similar broad and somewhat romantic conception of religion for a
secular generation.
Page 18 of 21
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
History, Succession, and German Romanticism
(22) . See e.g., Reinhart Koselleck, “The Status of the Enlightenment in German
History,” in The Cultural Values of Europe, ed. Hans Joas and Klaus Wiegandt
(Liverpool: Liverpool University Press, 2008), 253–64.
(23) . These terms come from Kant’s Critique of the Power of Judgment (§ 49);
their relevance to romanticism and contemporary philosophy in general is
discussed in my Kant’s Elliptical Path, chap. 15.
(24) . See Sanford Budick, Kant and Milton (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press, 2010), which picks up on themes first emphasized in W. Jackson Bate, The
Burden of the Past and the English Poet (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press, 1970), and Harold Bloom, The Anxiety of Influence (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1973).
(27) . This a point that Manfred Frank and others have documented in the wake
of the results of Dieter Henrich’s massive Jena research project. Manfred Frank
recounts this work in his contribution to this volume, chapter 1 above.
(29) . See Hölderlin, “On Religion” (1797), which speaks of a “more than
mechanical interrelation, a higher destiny,” Essays and Letters, 90.
(32) . Budick’s Kant and Milton (see above, notes 23 and 24) demonstrates the
many ways in which Kant’s philosophy is an attempt to thematize the problem of
succession as it occurs in Milton’s work. One can also argue that Kant’s own
work, and his theory of genius in particular, is meant to exemplify an
achievement of succession that can serve as a kind of model for later truly genial
philosophical writers—a challenge that the romantics immediately took up. See
my Kant’s Elliptical Path, chap. 13, “On the Extension of Kant’s Elliptical Path in
Hölderlin and Novalis.”
Page 19 of 21
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
History, Succession, and German Romanticism
(34) . Michael Hamburger, “The Sublime Art: Notes on Milton and Hölderlin,” in
Contraries: Studies in German Literature (New York: E. P. Dutton, 1957), 46.
(36) . In this way the poem can be read as a “Gottesdienst,” a literary substitute
for the career of an orthodox minister that Hölderlin felt he could not assume
within the establishment of his time.
(37) . “The all assembling, where heavenly beings are / Not manifest in miracles,
nor unseen in thunderstorms, / But where in hymns hospitably conjoined / And
present in choirs, a holy number, / The blessed in every way / Meet and
forgather.” Friedrich Hölderlin: Selected Poems and Fragments, trans. Michael
Hamburger (London: Penguin, 1998), 215.
(38) . Given his close reading of Kant, it may be no accident that Hölderlin’s
conceptual contrast of these two inadequate options (“thunderstorms,”
“miracle”) echoes the contrast Kant draws between the two inadequate options
of “being veiled in obscurity” (in Dunkelheiten verhüllt) and “being in the
transcendent region” (im Überschwänglichen), and the fortunate alternative
(“present”) of what “I see before me” (ich sehe—vor mir); see the conclusion of
the Critique of Practical Reason, the sentence directly after Kant’s most famous
phrase, concerning the “starry heavens” and “the moral law” (AA 5, 161–62).
(39) . The book of Numbers speaks of seventy elders who, “when the spirit
rested upon them—prophesied. But they did not do so again.” At this point, when
two others “outside the tent,” Eldad and Medad, start prophesizing and one of
Moses’s own chosen assistants, Joshua, pleads for Moses to stop them, Moses’s
reply is: “Are you jealous for my sake? Would that all the Lord’s people were
prophets, and that the Lord would put his spirit on them!” This point is taken to
be repeated and amplified in Mark. Here, after John says to Jesus, “Teacher, we
saw someone casting out demons in your name, and we tried to stop him,
because he was not following us,” the reply of Jesus is, “Do not stop him—
whoever is not against us is for us.” The general idea then appears again, in
James, which stresses that “whoever brings back a sinner from wandering—will
cover a multitude of sins.” New Revised Standard Version with Apocrypha,
Page 20 of 21
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
History, Succession, and German Romanticism
Augsburg Fortress Press, 1992. It is striking that the passage from Mark is cited
in Kant’s Religion (AA 6, 84).
(42) . “vesten Buchstab,” from Patmos. The mention of “tending” should not be
taken to imply a merely retrospective project. The writer’s vocation is to use the
“letter” to lead humanity into the “Gesang” of the future, that is, a kind of poetic
existence in general. (My thanks to Martin Sticker for a reminder of the
importance of this point.) For a complementary theological discussion of
Hölderlin’s significance, see Cyril O’Regan, “Aesthetic Idealism and its relation
to theological formation: reception and critique,” in The Impact of Idealism. The
Legacy of Post-Kantian German Thought, vol. 4: Religion, ed. Nicholas Adams
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2013), 142–66, which draws on Jean-
Luc Marion’s perceptive study of Hölderlin’s poetry in The Idol and Distance:
Five Studies (New York: Fordham University Press, 2001), 298–338.
Page 21 of 21
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Romanticism and Language
DOI:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199976201.003.0005
Page 1 of 25
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Romanticism and Language
Friedrich Schlegel adopted versions of doctrines (1) and (2). For example, as
early as 1798–99 he writes that “every spirit has its word, the two are
inseparable”;3 in the Cologne lectures on philosophy from 1804 to 1806 he
connects reason intimately with language,4 and states that “each concept must
be a word”;5 and he opens the Cologne lectures on German language and
literature from 1807 by saying that language is fundamental to all human
activities because “one cannot think without words.”6 Similarly, in the Lectures
on the History of Literature (delivered in 1812, published in 1815), he says:
“What is there more completely characteristic of man or of greater importance
Page 2 of 25
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Romanticism and Language
to him than language? Reason alone excepted, and even she must perforce
employ the vehicle of language...Reason and language, thought and word,
are...essentially one.”7 In addition, while it is less clear that Friedrich espoused a
version of doctrine (3), it is at least clear that his brother August Wilhelm did.
For example, August Wilhelm says that “the sense of words is determined
according to the intuitions which people are in the habit of associating with
them; so that we are in constant danger of ascribing to the words of the Greek
poets a quite different meaning than they had for them and their audience, even
when we understand them grammatically as exactly as you please.”8
Page 3 of 25
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Romanticism and Language
4.2. Linguistics
Friedrich Schlegel essentially founded the modern discipline of linguistics,
namely in On the Language and Wisdom of the Indians. He did so on the basis of
the central Herderian doctrines in the philosophy of language just discussed, in
particular doctrines (1) and (2), together with two additional Herderian
doctrines:
(4) Herder had argued that human beings exhibit profound differences in
their modes of thought, concepts, and language, especially between
different historical periods and cultures, but even to some extent between
individuals within a single period and culture.16
(5) In light of doctrines (1) and (2), he had also argued that investigating
the differences in the characters of people’s languages can, and should,
serve as a primary and reliable means for discovering the differences in
their modes of thought and concepts.17
Schlegel takes over this whole set of Herderian doctrines in On the Language
and Wisdom of the Indians. Concerning doctrines (1) and (2), we already saw
evidence of his commitment to these in both earlier and later works. Concerning
doctrine (4), he had already written in the Philosophy of Philology (1797) of “the
immeasurable difference..., the quite distinctive nature of antiquity,”18 and a
similar insight into sharp cognitive differences remains fundamental to On the
Language and Wisdom of the Indians. Concerning doctrine (5), this is the
implicit foundation of his procedure in that work of undertaking an investigation
of the Sanskrit language in the first part as a prelude to then exploring Indian
thought and conceptualization in subsequent parts. Indeed, doctrine (5)
Page 4 of 25
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Romanticism and Language
constitutes the most important motive for the new science of linguistics that (p.
72) he begins to develop in the work: it is supposed to provide a reliable
window on people’s varying modes of thought and conceptualization.19
Schlegel’s own holism concerning language, his conception that languages are
“organisms,” and in particular that their fundamental unifying principle is their
grammar, is also fundamental to his project of founding linguistics in On the
Language and Wisdom of the Indians.
Building on all these materials, he develops the new discipline in the work
roughly as follows:
(a) Whereas the early Herder of the Treatise on the Origin of Language
had implied at one point that grammar is inessential to language in its
more original and natural forms, merely being a product of the late
theoretical oversophistication of grammarians,20 and at another point
(rather inconsistently) that grammar is basically the same across all
languages (with the exception of Chinese),21 the later Herder of the Ideas
for the Philosophy of History of Humanity (1784–91) had argued that
languages differ dramatically in their grammatical structures: in addition
to exhibiting rich variety in other ways, “in the structure [Bau] of
language, in the relation, the ordering, and the agreement of the parts
with each other, it is almost immeasurable.”22 Schlegel rejects the early
Herder’s position but embraces this later position of Herder’s, himself
arguing that grammars differ deeply in their character from one language
to another, thereby constituting deep differences in particular words/
concepts as well (which may also differ for more superficial reasons).23
(b) Schlegel consequently identifies “comparative grammar” (an
expression/concept that he virtually coined in On the Language and
Wisdom of the Indians)24 as the primary task of an empirical investigation
of languages.
(c) Besides the fundamental motive mentioned above of providing a
reliable window on the different modes of thought and concepts that
occur, an additional important motive behind this project of comparative
grammar that Schlegel emphasizes lies in his conviction that it promises
to shed more light on the genealogical relations between languages than
merely lexical comparisons can.25
(d) Schlegel himself begins the task of actually comparing different
grammars in an empirically careful way. In doing so, he introduces the
following broad typology: a contrast between, on the one hand, “organic,”
or highly inflected, languages, of which Sanskrit is his paradigmatic
example, and on the other hand, “mechanical,” or (p.73) uninflected,
languages, of which Chinese is his main example.26 He also demonstrates
the genealogical relations between the various Sanskritic (or as we would
Page 5 of 25
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Romanticism and Language
4.3. Hermeneutics
Friedrich Schlegel and Schleiermacher also made vitally important contributions
to the development of both hermeneutics, or the theory of interpretation, and
the theory of translation.
Their theories in these areas build on ones that had already been developed by
Herder. Most fundamentally, they build on Herder’s doctrines (1)–(4). Doctrine
(4) poses a profound challenge to both interpretation and translation, and the
main task of all the theories in question is to cope with this challenge. (p.74)
Schlegel’s and Schleiermacher’s theories also fundamentally presuppose their
own new insight into the holistic nature of linguistic meaning, which exacerbates
the sorts of cognitive differences involved in (4), and hence adds to the difficulty
of interpretation and translation.
Page 6 of 25
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Romanticism and Language
(e) Before interpretation proper can even begin, the interpreter must
acquire a good knowledge of the text’s historical context.31
(f) Interpretation always has two sides: one “linguistic,” the other
“psychological.” Linguistic interpretation’s basic task (which rests on
doctrine (2)) is to infer from the particular known uses of a word to the
rule that governs them, that is, to its usage, and thus to its meaning.
Psychological interpretation instead focuses on the author’s individual
psychology. Linguistic interpretation is mainly concerned with what is
Page 7 of 25
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Romanticism and Language
Page 8 of 25
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Romanticism and Language
Page 9 of 25
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Romanticism and Language
But Friedrich Schlegel (followed by his brother) in addition made two very
important new applications of these Herderian insights about genre. One of (p.
78) these concerned the interpretation of ancient Greek tragedy. Before
Friedrich Schlegel the understanding of Greek tragedy as a genre had been
dominated by Aristotle’s treatment of it in the Poetics, which had been
considered virtually sacrosanct not only by most French dramatists and critics
but also by their recent German opponents Lessing and Herder. With Friedrich
Schlegel, especially in History of the Poetry of the Greeks and Romans (1798),
there emerged for the first time—in light of his Herderian awareness of the
historical mutability of genres and of the dangers of assimilating one genre to
another, more familiar genre, together with a more scrupulous empirical
investigation of the surviving Greek tragedies themselves conducted in the spirit
of Herder’s methodological empiricism—a realization that Aristotle’s treatment
of Greek tragedy was in fact at least as much an obstacle to properly
understanding it as an aid. Among other things, Friedrich Schlegel saw that
Aristotle had falsely assimilated tragedy’s greatest fifth-century forms to later
forms of it that had become prevalent in his own day, and that largely as a result
of this he had misrepresented it in important respects, for example obscuring its
deeply religious-Dionysiac and civic-political nature. By breaking Aristotle’s
undue influence on the interpretation of Greek tragedy in this way, Friedrich
Schlegel (followed by his brother) initiated a deep rethinking of its nature that
subsequently continued with Nietzsche’s The Birth of Tragedy and still continues
today (e.g., in the work of Vernant, Vidal-Nacquet, Goldhill, and Winkler).39
Another new application of Herder’s basic insights about genre concerned the
very birth of romanticism itself. For when the young Friedrich Schlegel in a
famous preface that he added to his On the Study of Greek Poetry (1795) in 1797
suddenly changed from an initial classicism concerning the distinction between
Page 10 of 25
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Romanticism and Language
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Romanticism and Language
above all Schlegel who developed this idea into a principle that the
interpreter must penetrate beyond an author’s conscious meanings and
thoughts to discover his unconscious ones as well. Thus he writes in On
Goethe’s Meister that “every excellent work...aims at more than it
knows”; and in Athenaeum Fragments, no. 401 that “in order to
understand someone who only partially understands himself, you first
have to understand him completely and better than he himself does.”
(d) A fourth important contribution Schlegel made to hermeneutics
concerns the presence of inconsistency and confusion in texts. The
important hermeneutic theorist Ernesti had already encouraged the
interpreter to attribute inconsistencies and other forms of confusion (p.
80) to profane texts when appropriate, and Herder had extended that
principle to sacred texts as well. Schlegel accepts Herder’s broader
version of the principle. But he also places even more emphasis on it and
develops it further, not only insisting that confusion is a common feature
of texts and should be recognized when it occurs, but also arguing that in
such cases the interpreter needs to seek to understand and explain it.
Thus he already writes in a note from 1797: “In order to understand
someone, one must first of all be cleverer than he, then just as clever, and
then also just as stupid. It is not enough that one understand the actual
sense of a confused work better than the author understood it. One must
also oneself be able to know, to characterize, and even construe the
confusion even down to its very principles.”41
(e) A fifth important contribution Schlegel made to hermeneutics
concerns the interpretation of nonlinguistic (or perhaps: “nonlinguistic”)
art—that is, painting, sculpture, architecture, instrumental music, and so
on. Herder had begun his career arguing in the early parts of the Critical
Forests (1769) that nonlinguistic art does not express meanings or
thoughts at all but is instead merely sensuous in nature. On such a view,
the question of interpreting it would not even arise. But Herder had
subsequently changed his mind about this, instead coming to recognize
that nonlinguistic art often does express meanings and thoughts, namely
(in order to stay consistent with doctrines (1) and (2)) ones that are
implicitly grounded in the artist’s language, and that it therefore does
need to be interpreted. This later position of Herder’s is far more
plausible. Schleiermacher is usually retrograde on this issue, and
therefore restricts hermeneutics to texts and discourse. But Schlegel
deserves great credit for taking over Herder’s later position and
developing it in some very insightful ways. In particular, he develops a
rich set of hermeneutic principles to guide the interpretation of
nonlinguistic art. Some of these principles are similar to the ones that he
espouses for interpreting linguistic texts, but others are distinctive to the
interpretation of nonlinguistic art, in particular principles concerning a
Page 12 of 25
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Romanticism and Language
After Schlegel and Schleiermacher, the latter’s pupil August Boeckh, an eminent
classical philologist, recast Schleiermacher’s hermeneutics in an even more
systematic and elaborate form in lectures that were eventually published
posthumously under the title Encyclopedia and Methodology of the Philological
(p.81) Sciences (1877). In the course of doing so he laudably restored genre to
the central place that it had received in the hermeneutics of Herder and
Schlegel. The combined influence of Herder’s, Schlegel’s, Schleiermacher’s, and
Boeckh’s treatments of hermeneutics secured for this tradition of hermeneutics
something very much like the status of the official interpretive methodology of
nineteenth-century Germany across such fields of research as biblical
scholarship, classical philology, history, and history of philosophy. The
extraordinary quality of that research constitutes eloquent testimony to its
value.
Page 13 of 25
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Romanticism and Language
As has already been mentioned, when Schlegel moved to Berlin in 1797 and
befriended Schleiermacher there, they developed an ambitious joint project of
translating the works of Plato. Accordingly, some of Schlegel’s writings from
around this period are concerned with the theory of translation—especially, his
Philosophy of Philology (1797) and fragments from the late 1790s.43 In addition,
(p.82) his Cologne lectures on German language and literature from 1807
contain comments about meter and its reproduction in another language, while
shortly afterwards On the Language and Wisdom of the Indians likewise contains
a little theorizing about translation as well as some actual translations of
Sanskrit texts. From these materials it is possible to reconstruct the main lines
of his early theory of translation. It includes the following principles:
Page 14 of 25
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Romanticism and Language
Page 15 of 25
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Romanticism and Language
(b) The central challenge for translation, though, lies in its primary task
of reproducing meaning accurately, and arises from the fact that
translation typically faces a conceptual gulf between the source language
and the target language (as they already exist). (This point is an
application of Herder’s doctrine (4).)
(c) Schleiermacher in particular notes the following complication that
arises here (one might call this the paradox of paraphrase): if, faced with
the task of translating an alien concept, a translator attempts to
reproduce its intension by reproducing its extension by means of an
elaborate paraphrase in his own language, he will generally find that, as
he gets closer to the original extension, he undermines the original
intension in other ways.
How, therefore, should translation proceed? The following points constitute the
core of Schleiermacher’s answer:
Page 16 of 25
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Romanticism and Language
Page 17 of 25
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Romanticism and Language
positions listed above, examples of this occur in (a), where the ideal of making
clear in a translation at which points an author is being conceptually
conventional and at which points conceptually original, and the strategy for
achieving this, are new; (c), where the paradox of paraphrase is original; (h),
where the point that the discomfort that the “bending” approach causes readers
actually serves positive functions is novel; (i), where the point that this approach
needs to be implemented on a large scale is new; (j), where the point that
semantic holism inevitably limits the success of such translations is original; and
(l), which plausibly contradicts Herder.57
Notes:
(1) . For a more detailed treatment of some of the topics that follow, see my After
Herder: Philosophy of Language in the German Tradition (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2010) and German Philosophy of Language: From Schlegel to
Hegel and Beyond (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011).
(2) . Schlegel’s On the Language and Wisdom of the Indians can be found in KA
8. Schleiermacher’s psychology lectures can be found in FSSW 3/6.
(4) . Friedrich Schlegels philosophische Vorlesungen aus den Jahren 1804 bis
1806, ed. C. J. H. Windischmann (Bonn: Eduard Weber, 1846), 2:28–29, 223.
(7) . Friedrich Schlegel, Lectures on the History of Literature (London: Bell and
Daldy, 1873), 6–7.
Page 18 of 25
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Romanticism and Language
(9) . There are two main editions of the hermeneutics lectures, both of which are
available in English: Hermeneutics and Criticism, ed. A. Bowie (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1998) and Hermeneutics: The Handwritten
Manuscripts, ed. J. Duke and J. Forstman (Atlanta: Scholars Press, 1986).
(12) . For example, whereas Herder’s version of doctrine (1) restricts itself to a
claim that thought is essentially dependent on and bounded by linguistic
competence, Schleiermacher turns this into a principle of the outright identity of
thought with language, or with inner language. But such strong versions of the
doctrine turn out to be philosophically untenable—vulnerable to
counterexamples in which thought occurs without any corresponding (inner)
language use, and vice versa. Again, Schleiermacher’s late attraction to Kant’s
theory of empirical schematism turns out to be problematic. For Kant’s theory
implied a sharp dualism between concepts or meanings (conceived as purely
psychological) and word-usages, so that Schleiermacher’s espousal of it implies
the same, and hence conflicts with his commitment to doctrine (2).
(14) . A decent English translation of this essay by A. Lefevere from which I shall
quote in this article can be found in German Romantic Criticism, ed. A. L. Wilson
(New York: Continuum, 1982). However, it should be noted that the translation is
not completely reliable, in particular because it omits an important long footnote
concerned with the translation of poetry.
(15) . Wilhelm von Humboldt is another figure, closely related to and strongly
influenced by the Romantics, who took over Herder’s philosophy of language
and developed it in the direction of holism. As we shall see, he was also a fellow
traveler of the Romantics in the areas of linguistics, hermeneutics, and
translation theory.
(16) . See, for example, “Von der Veränderung des Geschmacks” (On the Change
of Taste) (1766) in HW 1 and “Auch eine Philosophie der Geschichte zur Bildung
der Menschheit” (This Too a Philosophy of History for the Formation of
Humanity) (1774) in HW 4.
Page 19 of 25
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Romanticism and Language
(17) . For example, he writes in Ideen zur Philosophie der Geschichte der
Menschheit (Ideas for the Philosophy of History of Humanity) (1784–91): “The
finest essay on the history and the diverse character of the human
understanding and heart...would be a philosophical comparison of languages: for
a people’s understanding and character is imprinted in each of them” (HW 6,
353).
(20) . HW 1, 762.
(21) . HW 1, 803.
(22) . HW 6, 353.
(24) . Strictly speaking, it had already been used by his brother August Wilhelm
in a review article from 1803.
(25) . Schlegel had some forerunners in this idea. See H. Gipper and P.
Schmitter, Sprachwissenschaft und Sprachphilosophie im Zeitalter der Romantik
(Tübingen: Gunter Narr, 1985), 22–26.
(26) . Concerning the latter type, Schlegel also cites Alexander von Humboldt’s
collection of Native American grammars and Wilhelm von Humboldt’s already
ongoing work on the Basque language (KA 8, 153–55).
(27) . In doing so, he builds on, and also credits, the work of Sir William Jones.
Cf. Gipper and Schmitter, Sprachwissenschaft und Sprachphilosophie, 47–48.
Page 20 of 25
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Romanticism and Language
Europe and Asia are “one large family,” as he actually put it), and that he took
considerable pains to try to forestall any inference from his normative ranking of
languages to an invidious ranking of peoples.
(29) . Bopp’s work follows Schlegel’s On the Language and Wisdom of the
Indians closely not only in its contents but even in its form (e.g., like Schlegel’s
work concluding with a set of translations).
(30) . Concerning this subsequent history, see also J. Trabant, Apeliotes oder der
Sinn der Sprache. Wilhelm von Humboldts Sprachbild (Berlin: Akademie Verlag,
1986), 163; Gipper and Schmitter, Sprachwissenschaft und Sprachphilosophie
(as well as other works by Gipper); H. Nüsse’s introduction to KA 8; and Fiesel,
Die Sprachphilosophie der deutschen Romantik, 110ff.
(32) . The widespread conception in the secondary literature (e.g., Dilthey and
Gadamer) that for Schleiermacher “divination” is a process of psychological self-
projection into texts is basically mistaken. Like Herder before him, because of
principle (4), he is rather concerned to discourage interpreters from assimilating
the outlooks of people they interpret to their own. For example, he writes in the
hermeneutics lectures: “Misunderstanding is either a consequence of hastiness
or of prejudice. The former is an isolated moment. The latter is a mistake which
lies deeper. It is the one-sided preference for what is close to an individual’s
circle of ideas and the rejection of what lies outside it. In this way one explains
in or explains out what is not present in the author [sic]” (Hermeneutics and
Criticism, 23).
(34) . See especially Herder’s “Über Thomas Abbts Schriften” (On Thomas
Abbt’s Writings) (1768) in HW 2 and “Vom Erkennen und Empfinden der
menschlichen Seele” (On the Cognition and Sensation of the Human Soul)
(1778) in HW 4.
(35) . See especially Herder’s “Die Kritischen Wälder zur Ästhetik” (Critical
Forests) (1769) and This Too a Philosophy of History. (Note that holism as a
method of discovering meaning is quite different from holism as a thesis about
the very nature of meaning, i.e., the thesis that the Romantics were the first to
introduce. The former might indeed be based on the latter, at least in part, but it
need not be and was not yet in Herder. It is plausible, however, to hypothesize
that earlier commitments to the former by Herder and others made a significant
contribution to the eventual development of the latter by the Romantics.
Incidentally, a similar transformation of a merely epistemological thesis into a
stronger ontological one had already occurred previously concerning the
Page 21 of 25
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Romanticism and Language
connection between meaning and word-use: Ernesti had merely held that
investigating word-usage was the right way to discover meaning, but Herder had
then strengthened that position into a doctrine that meaning was word-usage.)
(36) . Two examples of this have already been mentioned in a previous note and
concern Schleiermacher’s specific formulations of doctrines (1) and (2), namely
his outright equation of thought with language and his adoption of Kant’s theory
of schematism. But there are further examples as well. One is the fact that
whereas for Herder principle (4) is only an empirically established rule of thumb,
Schleiermacher purports to give an a priori proof that conceptual-intellectual
and linguistic diversity occurs even at the level of individual people universally—
a proof that is not only very dubious in itself (both in its a priori status and in its
specific details), but also has the highly counterintuitive consequence (often
explicitly asserted by Schleiermacher) that, strictly speaking, no one ever fully
understands another person. Again, unlike Herder, Schleiermacher specifies
psychological interpretation more closely as a process of identifying, and tracing
the necessary development of, a single “seminal decision” (Keimentschluß) in
the author that was the source of his work and unfolded itself as the work in a
necessary fashion. But this too seems an unhelpful move. For how many works
are actually composed, and hence properly interpretable, in such a way (rather
than, say, involving a whole series of decisions, perhaps together with some
serendipity along the way)? Again, whereas Herder includes among the evidence
relevant to psychological interpretation both an author’s linguistic behavior and
his nonlinguistic behavior, Schleiermacher normally insists on a restriction to the
former. But this seems misguided (e.g., the Marquis de Sade’s recorded acts of
cruelty are surely no less relevant to establishing the sadistic side of his
psychology than his cruel statements). Again, whereas Herder rightly
emphasizes that the correct identification of genre plays an essential role in
interpretation, and that this is often extremely difficult due to variations in
genres that occur between historical periods, cultures, individuals, and
sometimes even different works by the same individual, Schleiermacher pays
little attention to this. Again, unlike Herder, who normally considers
interpretation and natural science to be similar activities, Schleiermacher
regards the central role that “divination,” or hypothesis, plays in interpretation
as a ground for sharply distinguishing interpretation from natural science, and
hence for classifying it as an art rather than a science. However, he should
instead have seen it as one good ground for judging them similar. (His mistake
here was caused by a false assumption that natural science works by plain
induction rather than by hypothesis.)
(37) . Josef Körner and Hermann Patsch have both made cases for Schlegel’s
importance for hermeneutics on these grounds. Their cases differ in details but
both essentially take the form of arguing—largely on the basis of the evidence
supplied by Schlegel’s Philosophy of Philology from 1797, a set of notes that
roughly coincided with the beginning of his relationship with Schleiermacher in
Page 22 of 25
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Romanticism and Language
(38) . However, it should be noted here that there are also some contrary strands
in Friedrich Schlegel’s thinking about genre. These have been well explained,
but with misguided enthusiasm, by Peter Szondi.
(40) . For more on this subject, see my “Friedrich Schlegel” and “Friedrich
Schlegel’s Hermeneutics,” in German Philosophy of Language, and especially my
“Herders Beitrag zur Entstehung der Idee romantisch,” in Die Aktualität der
Romantik, ed. M. N. Forster and K. Vieweg (Berlin: LIT, 2012).
(42) . For Schlegel’s espousal and development of Herder’s later position, see
especially Athenaeum Fragments, no. 444; KA 4 (on painting), passim; Friedrich
Schlegel’s Vorlesungen aus den Jahren 1804 bis 1806, 2:244–45; Lectures on the
Page 23 of 25
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Romanticism and Language
History of Literature, 190–91. For a more detailed discussion of this topic, see
my “Friedrich Schlegel’s Hermeneutics.”
(45) . Concerning the latter, see the Cologne lectures on German language and
literature from 1807, at KA 15/2, 94–99.
(47) . Ibid.
(49) . Ibid.
(53) . KA 8, 324–25.
(55) . Ibid. Cf. the Dialogue on Poetry (1800): “The translation of poets...has
become an art.”
(57) . Besides Herder, Friedrich Schlegel, and Boeckh, another important figure
from this period who was in broad agreement with Schleiermacher’s theories of
interpretation and translation is Wilhelm von Humboldt. For example,
concerning interpretation, like Schleiermacher, Humboldt argues in his Kawi
introduction of 1836 that not only nations but also individuals within nations are
always deeply different linguistically and conceptually-intellectually so that “all
understanding is always at the same time a misunderstanding.” And concerning
translation, he argues in the introduction to his translation of Aeschylus’s
Agamemnon (1816) for an approach to translation that is virtually identical to
Schleiermacher’s.
(58) . See esp. A. Berman, L’épreuve de l’étranger (Paris: Gallimard, 1984) and L.
Venuti, The Translator’s Invisibility: A History of Translation (London: Routledge,
1995).
Page 24 of 25
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Romanticism and Language
Page 25 of 25
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Hermeneutics, Individuality, and Tradition
Kristin Gjesdal
DOI:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199976201.003.0006
Page 1 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Hermeneutics, Individuality, and Tradition
It is the aim of this paper to shed critical light on the notion that there is a
sharp, unbridgeable division between the romantics and Hegel or, more
precisely, between the emphasis on individuality and the commitment to
philosophy of Bildung, that is, education in and through culture. My point of
departure—my test case, as it were—is Friedrich Schleiermacher’s theory of
interpretation, a model that is often viewed as a proto-example of aesthetic-
romantic attitudes, be it taken as a point of criticism (Hegel and Gadamer) or as
an occasion for praise and laudation (Szondi, Ricoeur, Frank). In my view,
Schleiermacher’s hermeneutics is not about aesthetic feeling or a celebration of
style. His is a model that addresses meaning and thought as expressed in the
communal medium of language and thus views Bildung and understanding as
two sides of the same coin.2
From this point of view, the chief difference between Hegel and the romantics is
not that Hegel has a notion of Bildung and the romantics do not. In early
nineteenth-century philosophy, we do not encounter positions for or against
Bildung. Instead we face a set of alternative conceptions of Bildung, be it, with
Hegel, along the lines of a rational, continuous tradition, or, with
Schleiermacher, with the awareness that tradition carries with it the risk of
turning into a stifling interpretative scheme and is thus in need of revitalization
from the point of view of critical engagement with concrete, symbolic
expressions. This latter notion of Bildung complements Hegel’s model, and is, as
such, deserving of rehabilitation—be it within the field of interpretation studies
or within the larger, philosophical discourse of Bildung.
Page 2 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Hermeneutics, Individuality, and Tradition
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Hermeneutics, Individuality, and Tradition
welcomes this maneuver by quoting, as the epigram to the third part of Truth
and Method, Schleiermacher’s claim that “everything presupposed in
hermeneutics is but language.”9
With regard to Schleiermacher’s notion of individuality, the first thing that must
be noted is that it does not, within the context of his hermeneutics, refer to the
feelings or inner life of a particular person. It refers to a given use of language,
an aspect of our symbolic-expressive capacity (HC 10). As such, (p.95)
individuality serves as a generic concept that covers all aspects of language use
that cannot be understood solely with reference to a universal genre, rule,
concept, or grammatical grid. The literature of a certain period can emerge as
individual. The same applies to a constellation of writers that work together or
are being exposed to the same source of influence and thus share a certain
literary orientation. Further, a given language-user might be characterized by
reference to an individual style, gesture, or use of language that differs from
that of his or her peers. But there might also be differences within his or her
language-use that make it plausible to speak, in the case of a literary expression,
about a given author’s early as opposed to his or her late work. In this way,
individuality functions as an interpretative lens with different scopes and
adjustments.10
Page 4 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Hermeneutics, Individuality, and Tradition
(a) Schleiermacher’s guidelines for interpretative work are obscured by his use
of technical terms and a somewhat inconsistent application of his chosen
vocabulary. He speaks about the need to proceed through a combination of
grammatical interpretation, geared towards the universal linguistic resources
available to the given language-user and his peers, and technical interpretation,
geared towards the individual application of the shared resources (HC 94).
However, sometimes Schleiermacher also talks about psychological
interpretation. Even though Schleiermacher wavers between these two terms, it
is fair to say that both designate the concrete use, and thus the realization, of
communal symbolic resources (and not an inner individual realm of
intentionality, emotions, and feelings).
Page 5 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Hermeneutics, Individuality, and Tradition
(p.97) Does that, then, mean that Schleiermacher ditches the idea of correct
interpretation? Not necessarily. For Schleiermacher—and here he clearly
distinguishes himself from hermeneuticians of a more Heideggerian persuasion
—interpretations vary by degree of adequacy and correctness. The meaning of
the text does not, as in the case of Gadamer, rest with its being applied in ever
new contexts of understanding.12 Interpretations are not simply different, they
are also more or less plausible when assessed in light of their purported claim to
validity. The idea of correct interpretation serves as a point of orientation, a
regulative idea, lending the interpreter purpose, direction, and motivation.13 A
correct interpretation would be one in which the historical situatedness of the
interpreter is quelled, suspended, or otherwise put out of play. However, in
Schleiermacher’s understanding, the interpreter is always already individualized
and situated in history. A neutral interpretative “point of nowhere” is not within
reach. Interpretation is, by definition, fallible and subject to constant revision.
Precisely because interpretation is fallible and subject to constant revision, is it
crucial that the interpreter distinguish between the activity of understanding, on
the one hand, and the application of the insights she arrives at, on the other. If
the distinction between interpretation and application of the meaning (truth or
insight) of the text collapses, there would be no way that the interpreter could
make the encounter with a text from a culturally or temporally distant context
challenge her own prejudices and beliefs.14
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Hermeneutics, Individuality, and Tradition
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Hermeneutics, Individuality, and Tradition
Whether a text is close to or distant from the horizon of the interpreter, there is
always a risk that the interpreter hypostatizes thoughts that are peripheral to
the concerns of the author (and possibly more congenial to the interpreter’s
horizon of interpretation), and, as a consequence, allows the interpretation to be
colored by prejudices. By referring to historical context or other works by the
same author, the interpreter can support his or her interpretation or point out
how a given reading of a text misrepresents its meaning or is lacking in
justification. A positive and concluding justification of a given account of the
relationship between primary and secondary thoughts cannot, however, be
provided. As such, these terms do not present a methodological device that
guarantees the successful outcome of interpretation, but, again, only a heuristic
guideline that grants direction to the process of understanding.17
Page 8 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Hermeneutics, Individuality, and Tradition
(a) In the secondary literature, little attention has been paid to Schleiermacher’s
notion of tradition. One reason for this oversight might be that his reflection on
tradition emerges out of his early theological writings, which, in turn, have often
been isolated from his more technical hermeneutical work. Particularly
important in this context is On Religion, a work in which Schleiermacher
discusses the challenges of a tradition that no longer appears alive and worthy
of real, intellectual engagement.20
Page 9 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Hermeneutics, Individuality, and Tradition
the lens provided by the established paradigm. In this way, religion is subject to
a barren uniformity (OR 108). We face dead letters (OR 108, see also OR 85 and
91), not a disclosure of philosophical, theological, or existential meaning.
Interpretation is reduced to a scholastic quibbling, a hermeneutic lethargy that
Schleiermacher deems the sign of a new barbarism (OR 151). Schleiermacher
draws from this that what the despisers of religion really despise, though they
themselves may not know it, is the passive mediation of older texts. The
despisers of religion conflate the meaning that a dominant interpretative
tradition has ascribed to a given text with the meaning of the text as such.
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Hermeneutics, Individuality, and Tradition
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Hermeneutics, Individuality, and Tradition
Articulating the dos and don’ts of a free social life, Schleiermacher’s Essay on a
Theory of Social Behavior has been read as a philosophical defense of the
romantic salon.27 Schleiermacher, indeed, was a regular in the Berlin salons at
the time and was seen, even by his contemporaries, as the philosopher who had
Page 12 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Hermeneutics, Individuality, and Tradition
Page 13 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Hermeneutics, Individuality, and Tradition
5.5. Conclusion
Against the background of such a reading, the notion of a bifurcation of
nineteenth-century thought into the clearly marked-off constellations of the
romantics and Hegel will have to be questioned. As represented by
Schleiermacher’s hermeneutics, the romantic project does itself entail a notion
of tradition and the individual’s formation in and through engagement with the
past.31 This, however, does not imply that Schleiermacher (or, for that sake,
romanticism more broadly) and Hegel represent the same view. What it does
imply, though, is that rather than pitching Hegel’s relation to the romantics in
light of a contrast between aesthetic individuality and Bildung, we should take
these models to represent two different responses to one and the same problem:
the interrelation between selfhood and historicity, criticism and prejudice in
tradition, that is captured in the nineteenth-century turn to Bildung in the first
place. When viewed in this light, the contrast between the romantics and Hegel
is not a matter of being for or against Bildung, historicity, or a notion of the self
as intersubjectively meditated. From Schleiermacher’s point of view, such a
contrast would make no sense: as a meaning-producing agent, the self is always
already situated within a context of tradition—that is, a shared space of action
and meaning. Hence the problem—ethically as well as epistemologically
speaking—is how to keep tradition, as a space of understanding, open, dynamic,
and achieving a balanced relationship between preservation and criticism.
Understood in this way, Hegel and Schleiermacher present two different ways of
thinking about Bildung: on the one hand, an emphasis on the continuity and
intrinsic rationality of tradition (as a space of possible meaning), on the other, a
stressing of the constitutive importance of a plurality of different historical and
individual perspectives that constantly transcend and challenge the synthesis of
tradition.
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Hermeneutics, Individuality, and Tradition
Schleiermacher does not take as his point of departure the notion of a unifying
and totalizing tradition. For Schleiermacher, tradition is a condition of possibility
for understanding. However, tradition is also a field in which prejudices and
systematically distorted beliefs can be bolstered and handed down. For him,
hermeneutics is committed to a consideration of individual points of view, an
acknowledgment of the diversity of standpoints and the need for a gradually
expanding understanding of the world. This is in my view where
Schleiermacher’s philosophy should be located—in the very intersection
between nineteenth-century philosophy of Bildung and interpretation theory
more broadly conceived.
Notes:
(1) . For Hegel’s criticism, see for instance Hegel, Lectures on the History of
Philosophy, vol. 3, Medieval and Modern Philosophy, trans. E. S. Haldane and
Frances H. Simson (Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press, 1995), 506–10. For a
study of the complexity of Hegel’s relationship to romanticism, see Otto
Pöggeler, Hegels Kritik der Romantik (Bonn: Friedrich Wilhelms-Universität,
1956 [dissertation]).
Page 15 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Hermeneutics, Individuality, and Tradition
(9) . Hans-Georg Gadamer, Wahrheit und Methode, trans. Joel Weinsheimer and
Donald G. Marshall (New York: Continuum, 2003), 381.
(13) . As Schleiermacher puts it, “nobody can be satisfied with simple non-
understanding” (HC 29).
(14) . Whereas Gadamer views interpretation and application as two sides of the
same coin, Schleiermacher insists that the hermeneutician may encounter texts
that can be understood (i.e., they can be seen as coherent, meaningful, and a
rational response to a given problem), yet their meaning cannot be applied (if,
say, the problem to which the text responds is no longer recognized as relevant).
Further, he keeps open the possibility that a text, in its approach to a given
subject matter, problem, or issue, can put into perspective, possibly also
question, the way in which a problem or issue is typically addressed within the
Page 16 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Hermeneutics, Individuality, and Tradition
(15) . Yet “style” in his work is defined as “individuality of presentation” (HC 95),
thus implying that something is presented in the first place.
(16) . Thought, however, is not reduced to propositional content, but includes the
free play of poetry (HC 64).
(18) . This is particularly clear in the work of Manfred Frank. Not only does
Frank draw on Schleiermacher’s dialectics in Das individuelle Allgemeine, but he
also published a version of Schleiermacher’s hermeneutics that is supported
with excerpts from the dialectic lectures as well as his late ethics. Friedrich
Schleiermacher, Hermeneutik und Kritik, ed. Manfred Frank (Frankfurt am
Main: Suhrkamp, 1977). Two exceptions to this tendency are Christian Berner,
La philosophie de Schleiermacher. Herméneutique. Dialectique. Ethique (Paris:
Les Éditions du Cerf, 1995) and Gunter Scholtz, Ethik und Hermeneutik.
Schleiermachers Grundlegung der Geisteswissenschaften (Frankfurt am Main:
Suhrkamp, 1995).
(19) . Schleiermacher makes this point himself when he argues for “The
dependence of both [hermeneutics and rhetoric] on dialectics” (HC 7).
(20) . As already Dilthey makes clear, this is in line with the broader orientation
of Lutherian theology.
(23) . Thus, in the hermeneutics lectures, no other text gets more attention than
the Bible and the question as to how the Bible can and should best be
understood. These discussions are ample; for an example, see HC 15–20.
Page 17 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Hermeneutics, Individuality, and Tradition
(25) . See for example Frank’s reading in Das individuelle Allgemeine, 91–94.
(26) . As Schleiermacher puts it, “In every self-consciousness there are two
elements, which we might call respectively a self-caused element (ein
Sichselbstsetzen) and a non-self-caused element (ein
Sichselbstnichtsogesetzthaben).” Friedrich Schleiermacher, The Christian Faith,
ed. H. R. Mackintosh and J. S. Stewart, trans. D. M. Baille et al. (London: T&T
Clark, 1999), 13.
(29) . For a discussion of this point, see Andreas Arndt, “Geselligkeit und
Gesellschaft. Die Geburt der Dialektik aus dem Geist der Konversation in
Schleiermachers ‘Versuch einer Theorie des geselligen Betragens,’” in Salons
der Romantik. Beiträge eines Wiepersdorfer Kolloquiums zu Theorie und
Geschichte des Salons, ed. Hartwig Schultz (Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1997),
45–61.
(30) . At this point, Schleiermacher goes beyond Schiller, whose 1795 letters on
aesthetic education address the free play between the different aspects of
humanity, but not the interplay between different individuals.
Page 18 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Hermeneutics, Individuality, and Tradition
Page 19 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Sociability and the Conduct of Philosophy
Jane Kneller
DOI:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199976201.003.0007
Keywords: early German romanticism, Friedrich Schlegel, Novalis, Schleiermacher, Kant, aesthetic
ideas, sociability
At the end of the “Critique of Aesthetic Judgment” Kant gestures towards the
possibility of a society that creatively engages intellectual, moral ideas with
natural human feeling to construct a truly human sociability. He defines
“humanity” as the combination of two universal capacities, namely “the feeling
of participation, and the ability to communicate universally one’s inmost self,”
and goes on to say that the realization of these capacities “constitutes the
sociability that befits our humanity.” Such a society would develop the “art of
reciprocal communication” that would discover “the mean between higher
Page 1 of 17
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Sociability and the Conduct of Philosophy
culture and an undemanding nature,” fully developing taste into “the universal
human sense” (AA 5, 355–56). This possibility is merely suggested by Kant here,
but the gesture is important for expressing Kant’s recognition that the capacity
that underlies what the eighteenth century called “taste,” namely, aesthetic
reflective judgment, is a cognitive condition of social communication necessary
for the construction of a higher form of human sociability. This “social”
sociability, deliberately and progressively constructed, stands in sharp contrast
to Kant’s hypothetical “unsocial” sociability that drives humanity to better its
own condition without regard to (and often in spite of) individual human
choices.1
In what follows I will argue that the early German romantics took up the project
of deliberately constructing this sort of social sociability by experimenting with
and theorizing new forms of social discourse that balanced expressions of high
culture on the one hand, and the unpretentious originality of ordinary human
nature on the other. That is to say, using Kant’s idiom, the early German
romantic movement aimed to create new modes of participatory feeling and (p.
111) self-expression that pushed the art of reciprocal philosophical
communication to new, higher levels. This essay will examine the methods of
philosophizing undertaken by the early German romantics in the 1790s,
concluding with an examination of Friedrich Schleiermacher’s attempt to
summarize and generalize romantic philosophical practice into a “theory of
human sociable conduct.”
[The ideal of the seminar] was reflected quite clearly... in certain of the
literary works that emerged at Jena just at that time [in 1798]... it was
precisely the coincidence of the rudimentary form of the seminar, the
familiar model of the Platonic dialogue, and the lively exchange of the
social setting that contributed in a typically Romantic interaction to the
first true realization of the academic seminar.3
Page 2 of 17
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Sociability and the Conduct of Philosophy
This was a heady message for the students of Jena, who saw themselves
challenged by the compelling moral presence of the age not merely to lift
themselves out of the mire of brutishness that had hitherto characterized
their university but also to prepare themselves to be the teachers, the
educators, and even the priests of mankind.5
What Ziolkowski calls the “Jena mode of discourse” that took hold among the
circle of romantic philosopher poets in the 1790s was indebted, he argues, to
this new “discourse of the academy” in a historical moment of genuine scholarly
communication led by a succession of gifted professors at the University of
Jena:6 Early German romanticism is thus to be distinguished from other
“romanticisms” by its use of academic genres such as the lecture, the persuasive
public speech, and the dialogue: “In sum, the modes of discourse preferred by
the Jena Romantics show the pronounced influence of the lecture hall and the
seminar room—places ideally suited to the kind of Symphilosophieren of which
Friedrich Schlegel, Novalis, and their contemporaries so often spoke.”7
Given the sense that attaches to the term “academic” in our own time, it may
seem very odd to suggest that the early German romantic style, which is
anything but dry and pedantic, was an emulation of academic discourse. The
point, however, is that these academic forms were being reinvented during the
1790s in Jena. The “heady” messages of these enthusiastic academic voices
turned dusty intellectual discourse into a bright, impassioned call for social and
moral progress. In the crucible of the French revolutionary era the creativity and
moral enthusiasm of “academics” like Schiller and Fichte in Jena transformed
the old institutions. Kant’s call for a new form of reciprocal communication was
already being put into practice at the time Kant wrote it, and indeed by some of
the most gifted minds of the time. When in their lectures, seminars, and
speeches Schiller and Fichte urged their students to become a part of their
Page 3 of 17
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Sociability and the Conduct of Philosophy
academic discourse, and when they expressed to their students their own view
that individuals shared universal interests in the continuing progress of history,
these new academics were in effect carrying out Kant’s call for the construction
of a reciprocal communication based on feelings of participation and the
universalization of the individual’s innermost self.
From the very start the early German romantics were captivated by the
problems and promise of aesthetic reflective dialogue. Touched by social
changes in their midst and abroad, and challenged to shoulder their share of
social responsibility and carry it into the dawn of a new century, their project
was social to the core. Like Kant they saw the need to include the cultural and
aesthetic claims of individuals from different social and historical backgrounds,
but for the early German romantics this variety of perspectives became the very
form and substance of their entire enterprise: In full recognition of the problem
of the incommensurability of subjects’ positions, they nevertheless
enthusiastically embraced the project of giving voice to a chorus, and a chaos, of
multiple perspectives. Their writings and discourses aimed at maximizing
mutual understanding without minimizing discordant notes, and even provoked
them (e.g., Schlegel’s exquisitely ironic “On Incomprehensibility”). They
Page 4 of 17
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Sociability and the Conduct of Philosophy
addressed the problem of how subjective experience and the inner life of the
individual can ever “get outside itself” (e.g., Novalis’ Fichte and Kant studies
and his Novices of Sais), and they returned again and again to the larger issue of
how a society or social group with members from different vocations, religious
backgrounds, and genders can find common ground through self-expression
(Schlegel’s Dialogue on Poetry, Schleiermacher’s Speeches on religion and his
Theory of Sociable Conduct).
(KA 2, 182–83)10
Page 5 of 17
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Sociability and the Conduct of Philosophy
Poetry (Poesie) is universal because it aims at an ideal that is itself never fully
articulable and thus “incomprehensible.” It is progressive because it never gives
up attempting to comprehend and be comprehensible, that is, it aims constantly
to better communicate itself to others, both present and future. Schlegel
describes how in response to the charge of incomprehensibility he had initially
resolved to (p.115)
have a talk about this matter with my reader, and then create before his
eyes—in spite of him as it were—another new reader to my own liking: yes,
even to deduce him if need be. I meant it quite seriously... I wanted for
once to be really thorough and go through the whole series of my essays,
admit their frequent lack of success with complete frankness, and so
gradually lead the reader to being similarly frank and straightforward with
himself.
Schlegel continues describing how he had hoped to show the reader, in the
clearest terms, how incomprehension is “relative” to each individual and that the
highest form of incomprehension occurs precisely in the arts and sciences,
where the aim is total clarity of comprehension. But this confession artfully
shades off into a mock encomium to the recent discovery (by Kant) of a “real
language” and to the “critical age” he lives in, in which “everything is going to
be criticized except the age itself” and in which, in the newly dawning
millennium “humanity will at last rise up in a mass and learn to read.” Elizabeth
Millán Zaibert sums up the piece, and Schlegel’s use of irony, nicely:
Irony is a sort of play that reveals the limitations of a view of reality that
presumed to have the last word. With the use of romantic irony, Schlegel
showed that there was no last word. And once we give up a last word,
aesthetic methods become sensible alternatives to the methods of
mathematics and the natural sciences.11
One of the aesthetic methods prized by the early romantics was the dialogue
form, and here again Schlegel provides a model of the romantic mode of
discourse that fused philosophy and poetry in an attempt to make them “lively
and sociable” and to make “life and society poetical.” In his introduction to the
Dialogue on Poetry, modeled upon the many actual conversations of the early
romantics, Schlegel insists upon the social nature of poetry: it “befriends and
binds with unseverable ties the hearts of all those who love it” no matter how
much at odds they otherwise may be “in their own lives” (KA 2, 284–87).12
Poetry is expansive by nature and true poetry exists when one seeks to expand
one’s poetry to increasingly incorporate the work of others. Aware that one will
always return to oneself, poetry requires “reaching out time and again beyond
oneself to find the complement of one’s innermost being in the depths of
Page 6 of 17
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Sociability and the Conduct of Philosophy
The fact that the “real heart of the matter” is no more comprehensible than a
“real language” in no way hinders, and in fact is precisely what drives, the
romantic project to attempt to get to it. The goal is the striving—that is, the
striving for an increasingly expansive poetry that “approximates the loftiest
possibility of [poetry] on earth” through reciprocal communication leading to the
discovery of multiple views to be incorporated into one’s own.
Page 7 of 17
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Sociability and the Conduct of Philosophy
On humanity. Its pure complete development must first be in the art of the
individual—and only then pass over to the great masses of people and then
the species. To what extent is the species an individual?
(NS 2, 271, no. 567; 296, no. 667; Kneller, 169; 194)
(p.117) This fundamental interplay of the inner self with the outer world—
especially with other “selves”—becomes a trope in Novalis’s maturing
philosophical and literary work. In his studies of Kant he muses that philosophy
includes treating the sciences (die Wissenschaften) both scientifically and
poetically, and raises the question whether the poetic is not perhaps identical to
the practical, in the sense of being a specification of it. He worries about
whether there are means other than mere sense perception for “getting outside
ourselves and reaching other beings” (NS 2, 390). One of his last literary efforts,
the Novices of Sais, makes clear that for Novalis, the answer to these
metaphysical questions about the nature of the subject is that it is essentially
social, and specifically it is most itself when it is “in love” with other human
beings. The work depicts many “interpersonal” exchanges with nonsubject
selves (plants, rocks, the ocean) in which “both types of perception [feeling and
thinking] gain: the outer world becomes transparent and the inner world
becomes varied and meaningful” (NS 1, 71–109).14 But a crucial “fairy tale” told
by one of the novices underscores Novalis’s commitment to the primacy of the
social: a young man journeys to the veiled statue of a woman said to be “the
mother of things,” but the story ends not, as in Schiller’s poem, with the death of
the seeker from despair induced by what he had unveiled, but with the young
seeker of knowledge lifting the veil to discover once again the lover, and
eventually the family, friends, and community he had earlier spurned in his quest
for knowledge. This extraordinary little story of the fantastic journey culminating
in everyday life is typically early romantic, and in its portrayal of fundamental
human wisdom as rooted in community with others, it encapsulates a
fundamental principle of early romanticism.
Page 8 of 17
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Sociability and the Conduct of Philosophy
sections (p.118) yield a fascinating glimpse into the world of the Berlin salons
of which he and his close friend Friedrich Schlegel were both active. The Essay
illustrates the centrality of the very idea of social reflective activity for early
romantic philosophy, picking up the thread of Kant’s comment at the end of the
“Critique of Aesthetic Judgment” about the need for developing a “sociability
that befits our humanity.” Schleiermacher begins with the claim that free
sociability is a “higher goal of humanity”: “free sociability, neither fettered nor
determined by any external end, is demanded vociferously by all educated
people as one of their primary and most cherished needs” (KGA 165; Foley, 153).
He elaborates by pointing out that people’s jobs (their “civil life”) and their home
life take up so much time and energy, that their sphere of “mental activity” is
increasingly narrowed and their perspectives and activities become increasingly
one-sided. Thus he says, the higher aim of free and unfettered conversation with
others is to expose us to the widest possible variety of perspectives:
Only here, owing to the inherent lack of civil authority, everyone must be
their own legislator and must see to it that the common good sustains no
damage. All improvement must proceed from this principle and can only
really be brought about by every individual adjusting his or her behavior in
accordance with that common goal.
There is an important difference, however: This romantic society is real and its
members are there not only intellectually but in the flesh. They conduct
themselves freely with an eye to the good of the society and also “in accordance
with [their] inclinations” (KGA 165; Foley, 154). Both individuality and pleasure
in the activity of social reflection are a part of this embodied, aesthetic realm of
ends. Because these societies are made of real people, Schleiermacher (p.119)
Page 9 of 17
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Sociability and the Conduct of Philosophy
is acutely aware of the difficulties of setting up and sustaining them. Still, his
own experiences in the salons of Berlin convinced him that, if only he can root
this account solidly within common human nature, some systematic account of
how they must be formed and conducted is possible. Thus he describes the free
society as a construct for which guidelines may be set out in theory, beginning
with the “view that free sociability [is] a natural tendency that cannot be
circumvented” and “the point of departure will be merely the initial concept of
sociability that is available of its own accord in every person” (KGA 168; Foley,
156). Since free sociability is naturally sought for its own sake, the continuous
and uninterrupted free activity of all the individuals involved in forming and
maintaining these societies is also desirable in itself. Furthermore, “If we
analyze the concept of free sociability of society in its truest sense,”
Schleiermacher says, then “we find that several people should affect each other
and that this affecting is by no means permitted to be one-sided” (KGA 169;
Foley, 157–58). To this end the distinctive character of such societies is one of
reciprocity, that is, the free and equal participation of each member aimed at
“nothing but the free play of thoughts and feelings by means of which all
members excite and animate one another” (KGA 170; Foley, 159).
Because societies are made up of participating individuals they will each have
their own special character, and yet certain rules apply to them all. First, all
communication must be reciprocal (form) and second, what is communicated
should be an expression from and about each individual.16 Since individuals are
of a variety of types unique to every group, Schleiermacher says, “Each society
has its own outline and profile: whosoever fails to contribute to creating this; or
whosoever does not know how to remain within the confines of this, is as good
as not there for this society” (KGA 170; Foley, 159). Hence a third rule applies,
namely that individual members must limit their activity to what will not
undermine the society as a whole. To avoid the formation of exclusionary groups,
“Nothing should be evoked that does not belong to the communal sphere of
all” (KGA 171; Foley, 160). This creates another problem, namely that for the
individual to limit herself is to fail to express her unique individual self to the
society. Societies are easily destroyed by self-centered members, but self-
deprecating team players are just as destructive because they do not contribute
their own, unique share. Alternating between the two types of contribution (of
self-aggrandizing and self-effacing) is no solution, Schleiermacher says: “the
one-sidedness is not avoided by doubling it” (KGA 172–73; Foley, 61–63). Thus a
major problem for free sociability is that of figuring out how to contribute one’s
individuality completely and at the same time to fully participate in the
character of the society.
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Sociability and the Conduct of Philosophy
destroying the character of the society, whereas the character of the society is
set by its subject matter (“tone”), which ought to be limited. Schleiermacher also
gives guidelines for delineating the subject matter: It is to be determined by a
kind of sensitive, reflective equilibriation on the part of all the members,
between the poles of each individual’s own interests and the intersection of
those interests that are common to all. Beginning from each side and reflectively
balancing our concerns, we “seek to determine the sphere of the society
between the given limits with ever increasing precision,” he says. Ideally then,
every contribution of every individual fully establishes the society’s tone and
character while at the same time allowing each participant to express him- or
herself fully in a unique individual manner. Schleiermacher does not worry about
a domineering person or subgroup hijacking the conversation: “To hold one’s
disagreeable qualities within bounds is the task of the others, and they will
surely attend to that” (KGA 175; Foley, 165).
This meaning should be one that I should like to call the common
denominator and is related directly to maintenance [of the society’s
character]... and another, as it were, a higher one that is thrown out with
some uncertainty to see if someone will pick up on it and pursue the
intimations it contains.
The ways in which this can be carried out, he says, are practically uncountable,
and the doubling of purpose in every individual’s statements lends itself to
insinuation, banter, irony, and parody, all of which, so long as they are not
directed against another individual absent or present, are fine ways of moving
the social interactions to a high point. The Essay ends with a caution: “it is in the
nature of a theory and does not really require explicit evincing that the ideas
presented here are ideals that practice is only meant to approach” (KGA 181–82;
Foley, 173).
Two comments on this theory should be stressed. First, the final description
clearly owes much not only to the actual sociability of the meetings of the Berlin
salons and the Jena sessions that Schlegel and Novalis dubbed
“symphilosophizing,” but it also portrays the romantic program defined by
Novalis, namely that of romanticizing, carrying an activity in two directions at
once, elevating and lowering, making the ordinary extraordinary and the
extraordinary common (NS 2, 545, no. 105). By placing this poetic demand in
the setting of a social gathering (p.121) of individuals, Schleiermacher
personalizes Novalis’s definition and brings into relief the element most
Page 11 of 17
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Sociability and the Conduct of Philosophy
Page 12 of 17
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Sociability and the Conduct of Philosophy
(AA 5, 313)
In Kant’s terms, what such conversations lack is aesthetic spirit, where “spirit”
is defined as “the animating principle in the mind” (AA 5, 313).
(AA 5, 313)
Page 13 of 17
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Sociability and the Conduct of Philosophy
(AA 5, 316)
Genius then, is the ability to discover and express aesthetic ideas, and
Schleiermacher’s theory of sociable conduct is the functional, intersubjective
equivalent of Kant’s “inner” subjective account of genius. For Schleiermacher,
Kant’s account of the inner state of the subject—the mind of the genius—is writ
large in the sociable (romantic) “society,” that is, an assemblage of individuals
whose sole purpose in gathering is to discover their social capacity (their
humanity) and to further it in free, reciprocal dialogue. Their only purpose is the
regulative one of creating a society that is an expression of the union of their
multiple individualities and their shared social community. Each member
expresses her views in her own “manner,” leaving her professional standing, her
class and family standing, and so on, aside (except to the extent that it will
manifest itself in the manner of her expression). In Kant’s terms, her expressions
together with all the others, serve to constitute a “multiplicity of partial
presentations,” and these serve to enlarge but not determine the “given
concept.” In Schleiermacher’s terms, her contributions along with the others
serve to maintain and entertain (unterhalten) the whole group and at the same
time to elevate the subject of the conversation, and human sociability itself.
Page 14 of 17
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Sociability and the Conduct of Philosophy
point of the romantic society is free play and the disinterested pleasure that this
freedom brings its members, but this social reflective freedom also serves a
larger purpose insofar as it discovers and creates enlarged philosophical
perspectives and new ways of looking at old concepts.
In his interpretive account of the Essay, Peter Foley argues that the role of the
salons in Berlin was extremely important in shaping Schleiermacher’s model of
sociability: the Berlin salons of Henrietta Herz, Rahel Levin, and other were
diverse not only in gender and religious ethnicity but also in professional
occupations and in degree and kind of education. At their best they were largely
successful experiments in cross-cultural understanding and intellectual
discovery. Schleiermacher is quite clear that a multiplicity of such societies is
possible and desirable, and that each must formulate its own tone, and find its
own equilibrium. Like Kant’s genius, the successful sociable society cannot
formulate the rules by which it operates in such a way that others can clone that
success simply by following these rules. Creative free societies can serve as
exemplars for other would-be societies, just as genius can give examples to other
budding genius. Genius must create itself from its own inner resources, just as a
successful society must create itself through the particular individuals that
constitute it. In short, based on his own experience in the romantic mode of
discourse, Schleiermacher was able to sketch in some detail an ideal of an
egalitarian society that values individual difference—indeed, requires it—in the
process of constructing a unique discursive community.
Page 15 of 17
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Sociability and the Conduct of Philosophy
Notes:
(1) . Kant introduces this hypothesis in his “Idea for a Universal History from a
Cosmopolitan Point of View” published in 1784. AA 8, 15–31.
(2) . Ernst Behler and Roman Struc, introduction to their edition of Friedrich
Schlegel: Dialogue on Poetry and Literary Aphorisms (hereafter Behler and
Struc) (University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press, 1968), 4.
(10) . For English translation, see Friedrich Schlegel’s “Lucinde” and the
Fragments, trans. Peter Firchow (hereafter Firchow) (Minneapolis: University of
Minnesota Press, 1971), 31–32.
(12) . Friedrich Schlegel, “Gespräch über die Poesie”; for the English translation,
see Behler and Struc, 53–55.
(13) . Novalis, Fichte-Studien; for the English translation, see Novalis, Fichte
Studies, ed. Jane Kneller (hereafter Kneller) (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 2002), 166.
(14) . Die Lehrlinge zu Saïs; for the English translation, see The Novices of Sais,
trans. Ralph Manheim, with sixty drawings by Paul Klee (New York: Curt
Valentin, 1949), 77.
Page 16 of 17
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Sociability and the Conduct of Philosophy
(15) . The Essay’s authorship was only determined in the early twentieth century.
The reasons for its being abandoned include the fact that Schleiermacher found
himself finishing it in social isolation, and that he was working on several other
projects at the time. See Peter Foley’s Friedrich Schleiermacher’s “Essay on a
Theory of Sociable Behavior” (1799): A Contextual Interpretation (Lewiston:
Edwin Mellon Press, 2006), 125ff. References to Schleiermacher’s Essay in what
follows are to KGA volume 12, followed by the pagination in Peter Foley’s
translation (hereafter Foley), included in his book.
Page 17 of 17
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
“Doch Sehnend Stehst/Am Ufer Du” (“But Longing You Stand on the Shore”)
Richard Eldridge
DOI:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199976201.003.0008
7.1.
As the name of the discipline implies, philosophy is centrally concerned not
simply with knowledge alone, but with wisdom or with the problem of
orientation or with the achievement of a life of felt and reasonable
meaningfulness. In strongly traditional societies, this problem may not arise, or
solutions to it may be held in place as what is simply to be done, without diverse
paths or possibilities of reflection on them significantly presenting themselves.
Within modern social economies, marked in contrast by technological
development and strongly divided labor, things are much less settled, in ways
that can provoke both anxiety and reflection. But how is reflection then to
develop fruitfully? If it is significantly abstract overall, then it threatens both to
lose touch with concrete life practices and in doing so to turn either emptily
escapist or dogmatically tyrannical. Yet if it lingers entirely in the concrete, then
Page 1 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
“Doch Sehnend Stehst/Am Ufer Du” (“But Longing You Stand on the Shore”)
Writing roughly between 1795 and 1815 in the wake of emerging secularization
and showing a strong consciousness of social life as both fractured (p.130) and
unavoidable, a number of writers whom we now class as Romantic—pre-
eminently Hölderlin and Wordsworth, Goethe in his lyric poetry, and Blake and
Coleridge—developed a kind of practice of philosophy by other means. Swerving
between abstract reflection and concrete description and between rationalism
and empiricism, they developed strong senses of human subjects as bound to a
temporality that is not discernibly plotted and yet with which one can (so they
suggested) at times come to terms. They accept neither human fatedness to life
within unintelligible and impersonal processes alone nor fantasies of either
escape or full control of the conditions of life, so that “romanticism” becomes a
name for philosophy done, the problem of orientation addressed, otherwise than
only in abstract distantiation from the ordinary. Its images of coming to maturity,
even if imperfectly and without dogmatism and final closure, stand as models
that are distinctly relevant to our thinking about maturity and orientation in life,
given a modern social economy that we significantly share with them.1 Attention
to their strongly temporalized thought and writing can help alert us both to how
philosophy and poetry may be entangled with one another in relation to certain
central problems of modern human life and to possibilities of maturity that we
might otherwise fail to notice or articulate.
7.2.
It is well known that Hölderlin’s mature poetry is significantly motivated by his
sense, developing out of his criticism of Fichte, of the self-occlusion of the
Absolute. As in German idealism generally, “the Absolute” names that which is
not dependent on anything else and simply is––a self-determining whole that
includes all of nature and human life. Contra Fichte, Hölderlin argues, “If I say:
‘I am I, [then] the subject (“I”) and the object (“I) are not united in such a way
that no separation could be performed without violating the essence of what is
to be separated; on the contrary, the I is only possible by means of this
separation of the I from the I.”2 Ignoring the mistaken treatment of the is of
identity as the is of predication, the argument is straightforward and compelling.
Being a subject—that which we primarily refer to by means of “I”—implies
apperceptive unity; that is, it implies at least the possibility of coming to be
explicitly aware of the contents of one’s consciousness as the contents of one’s
consciousness. Any thing that lacked this capacity could not properly be called a
subject. But this capacity in turns implies the ability, as it were, to separate
oneself from oneself, in particular to focus on the contents of one’s
consciousness as not essential to what one is. I am thinking of a dog, say, but I
could be thinking instead (and sometimes do think instead) of a cup of coffee.
Hence neither of these contents is itself essential to my identity as a subject. But
Page 2 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
“Doch Sehnend Stehst/Am Ufer Du” (“But Longing You Stand on the Shore”)
for the Absolute, in contrast, everything is essential. That is, it is not subject-like.
And hence, further, we, as (p.131) finite subjects are separated, cast out, from
this original, all-embracing unity of Being as such. Insofar as we do possess a
consciousness that is both apperceptively unified and discursive (such that we
are able to form judgments), we are “outside” a more original, inclusive unity,
able to attend to this or that, but never simply bound within the flow of the
whole. Our status as subjects is marked, as Hölderlin puts it, by an “arche-
separation,” an Ur-theilung.3 Both reflection and we as subjects capable of
reflection are somehow within the Absolute, but also separated from its
continuous self-development, not essential to it.
It is not immediately clear how much of this argument is sound or what its
implications are. It might well be conceded that the Absolute—supposing to
begin with that we find much use for a concept of the whole of Being—is not
itself subject-like or reflective or apperceptively unified in the way that we are as
finite subjects. But why should that thought imply the further thought that we,
as finite subjects, are somehow exterior to it, separated or cast out from it?
Page 3 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
“Doch Sehnend Stehst/Am Ufer Du” (“But Longing You Stand on the Shore”)
Page 4 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
“Doch Sehnend Stehst/Am Ufer Du” (“But Longing You Stand on the Shore”)
beauty, and (p.133) passion) persist always in tension with one another, with no
standing resolution and only moments of relative balance.6
The result in Hölderlin’s writing, both theoretical and poetic, that enacts this
tension is a kind of back-and-forth movement between distantiated, abstract
theorizing and immersive, absorptive dwelling in perception and feeling as
given. In the mode of abstract theorizing, he seeks the “true profundity” of
“complete knowledge of the parts that we must found and combine into one, and
deep knowledge of that which founds and comprehends, piercing to the farthest
end of knowledge.”7 Without fundamental knowledge of one’s place in the whole,
there is neither dignity nor actively maintained orientation. In more optimistic
Fichtean moments, Hölderlin suggests that “he who truly acts according to the
whole is by himself thereby more consecrated to peace and more disposed to
esteem the individual.”8 This implies that action according to the whole is
possible and hence that the wages of reflection on the whole that issues in
appropriate action need not be only distantiation and alienation. Likewise, in a
1797 letter to Schiller, Hölderlin argues that abstract reflection, shying from life
into thought, while difficult, is also both natural and fruitful.
Page 5 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
“Doch Sehnend Stehst/Am Ufer Du” (“But Longing You Stand on the Shore”)
(p.134) In recoil, then, from a life of abstract reflection that produces as much
continuing anxiety as direction, Hölderlin also celebrates the fact that the “airy
spirits [Luftgeister] with metaphysical wings”10 have left him, thus enabling
greater peace in freedom from reflection. Persistent thinking about orientation,
without fixed and stable results, yields only restlessness; without receptivity,
there is no composure. Something must come from without, in order to inform
and give content to thinking. Thought alone is unable to generate determinate
objects. “When I think an object as possible, then I only repeat the previously
existent consciousness by means of which it is actual. There is for us no
thinkable possibility that was not at one time actuality.”11 As Violetta Waibel
usefully comments, “Hölderlin seems not simply to negate principles and a priori
moments of thinking, but rather to regard them as forms of abstraction that are
not thinkable independently and without being bound to concrete states of
affairs.”12 Broadly speaking, as Waibel also notes, a suspicion of abstract
thinking on Hölderlin’s part is a continuing point of contact between his
poetological writings and the skepticism of Jacobi. Both Jacobi and Hölderlin, as
Waibel puts it, give primacy to “existential orientation in the world
[Befindlichkeit in der Welt]” and so “assign to anthropology...a precedence over
a philosophical mode of explanation that threatens to become an intellectual end
in itself.”13 This suspicion of abstract thinking is further reinforced by
Hölderlin’s reading of Plato, especially of the Symposium, where love (eros) is
presented as a force of attraction to concrete things that is co-primordial with
the emergence of consciousness itself. Or in Hölderlin’s own formulation:
As our original infinite essence became suffering for the first time and as
our free, full power felt its first limits, as poverty mated with exuberance,
then there was love. Ask yourself: when was that? Plato says: on the day
that Aphrodite was born. Thus just then, when the beautiful world began
for us, when we came to consciousness, then we became finite.14
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
“Doch Sehnend Stehst/Am Ufer Du” (“But Longing You Stand on the Shore”)
And yet Hölderlin does not quite abandon reason and reflection altogether. He
continues to see the pursuit of autonomy and self-command, grounded in
rational reflection and expressed in adherence to principles, as also part of
man’s higher than merely animal nature. Unlike other animals, we are, as both
burdened and gifted with reflection, anticipation, and memory, open to “infinite
satisfaction, ...provided that [man’s] activity is of the right kind, is not too far-
reaching for him, for his strength and skill, that he is not too restless, too
undetermined nor, on the other hand, too anxious, too restricted, too
controlled.”19 As the unresolved two directions of mutual qualification in this
passage show—we must be determined, resolute, in charge of what we do, but
not too much; and we must be receptive, open, and ready to accept what
happens but not too much20 ––Hölderlin develops a philosophical anthropology
that combines elements from Kant, empiricism, and what would become
Hegelianism, but that also differs strikingly from each of them. As in Kant, the
exercise of reason and reflection to generate a moral law matters as a
fundamental aspect of our dignity, but in contrast with Kant this exercise cannot
take place on its own, apart from intense experiences of attraction. As in
empiricism, receptive sense-experience is an essential source of content for
orientation in life, but in contrast with empiricism sense-experience is not simply
dispositive, and it is available not continuously, but only intermittently, in
moments of intense attraction to a concrete object, person, or scene. As in
Hegel, there is prereflective orientation to the world that can be to some extent
articulated, but in contrast with Hegel the relevant articulation that yields
orientation is itself temporary, strongly temporalized, and bound up more with
erotic attractions, embodiment, and openness to natural beauty than with
participation in public life.
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
“Doch Sehnend Stehst/Am Ufer Du” (“But Longing You Stand on the Shore”)
of all, and the best powers are often consumed in fruitless wrestling with it.
Remain closer to the world of the senses so that you will be less in danger either
of losing sobriety [Nüchternhheit] in rapture [Begeisterung] or of straying into a
contrived [gekünstelt] expression.”21 For Schiller, philosophy and abstract
reflection could and should be left behind, as Schiller indeed abandoned them
and returned to drama after the period of his intense absorption in Kantianism
from 1793 to 1795. In contrast, instead of turning away from philosophy and to
poetry as a separate and distinct practice, Hölderlin takes up the task of
incorporating alternations between moments of abstract reflection and moments
of intense absorption into a self-developing poetic whole. As he comments in a
1799 letter to his brother,
Poetry unites men not, I say, in the manner of play; it unites them, namely,
when it is genuine and functions [wirkt] genuinely––with all the manifold
suffering, happiness, striving, hoping and fearing, with all the opinions and
errors, all the virtues and ideas, with everything great and small, that is
among them—as a living, thousandfold divided [gegliedert] heartfelt [innig]
whole.22
The consequence in the poetry of the bearing of this task is that poetry remains
internally related to philosophy, as it is oriented around what Hölderlin calls
transitions (Wechsel) in mood, where the transitions themselves are marked by
the same sort of difficulty and abruptness that mark their occurrence in daily
life. Or as Hölderlin puts it to his brother, “I cannot easily find my way out of
reasoning [Raisonnement] and into poetry, and vice versa....Perhaps only a few
people will have as much difficulty with the transition [Übergang] from one
mood to another as I do.”23
The result is a difficult poetry more continuously of open, even abrupt, transition
than of completed doctrinal closure. As Waibel usefully puts it, Hölderlin’s
concept—decisive for his poetry—of reciprocal determination
(Wechselbestimming) of moods must be understood in the framework of a theory
of drives. One concept at the same time determines its opposite, so that both
stand in a relation of reciprocal determination. Something must stand opposed
to the I that is infinite in itself—either an object or alternatively a world of
objectivity—in order for it to feel and cognize. In the same way, a striving toward
the infinite, that is, a striving to realize ideas, is also unthinkable, (p.137)
without a simultaneous striving toward limitation, that is, toward an actual
recognition of the conditioned character of existence.24
Neither drive—neither the drive toward selfhood and fully autonomous activity
in self-sustaining abstract thinking, nor the drive toward receptivity to and
absorption in the finite—can properly be denied, abandoned, or avoided. Or as
Hölderlin puts it in a prose fragment of the metrical version of Hyperion, “we
cannot deny the drive to free ourselves, to ennoble ourselves, to progress into
Page 8 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
“Doch Sehnend Stehst/Am Ufer Du” (“But Longing You Stand on the Shore”)
the infinite. That would be animalistic. But we can also not deny the drive to be
determined, to be receptive; that would not be human.”25 Since both drives
remain present and undeniable, with neither being sacrificed to the other and
with no possibility of their stable integration, the result, as Waibel puts it, of “the
thought-figure of reciprocal determination” is “a metaphysics of the finite” that
continuously accepts and embraces “the possibility of reversal.”26
Within the poetry that enacts this sense of the subject always open to the
possibility of reversal, it is necessary, always, “to bear the momentarily
incomplete.”27 “Real effectiveness” requires neither too much mingling of self-
determining, ennobling, reflective activity with sensuousness, receptivity, and
the ordinary nor too much isolation from them.28 Instead of simply reaching a
doctrinal conclusion, and instead of maintaining itself either in the sphere of
pure reflective activity or in the sphere of the registering of the sensuously
given, the successful poem must instead work through reflective-rational activity
in relation to experience of a sensuously given object. The proper thematic
subject matter of poetry in general is thus, one might say, not a given object, but
rather an object as-it-is-experienced-by-a-subject-prompted-to-feeling-and-
reflection in relation to it. In close proximity to the Wordsworthian thought that
it is “the feeling [and associated reflection] therein developed [that] gives
importance to the [given] action and situation, and not the action and situation
to the feeling,”29 self-recognition is possible only by attending to and working
through relations between subject activity and determinate objects. As Waibel
summarizes the point, for Hölderlin
Page 9 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
“Doch Sehnend Stehst/Am Ufer Du” (“But Longing You Stand on the Shore”)
The successful poem that begins in 1, moves through 2 and 3, and completes
itself constructively in 4 is thus itself an achievement of a good-enough self-unity
despite the omnipresent fact of reversals of subject activity by sensuous
givenness and of sensuous givenness by subject activity. Hence the underlying
thought that is embodied in successful Hölderlinian lyric poetry is that “Es war
doch so schön”32 ––it was all so beautiful anyway. In its registering, expressing,
and enacting of the play of opposed drives, the successful lyric poem is an
acknowledgment of the fundamental circumstances of human life as a life of
conditioned subject activity open to reversals. It is, hence, not the abandonment
of philosophy and reflective activity in favor of poetry, but instead their situation
as conditioned within the context of ongoing human life.
7.3.
Thematically and formally, Hölderlin’s poetic practice that situates philosophical
reflection within the course of life develops out of a number of earlier
experimentations in theme and form. His earliest poems, such as his early
Tübingen hymns, alternate between sentimental expressiveness of a subjective
mood in the style of Klopstock (as in “The Oaks” and “To the Aether”) and a
more objectively celebratory mode derived from Schiller (as in “Hymn to the
Goddess of (p.139) Harmony” and “Hymn to Immortality”). Significantly,
however, already these early hymns display a certain awkwardness in stance, as
though the standpoint for what is either to be worshipped or objectively
celebrated were not entirely secure.33 During his Frankfurt period from January
1796 to September 1798, Hölderlin produced a number of Diotima poems,
inspired by Suzette Gontard, as well as nature poems and shorter, epigrammatic
odes.34 A sharper sense of the difficulties of maintaining an enthusiastic or a
celebratory stance and voice, a sense that is evident also in the contemporary
correspondence and theoretical writings, then seems to develop during the
composition of Hyperion in the period from 1794 to 1797, perhaps influenced by
the difficulties of his clandestine relations with Suzette/Diotima. As Hölderlin
famously writes in the preface to the penultimate version of the novel,
Page 10 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
“Doch Sehnend Stehst/Am Ufer Du” (“But Longing You Stand on the Shore”)
We all run through an eccentric path [eine exzentrische Bahn], and there is
no other way possible from childhood to completion [Vollendung].
Blissful unity, Being in the unique sense of the word, is lost for us and we
had to lose it if we are to strive after it and achieve it.
...We have fallen out with nature, and what was once (as we believe) One is
now in conflict with itself, and mastery and servitude alternate on both
sides. It often seems to us as if the world were everything and we nothing,
but often too as if we were everything and the world nothing.
...But neither our knowledge nor our action can attain in any period of our
existence to that point at which all conflict ceases, where All is one; the
determinate line can be united with the indeterminate only through an
infinite approximation [in unendlicher Annäherung].35
The result of this sense of the subject position as always already bound up in
conflict is a poetry of loss and finitude that tracks and expresses this plight of
the subject without resolving it. It narrates arcs of motion through moments of
absorption in the given that are always liable to be ruptured by reflection and
moments of reflection, power, and insight that are always liable to be ruptured
by a returning, attractive but recalcitrant given. Rather than announcing (p.
140) a doctrine achieved, whether conciliatory or despairing, it moves in fits
and starts, halted by this moment of perception, then regaining an energy of
compositional onwardness in registering it, then faltering again as the energy
cannot be sustained in any single continuing direction. That is, the major poetry
enacts an effort together with its foundering. It tracks and locates the place of
the human subject as a being capable of self-initiated attention, reflection, and
thought within a whole that it should know, but cannot, and within which it
should be at peace, but cannot be. It is neither within philosophy nor outside it,
but is rather marked internally by both philosophy and its foundering, just as we
live neither continuously within reflectiveness nor altogether outside it, neither
altogether at home nor altogether as nomads.
Page 11 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
“Doch Sehnend Stehst/Am Ufer Du” (“But Longing You Stand on the Shore”)
7.4.
Among Hölderlin’s major poems, the substantial but still incomplete
“Rousseau” (1800) is especially clear thematically in illustrating Hölderlin’s
mature sense of the problem for the human subject of living simultaneously
within the necessity of reflection and the impossibility of completing it. It is in
part a reworking into an alcaic ode of the slightly earlier asclepic ode “To the
Germans.” (Its opening line is line 1 of strophe 11 of “To the Germans.”) Its
general project is simultaneously to praise Rousseau’s exemplary achieved
subjectivity while also describing its limitations, thus avoiding any triumphalist
doctrinalism. Rousseau, as Hölderlin sees him, bears up, one might say, under
the burden of a subjectivity given over both to visionary reflection on new
possibilities of more meaningful human life and to their standing
incompleteness. Hölderlin had read Rousseau’s The Social Contract in 1791. As
one of the so-called uncouth Jacobins, Hölderlin planted a Liberty Tree in a
meadow near the Tübingen seminary on Bastille Day, 1793, an act that provoked
Duke Karl Eugen to place the group under surveillance. While in Jena in
September 1795, Hölderlin planned to draft a new educational program modeled
on Rousseau’s Emile and Julie, ou la nouvelle Héloïse.36 Noting that Rousseau’s
name is the first name of a modern writer that appears on a list of writers on
whom Hölderlin planned to write for his projected journal Iduna, Stanley
Corngold remarks that Rousseau “represents Hölderlin’s first leap of thought to
modern writing; he constitutes Hölderlin’s frame for his grasp of literary
modernity.”37 Commenting on the appearances of Rousseau in “The
Rhine” (1801), Paul de Man notes that Rousseau is, for Hölderlin,
paradigmatically the one who exercises the distinctive powers of a human
subject in using language: “Rousseau, as in the ode that bears his name, appears
above all as the man of language: he listens (l. 143) he speaks (l. 144), he gives
language (l. 146), and song (l. 165).”38 Richard Unger describes Rousseau (p.
141) as functioning as a precursor figure and uncanny double for Hölderlin
himself. “Rousseau’s “strangeness” for Hölderlin is...the uncanniness a poet
must experience in another man who ultimately projects his own destiny.
Paradoxically, Hölderlin views Rousseau, a writer of prose, as the man who most
clearly anticipates the poetic fulfillment he himself desires.”39
Both the destiny of the modern human subject as the bearer of language and
reflectiveness and the sort of qualified poetic fulfillment that is possible for such
a subject are then projected onto Rousseau in the poem “Rousseau,” and the
itinerary of the bearing of that destiny and of the achievement of that qualified
fulfillment is tracked narratively. The poem consists of ten strophes, with the
first four in strict alcaic metric patterns (lines of 11, 11, 9, and 10 beats with a
regular pattern of stresses) and the last six in uncompleted approximations to
the alcaic. The first line of the seventh strophe includes an unfilled in past
participle prefix (“ge”), marking it as uncompleted. The last line of the tenth and
final strophe is a nonstandard, more abrupt seven-beat line that lends an air of
Page 12 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
“Doch Sehnend Stehst/Am Ufer Du” (“But Longing You Stand on the Shore”)
Rousseau
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
“Doch Sehnend Stehst/Am Ufer Du” (“But Longing You Stand on the Shore”)
Page 14 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
“Doch Sehnend Stehst/Am Ufer Du” (“But Longing You Stand on the Shore”)
The plot of the fragment divides into roughly three parts. Strophes 1–4 describe
Rousseau’s alienation from and outsiderliness to his contemporaries and his
failure to win an audience for his writing. Strophes 2–8.2 describe a kind of
consolation available to Rousseau in having lived and produced something
anyway. Strophes 8.2–10 offer generalizations about the stance of anyone who
might be moved to flights of vision and composition.
Part I begins with a generalization that emphasizes the general fact of human
finitude, without specific reference to Rousseau. Rousseau then appears as the
second-person, past-tense addressee in line 2, where he is described as having
been, having seen, and having been astounded by things. But that time of vision
is past. The years pass by, as though their passing were the natural course of
things, without occasioning any particular pain. In the second strophe, however,
Rousseau is particularly marked as someone who stands out against his time, on
the shores of something different, an annoyance or scandal to his kin and a
shadow who is unable to love them. The third and fourth strophes then reinforce
and deepen this outsiderliness, as those to whom he has called do not appear, so
that Rousseau himself, metonymized as “lonely speech” (Einsame Rede), stands
alone, without being heard, without echo or reception, hence unreceived, like
the unburied, and given over to inconstancy, restlessness, and errancy, without
any allotted path to follow. Far from treating Rousseau as a successful and
confident prophet, the master thought in these (p.144) first four strophes is of
Rousseau in his reflective visionariness and hopes for more meaningful life as
inherently outside the common and barred from any terms of reception.
The main pivot of the poem then comes in the first line of strophe 5, as the
speaker offers Rousseau a kind of consolation or at least a command to be
satisfied anyway, inasmuch as the tree that outgrows its ground nonetheless
remains connected to it, casting its branches downward. So too might Rousseau,
mourning, remain in contact with the people who fail to receive him. And so too,
though he is unable successfully to grasp or understand it in order to master it,
might there remain a life or power in him that produces something, as the tree
produces its fruit unknowingly. One who accepts this consolation will then have
lived and written anyway and so stood within a movement of life that
nonetheless cannot be understood and mastered. Thus in writing Rousseau will
have written for those who are yet to come, even if this writing remains less the
purveying of a doctrine than a felt interpretation of the soul or life energy that
they are to actualize expressively in a new life of autonomy blended with love.
Rousseau himself then remains in the position of the one who is longing (“dem
Sehnenden”), not the one who confidently knows and guides.
Page 15 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
“Doch Sehnend Stehst/Am Ufer Du” (“But Longing You Stand on the Shore”)
Notes:
(1) . For an extended argument in support of this characterization of
romanticism, see Richard Eldridge, The Persistence of Romanticism (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2001), esp. 1–28, 102–23, and 229–45.
(2) . Friedrich Hölderlin, “Judgment and Being,” in Hölderlin, Essays and Letters
on Theory, trans. and ed. Thomas Pfau (Albany: State University of New York
Press, 1988), 37–38; emphasis added.
(3) . Ibid., 37, where “arche-separation” translates “Urtheilung”; HSW 4/1, 216.
(4) . Hölderlin, “Letter no. 121, To his Brother,” June 2, 1796, in HSW 4/1, 133.
Page 16 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
“Doch Sehnend Stehst/Am Ufer Du” (“But Longing You Stand on the Shore”)
(7) . Hölderlin, “Letter no. 121, To his Brother,” in Essays and Letters on Theory,
133.
(8) . Hölderlin, “Letter no. 219, To his Brother,” HSW 4/1, 419; my translation.
(9) . Hölderlin, “Letter no. 144, To Schiller,” HSW 4/1, 249; my translation.
(10) . Hölderlin, “Letter no. 128, To Hegel,” HSW 4/1, 222; my translation.
Page 17 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
“Doch Sehnend Stehst/Am Ufer Du” (“But Longing You Stand on the Shore”)
(21) . Friedrich Schiller, “Letter no. 28, To Hölderlin,” in HSW 7/1, 46; my
translation.
(22) . Hölderlin, “Letter no. 172, To his Brother,” in HSW 4/1, 306; my
translation.
(32) . This line, appearing in both the Song of the Tower Warden in Goethe’s
Faust and as the last line of Wedekind’s Pandora’s Box, is taken by Herbert
Marcuse as the formula, as it were, of successful art, art that achieves “the
reconciliation which...catharsis offers [that] also preserves the irreconcileable.”
Marcuse, The Aesthetic Dimension, trans. Herbert Marcuse and Erica Sherover
(Boston: Beacon Press, 1977), 59.
(33) . See Richard Unger’s summary of the earliest work in Hölderlin’s Major
Poetry: The Dialectics of Unity (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1975),
11–20.
(35) . Hölderlin, Hyperion: Die vorletzte Fassung, in HSW 3, 326; trans. Richard
Unger in Ibid., 22–23, 25, supplemented by my translation.
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
“Doch Sehnend Stehst/Am Ufer Du” (“But Longing You Stand on the Shore”)
Selected Poems (New York: Continuum, 2002), xi, and Scott J. Thompson,
“Friedrich Hölderlin: A Chronology of His Life,” http://www.wbenjamin.org/
hoelderlin_chron.html.
(40) . HSW 2/1, 12–13; Hölderlin, Odes and Elegies, trans. Nick Hoff
(Middletown, CT: Wesleyan University Press, 2008), 89, 91.
Page 19 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
On the Defense of Literary Value
Brady Bowman
DOI:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199976201.003.0009
Keywords: Beauty and truth, cognitive value of literature, Erklären versus Verstehen, German
idealism, German romanticism, literature and philosophy, literature and science, nonpropositional
cognition, philosophy of literature, value of the humanities
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
On the Defense of Literary Value
cultural and institutional fate of literature. Since the inception of literary studies
as an academic discipline in the nineteenth century, the maintenance of the
literary heritage in scholarly editions, the cultivation of literary sensibility in the
next generation of readers and writers, even the transmission of practical know-
how and the support of literary artists have increasingly been entrusted to our
university systems—despite some authors’ scorn for academia and the
“academic poetry” created there. As we know, these institutions are sensitive to
a variety of political, social, and economic pressures. In this context, the
humanities generally and literary studies in particular are vulnerable.
This child of German romanticism thus exists today both as a key institution in
the production and reception of literature and in a state of more or less
permanent crisis.5 That this should be so is partly the consequence of the
ambivalent fortunes of romanticism itself. Jena romanticism was a remarkably
unified movement in literature, philosophy, and—importantly—in the post-
Newtonian natural sciences of chemistry and electromagnetism that held out
prospects of bridging the gap between physics and organic life and even the life
of the mind.6 It sought to go beyond the mechanistic paradigm of scientific
explanation that rendered both the natural existence of freedom and the
phenomenon of life—the two most intimate components of human self-
understanding—virtually inexplicable, drawing a veil between our lived
experience and its ultimate grounding in the real. Romantic science and
philosophy of nature strove to establish a new paradigm of understanding that
could unify the basic forces of matter with the fact of organic life and the
Page 2 of 18
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
On the Defense of Literary Value
(p.149) Art in general and poetry in particular were thus accorded supreme
status in the romantic hierarchy of human cognition.8 Recall Schelling’s famous
remarks at the close of his System of Transcendental Idealism (1800):
For the philosopher... art is supreme, for it opens to him the holiest of
holies, where that which is separated in nature and history, and which can
never be united either in life and action or in thought, burns as though in a
single flame in eternal and primordial unity.... Just as in the childhood of
the sciences philosophy was born of poetry and nurtured by it, so too,
when these are brought to perfection, they will all flow back like diverse
rivers into the single ocean of poetry from which they first arose.
Page 3 of 18
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
On the Defense of Literary Value
Page 4 of 18
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
On the Defense of Literary Value
continual process of self-creation and destruction and the quasi dialectics of wit
and irony.”16
Page 5 of 18
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
On the Defense of Literary Value
John (p.152) Gibson have furthermore argued that nondiscursive forms are in
important ways more basic and hence prior to discursive thought (the priority
thesis).23 And Gibson further suggests that literary cognition is in fact the proper
fulfillment of discursive knowledge (the fulfillment thesis). In this section I will
argue, first, that the best defense of the complementarity thesis must be
mounted by way of the much stronger priority and fulfillment theses. My second
point is that the strong claims of priority and fulfillment put forward in recent
analytic philosophy of literature have an important source in Jena romanticism
and that renewed consideration of romantic thought can help in formulating a
contemporary philosophy of cultural value along the lines of the fulfillment
thesis.
Such a notion of complementarity between the aesthetic and the discursive can
help orient debates about the relation of literature and philosophy. As Manfred
Frank writes, an important function of literary art is to open what he calls a
“space of intelligibility...that must be there already in order that propositions can
take their place within it.”26 Hence, as he argues against Habermas, it would be
misguided to argue against the poststructuralist leveling of the distinction
between literature and philosophy by insisting on an unbridgeable gulf between
“world-disclosure” on the one hand and “truth-committed argumentation” on the
other.27
This same point has recently been pressed by philosophers in the analytic
tradition. In his 2007 book Fiction and the Weave of Life, John Gibson argues
that the activity of literature “enjoys a certain priority to the search for truth and
knowledge, at least, and perhaps only, in this respect: before we can query the
truth of a vision of our way in the world, we must first have the vision itself. That
is, what makes possible the search for truth is a prior cultural accomplishment:
the construction of varying ways of taking our world to be.”28
Page 6 of 18
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
On the Defense of Literary Value
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
On the Defense of Literary Value
available for expression and thus for acknowledgment is not a new (p.154) fact
or experience, but a conceptual space that we already inhabit yet without having
an explicit consciousness and mastery of the concepts proper to it.36 But if this is
right, then to assume that literature seeks to convey knowledge and that it is
such knowledge that is complementary to that of more overtly truth-seeking
disciplines, is to be confronted with the apparent cognitive triviality of
literature.37
Page 8 of 18
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
On the Defense of Literary Value
Second, I have insisted that this idea, too, is part of the romantic legacy, and
that we find it explicitly stated by romantic thinkers in a manner that is
thoroughly compatible with scientific realism. This strain of romantic thought
offers important resources for defending the value of literature and literary
studies in the context of the post-Humboldtian university. Early romanticism
brought modern literary scholarship to the academy and it still harbors powerful
arguments for why it should remain there.
Third, I have tried to show how the two different strains of romantic philosophy
of literature have shaped twentieth-century thought, and that the
complementarist strain in particular is re-emerging in some contemporary
analytic philosophy of literature. The sphere of cognition is not defined solely by
truth, nor is rational discourse confined to the propositionally “sayable”—this
insight is accessible from either side of the analytic-continental split; to explore
its ramifications is the privilege of neither.
Page 9 of 18
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
On the Defense of Literary Value
odes such as Dichtermut and Blödigkeit or the elegy Brot und Wein) go beyond
resignation and nostalgia; they evince a faith in the power of the literary
imagination to reveal, transfigure, and create an authentic second nature in
which the human can after all be at home. It is the same faith evinced in the
passage from Schelling quoted above, where he says that, in art, “that which is
separated in nature and history...burns as though in a single flame in eternal and
primordial unity.” The absence of such unity in our primary experience of nature
—and the alienation, skepticism, and nihilism that form our response to that
absence—do not tell against its reality. Rather, it is the imperative of culture to
create a second nature in which the human is at home in a more than human
world. And that, as the romantics teach us, is the work of poetry.
Notes:
(1) . It might be objected that in the case of ancient Greece, the status of
literature especially as embodied in Homer was authoritative, and that the case
of Greece may not be singular: So the value of literature would not always have
been in question. Indeed, in its strongest form, the “priority thesis” I will argue
for below states that art, science, and religion all originally spring from
literature (“poetry”) as their source. This again implies a state of affairs in which
the value of literature would not have been in question. We ought, however, to
distinguish between what we have come to call literature and the related
practices and institutions prior to the acceleration of cultural differentiation that
renders religion, art, science, and poetry into distinct realms of cultural
endeavor. Socratic philosophy represents a crucial moment in the history of this
process of differentiation in the West, and it is no coincidence that a
fundamental critique of the authority and value of poetry is its concomitant. I
acknowledge, however, that Plato’s accomplishments as a writer indicate that
his attitude toward literature must surely have been more complex than his
explicit critique of poetry would seem to allow.
Page 10 of 18
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
On the Defense of Literary Value
(4) . Insistence on the nonscientific character of literary studies does not entail
commitment to the dichotomy of “two cultures”—one scientific, one humanistic
—whose basic incompatibility is ensured by the psychological distinction of two
opposed modes of cognition, Erklären versus Verstehen.
(6) . For a recent discussion of romantic Naturphilosophie and its seminal role in
the early scientific investigation of electrochemistry and electromagnetism and
its influence on the work Ørsted and others, see Michael Friedman, “Kant—
Naturphilosophie—Electromagnetism,” in Hans Christian Ørsted and the
Romantic Legacy in Science: Ideas, Disciplines, Practices, ed. Robert Brian,
Robert Cohen, and Ole Knudsen (Dordrecht: Springer 2007), 135–58.
(7) . Schelling follows up on his promise in the dialogue Bruno oder über das
göttliche und natürliche Princip der Dinge (HKA 1/11) and in his 1802/3 lectures
on the philosophy of art (HKA 2/6) (thanks to Dalia Nassar for pointing this out).
Cf. Hölderlin’s letter no. 179 to his brother (June 4, 1799), in HSW 6, 329. On
the character of romantic science and its institutional framework in Jena see
Paul Ziche and Olaf Breidbach, eds., Naturwissenschaften um 1800.
Wissenschaftskultur in Jena-Weimar (Weimar: Hermann Böhlaus Nachfolger
2001); see also Ziche “Naturforschung in Jena zur Zeit Hegels. Materialien zum
Hintergrund der spekulativen Naturphilosophie,” Hegel-Studien 32 (1997): 9–40,
and Ziche, “Gehört das Ich zur Natur? Geistige und organische Natur in
Schellings Naturphilosophie,” Philosophisches Jahrbuch 108 (2001): 41–57.
Page 11 of 18
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
On the Defense of Literary Value
(8) . In this paper I do not distinguish systematically between the terms “poetry”
and “literature.” The romantics themselves preferred to speak of
“poetry” (Dichtung, Poesie) and would presumably have balked at identifying it
with the broader category of Literatur (or Litteratur, as it was then commonly
spelled) encompassing the totality of published writing. But “poetry” in
contemporary English is more narrowly and thus misleadingly associated with
verse than the romantics’ term Dichtung or Poesie, and in the present context
my use of “literature” to cover roughly the same range of phenomena seems
unlikely to cause confusion or prompt unwanted associations with other uses of
the term, e.g., as used when speaking of “the literature” on a given subject.
(9) . Unless otherwise indicated, here and in the following all translations from
German editions are my own. Schelling’s words obviously echo Schiller’s
philosophical ode, Die Künstler (1789), which makes similar claims for the prior
role of art and poetry in the generation of the sciences and for poetry’s role as
the culminating point of unity of completed science. See Schillers Werke.
Nationalausgabe (Weimar: Hermann Böhlaus Nachfolger, 1943ff.), vol. 1, 201–
14, especially the concluding strophe and its image of differentiation and
reintegration: “Wie sich in sieben milden Strahlen / Der weiße Schimmer lieblich
bricht, / Wie sieben Regenbogenstrahlen / Zerrinnen in das weiße Licht...so
fließt in einen Bund der Wahrheit / In einen Strom des Lichts zurück! [As into
seven gentle rays / the white luster gently breaks, / as seven rainbow beams
dissolve / returning into lustrous white..., so too shall you flow back into a single
bond of truth / a single stream of light].” These same lines are echoed by
Hölderlin in Hyperion, see HSW 3, 81.
(10) . Perhaps the decisive word in these debates has been spoken by Jaegwon
Kim, who contests the very coherence of nonreductive physicalism as an
explanatory project: see his Mind in a Physical World: An Essay on the Mind-
Body Problem and Mental Causation (Cambridge: MIT Press, 2000), esp. 89–121.
See also his earlier paper “Multiple Realization and the Metaphysics of
Reduction,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 52 (1992): 1–26,
reprinted in Kim, Supervenience and Mind: Selected Philosophical Essays (New
York: Cambridge University Press, 1993). The biological paradigm has come to
guide teleo-functional approaches in the philosophy of mind (see especially Ruth
Millikan, Language, Thought, and other Biological Categories [Cambridge, MA:
MIT Press, 1984] and Language: A Biological Model [Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 2005]), but the basic philosophical case for organic life being a necessary
condition of mindedness has not yet been convincingly made (pace John S.
Searle, The Rediscovery of the Mind [Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1992]).
(11) . Cf. Charles Larmore, The Romantic Legacy (New York: Columbia
University Press, 1996), 7–21, 84–97.
Page 12 of 18
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
On the Defense of Literary Value
(12) . The central concern of this paper thus converges with recent discussions
in epistemology about the value of knowledge, particularly with a position such
as the one taken by Jonathan Kvanvig, who argues that epistemic value does not
reside in truth per se (though truth remains a necessary condition of
knowledge), but in understanding; see The Value of Knowledge and the Pursuit
of Understanding (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003). I suggest that
in its most comprehensive form, such understanding is the work of literature.
Page 13 of 18
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
On the Defense of Literary Value
(17) . Cf. for example Novalis: “The perfected form of the sciences must be
poetic” (NS 2, 527, no. 17); “Every science becomes poetry [Poesie]—after
becoming philosophy” (NS 3, 396, no. 684; cf. the letter to A. W. Schlegel from
Dec. 12, 1794, NS 4, 252). We find similar dicta in the Athenaeum: “The highest
philosophy...would become poetry [Poesie] again” (KA 2, 216, no. 304). The
intimate proximity of literature and philosophy is manifest in the case of
Kierkegaard and Nietzsche. On Wittgenstein’s conception of the unity of
philosophy and poetry, see Manfred Frank, “Wittgensteins Gang in die
Dichtung,” in Wittgenstein. Literat und Philosoph (Pfullingen: Neske, 1989), esp.
60ff. Derrida’s texts Glas (1974) and The Post Card: From Socrates to Freud and
Beyond (1980) are the most sustained instances of his synthesis of literary and
philosophical language. The cases of Adorno and (late) Heidegger are complex.
On the one hand, both emphasize the specific difference and complementarity of
literature and philosophy (cf. Adorno, Ästhetische Theorie [Frankfurt am Main:
Suhrkamp, 1973], 191, 197, 392, 519; Heidegger, “Was heißt Denken?” in
Vorträge und Aufsätze, 132). On the other hand, both also explicitly break with
discursive forms of language and develop their thoughts in close dialogue with
works of poetry and art: as Heidegger says about his interpretation of Hölderlin:
“In thinking, it is almost as though one were participating in the creation of the
poem [Das Denken ist fast wie ein Mitdichten]” (“Hölderlins Hymne ‘Andenken,’”
in Martin Heidegger, Gesamtausgabe 2/52 [Frankfurt am Main: Klostermann,
1982], 55). Adorno describes the compositional idea according to which his
(unfinished) Aesthetic Theory was to be organized in terms close to those he
uses in his interpretation of Hölderlin; he contrasts it with the linearity of
argumentation from premises (cf. Ästhetische Theorie, 541); on the literary form
of Adorno’s philosophical writing see Gerhard Richter, “Aesthetic Theory and
Nonpropositional Content in Adorno,” New German Critique 97 (Winter 2006):
119–35; for a comparison of Adorno and Wittgenstein, also see Gottfried Gabriel,
Zwischen Logik und Literatur. Erkenntnisformen von Dichtung, Philosophie und
Wissenschaft (Stuttgart: Metzler, 1991), esp. 47ff.
Page 14 of 18
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
On the Defense of Literary Value
(20) . Though they start from diverse standpoints, both Manfred Frank (Stil in
der Philosophie [Stuttgart: Reclam, 1992]) and Gottfried Gabriel (“Literarische
Form und nicht-Propositionale Erkenntnis in der Philosophie,” in Gottfried
Gabriel and Christiane Schildknecht, Literarische Formen der Philosophie
[Stuttgart: Metzler, 1990], 1–25) arrive at similar conclusions regarding the
complementary relation between philosophy and literature.
(22) . Cf. Frank, Stil in der Philosophie and Gabriel, Zwischen Logik und
Literatur.
(24) . On Hölderlin see especially Helmut Hühn, “Bilder des Lebendigen. Zur
Erkenntnisfunktion der dichterischen ‘Mythe’ im Werk Hölderlins,” in Bowman,
Darstellung und Erkenntnis, 117–133. See also Dieter Henrich, Der Grund im
Bewußtsein. Untersuchungen zu Hölderlins Denken (Stuttgart: Klett-Cotta,
1992). Schelling, Hölderlin, and Hegel have each variously been claimed as the
true author of the fragment that has come to be known as “the oldest system
program of German idealism.” The only undisputed fact is that it is in Hegel’s
handwriting. The fragment itself and a number of influential articles on its
authorship and significance are to be found in Christoph Jamme and Hans
Schneider, eds., Mythologie der Vernunft. Hegels ältestes Systemprogramm des
deutschen Idealismus (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1988). For a critical
discussion of the scholarship on the fragment see Frank-Peter Hansen, Das
älteste Systemprogramm des deutschen Idealismus. Rezeptionsgeschichte und
Interpretation (Berlin: de Gruyter, 1989). For a more recent overview with
further bibliographical references see Walter Jaeschke, Hegel-Handbuch
(Stuttgart: Metzler, 2003), 76–80.
(25) . This conception of art and poetry as bearing essentially upon the same
objects and concerns as science (and philosophy) is a constant in early romantic
thought that is still discernible in Hegel’s later lectures on aesthetics. Adorno’s
thesis that art both supersedes the “logic of identity” and demands philosophical
interpretation in the discursive medium constituted by that very logic is an
equally obvious scion of romanticism (cf. Aesthetische Theorie, 193ff.).
Page 15 of 18
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
On the Defense of Literary Value
(28) . Fiction and the Weave of Life, 144. See also the essays in John Gibson,
Wolfgang Huemer, and Luca Pocci, eds., A Sense of the World: Essays on Fiction,
Narrative, and Knowledge (New York: Routledge, 2007).
(29) . Cf. Gibson, Fiction and the Weave of Life, chapters 2.2 and 3.3.
(31) . Cavell’s engagement with the romantic tradition is of course most obvious
in the book In Quest of the Ordinary: Lines of Skepticism and Romanticism
(Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1988), but it is present in his other work
as well. The legacy of romanticism is also present indirectly by way of Cavell’s
formative engagement with Wittgenstein. For a recent discussion see Simon
Critchley, “Cavell’s Romanticism and Cavell’s ‘Romanticism.’” See also Keren
Gorodeisky’s contribution to this volume, chapter 9 below.
(32) . See (among other texts) Stanley Cavell, “Knowing and Acknowledging,” in
Must We Mean What We Say? (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2002),
238–66.
(35) . Cora Diamond, “Losing Your Concepts,” Ethics 98, no. 2 (1988): 255–77,
here: 263.
(36) . Tyler Burge has suggested that Frege makes room for a distinction
between the sense of an expression and a subject’s conscious grasp of that sense
(“Frege on Sense and Linguistic Meaning,” in Truth, Thought, Reason: Essays on
Page 16 of 18
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
On the Defense of Literary Value
Frege [New York: Oxford University Press, 2005], 242–69, esp. 252–57): the full
and precise sense of an expression may transcend the subject’s actual, conscious
grasp of that sense in any number of ways, even though the sense contributes to
the structure and individuality of the subject’s mind. So even the most
competent speakers of a language, those who grasp the linguistic meaning of the
expressions in their language most thoroughly, may fail to understand the
deeper rationale that underlies their deployment of a concept. I have something
similar in mind here, although in the present context I would like to de-
emphasize the more austerely rationalist and Platonist elements of the Frege-
Burge conception and emphasize rather the notion of historically emergent
conceptual spaces that shape how we think and speak without wholly coinciding
with the actual thought and speech of individuals. (A detailed attempt to extend
Burge’s account beyond formal sciences such as logic and mathematics has been
undertaken by James Higginbotham, “Conceptual Competence,” Philosophical
Issues 9 [1998]: 149–62.) Although Burge himself plausibly charges ordinary
language philosophy with blindness toward the relevant distinction in Frege
(“Frege on Sense and Linguistic Meaning,” 269), it seems to me that Cavell’s
richer understanding of ordinary language philosophy gets some purchase on
the same territory that Burge is interested in. In asking “what we should say
when,” we are not merely clarifying— on dubious authority— linguistic meaning,
but a structure of reality itself that cuts across the fact-value distinction: cf.
Cavell, “Must We Mean What We Say?” in Must We Mean What We Say? Updated
Edition [Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002], 1–43, esp. 18–22; cf.
Burge, “Frege on Sense and Linguistic Meaning,” 258, 261). The upshot is that
we can and in fact often do inhabit a conceptual space that is constitutive of our
actual thoughts without our for that reason necessarily counting as possessing a
mastery of the relevant concepts.
(39) . Truth, then (pace Keats), is not beauty, but neither is it more than beauty
in the emphatic sense I’m using the term here. As Kant was the first to
recognize, beauty is the immediate experience of that space of intelligibility in
Page 17 of 18
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
On the Defense of Literary Value
which science arises and which it strives—infinitely—to fill out with a system of
truths.
(41) . On the infinity of the scientific task and the impossibility of individual
human satisfaction that implies, see Max Weber, “Science as a Vocation,” in The
Vocation Lectures (Indianapolis: Hackett, 2004), 1–31.
(43) . Arthur Schopenhauer, Die Welt als Wille und Vorstellung, in Werke in fünf
Bänden, ed. Ludger Lütkehaus (Zurich: Haffmans, 2006), vol. 1, 252.
(44) . For a convincing discussion of this point see Gibson, Fiction and the Weave
of Life, 147–57.
(45) . Cf. for example An die Natur (1795), in Friedrich Hölderlin, HSW 1, 198–
200.
Page 18 of 18
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
“No Poetry, No Reality”
Keren Gorodeisky
DOI:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199976201.003.0010
9.1. Introduction
Friedrich Schlegel’s remarks about poetry and reality are notoriously baffling:
Page 1 of 26
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
“No Poetry, No Reality”
No poetry, no reality.... There is, despite all the senses, no external world
without imagination... all things disclose themselves to the magic wand of
feeling alone.1
What should one say about these observations? Perhaps that they are outlandish
and eccentric? “Who in his right mind would argue publicly that (p.164) reality
rests on poetry, on a mere fiction? The speaker must be a madman, one who has
lost all sense for the difference between what is real and what is merely a
figment of the imagination.” Or one might say that, rather than philosophical
observations, Schlegel’s remarks are merely “poetically exaggerated”
reflections.5
Yet another person might claim that these observations manifest a lack of
mastery of our language. “The concept “poetry” and the concept “reality,” this
respondent may say, “have precise semantics, and very clear criteria of
application. Schlegel has clearly not mastered those concepts.”
I take all these responses to be mistaken. Schlegel’s remarks about poetry and
reality are not merely outlandish or eccentric, but deeply revealing about a
prevalent confusion in theoretical approaches to the distinction between fiction
and reality.6 Rather than mere poetic exaggerations, I believe that Schlegel’s
pronouncements are philosophical observations that respond to a genuine
confusion, a confusion that led him to express, time and again, what initially
looks like eccentric views about poetry and reality.7 The confusion at stake is
expressed by the last envisioned response to his remarks. The response of the
so-called semanticist presupposes mistakenly that the distinction between
“fiction” and “reality” is fixed “once and for all” by a criterion, which is
determined prior to any application of those concepts. Our imagined semanticist,
and, I think, some contemporary philosophers of art, assume that the distinction
between fiction and reality is and must be fixed independently of the ordinary
practices of using the terms “fiction” and “reality” to mean something in specific
situations.
I argue that we should understand Schlegel’s knotty remarks about poetry and
reality as addressing this assumption. I propose that we think of them as
forming a kind of “transcendental criticism,” to borrow Kant’s label for his
diagnosis of, and challenge to, what he takes to be a “natural and inevitable
Page 2 of 26
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
“No Poetry, No Reality”
illusion” of the human mind.8 Since the assumption I just mentioned shapes a
line of thought in contemporary aesthetics, Schlegel’s concern with this illusion
is as relevant today as it was in his day.
We can begin to see the depth of Schlegel’s concern by first tracing some
affinities between his thought and Ludwig Wittgenstein’s later philosophy. This
should not be too surprising. The surface similarities between Wittgenstein’s
remarks in Philosophical Investigations and in the aphorisms collected in Culture
and Value, and the pronouncements in Schlegel’s writings are nothing short of
remarkable. Here is a very limited sample:
The main thing [in philosophy] is to know something and to say it. The
attempt to prove or even to explain it is quite superfluous in most cases....
There is doubtless more difficulty in stating something than in explaining
it.12
Whoever knows this cannot be reminded often enough that he knows it. All
of the highest truths of every kind are altogether trivial; and for this very
reason nothing is more necessary than to express them ever anew... so that
it will not be forgotten that they are still there.15
4. One might also give the name “philosophy” to what is possible before all
new discoveries and inventions. /// If one tried to advance theses in
philosophy, it would never be possible to debate them, because everyone
would agree to them.16
To those who knew it already, philosophy of course brings nothing new; but
only through it does it become knowledge and thereby assume a new
form.17
Page 3 of 26
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
“No Poetry, No Reality”
The task of this paper is to advance what Cavell has only started on this front,
with the aim of shedding light on Schlegel’s response to skepticism and to
traditional philosophy, on his concept “wit,” and, above all, on the way we
should, following him, approach a family of concepts—“poetry” or “fiction,”
“reality,” and “feeling.” For that purpose, section 2 explores the affinities
between the Schlegelian spirit and the Wittgensteinian spirit, and section 3
explains how these commonalities, when applied to a confusion about poetry and
reality, shed light on the remarks that open the paper.
Page 4 of 26
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
“No Poetry, No Reality”
allow her interlocutor to see the particular aspects that make it powerful in the
way that they do. The critic must enable her interlocutor to stand to the work in
a relation that allows her to see in it what the critic sees in it, and to feel for it
what the critic feels for it.
Wittgenstein suggests that this aim requires that we align the work we love with
other works that are similar to it, and dissimilar from it in revealing ways: works
by the same artist, works belonging to the same genre, or to the same historical
period.27 Schlegel seems to agree. We should not expect philosophy, he argues,
to give us an absolute, a priori definition of art, but we can, and perhaps should
expect it to help us “order the given artistic experiences and the existing artistic
principles...and raise the appreciation of art, extend it with the help of a
thoroughly learned history of art.”28 Nor can we answer “the simplest and most
immediate questions...without the deepest consideration and (p.167) the most
erudite history of art.”29 You understand “Sapphic poems” only when you
compare them with Petrarch’s and with Horatian poems.30 And the comparison
of different works, particularly a historical comparison, is, for Schlegel, the
essence of criticism.31
It is all too tempting to misinterpret Wittgenstein on this point. One might think
that he pursues philosophy by comparing different ways we use words because
he believes that “meaning is use,” a slogan often associated with PI §43. This
may well be true, depending on how we read §43. I read this passage as
suggesting neither that understanding the meaning of a word or a sentence
requires a pragmatic analysis over and above a semantics and syntax,34 nor that
the meaning of a word is determined simply by a certain context.35 Rather,
according to Wittgenstein, we cannot understand the meaning of a word or a
sentence in isolation from the particular way(s) the word or the sentence can be
used to mean something specific on a particular occasion. In order to grasp the
meaning of a word we need to remind ourselves, to imagine or observe, how it
can be used by someone to mean something specific.
What motivates Wittgenstein to align meaning and use in this way is not a wish
to guide our understanding, but a concern about a prevalent confusion about
meaning, which Cavell calls “an illusion of meaning.” A person is under this
illusion when he “imagines himself to be saying something when he is not, to
have discovered something, when he has not.”36 What happens when a person
Page 5 of 26
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
“No Poetry, No Reality”
Usually, when a person is under this illusion she fails to use the words in a way
that grants them their necessary connections to some other words and human
practices. I might speak outside of a language-game if, for instance, I say, “Only I
know my feelings” in a way that is detached from any specific situation in which
it can make sense (independently, for example, of any anger I might feel toward
someone, perhaps my therapist, or my mother, for ascribing to me certain
feelings that I either don’t believe I have, or am not willing or capable of
ascribing to myself). I use this sentence outside of a language-game if, detached
from any such practice in which it naturally makes sense, I use it to mean (I
imagine that it means) that the feelings of another are accessible to no one other
than the feeling person.
Page 6 of 26
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
“No Poetry, No Reality”
rule that shows the necessary, systematic, and fixed nature of language and
meaning. “The confusions which occupy us arise when language is like an
engine idling, not when it is doing work.”42 This kind of confusion can be
resolved only by reminding the speakers who use language indolently how
language actually works, how it must work if it is to do any work.43
Such a work of reminders has to be of a special kind because of the great “urge
to misunderstand,” because of the tendency to be bewitched by the workings of
our language, and because “the aspects of things that are most important for
us,” particularly, those that allow words to mean, “are hidden because of their
simplicity and familiarity....The real foundations of his enquiry do not strike man
at all. Unless that fact has at some time struck him.—And this means: we fail to
be struck by what, once seen, is most striking and most powerful.”44
You may think that Schlegel can in no way be viewed as responding to the
skeptic, either in a “Wittgensteinian” or in any other way. And you might think
so because you believe that Schlegel himself is a skeptic. Schlegel undoubtedly
doubts the possibility of absolute foundations48—in a spirit similar to
Wittgenstein’s doubt about the existence of an absolute, fixed system of rules as
the foundation of language. And he questions the possibility of an absolute
comprehension of the world—just as Wittgenstein believes that explanations
“come to an end.”49
I wanted to point out that words often understand themselves better than
do those who use them, wanted to draw attention to the fact that there
must be secret societies among philosophical words, words that, like a host
Page 7 of 26
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
“No Poetry, No Reality”
of spirits sprung forth too early, confuse everything, and exert invisible
force of the world spirit even on those who do not wish to acknowledge
them.... I had to think in terms of a popular medium, in order to bond
chemically this holy, delicate, fleeting, airy, fragrant, and as it were
imponderable thought. Otherwise, how severely might this thought have
been misunderstood, since it is only through its well-understood use an end
could be put to all the understandable misunderstanding?52
That Schlegel is not a skeptic, but a subtle critic of skepticism who challenges it
by employing some of Wittgenstein’s later terms of criticism is supported by his
following observations: “Eclecticism and Skepticism lead to Mysticism, the abyss
into which everything sinks.”53 But abyssal as skepticism may be, no (p.170)
counterargument can silence it. Properly responding to the skeptic requires that
we allow her to see the incoherence internal to her own position:
Page 8 of 26
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
“No Poetry, No Reality”
suspicious and critical of this use (or misuse) of philosophical language, he also
reminds us that we can do philosophy in a different spirit, positively, not only
negatively by pointing to philosophy’s limitations: “Wouldn’t it be worthwhile
trying now to introduce the concept of the positive into philosophy as well?”59
Both Schlegel and Wittgenstein suggest that the “urge to misunderstand,” and
misuse words is neither rare, nor exclusive to the skeptic. A skeptical voice, “the
skeptic in oneself,”62 inheres in all of us. We are all prone to certain confusions
and illusions that affect our use of words. The “voice of temptation” is as much a
part of each self as the “voice of correction.”63
Page 9 of 26
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
“No Poetry, No Reality”
distinguish between different kinds of writers, for example, between the analytic
writer and the synthetic writer.65 To understand suicide, we need to remind
ourselves in what circumstances we call it an action, and in what circumstances
we call it an accident, and what we must mean when we say that it is wrong.66
Reminding ourselves of the distinction between folly and madness has both
philosophical and political consequences.67 And to understand the novel, the
best we can do is to compare Shakespeare with Boccaccio, the two of them with
Cervantes, and all of them with a detailed reading of Goethe. Above all, in a
Wittgensteinian spirit, (p.172) Schlegel claims that philosophy can teach us
nothing new. And yet only through philosophy do we come to know, to be
reminded of and become familiar with, what it teaches us—what we have always
already “known.”68
Schlegel takes up this “work of reminders” also, I believe, by reviving the power
of wit, a power that he regards as profoundly philosophical: “Even philosophy
has blossoms. That is, its thoughts; but one can never decide if one should call
them witty or beautiful.”69 Wit does not have the special power of reminding us
of what we are already familiar with but for the most part fail to notice simply
because, as a matter of fact, it is a figure of speech that is used in ordinary
conversation. Wit’s special force lies in its characteristic way of behaving. For it
is wit that, through humor and surprise, often startles us, challenges what we
take for granted, and, by so doing, allows us to look at our life and words from a
fresh perspective, and thus to see, as if for the first time, what we are already
familiar with.70 The meaning of “a witty idea which is enigmatic to the point of
needing to be solved should be immediately and completely clear as soon as it’s
been hit upon.”71 Once achieving complete clarity, Schlegelian wit dissolves
(rather than directly solves) the problem it was meant to address. For like
philosophy, wit “brings us nothing new”—it only puts us in touch with what we
are already familiar with by showing it in a new light. Through the surprising
power of wit, the ordinary becomes for the first time an object of awareness and
knowledge.72 And so, “imagination and wit are everything to you!”73
Page 10 of 26
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
“No Poetry, No Reality”
Different as these two distinctions are, Schlegel’s remarks suggest that the
prevalent theoretical approaches to both of these distinctions are based on a
shared confused picture: Schlegel points to a tendency, manifest primarily in
philosophy and literary criticism, to think that poetry and reality, as well as our
feelings for the former and our feelings for the latter, are distinguished once and
for all by a fixed criterion, which is determined independently of our life with
these terms.
I take this prevalent approach to the distinction between the real and the
fictional to be structurally analogous (but by no means identical) to the skeptic’s
approach that I described above. And for that reason, I regard both of them as
calling for a similar response. This is what I mean: The skeptical doubt about the
existence of the external world, on the one hand, and the confusion about reality
and fiction, on the other, are not similar in content. I do not claim that the latter
raises a question about our epistemic capacity to tell reality from fiction, or that
it challenges our capacity to ever know that what we experience is real rather
than fictional. Nor do I claim that the philosophers whose views are shaped by
this confusion are searching, like the external world skeptic, for some
experiential “marks and features”79 to distinguish reality from fiction. But the
assumption that governs their confusion is analogous to the one that governs the
skeptical confusion, and the source of the two is a misunderstanding about
meaning.
The confusion at stake in this paper is guided by the mistaken belief that every
judgment in which we apply certain concepts is essentially underdetermined if
the judgment is not grounded in a stable determination of these concepts prior
to their applications. In short, this picture is based on a misunderstanding of the
way language works. One might be prone to this confusion because of an
inclination to think that language is based on an absolute foundation. But
Schlegel suggests that viewing language in this manner expresses “a fad for the
Page 11 of 26
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
“No Poetry, No Reality”
absolute [die Liebhaberei fürs Absolute],” from which we must find “a way
out,”80 just as we must overcome the urge to ground philosophy in absolute
foundations.81 Because this approach to fiction and reality is grounded in a
misunderstanding of the meanings of words, and their necessary relation to
ordinary language, the proper response to it is not a refutation, but the response
that I take Schlegel to offer—a response that allows his interlocutor to recognize
for herself how words acquire their meanings when we use them ordinarily.
(p.174) It seems that Schlegel found a variant of this attitude towards poetry
and reality to be the picture that he himself, the early Schlegel, had been captive
by a few years before he wrote the statements that open this chapter. The
remarks about poetry and reality, from his so-called mid to late period, starting
approximately in 1797,82 may be designed to challenge the picture that had
shaped the early Schlegel’s faith in the absolute distinction between reality and
poetry. They challenge, particularly, his early belief that, in its perfected mode
(exhibited in the works of antiquity), poetry is “an utterly peculiar activity of the
human mind; it is distinguished from every other activity by eternal boundaries
[because it is the expression of] an eternal human objective...that is only
indirectly connected to man.”83 Schlegel uses the remarks quoted at the opening
of this chapter in part to take issue with the faith in the possibility of an
objective science that could irrevocably distinguish the “real”—the everyday life
of ordinary men and women who live in actual, empirical surroundings—from
the absolutely objective, pure, and self-sufficient realm of poetry and art, the
embodiment of the “ideal.” Proclaiming that without poetry there is no reality,
that the distinction between reality and appearance is not poetical, and that “life
and society should become poetic”84 may be a way of raising a question about
the assumption that “there [is] more than one world”85—the real world and the
world presented by the art of fiction—a self-sufficient, “isolated,” ideal world,
which is only “indirectly [mittelbar] related to man.”
Perhaps surprisingly, the picture of poetry and reality that I take Schlegel’s
remarks to address does not shape only his early view, but also a contemporary
debate in aesthetics: the debate about whether the emotions we feel for fictions
are real and rational. Before I introduce this debate, two qualifications are in
order. First, I do not claim that Schlegel had in mind this contemporary debate
in aesthetics. And yet, I suspect, both that he was responding to a related
illusory picture, the one that shaped his early thought, and that his reflections
on poetry and reality include resources for clearing away the confusion in the
contemporary literature about fiction. Due to limitations of space, in this paper I
merely gesture towards the way in which these resources can address the
contemporary discussion. Second, I do not argue that the parties to this debate
presuppose, like the early Schlegel, that “poetry” and “reality” (in their terms,
“fiction” and “reality”) are two distinct “domains” or “worlds.” But I do think
that a central line in this debate presupposes that our emotional responses to
fiction and our emotional responses to “real” situations and individuals are
Page 12 of 26
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
“No Poetry, No Reality”
How does this confusion enter into the contemporary literature? In taking for
granted that an emotion can be “real” only if it involves a belief in the existence
of its object,86 some parties to this debate assume that what is “real” and what is
“fictional” (what is merely part of a game of make-believe, to use the terms that
Kendall Walton contributed to this debate) is already determined, independently
of what we actually do and say when we are engaged with “real” people, and
with fictions, and the criteria we use when engaged in such ways.87 For
example, Walton holds that we do not “really” feel, say, pity and pain for Anna
Karenina, but feel them only as part of a “make-believe” game because “real”
emotions always require a belief in the existence of the objects of those
emotions.88 Walton thus assumes that the distinction between “real” and
“fictional” emotions is set independently of any language-game.89
Why is it not to be taken for granted? For one, poetry and reality do not seem to
be distinguished in the same way that ordinary objects, like tables, trees, or
birds, are distinguished. If someone says, “This is a goldfinch,” it is reasonable
in certain circumstances to ask him how he knows that it is a goldfinch and not a
goldcrest. If such a doubt arises, the speaker, if he knows what he is talking
about, can easily pacify the doubt. “I know that it is a goldfinch because, though
goldfinches and goldcrests both have a red head, there are no goldcrests in
those areas,” or “Goldcrests have pinkish-red head, but goldfinches have wine-
red heads.” No matter how “alike” goldfinches and goldcrests are, there are
clear “marks and features” that distinguish the one from the other, marks and
features that we can come to know if we receive the right kind of training, and if
we are situated properly. It is questionable whether there are similar marks and
features to distinguish the fictional from the real, if any doubt arises. What can I
possibly answer Betsy, my neighbor, if she asks me how I know that the
Page 13 of 26
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
“No Poetry, No Reality”
neighborhood we live in is real, rather than the setting of a novel? For her to ask
that question would bespeak a misunderstanding of the nature of the distinction.
By making these and other remarks, Schlegel suggests that whether what we do,
undergo, or encounter is real or fictional can be determined only in light of our
language-games with fiction—only in light of what we ordinarily do or don’t do
when we are engaged with fictions, for those language-games alone embody the
criteria of what can and cannot count as either fiction or reality. Schlegel
proposes that any effort to use the terms “real” and “fictional”95 as if their
meaning is determined in isolation from the particular practices in which
specific speakers use them could only result in our failing to mean what we say.
Just as the activity of modern poetry lacks “a firm basis,”96 but depends instead
on the activity of each individual poet, so too what counts as “poetry” and what
counts as “reality” lacks a “firm basis,” but depends instead on particular uses of
the terms.
But this does not imply that the meaning of our concepts is arbitrary, subjectivist
or even merely conventional. Schlegel claims that even though modern poetry
has no “firm basis” other than the creative talent of individual poets, it is not
merely arbitrary, or “idealist”—it is not the expression only of the ideals, or the
mind, of the particular poets who create it, as contrasted with reality. Rather,
modern poetry does not only facilitate genuine realism, a true expression of the
reality in which modern poets live, but it also constitutes “the harmony of the
ideal and the real.”97 Similarly, even though meaning is not determined once and
for all, independently of what we mean when we use words in particular
situations, it is not arbitrary, subjectivist, or conventional. Cavell writes, “I am
trying to bring out...that any form of life and every concept integral to it has an
indefinite number of instances and directions of projection; and that this
variation is not arbitrary. Both the ‘outer’ variance and the ‘inner’ constancy are
Page 14 of 26
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
“No Poetry, No Reality”
Notice that Schlegel’s remarks about poetry and reality are not to be read as a
refutation of the philosopher who is subject to the confused picture about fiction
and reality that I am attempting to flesh out in this section. Instead, he invites
his interlocutor to share his own world, a world that is made perspicuous, is
animated and maintained by the fictional works we are engaged with as much as
it is animated and maintained by the “real” people we interact with.99 And he
invites the interlocutor (and us, his readers) to do so by reminding us that seeing
how the words “poetry,” “reality,” and “feeling” acquire their meaning, and
recognize the criteria for applying them in different situations only requires that
we observe the ordinary practices of reading and appreciating, of meeting
friends to engage in a “lively discussion about a new play”100 and so on.
Schlegel writes, “The first principle in love is to have a sense for one another,
and the highest principle, faith in each other.”102 Rather than a belief in the
existence of the beloved—the requirement of real feelings for anything according
to the contemporary aestheticians I mentioned above—the requirement for real
love is a sense for, and faith in the other. That is what we seem to demand of real
Page 15 of 26
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
“No Poetry, No Reality”
love, and perhaps other emotions, at least in many circumstances. The sorrow I
feel for Anna, then, might not be real if, for example, I think that she (p.178)
deserves her dismal end, or if I think that she brought it on herself. My sorrow is
not real, in other words, if I have no faith in her decisions and actions. This
means that there are criteria for distinguishing “real” emotions from “unreal”
ones (where the latter refers to faked or insincere emotions). But these criteria
are part of the ordinary grammar of the concepts of these emotions, part of the
life surrounding our emotional lives. They are not determined independently of
the ways in which we usually respond to, behave around, and talk about our
emotional lives, and they suggest that our emotions for fictions often count as
real. Assuming that whether our emotions for fictions are “real” depends solely
on whether they involve a belief in the existence of their objects ignores the
variety of criteria that we ordinarily use to determine whether an emotion is
real. Indeed, sometimes we must conclude that an appearance of emotion is not
real, but only a mere appearance, because it does not involve such a belief. But
Walton’s assumption ignores the fact that, for the most part, whether or not a
seeming emotion is real, apparent, or only a part of a make-believe game does
not depend on the existence of such a belief, but on a host of other criteria.103
When the declaration “no poetry, nor reality” opens a remark about the
necessity of feeling for properly responding to actual individual human beings
and to the world as such, it cannot mean that there is no difference between
poetry and reality.104 Instead of reading this passage as obliterating the
distinction, or as suggesting that there is no way out of poetic and linguistic
constructions, it would be more natural to read it as proposing that we learn
how to properly respond to our fellow human beings (and to the “external world”
of which we are a part), when we become attuned to poetry, and, at the same
time, we learn how to properly respond to poetry, when we learn how to be
responsive to our fellow human beings, and to the world as such. “Whoever
conceives of poetry or philosophy as individuals has a feeling for them.”105
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
“No Poetry, No Reality”
words, but also our investments in the practices to which our words belong, and
the different concerns, cares, and commitments embodied in our ordinary use of
them. As J. L. Austin puts it, “Our common stock of words embodies all the
distinctions men have found worth drawing, and the connections they have
found worth making.”107 Rather than wishing to obliterate the distinction
between poetry and reality, or to suggest that “art...does not need to point
beyond itself,”108 when making the remarks that open the paper, and many
others that relate to them, Schlegel meant to remind us of how intimate we are
with the fictions we read (and hear, and behold, and experience) on an everyday
basis, and to invite us to feel this intimacy for ourselves.
Notes:
(1) . Athenaeum Fragments in KA 2, 227, no. 350.
(5) . This is a paraphrase of the epithet that Rudolph Haym ascribed to Novalis,
when he called him a “poetically exaggerated Fichte.” See, Die romantische
Schule (Berlin: Gaertner, 1882), 332.
(6) . Schlegel, of course, speaks about “poetry” and “reality,” never about
“fiction” and “reality.” However, I think that in those specific remarks about
poetry and reality, he uses “poetry” to refer to what we today call “fictional”—
that which is constructed by the creative imagination; that which belongs to,
occurs in, or is a feature of a work of fiction. Therefore, I take it to be legitimate
to regard those remarks as concerning a confusion in the way we think about the
distinction between what we today would call, not “reality” and “poetry,” but
“reality” and “fiction.” Accordingly, when I speak of this confusion in sections 1
and 3, I will interchangeably speak about it as a confusion about “reality,” and
“poetry” and as a confusion about “reality” and “fiction.”
Page 17 of 26
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
“No Poetry, No Reality”
(20) . Richard Eldridge’s work is a valuable exception to this rule. In his different
writings, Eldridge pursues and develops the romantic legacy in Wittgenstein’s
thought. However, Eldridge focuses on Hölderlin and Wordsworth. See mainly,
Leading a Human Life: Wittgenstein, Intentionality, and Romanticism (Chicago:
Page 18 of 26
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
“No Poetry, No Reality”
(21) . By no means do I want to claim that Schlegel was motivated by the same
kind of considerations that motivated the late Wittgenstein, or that they
understood traditional philosophy in exactly the same way. Nor do I claim that
Schlegel anticipated Wittgenstein. I argue only that reading Schlegel with
Wittgenstein in mind, as approaching certain philosophical tendencies in a
similar spirit, can help to explain much that is obscure in Schlegel’s writings.
(24) . G. E. Moore, Philosophical Papers (London: Allen and Unwin; New York:
Macmillan, 1959), 315.
(25) . E.g., “The critics are always talking about rules, but where are the rules
that are really poetic and applicable for all works of art and not merely
grammatical, metrical, logical?” (Schlegel, Fragments on Literature and Poetry,
KA 16, 108, no. 286).
(26) . Cf. The aim of interpreting a rule and of understanding the meaning of a
word is, according to Wittgenstein, “not an agreement in opinions but in form of
life” (PI, §241).
(27) . Cf. Stanley Cavell, “Austin at Criticism,” in Must We Mean What We Say,
104.
(31) . Schlegel speaks here about a comparison of works that could “reconstruct
[a work’s] course and its structure [as well as] its inner history” (“The Essence
of Criticism,” in Lessing’s Thoughts and Opinions, KA 3, 60).
Page 19 of 26
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
“No Poetry, No Reality”
(37) . Ibid. See mainly in the Claim of Reason, Part I, chap. 8, 191–243.
(39) . It is part, you may also say, of her confusion about the way language
works.
(40) . This is equally true of the success of her traditional opponent, the
antiskeptic, or as Cavell calls him following Kant, the dogmatist. See, Cavell,
Claim of Reason, 46, and Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, A viii.
(43) . “[Philosophical problems] are solved, rather, by looking into the workings
of our language...in such a way as to make us recognize those workings; in
despite of an urge to misunderstand them....Philosophy is a battle against the
bewitchment of our intelligence by means of our language” (PI, §109).
(45) . Another way (or perhaps the same way, or at least a way that is
structurally akin to the first) is to read literature, fiction, to engage with the
practice that has long been associated with the capacity to defamiliarize the
familiar.
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
“No Poetry, No Reality”
a response that elicits the kind of criteria that are supposed to establish the
existence of objects, or the knowledge of other minds with certainty. Rather,
Wittgenstein’s appeal to the ordinary is meant as an invitation, a summons,
addressed to the interlocutor, to share with him the ordinary world we all
inhabit.
(48) . See mainly, Concerning the Theory of Scientific Knowledge, KA 16, 3–14,
nos. 1–125; The Spirit of the Science of Knowledge (1797–98), KA 13, 31–39, nos.
126–227; and Beilage I and Beilage II, KA 18, 505–16, 517–21. For detailed
discussions of Schlegel’s criticism of absolute foundations, see Manfred Frank,
Unendliche Annäherung. Die Anfänge der philosophischen Frühromantik
(Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1997), Beiser, The Romantic Imperative, and
Beiser, German Idealism: The Struggle against Subjectivism, 1781–1801
(Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2002).
(49) . PI §1. In addition to questioning the role of general rules and principles in
art criticism, Schlegel writes, “Principles are to life what instructions written by
the cabinet are for the general in battle” (Athenaeum Fragments, KA 2, 178, no.
85). And he famously claims, in a fragment that echoes one of Wittgenstein later
remarks, “it is equally fatal for the mind to have a system and not to have one. It
must therefore have to decide to unite the two” (Athenaeum Fragments, KA 2,
173, no. 53). Cf. “Above all, someone attempting the description lacks any
system. The systems that occur to him are inadequate, and he seems suddenly to
himself in a wilderness instead of the well laid out garden that he knew so
well” (Wittgenstein, Remarks on the Philosophy of Psychology, ed. G. E. M.
Anscombe and G. H. von Wright [Oxford: Blackwell, 1980], vol. 1, §557).
(56) . Philosophical Fragments, KA 18, 5, no. 15. Notice too that Schlegel, like
Cavell, does not regard skepticism as opposed to dogmatism. Skepticism and
dogmatism are two sides of the same coin—two philosophical moods that are
grounded in the same confused picture: “As opposed to criticism, the three
Page 21 of 26
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
“No Poetry, No Reality”
positions may be called dogmatism” (KA 18, 5, no. 10; cf. no. 83. Cf. Cavell,
Claim of Reason, 46).
(57) . Azade Seyhan, “What Is Romanticism, and Where Did It Come From?” in
Cambridge Companion to German Romanticism ed. Nicholas Saul (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2009), 17.
(60) . “The present dialogue...is intended to set against one another quite
divergent opinions, each of them capable of shedding new light upon the infinite
spirit of poetry from an individual standpoint, each of them striving to penetrate
from a different angle into the real heart of the matter. It was my interest in this
many-sidedness that made me resolve to communicate publicly things that I had
observed in a circle of friends” (Dialogue on Poetry, KA 2, 286).
(64) . Eg., CF, KA 2, 162, no. 121, and 163, no. 123.
(72) . Cf. “It was wit, not logic, that was the ‘highest principle of knowledge,’ and
the ‘principle scientific inventiveness’, since Schlegel took it to be a mode
Page 22 of 26
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
“No Poetry, No Reality”
(77) . Even though I read those remarks in a Wittgensteinian spirit, I will not
introduce Wittgenstein’s own treatment of the distinction between fiction and
reality, nor compare it with Schlegel’s. For an instructive treatment of
Wittgenstein on this topic, see David Schalkwyk, “Fiction as ‘Grammatical’
Investigation: A Wittgensteinian Account,” Journal of Aesthetics and Art
Criticism 53, no. 3 (1995): 287–98; and his Literature and the Touch of the Real
(Newark: University of Delaware Press, 2004).
(78) . See note 6 for the justification for my use of “poetry” and “fiction”
interchangeably in this section.
(81) . This picture of the relation between fiction and reality might also be
motivated by some kind of fear—we might worry that everything we know to be
real will turn out to be “unreal” in some way, if reality is not absolutely
distinguished from what is “merely fictional,” an invented “figment of the
imagination.” We seem to worry that if the real and the fictional are not
irrevocably distinguished and separated as two independent and self-sufficient
realms, we might not be real to ourselves, we might not be.
Page 23 of 26
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
“No Poetry, No Reality”
(82) . For this distinction of Schlegel’s career into different periods, see, for
example, Arthur Lovejoy, “Schiller and the Genesis of German Romanticism,” in
Essays in the History of Ideas (New York: Putnam, 1963): 207–27; Eichner,
Friedrich Schlegel; Dieter Henrich, Konstellationen: Probleme und Debatten am
Ursprung der idealistischen Philosophie (1789–1795) (Stuttgart: Klett-Cotta,
1991); Frank, Unendliche Annäherung; and Beiser, “Friedrich Schlegel: The
Mysterious Romantic,” in The Romantic Imperative.
(86) . E.g., “Pity, worry about, hate, and envy are such that one cannot have
them without believing that their objects exist, just as one cannot fear something
without believing that it threatens them” (Kendall Walton, “Fearing Fictions,”
Journal of Philosophy 75 [1978]: 21 n. 15).
(87) . Walton’s other two relevant texts on the topic are Mimesis as Make-
Believe: On the Foundations of the Representational Arts (Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press, 1990), and “Spelunking, Simulation, and Slime: On
Being Moved by Fiction,” in Emotion and the Arts, ed. Mette Hjort and Sue
Laver (New York: Oxford University Press, 1997), 37–49. For other philosophers,
who, like Walton, adopt what is known in the literature as the “Pretense
Theory” (the theory that holds that we have “quasi-emotional” responses to
fiction), see, for example, Susan Feagin, “Imagining Emotions and Appreciating
Fiction,” in Emotion and the Arts, ed. Mette Hjort and Save Laver (New York:
Oxford University Press, 1997), 50–62, and Gregory Currie, The Nature of
Fiction (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990). Richard Moran has
articulated one of the best criticisms of this line of thought to date in his “The
Expression of Feeling in Imagination,” Philosophical Review 103, no. 1 (1994):
75–106.
(88) . Walton does not deny that we do feel something for fictional characters.
But he denies that what we feel is of the same kind as “real” emotions—what we
feel for real people (for example, Mimesis as Make-Believe, 247, and
“Spelunking, Simulation, and Slime,” 38).
(89) . The plight of this line of thought is analogous to the plight of the skeptic as
I discussed it above. In order for their argument to get off the ground, the
philosophers I just described must use the terms “fictional” and “real” both in
the way we ordinarily use them, and in a special, “unordinary” way. For example,
if Walton’s argument is to work, if it is to conflict with what we ordinarily think
and say about whatever we feel when we read a novel, or watch a film—as
Walton suggests that it does—Walton must use the term “real” as we ordinarily
Page 24 of 26
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
“No Poetry, No Reality”
use it. Otherwise, there would not be any conflict between what Walton claims to
discover about our emotions, and the way most of us think and speak about our
emotions. However, in order to establish the claim that no one ever feels “real”
feelings for fictions, as Walton holds, he must also use the term “real” in a
special, nonordinary way. For Walton holds that what is “real” is determined
once and for all, as if “by language itself,” independently of what we mean by the
term when we use language, and that what he has discovered holds for every
and any feeling we might have for fiction. None of those feelings, on Walton’s
view, can be real. This use of the terms departs from our ordinary use of it. And
so, in order for the argument to work, Walton has to use those terms in two
conflicting ways.
(91) . For Cavell’s instructive discussion of this distinction, and his claim that
there are no criteria for distinguishing the real from the unreal, see The Claim of
Reason, 49–64.
(95) . Again, by “fictional” I do not mean “fictitious,” or “unreal,” but that which
belongs to, occurs in, or is a feature of a work of fiction.
(97) . Ibid., 315. In the same work, Schlegel also suggests that confessions—the
expression of a subject—can be more “realistic” than the novels, for example, of
Richardson, which are standardly considered to be quintessentially realistic
because of their attention to, and description of details of everyday experience
(KA 2, 337–38).
(99) . This animation might rest on the work of the imagination, as a (cognitive)
capacity that reveals reality, not simply fantasy. More would have to say about
this capacity in an elaboration on this paper.
Page 25 of 26
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
“No Poetry, No Reality”
(103) . Compare with the different though related idea that Moran uses to
challenge Walton’s view: “It is unlikely that the various responses we classify
with the emotions form anything like a natural-kind.... For this reason it is
unlikely that there could even in principle be a general problem of fictional
emotions” (“Expression of Feeling in Imagination,” 81).
(104) . This is the full fragment: “No poetry, no reality. Just as there is, despite
all the senses, no external world without imagination, so too there is no spiritual
world without feeling, no matter how much sense there is. Whoever only has
sense can perceive no human being, but only what is human: all things disclose
themselves to the magic wand of feeling alone. It fixes people and seizes them;
like the eye, it looks on without being conscious of its own mathematical
operation.”
Page 26 of 26
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
The Simplicity of the Sublime
Laure Cahen-Maurel
DOI:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199976201.003.0011
Keywords: Caspar David Friedrich, painting, sublime, veiling, Rückenfigur, imagination, Kant, Novalis,
Anish Kapoor
—Anish Kapoor1
Page 1 of 16
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
The Simplicity of the Sublime
10.1. Introduction
It has been almost forty years since the art historian Robert Rosenblum in his
book Modern Painting and the Northern Romantic Tradition: Friedrich to Rothko
traced the origin of abstract expressionism in post–World War II America to the
vast and barren seascape of Caspar David Friedrich’s Monk by the Sea (1810).2
Indeed, according to Rosenblum, it is simply a matter of removing the figure of
the monk from Friedrich’s painting to arrive at the colored rectangles of
Rothko’s Green on Blue (1956), which hover above one another on a
monochrome background.3 Thus, Friedrich’s treatment of pictorial space may be
seen as an early formulation of what the artist Barnett Newman would later
consider to be the newfound dominance of the United States over Europe in art,
and which subsequently became known as the “American sublime.” More
recently, in the early twenty-first century, and with a keen awareness of history,
the British sculptor Anish Kapoor has attempted to restore a metaphysical (p.
187) function to art with his explorations of space at the intersection of
painting, sculpture, and architecture. As we shall see, Kapoor directly situates
his work in the artistic tradition of Caspar David Friedrich, reimagining the
latter’s Sea of Ice (1824) in a monumental installation entitled Svayambh (2007).
In short, from the formal standpoint of art history and artistic creation there is
not only a sublime grandeur but something progressive and even visionary about
this landscape painting that makes Friedrich one of the most celebrated and
studied artists of romantic art today.
From the more philosophical point of view of the content, many commentators
think that the romantic sublime is above all embodied in Friedrich’s painting
Wanderer above the Sea of Fog (1818). Here a solitary figure, painted with his
back to us, stands on a rocky elevation, contemplating a grandiose high
mountain landscape extending into the distance. Yet it might be objected that
the wanderer’s somewhat artificial and theatrical pose should be labeled more
“kitsch” than sublime, and served an overtly political agenda. Accordingly,
instead of conveying a visionary sublimity Friedrich’s art would then partake in
the regressive idea of landscape painting as an expression of the “German soul,”
which pertains to a darker form of patriotic and nationalistic kitsch.
Furthermore, the philosophical analysis of his paintings still has not been able to
provide a convincing answer to the question whether one can conceptually apply
the Kantian distinction between the beautiful and the sublime to Friedrich’s
landscapes, as well as reconciling the experience of the sublime with the
religious vocation of his art. In this regard a number of commentators of
Friedrich maintain that the category of the sublime has no relevance at all for
his Weltanschauung.4
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
The Simplicity of the Sublime
Page 3 of 16
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
The Simplicity of the Sublime
Even though the romantic sublime is not a new subject for research, the debate
over the sublime in the philosophical reception of Caspar David Friedrich is still
far from settled. The controversy about the applicability of the concept of the
sublime to his paintings cannot be ignored, since it raises a substantial question
of principle. Three main interpretative tendencies may be singled out.
Page 4 of 16
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
The Simplicity of the Sublime
Page 5 of 16
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
The Simplicity of the Sublime
Because surely we mean [by “sublime”] that the choice of the subject
matter has the ability to more deeply and intimately seize (ergreifen) and
captivate (fesseln) the spectator. Of course, everything in nature is
significant and grand, beautiful and noble, but some of it is more
significant, appropriate, and evocative for presenting in a picture than
others. For depicting the most beautiful and the highest and what seizes us
the most would obviously be the task of the true artist. And I do not
necessarily mean here towering mountains or endless abysses.14
First, far from conveying the notorious philosophical aesthetics of the sublime as
opposed to the beautiful in the tradition of Burke and Kant, the term “sublime”
in this passage amounts to an appreciative hyperbole, that is, to a superlative of
the beautiful. It is also clear from this passage that Friedrich understands the
artistic sublime in terms of its aesthetic (pathetic or emotive) impact: the artistic
sublime is what produces the most powerful effect. One could call this an
extremely banal and limited notion of the sublime, for to produce an effect is of
Page 6 of 16
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
The Simplicity of the Sublime
course the goal of all art. However, as we shall see, it is (p.192) precisely this
accentuation of the effect that constitutes a true aesthetics here, and not just a
hyperbolic appreciation. In the academic neoclassical tradition, represented
notably by Goethe, the highest aesthetic scope or impact of a work of art
depends on the intrinsic dignity of its subject matter. Natural objects do not
contain any idea or ideal. Ordinary everyday objects are generally only viewed
according to their physical or visual aspect, and occasionally perhaps as objects
capable of stimulating an emotion in us, but one that is itself ordinary. In order
to become a significant element and to develop the greatest possible aesthetic
range (or the highest affective power), the object of an artistic representation
must be an ideal object that the artist cannot merely find given in experience.15
For Friedrich, in contrast, all reality is significant a priori. In his writings the
term “significant” (bedeutsam) should indeed be taken literally, that is, in its
primary meaning as signification (Bedeutung): it designates something that is “a
sign for something else,” something that refers to another thing that is exterior
to itself; in other words, something transcending it. Thus, a thing becomes a sign
by having a relation to another thing. In metaphysical painting, a concrete and
ordinary object of the sensible world may become significant, evocative, or
important as soon as it is understood or put into relation with something
abstract, invisible, and immaterial—in short, with something spiritual. This is the
core of Friedrich’s religious conception of the world: the incarnation, the word
made flesh, or the New Testament as the epoch of sensible mediation. It should
not be forgotten that the romantic painter was brought up in the pietistic faith
and imagination; he believed in the Incarnation of God in the body of the Son
and in the sacrament of the Eucharist. It is precisely this union of the divine
logos and sensible flesh in the incarnation that the Tetschen Altarpiece (1808)
celebrates, a landmark painting considered to be a manifesto of his pictorial
conception.
Page 7 of 16
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
The Simplicity of the Sublime
(p.193) “Art serves as a mediator between nature and man. The archetype
(Urbild) is too large and too sublime to be grasped by the masses. Its reflection
(Abbild)—the work of man—is much more accessible to the weak.”16
Consequently, the artistic sublime is a means for this stated goal of art. Its
concrete description in the earlier passage indicates that the artistic sublime is
the concept that most directly deals with the interiority of the subject. It is not a
question of any kind of pathos or sentimentality but of the spiritual strength of
the affect that is able to move the soul powerfully, “deeply,” and “intimately.”
That is to say, the artistic sublime pertains to art’s active virtue of strengthening
the relation between the created and the Creator by means of a more direct
feeling, experienced in the interiority as the meeting point of two worlds, the
corporal and the spiritual, the sensible and the intelligible. In other words, in the
strict sense Friedrich conceives the artistic sublime as the religious efficacy of
art.
Page 8 of 16
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
The Simplicity of the Sublime
This painting is large; and yet we wish it were larger still. For the sublimity
in the conception of the subject matter has been experienced in all its
greatness and requires an even larger extension in space. Therefore, it is
always praiseworthy for a painting to say we wish it were even larger.19
Thus, Friedrich’s use of the sublime of scale as creation of space on the canvas
breaks with the oversaturation of the gaze caused by naturalistic landscapes. It
seeks to liberate both space and the gaze of the spectator to allow her (p.195)
to experience the distance between things. This explains the dilation and the
emptiness in many of Friedrich’s landscapes, which were rarely painted in large
formats.
Page 9 of 16
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
The Simplicity of the Sublime
The second method is more concerned with the two modalities of visibility:
transparency and opacity. A number of the romantic artist’s paintings admit us
into the presence of an inner, spiritual, and dreamlike vision—one could say, into
the transparency of the sublime. We immediately enter into the fictive space of
the image, for it creates an effect of direct confrontation with nature by
suspending the illusion of distance found in classical forms of representation due
to an unobstructed foreground. Nevertheless, opacity still remains the general
rule of the sublime, and this is necessary for it to play the full role assigned to it,
that is, to capture our attention and penetrate ever deeper into the living sphere
of our interiority. There are numerous modalities of this opacity for outer
physical sight in Friedrich’s paintings. But the most sublime of all these
deployments of opacity is the veiling principle of mist or fog. Let us quote again
the words of the romantic painter in his Considerations:
When a region is covered with fog it seems larger and more sublime; like
the appearance of a young woman covered with a veil, it heightens the
imagination and raises expectations. The eye and the imagination are more
attracted by misty distances than by what is closely and clearly seen.20
These lines might be read in light of the problem of the veiling and unveiling of
nature. From antiquity up to the Enlightenment, Mother Nature was frequently
personified under the guise of the goddess Isis-Artemis. Allegorically
represented as hidden behind a veil covering her face, she was inaccessible to
the gaze of mere mortals. In Kant’s Critique of the Power of Judgment, the image
of the veiled Isis goes hand in hand with a respect for the mysteries of nature,
inspired by that “most sublime” inscription on the goddess’s temple prohibiting
the lifting of her veil.21 In The Disciples of Sais, the romantic poet Novalis also
prefers the Orphic poet’s respectful attitude towards nature over the
Promethean attitude of modern science, yet advocates surmounting the
interdiction on lifting her veil. One can only do this by going beyond the limits
set by Kantian criticism, that is to say, by overcoming the limits of human
finitude: “According to that inscription, if it is true that no mortal has lifted the
veil, then we will just have to try to become immortal. Whoever does not wish to
lift it, is no true disciple of Sais.”22 In the paintings of Friedrich, fog is a natural
or material veil that is no longer merely an allegory of the secrets of nature and
their inaccessibility to mortals. Fog, moreover, does not simply impede our sight
and generate respect that keeps us at a distance from nature. It attracts our
sight. In the same way as the veiled body of a woman might excite the desire to
see it unveiled, fog stirs our imagination and the wish to see more by
penetrating the opacity.
(p.196) Friedrich’s painting entitled Fog (1807) perfectly illustrates this point:
in its extreme figurative simplicity it awakens our desire to see the fog-
enshrouded three-masted sailboat that is behind the rowing boat in the
foreground, then to see the distant shore behind the sailboat, and then again
Page 10 of 16
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
The Simplicity of the Sublime
perhaps to glimpse the horizon behind the distant shore. Of course, this desire is
not awakened in “those whose imagination is too poor to see in fog anything
other than gray.”23 This accentuation of desire defines the Friedrichian sublime;
it requires a certain attitude or state of mind on the part of the spectator, and
stimulates an inner dynamic response to the painting. Here Friedrich is strongly
opposed to an art of illusion, because the latter merely passively dazzles the
viewer, and precludes her from actively exercising this intimate activity or
appropriation of what the painting shows.
10.5. Anish Kapoor: Doing Away with the Mediation in the Friedrichian
Sublime?
In this concluding section I would like to draw attention to Anish Kapoor’s
reinterpretation of Friedrich’s Sea of Ice (1824), which, along with the Monk by
the Sea and the Wanderer above the Sea of Fog, is considered by commentators
to be one of the best examples of the sublime in Friedrich. The Kantian concept
of a “dynamic” and terrifying sublime is frequently applied to the Sea of Ice,
though it is precisely this painting that provides the clearest illustration of what
makes Friedrich’s art of the sublime radically different from the Kantian
analysis.
At first glance this painting, also known as The Wreck of Hope, seems to be a
narrative motif—a shipwreck—inspired by a real-life expedition to the North Pole
in 1819–1820. Yet an image emerges here in which the sublime experience no
longer resides in the tension of Kant’s “dynamic sublime” that is characteristic
of catastrophe paintings. From a Kantian perspective the resolution of this
tension involves human practical rationality. In contrast to this, Friedrich’s
painting carries out a kind of refocusing on nature. Swallowed by ice, the ship
itself is barely visible, whereas the stacked blocks of ice physically dominate the
center of the composition. Or more precisely, the image shows the fragmentation
of a ship whose debris mingles with natural forms. But this painting is even
more unique and troubling if one recalls that all human landmarks do not in fact
entirely disappear. The work involves the presence of a perceptive subject, yet
one that is not depicted. The image unfolds under this gaze and gives it a more
intimate nuance. For what strikes one above all in this painting is the impression
of silence and stillness—it almost emanates a sense of tranquility. The sublime
experience resides in a quiet and oneiric vision of a natural time, a cosmic and
archaic time that is opposed to the time of history and action, a (p.197) natural
time in its fundamental processes: the solidification of water into ice, or the
petrifaction of the ice in the foreground that gradually takes on the color of
stone. This elementary matter is marked and borne by the temporality of its
becoming. Yet it is a slow, infinitesimal movement that borders upon immobility,
if not upon eternity—the movement of a sea of ice.
Page 11 of 16
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
The Simplicity of the Sublime
Anish Kapoor has perceptively grasped all of this. The British sculptor freely
admits that his work draws its fundamental inspiration from the intrinsic aspect
of a dreamlike sublime in the landscape paintings of Caspar David Friedrich.
Kapoor declares he is “a painter working as a sculptor.” For he creates “mental
sculptures” that are no longer simply the embodiment of a real, tangible space,
but presuppose and demand an act of inhabiting a space through one’s viewing,
similar to Friedrich’s sublime of scale as a magnified space. Kapoor has made
architectural scale into a principle of his sculptures, often creating site-specific
work that acquires its own dimensions by developing in the site. This is the case
of the gigantic installation Svayambh, first conceived for the Musée des Beaux-
Arts of Nantes in France in 2007, and then exhibited at Munich’s Haus der
Kunst, which is in part a reinterpretation of the sublime vision of an archaic
nature in Friedrich’s Sea of Ice. Svayambh—a Sanskrit word meaning “born by
itself”—is a massive block of red wax moving almost imperceptibly on hidden
rails through the museum building along its west-east axis. The coming and
going of the block with the slowness of an infinitesimal movement that is almost
reduced to immobility, like the movement of a sea of ice, generates an
impression of primal and potentially infinite extension. The matter of the
sculpture is shaped through infinite duration and space itself; the original object
is seemingly endlessly reworked, carved, planed down by passing through the
arched door frames, leaving red traces on their immaculate white color as if the
block were slightly larger than the frames—or, as if the building were, so to
speak, swallowing the block. Viewed as a self-generating system, as an
uncreated or autonomous form that creates itself and whose origin is
immemorial, it is no longer historical.
Kapoor’s work, however, gives a different treatment of the sublime: “I think the
real subject for me, if there is one, is the sublime....It’s this whole notion of
somehow trying to shorten the distance of sublime experience....If one is looking
at a Friedrich painting of a figure looking at the sunset, then one is having one’s
reverie in terms of their experience....It is my wish to make that distance shorter
so that the reverie is direct. You’re not watching someone else do it; you’re
compelled to do it yourself.”24 That is to say, Kapoor aims at doing away with one
of the very emblems of Caspar David Friedrich’s art: the Rückenfigur—the figure
with its back turned to the viewer—like in the Wanderer above the Sea of Fog.
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
The Simplicity of the Sublime
the figure deploys its positive function. It institutes a form of reflexivity in which
we oscillate between two modes of contemplation, between the outer eye and
the inner eye. We are forced to “go back” in ourselves, to use our “inner eye” to
imagine the entire landscape that we wish we could see, because we are unable
to externally project ourselves into the view.
Thus, when Kapoor intends to “shorten the distance of sublime experience” “so
that the reverie is direct” and “you’re compelled to do it yourself,” he is perhaps
unaware that Friedrich has constructed this mediation precisely to compel us to
do it ourselves. For the natural (or divine) sublime is what we absolutely cannot
experience without an artistic mediation. Or to put it in Novalis’s words: the
Friedrichian sublime resides in a “qualitative potentialization,”25 in which our
sight is elevated to an inner vision, a vision of the purely spiritual and
transcendent principle of nature. And in line with Novalis’s definition of
romanticism, the “qualitative potentialization” of sight by means of a veiling
principle may also be inverted. Here the mystical becomes known through a
process of lowering or “logarhythmizing,” and the imagination concentrates on
the finite or the ordinary, such as a “simple wheat field.” For Friedrich and the
romantics at least, this is the only possible way to “shorten the distance of
sublime experience.”26
10.6. Conclusion
As we have seen, there is a threefold sublime in Caspar David Friedrich: a
divine, natural, and artistic sublime. To be sure, his art of landscape painting
strives to make the excess of the cosmic and divine sublime become perceptible
within the framed space of a canvas. And certainly, it aims at uplifting the spirit
of the spectator. But if one remains at an interpretation of Friedrich’s painting in
terms of the Kantian sublime, one fails to understand how his view of the
sublime cannot be reduced to one of hyperbolic grandeur exceeding the form.
Furthermore, if one only emphasizes the transcendence, the distance and
incommensurability between the divine cosmic order and the human order, one
overlooks the goal of the artistic sublime. The latter seeks to stir the spectator’s
emotive and imaginative participation and to reduce the distance between (p.
199) these two orders. While the Kantian sublime expresses a radical dualism
and tension between the sensible and the intelligible, in the religious
perspective of Friedrich’s art the material and the spiritual differ but are not
opposed. They are complementary rather than antagonistic, and the whole point
of his painting is to make us associate and not separate them. Hence, claims that
the experience of the sublime cannot be reconciled with the religious vocation of
Friedrich’s paintings, or that only the beautiful is at stake in his work, fail to
grasp that their religious vocation actually depends on the sublime.
Why should we care about Friedrich’s views? It might be argued that an art that
addresses the soul and aims at a recognition of the sacred is now historically
dated. But without seeking to abolish the historical distance between his epoch
Page 13 of 16
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
The Simplicity of the Sublime
and ours, Friedrich’s views offer artistic perspectives that are still relevant for
contemporary artists and theoreticians of art: a use of scale to liberate space,
perceptual opacity to stimulate both our outer and inner sight, and, above all, as
Anish Kapoor has attempted to do in the wake of minimalism, a simplification of
the work of art. All of which constitutes the simplicity of the sublime in the
works of that “metaphysician with the brush,”27 Caspar David Friedrich.
Notes:
(1) . Anish Kapoor, “‘I Don’t Know Where I’m Going,’“interview with Alastair
Sooke, The Telegraph, September 26, 2006, online: http://www.telegraph.co.uk/
culture/art/3655568/I-dont-know-where-Im-going.html.
(2) . I am grateful to Dalia Nassar for her helpful comments on an earlier version
of this text.
(3) . See Robert Rosenblum, Modern Painting and the Northern Romantic
Tradition: Friedrich to Rothko (New York: Harper & Row, 1975), 10f.
(4) . See especially Werner Busch, Caspar David Friedrich. Ästhetik und Religion
(Munich: C. H. Beck, 2003), 64f. Busch dismisses all interpretation of Friedrich’s
paintings as being in line with an aesthetics of the sublime by proclaiming the
sublime as “postreligious.” See too Johannes Grave, Caspar David Friedrich und
die Theorie des Erhabenen (Weimar: VDG-Verlag, 2001); Grave focuses his
analysis on the Sea of Ice and maintains that in this painting Friedrich is
ironically working against the philosophical conception of the sublime
elaborated by Kant and Schiller.
(5) . See among others Hilmar Frank, Aussichten ins Unermessliche (Berlin:
Akademie Verlag, 2004), 99–100; Eliane Escoubas, “La tragédie du paysage:
Caspar David Friedrich,” in L’espace pictural (Paris: Les Belles Lettres, 2011, 1st
ed. 1995), 69–90. Elsewhere Escoubas has argued for the “simplicity” of the
Kantian sublime, drawing on a quotation from the “General Remark” to § 29 of
the Critique of the Power of Judgment where Kant writes “Simplicity
(purposiveness without art) is so to speak the style of nature in the sublime,”
meaning that the context of the sublime is nature in its primitive purity devoid of
all artifice. See Eliane Escoubas, “Kant or the Simplicity of the Sublime,” in Of
the Sublime: Presence in Question, ed. Jean-François Courtine, trans. Jeffrey S.
Librett (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1993), 55–70. Here I will try
to show that the notion of “simplicity” is even more present in the Friedrichian
sublime.
(6) . See for example Brad Prager, “Kant in Caspar David Friedrich’s Frames,”
Art History 25 (2002): 68–86.
Page 14 of 16
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
The Simplicity of the Sublime
(13) . Friedrich, Äußerungen, 53. In the original German: “Ein Gefühl für das
Erhabene in der Natur fehlt es ihm doch wohl gewiß nicht?”
(15) . Cf. Goethe, Über die Gegenstände der bildenden Kunst (Zurich: Artemis
Verlag, 1961–66), vol. 13, 122–25. According to Goethe, the inherent dignity of
the subject matter is what we absolutely cannot know without the artistic
idealization that reveals it or brings it to light. This dignity relates to the
timeless essence of the object, an idea that the artist forms through an intimate
knowledge of nature. He should not regress into the fantastic, but move beyond
the given sensible phenomena to the timeless idea.
Page 15 of 16
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
The Simplicity of the Sublime
(21) . Kant, Critique of the Power of Judgment, § 49, trans. Paul Guyer and Eric
Matthews (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000), 194.
(24) . Rainer Crone and Alexandra Von Stosch, Anish Kapoor (London: Prestel,
2008), 27–28.
(26) . For a more detailed analysis of the romantic notion of potentialization and
the relationship between Caspar David Friedrich and Novalis, see my L’art de
romantiser le monde. Caspar David Friedrich et la philosophie romantique, PhD
thesis, Universität München/Université Paris IV, October 2013.
Page 16 of 16
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
The New Mythology
Bruce Matthews
DOI:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199976201.003.0012
Keywords: new mythology, humanism, romanticism, religion, Schelling, Manfred Frank, Frederick
Beiser
Page 1 of 17
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
The New Mythology
The Romantic Imperative, due to the fact that this proposed marriage of
religion’s divine necessities and the freedoms of humanism was never
consummated, “the problems that so troubled the romantics...are still with us.”1
Perhaps the most serious of these problems is that of our relationship to the
natural world—a problem whose consequences are far from academic. As
Manfred Frank has repeatedly warned, to surrender our subjectivity and free
will to the deterministic vocabulary of the natural sciences will not only
undermine the personal accountability that supports moral action, but it will also
lead to a “political fatalism” that will destroy the legitimacy of society’s defining
institutions.2
But nowhere is the problem of our inability to create new values more real than
in a problem the romantics also found so troubling, namely the damage and
destruction we are doing to nature. No one saw this inevitable crisis more
clearly than the young Schelling, who warned in 1804 that the course of (p.
203) modern philosophy, left to its own inner logic would lead to “the
annihilation of nature” (SW 1/5, 274).
Page 2 of 17
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
The New Mythology
Page 3 of 17
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
The New Mythology
It is on this very point of integrating freedom and necessity that Beiser contends
that the romantics’ use of Herder’s strategy fails to successfully overcome the
paradox of romantic metaphysics, since the romantics’ allegiance to Spinoza’s
naturalism necessitates their abandonment of Fichte’s “radical freedom,” and
with this, the surrender of autonomous political engagement to the
heterogeneous forces of traditional religion. This follows as a consequence of
Fichte’s understanding of radical freedom as spontaneity (Selbsttätigkeit) and
self-positing that “excludes determination by natural causes” of the material
world, and thus “presupposes the noumenal-phenomenal dualism” (RI 151). (p.
205) According to Beiser, Fichte’s account of freedom is radical on two counts.
First, because it advances a self whose only essence is to create itself through
the freedom of self-positing. Second, due to its total freedom from the material
world, it has the power to transform that material world into a “completely
rational world through infinite striving” (RI 171). Given this power of the self
over the not-self of nature, the self does not need to break out of its subjective
confines to integrate with the objective world, since its imperative is to remake
the objective world so that it conforms to the rational order of the subject. Of
course, “the romantics reject” this account of the self and the purpose of its
radical freedom (RI 151). Due to their allegiance to Spinoza’s naturalism, they
hold that since “everything is simply a mode of God,” and “God acts from the
necessity of his nature,” then human agency is actually divine agency, thereby
undercutting any claim to autonomous action (RI 185). The degree to which the
romantics abandon freedom falls short of Spinoza’s fatalism, but only barely,
since it is the optimistic form of fatalism—quietism—that is Beiser’s concluding
characterization of the romantics’ position (RI 151), a position, it must be added,
that he, following Heine and Marx, equates with a “reactionary” and thus
conservative religion that is directly at odds with the “progressive and liberal”
humanism that Fichte’s radical freedom supports (RI 174). And it is precisely
this problem of the irreconcilable demands of religion and humanism that so
troubles Beiser, since we are far from achieving a successful integration of these
opposing forces, so that the challenges presented by the paradox of romantic
metaphysics “are still with us” (RI 151).
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
The New Mythology
argues precisely the opposite of the position attributed to him by Beiser. Far
from contending that God’s nature determines humanity’s actions, Schelling
argues here for an organic, reciprocal relationship between God and humanity,
in which both are “co-poets” (Mitdichter) of our history (SW 1/3, 602). In fact,
both parties are so necessary to this collaborative process that if “our own
freedom” in creating our part were denied, “even...[God] himself would not
be” (SW 1/3, 602). Far from being a puppet of a deity, the existence of the divine
himself somehow depends on humanity’s freedom as we actively participate in
composing the poem of our history. In Schelling’s (p.206) words here, it seems
humans are indeed determined by God’s nature, but this nature is to live, create,
and be free. Thus when it is suggested that for the romantics “everything is
simply a mode of God,” and that “God acts from the necessity of his nature,” and
if this divine nature is to be alive and thus free, then far from undercutting
autonomous action, both God and humanity act from the necessity of their
nature as free beings (RI 185). Torturing Sartre’s words, we might say that
according to Schelling, as a mode of a living God, we are by this very necessity
of God’s nature condemned to be free. Beiser’s misreading of Schelling is all too
common, due to the almost default allegiance to a Kantian and Fichtean idea of
radical freedom that, in its Cartesian insistence on an almost gnostic-like
detachment from the natural world, reveals itself to be in fact the very antithesis
of Schelling’s conception of an organic freedom that, embedded in the fabric of
nature itself, frames his programmatic claim made in his Naturrecht (1796) that
life itself is the schema of freedom (SW 1/1, 249).
This claim demonstrates the degree to which Schelling invested our embodied
world with what he considered to be the divine presence of freedom. Consistent
with the philosophical theology of his upbringing, he maintained that our
conscious life is best understood through the same dynamic of self-manifestation
as that of God. Just after leaving the Stift, he asks in 1797 if he may borrow his
father’s dissertation on Leibniz’s theory of monads, written when Schelling Sr.
was a student in Tübingen under the supervision of Gottfried Ploucquet (1716–
1790), who, besides Wolff, was one of the most influential interpreters of
Leibniz’s philosophy, as well as a highly original thinker in his own right.3 In this
dissertation, with which the young Schelling was obviously quite familiar,
Schelling Sr. engaged Ploucquet’s own theory of monads, wherein the “Ich
(egoitas)” is a “self-manifestation (manifestatio sui),” which arises out of the
“reciprocal community (commercium)” of the Ich and the “Nicht-Ichheit” (“Non-
egoitas”).4 The significant dynamic at work here is that of our living self-
consciousness as the activity of a commercium, of a Wechselwirkung of an Ich
and a nicht-Ich, which in its incessant activity betrays the generative forces
offered through Plouquet’s idea of the divine self-manifestation.5 And it is
precisely this integrative dynamic that Schelling uses in the Naturrecht to argue
that the moral law and its “causality of freedom reveals itself through physical
causality” of living, self-conscious beings. The young Schelling pulls this off
Page 5 of 17
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
The New Mythology
employing Kant’s own categories more consistently than their author, exploiting
Kant’s use of the same relational category and its logical form of disjunction to
resolve the antinomy of freedom and the reciprocal interaction that drives
organic life. Setting the noumenal and phenomenal into the same type of
interdependent feedback loop as that of an organic system’s part to whole,
Schelling takes as his starting point the only organic system where we are
identical with (p.207) the thing in itself, namely the self as a living being,
which, as the point of union between the intelligible and the sensual, “must unite
within itself autonomy and heteronomy” (SW 1/1, 248). That is, there must be a
form of causality that unites both of these in a phenomenon that is both relative
and absolute, obeys the laws of nature, and yet is also in principle, because of its
autonomous power, incapable of ever being exhaustively accounted for.
Schelling’s position here is clear: “This causality is life.—Life is autonomy in
appearance, is the schema of freedom, to the degree that it reveals itself in
nature” (SW 1/1, 249).
The structural move Schelling makes here inverts Kant’s architectonic, setting
the dynamic categories of nature before those of mathematics. This inversion
brings with it a host of systematic consequences. Perhaps the most notable
makes the self-organizing dynamic of the organic foundational, and therewith
sets the inexponible category of Wechselwirkung and Gemeinschaft as the
primary category for understanding our world. The heart of this multivalent
intersection of opposing causal forces betrays a chaotic rhythm, whose
indeterminability finds each opposing yet complementary force superimposed in
the other, each entangled in dynamic interaction as both cause and effect of the
other. Kant recognizes this irreducibly nonmechanistic factor of reciprocal
Page 6 of 17
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
The New Mythology
These same principles are necessarily those of the sum total of nature and
thus ultimately of the All itself, and according to these [principles] we
would like to develop, as it were, symbolically in matter the entirety of the
inner driving power of the universe and the highest Grundsätze of
philosophy itself.
Page 7 of 17
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
The New Mythology
These principles of which Schelling here writes are those that animate “the most
sublime science,” whose goal can only be “to present...the actuality, (p.209) the
presence, the living Da-sein of God in the entirety and particularity of all things,”
since as the power of life itself, “everything lives in him” (SW 1/2, 376).
Given this account of Schelling, and accepting his Naturphilosophie as the only
source for a systematic account of romantic naturalism, I would have to modify
Beiser’s claim that the romantics shared Spinoza’s position that “everything is
simply a mode of God” to read instead that “everything is animated by the
organizing principles of the divine life.” Consequently, Beiser’s claim that “God
acts from the necessity of his nature” asserts nothing more than God’s nature is
life, which, according to Schelling, is the first predicate attributable to him. This
is a position that not only deflates Beiser’s claim that the romantics sacrificed
their autonomy on the altar of naturalism, but more importantly, it is a new
position that informs a way of thinking an organic philosophy that moves beyond
the debilitating limits imposed by the dualism required by Fichte’s radical
freedom.
Refusing to begin with the certainty of the ego, Schelling begins with the
inexponible unity of life as an organic system, whose organizing principles
inform and animate its development. Given this interconnectedness of nature, of
matter and mind being driven by the same principles of growth, we become
faced with the prospect of what Schelling termed our conscientia, or
Mitwissenschaft with nature. Refusing to accept the terms of “the skeptical
problems that motivated Cartesian epistemology”—in Beiser’s words, problems
such as “how do we know that there is a nature or history beyond
consciousness?” (RI 132)–Schelling reframes modernity’s epistemological
obsessions in accordance with the reciprocal dynamic of self-organizing systems
and our status as an organ of knowing within this system. From this standpoint
he contends that we can explain why we are capable of knowing with “direct
certainty” that “there are things beyond us,” even though this knowledge “refers
to something quite different and opposed to us” (SW 1/3, 343). We are capable of
knowing that which shows itself to be other than we are because we are “of this
world,” having been created through the very same dynamic organization that
has brought our entire cosmos into being. What precedes and thus unifies
knowing subject and known object is this underlying order of organic nature that
bonds us with the phenomenal world in which we live. Our power to appreciate
“the unfathomable intentionality, the unbelievable naiveté of nature in the
achievement of its purposes,” points to “the view of a true inner history of
nature” in “whose formation humanity can look into as into that of a related
being” (SW 1/10, 378; SW 1/10, 381). Most clearly demonstrated by the works of
Page 8 of 17
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
The New Mythology
the scientific and artistic genius, our function in the autoepistemic structure of
nature is that of an organ whereby nature comes to know herself.
Descartes, who through the cogito ergo sum gave philosophy its first
orientation to subjectivity, and whose introduction of philosophy (in his
Meditations) is in fact identical with the later grounding of philosophy in
idealism, could not yet present the orientations entirely separated—
subjectivity and objectivity do not yet appear completely divided. But his
real intention, his true idea of God, the world, and the soul he articulated
more clearly in his physics than through his philosophy. In the
comprehensive spirit of Descartes, his philosophy permitted the
annihilation of nature, which the idealism of the above mentioned form
[Fichte’s] extols, just as truly and factually as it actually was in his physics.
Page 9 of 17
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
The New Mythology
Beyond the obvious, yet unfortunately too often overlooked fact that in
destroying nature we harm ourselves, we can see that implicit in Schelling’s
critique of Descartes and Fichte’s treatment of nature is the demand to extend
Kant’s kingdom of ends to all the kingdoms of nature. This follows clearly from
his critique of the alienated subject of modernity, who values the gifts of nature
only if they can be transformed into “beautiful houses and proper furniture” or
“tools and household goods,” since it is only then that “as a tool of his lust and
desire” that the world of nature takes on meaning and value (SW 1/7, 111, 114).
Cutting straight to the heart of modernity’s early capitalist ambitions, Schelling
demand that we stop exploiting nature by making it subservient to our
immediate “economic-teleological ends” as if it had no inherent value in itself
(SW 1/7, 17). Consistent with his contention that “the highest speculative
concepts” must always be “simultaneously the most profound ethical concepts,”
the making absolute of the knowing cogito initiates an inversion of the ego’s
relationship to the physical world it inhabits, whereby the ego claims the right to
remake the world in its own image (SW 2/3, 67). No longer subject to acts of
Page 10 of 17
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
The New Mythology
The course modernity has taken, with its exaltation of the self, Schelling
diagnoses in the Freiheitsschrift as an “evil” brought about “through a misuse of
freedom” (SW 1/7, 366). We are free to elevate and inflate the self, to dominate
nature and to make it serve humanity’s “economic-teleological ends”; indeed, we
are free to even “annihilate nature.” But we are also at liberty to refuse freedom
as Herrschaft, and instead to dethrone the self and return it to an integrated and
balanced relationship of reciprocity with nature’s nexus of living forces. Acting
on this decision would then aim at the productive unity of self and nature,
generating an understanding of freedom as the essence of life lived embedded in
and informed by the oppositional interplay of nature’s processes. Acting on this
decision we might remove the cogito’s self-imposed limitations that exclude not
only the other of nature, but also omit the more familiar other of other human
beings.
To do this is to begin to overcome our alienation from these other beings, and in
this important sense Schelling claims that the overcoming of these limits
through the realization of the unity and mutual dependency of self and nature
will generate a knowledge that is, in fact, redemptive. Thus does “the most
sublime science” of his Naturphilosophie, in seeking “to present the actuality” of
“the living Da-sein of God in...all things” (SW 1/2, 76), seek to create an organic
frame for conceptualizing and realizing the redemptive harmony of the en kai
pan. The realization of this harmony, however, cannot be achieved by the parsing
of logical possibilities in the parlor-game manner a Descartes or Hume doubts
the existence of the world. It can only be grasped in an emphatic and
experiential act of knowing, in which what comes to be known is of such
importance that one could never be “indifferent (gleichgültig)” about it (SW 2/3,
26). Schelling injects an emotive force into his project, since if certainty is
superseded by unity, freedom must then trump logical necessity, with the result
Page 11 of 17
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
The New Mythology
(p.213) that a motive cause is now required to channel freedom’s power. As his
organic strategy seeks to integrate the opposing realities of the intelligible and
sensible, it follows that reason itself must reconcile with emotion, so that that
which grounds and animates philosophy once again becomes infused with
affective love of its desired wisdom.
The soteriological dimension emerges with the act of realizing our conscientia or
Mitwissenschaft with nature, engendering an identification of our subject world
with the object world of phenomenal being. This realized identity of human
consciousness with nature—in which identity signifies the unity of the reciprocal
interplay of our consciousness and nature—generates an unmediated
understanding that can never be the result of a deliberative argumentation (SW
1/8, 200; SW 1/9, 221). It is instead the inescapable beginning of Schelling’s
organic way of thinking that Fichte could never grasp, since it situates the
beginnings of our conscious freedom in an unconscious substrate of sensuous
nature, whose necessary force limits and thus remains opaque to the logos of
discursivity—an epistemological ground zero about which Schelling cites
Aristotle’s “fitting words” that “the starting point of thinking is not thinking, but
something stronger than thinking” (SW 1/2, 217). This starting point discloses
itself in the absolute of a living unity whose “symbolic presentation” is that
towards which “every true philosophy strives, which is objective in religion, an
eternal source of new intuitions, and a universal Typus of everything that is to
become, in which human activity strives to express and cultivate the harmony of
the universe” (SW 1/5, 115).
And with this, we begin to grasp Beiser’s unease with the heretical nature of
Schelling’s philosophy, since it aspires not just to a theoretical knowing, but,
more importantly, to the act of realizing a unity with nature, which as the
manifestation of divine, means that Schelling’s philosophy itself lives from what
“is objective in religion,” although “it is not in its principle religion.” Rejecting
“a knowledge of the absolute that emerges from philosophy as a result” (SW 1/5,
116), he instead demands the experience of this absolute as a precondition for
expressing and cultivating an understanding of this unitive source through the
discipline of philosophy. To do this, however, philosophy must become open to
the other of logos, with its obscure language of mythos that speaks with the
voice of nature as it “sensualizes truth” (Plitt 1, 37). This is a possibility that can
only be entertained, however, if unity becomes the telos of philosophy, thereby
challenging it to harness the disclosive powers of logos and mythos. Set into
opposition, mythos binds together the discrete moments of logos, functioning
organically as the inexponible whole that integrates and thus makes possible the
unending expression of the logoi, generating the transformative power to further
the development of our world. The loss of harmony and balance toward either
extreme, however, leads to stagnation and regression, be it the result of (p.214)
Page 12 of 17
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
The New Mythology
And it is precisely the absence of such a transformative myth that motivated the
romantics then, and Manfred Frank today, to search for a way to provide a
normative sanction to legitimize and orientate our social order—the central idea
and concern that motivated his series on the topic of The New Mythology. In his
lectures Der kommende Gott (1982), Frank argued that the contemporary
problem of the estrangement of state from society results not only in the
legitimacy of the state being undermined, but also in a general societal malaise
and political fatalism.10 Both of these concerns are symptoms of a deeper
metaphysical challenge that has faced the West throughout the past century,
namely how are we to sanction and thereby legitimize our social institutions and
practices in the shadow of God’s death. Moreover, as Frank has recently made
clear, with the ever expanding reach of the neurosciences, last century’s
philosophical “death of the subject” may just be followed by this century’s
scientific reduction of consciousness itself to neurobiological brain states. The
moral, legal, and societal consequences of this are almost unimaginable.
Dancing around ways these challenges might be met, he points out in his Kaltes
Herz unendliche Fahrt (1989) that “every myth and every religious worldview—
whether Christian or not—protects the supreme moral convictions that ground
the consensus of its members through the act of sanction.”11 Sanctio, however,
not in the instrumental sense of a Rorty-like pragmatic hypothesis that we could
change tomorrow, but in the profoundly numinous sense of a normative principle
worth dying for—what Frank calls “an absolute value” and “justification” that
can motivate and inspire people to risk their own self-interest for a higher
cause.12 Remaining true to the spirit of Kant’s critical philosophy, the only
support Frank can offer for such “quasi-religious justificatory claims” are
counterfactual positions that speak only to that which is not yet, das
Seinsollende. This is what he calls a “quasi-religious dowry” of the
counterfactual, a practical hypothesis that is the necessary presupposition for
moral action (KM 99). Such “practical beliefs,” however, are not “the result of an
argumentative discourse,” since what rational discourse decides is always
fallible (KM 101). And it is in this sense that Frank appears quite close to the
position of the romantics who first diagnosed this problem, and whose
prescribed cure could only be communicated in religious terms and symbols,
specifically the idea of a new myth for a new religion.
The most captivating prescription to address this ill is the so-called “Oldest
System Program of German Idealism” (1797), which announces the advent of a
new religion whose text is nature, which, as living, provides the schema of our
freedom.13 Further developing his earlier writings in which he posits myth as the
“schematism of nature” (SW 1/1, 472), Schelling posits a new mythology of
nature, which in this new religion will usher in an era of harmony through (p.
215) the realization of the divine in nature. Connecting this new mythology with
Page 13 of 17
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
The New Mythology
his Naturphilosphie, he argues in his Philosophy of Art (1803) that “in the
philosophy of nature...the first, distant foundation has been laid for that future
symbolism and mythology” (SW 1/5, 449). The content of this symbolism and
mythology is “the world of ideas,” which, however, “are not objects of
speculation but of action, and to that extent objects of a future
experience...something that should be realized in reality” (SW 1/5, 451; SW 1/1,
465). Such ideas are rather straightforward when Schelling considers Kant’s
regulative ideas of soul, world (freedom), and God, all of which aim at the
unconditioned unity of human knowledge and action, but a quite different
challenge arises when he widens his kingdom of ends to include all of nature.
While acknowledging the problematic challenge of speaking to this possible
future, Schelling suggests that this “new religion” will announce itself “in the
rebirth of nature as the symbol of eternal unity,” since “in nature the life of the
newly arisen deity” will manifest itself (SW 1/5, 120). Although Schelling’s
substantive meaning here is far from clear, his words suggest Friedrich
Christoph Oetinger’s understanding of creation as the suffering body of Christ,
whose “annihilation” at the hands of our “economic-teleologic” desires echoes
Jesus’s crucifixion on the cross. In a more speculative sense, we can see in
Schelling’s use of the future an echo of his idea that the tense of the absolute
itself is the future—an understanding of a future that is not predetermined by its
past, but rather offers unseen possibilities and thus an open-ended orientation to
what should be (das Seinsollende). Embedded in the weaving of freedom into the
very fabric of living nature, Schelling’s teleology departs from the hindcasting of
the Aristotelian model in which the telos is already prefigured in its formal
cause. To say that futurity is the tense of the absolute is to acknowledge that the
living absolute is, just like every self-organizing system, incessantly engaged in
the process of stochastic development and further self-differentiation. As
Schelling’s account of creation in his early text on the Timaeus makes clear, it is
precisely this incessant creating that is complete, and completeness in this
process speaks to the possibility of the future as the arena in which what should
be is realized as what is.14 And it is in this sense that this new teleology might
support what I would like to call utopian thinking.
The denigration of the utopian vision in our own society illustrates the values of
our ruling order, which embraces not only the concrete and positivistic
restrictions of the empirically real and politically powerful, but even the
intelligentsia of the academy. Opting for the risk-free embrace of fragmentation
in the face of the alleged totalizing dangers of Grand Narratives, the very
scholars who should know better opt to repeat the mistakes of the last
generation of intellectuals who faced the growing threats of political fascism. I
am thinking of the criticism of nonaction Ernst Bloch directed at the Left of the
Weimar years, which he attributed to their inability to understand and take
seriously (p.216) both the power of people’s utopian longing and the power of
myth to satisfy and direct that longing. Bloch’s argument was that if the Nazis,
Page 14 of 17
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
The New Mythology
To counter this, I suggest the idea of a utopian imperative that demands our
world be measured according to principles and ideals, rather than utility and
profits. It demands the cultivation of a “utopian conscience” that realizes the
value and necessity of imagination and yes, even illusion, in creating a future
different than our past by employing the power of the imagination to critically
reject an inhibiting reality in favor of a vision of what could become a reality.16
And indeed it is this dimension of irreality in the utopian vision that has a
subversive and emancipatory power, and it is this anticipatory illumination of a
reality not yet made real that is a fundamental category of a utopian
philosophizing that appeared in the first years of romanticism.17 And it is
precisely this subversive power of utopian thinking that makes romanticism so
important. Not only do we envy their learning and culture, we envy their
strength and courage in daring to create alternative futures and to imagine a
unified and integrated world of man and nature, of science and Bildung. The
example of Schelling and his suggestive sketch of a “mythology of nature” would
serve us well as a foil for considering how a utopian imagination might not only
integrate religion and humanism, but also envision how symbols of a suffering
god may be replaced by symbols of a suffering world—a challenge an orthodox
Kantian might reject, but a challenge nonetheless to utopian fantasy to imagine
not just a kingdom of ends that admits only rational beings, but a kingdom of
ends that encompasses all of creation.
Notes:
(1) . Frederick Beiser, The Romantic Imperative (Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press, 2002) (hereafter RI), 151.
(2) . Manfred Frank, Ulrich Schnabel, and Thomas Assheuer, “Ein Gespräch mit
dem Tübinger Philosophen Manfred Frank über die Illusionen der Hirnforschung
und ihre zweifelhaften politischen Folgen,” Die Zeit, August 29, 2009. http://
www.zeit.de/2009/36/Hirnforschung.
Page 15 of 17
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
The New Mythology
(3) . Letter of September 4, 1797, in which he also asks for further works of
Ploucquet to aid his work on his Von der Weltseele: eine Hypothese der höheren
Physik (1798). Aus Schellings Leben, in Briefen, ed. G. L. Plitt, 3 vols. (Leipzig:
Herzel, 1869–70) (hereafter Plitt), vol. 1, 205ff.
(7) . “Poured from the source of things and the same as the source, the human
soul has a co-knowledge (Mitwissenschaft) of creation” (SW 1/8, 200).
(9) . Novalis supplies a similar account in 1800 when he writes, “We will
understand the world when we understand ourselves, since we and it are
integrated halves. Children of god, divine seeds are we. One day we will be what
our father is” (NS 2, 548).
(10) . Manfred Frank, Der kommende Gott: Vorlesungen über die Neue
Mythologie (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1982), 11.
Page 16 of 17
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
The New Mythology
(14) . But complete in this process of development does not mean the telos of
this process is completely determined, a situation that for Schelling could only
generate “complete boredom” (SW 1/1, 472).
(17) . Ernst Bloch, The Utopian Function of Art and Literature, trans. Jack Zipes
and Frank Mecklenburg (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1993), xxxv.
Page 17 of 17
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Mathematics, Computation, Language, and Poetry
Paul Redding
DOI:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199976201.003.0013
Once, Georg Philipp Friedrich von Hardenberg, better known under the nom de
plume “Novalis,” had provided a handy stereotype for the nineteenth-century
“romantic” poet—mystical, otherworldly, and fixated on death. Such a picture
was largely constructed after his own death at the age of twenty-eight around a
few episodes of his life, especially the death, at the age of fifteen, of his fiancée,
Sophie von Kühn, an event reflected in his perhaps most well-known work,
Hymns to the Night.1 More recently, however, the complexity of the actual
person has come to disrupt this nineteenth-century myth, and the interests,
Page 1 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Mathematics, Computation, Language, and Poetry
Even when traditional stereotypes of the “romantic” have been corrected by the
actual activities of the Jena romantics, there are still aspects of Hardenberg’s
interests and pursuits that can seem hard to reconcile with his status as a
romantic, however. Broadly, the Jena romantics had taken Kant’s critique of
metaphysics as a cue to raise the stakes of areas of culture such as religion and
art whose cognitive status had in many ways been threatened in modernity by,
among other factors, the rise of the mathematized natural sciences. Following
Kant they took it that metaphysics could not give us a theoretically determinate
picture of the way the world was “in itself,” but the human longing for this could
be satisfied to some degree by the indirect presentations of the world and our
place in it achievable within the arts and religion. This did not mean that the
romantics had rejected the natural sciences, and distinctly “romantic”
approaches to the sciences developed well into the first half of the nineteenth
century, especially in relation to the emerging sciences of the living world. But
romanticism, nevertheless, is usually understood as representing a reaction
against the “disenchantment” of nature—that “reduction of circumambient
nature to a mechanical system whose lineaments are provided by the immaterial
forms of mathematical physics”—and part of the attraction of the “life sciences”
consisted in the fact that they seemed to demand explanatory principles not
reducible to mechanical ones.3 However, seemingly at odds with this
anti-mechanistic tenor to romanticism in general was Hardenberg’s interest in
Page 2 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Mathematics, Computation, Language, and Poetry
Page 3 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Mathematics, Computation, Language, and Poetry
logic to an epistemology and a philosophy of mind, and at its heart was the idea
of an ars combinatoria or universal characteristic—an “alphabet of human
thoughts.”13 Somewhat like the way in which the idea of “analysis” functioned in
the early years of analytic philosophy, the primitive concepts of Leibniz’s
universal characteristic were regarded as the ultimate termini of a process of
analysis in which “clear and confused” ideas could be decomposed into (p.224)
their “clear and distinct” elements, represented in the universal characteristic
in a way that showed their essential logical connections. Such analytic and
synthetic transitions were determined by strictly definable mathematical rules of
combination and transformation, resulting in a hierarchy of forms from simple to
compound concepts to propositions and the inferential relations linking them. In
this way, an inventory of all knowledge would eventually be able to be produced
—a “rational encyclopedia.”
Thus in volume 2 of his Science of Logic, Subjective Logic, Hegel sets out the
key features of the Leibniz-Ploucquet approach to the structure of judgment that
allow the application of algebra to logic, associating it with the reduction of
thought to a mechanical process.15 Hegel’s attitude to the Leibniz-Ploucquet
mathematization of logic was critical but nuanced. The “mathematical
syllogisms” represents the point of collapse of the traditional Aristotelian
syllogistic, which is brought down under the negative effects of its own dialectic.
As such this mathematical logic played a necessary but purely negative role in
the dialectic of logical thought generally. The mathematical syllogism is a stage
Page 4 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Mathematics, Computation, Language, and Poetry
through which logical thought must progress, but taken as anything other than a
purely negative moment of this progression and regarded as itself a model of
thought, the mathematical syllogism was an absurdity, and had in turn to be
overcome in the characteristic move of the “negation of negation.”16
Page 5 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Mathematics, Computation, Language, and Poetry
Among the romantics, the nature of language was theorized at a high level of
abstraction in the hermeneutic project associated with the practice of
translation by Friedrich Schleiermacher, and an explicit attempt at a Kantian
linguistics applied to the grammars of actual language was found in the work of
Wilhelm von Humboldt.24 Kant himself had suggested the analogy between the
architectonic of the understanding and the grammar of a language,25 although
he had refrained from identifying the two. In this context it is natural that older
conceptions of a language of thought as found in Leibniz and others would be
revived, and from such a perspective the crucial question to be answered
becomes whether the language in which one thinks is, following Hamann (and,
perhaps, the later Wittgenstein), one’s particular language or, following
Humboldt (and, perhaps, Chomsky), some type of universal language implicit
within each particular language. But Hardenberg, I will argue, undercut the
assumption on which this dichotomy is based, the assumption that the mind is
restricted to the processes of any internalized language itself. When talk of
“mental representation” becomes mixed with that of linguistic representation
Hardenberg avoids the Hamann-Humboldt dichotomy by denying the equation of
mental content and linguistic sign, in a way that undermines the traditional view
that linguistic signs somehow “express” a determinate conceptual psychological
content. While for Hardenberg, traditional talk of inner concepts grasped
without the capacity for use of linguistic signs is refused, this does not imply that
thought itself was considered to be a type of inner speaking.
Page 6 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Mathematics, Computation, Language, and Poetry
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Mathematics, Computation, Language, and Poetry
from the “matter” of that to which they refer. That the word “chair” resembles
the word “pear” will be part of its material, and nothing like this resemblance is
found between the concepts or their worldly extensions. But similarly, these
nonrepresentational properties of words are going to be relevant to a
“combinatory” or “computationalist” approach to language, as the types of
“combinations and permutations” intended are meant to be applied mechanically
to “uninterpreted” symbols. We can see how the interests of the poet and the
computationalist might converge on this point, and a point of convergence can
indeed be found in the strange case of the combinatorial poetics of Erycius
Puteanus, a seventeenth-century humanist whose generation of multiple verses
to the Virgin Mary from a single eight-word poem came to the attention of
Leibniz and other theorists of mathematics and language.
An eight-word, one-line Latin hexameter—“Tot tibi sund doles, Virgo quot sidera
caelo (Thou has as many virtues, O Virgin, as there are starts in heaven)”—
published in 1615 by the Jesuit Bernard Bauhuis formed the base from which
Puteanus generated 1, 022 verse permutations (this number thought to be the
actual number of stars in the firmament) in a work published two years later.33
The number of possible permutations of the eight words is 40, 320 (the number 8
factorial) but of course not all of these permutations preserve the poem’s meter,
and various attempts were made by mathematicians during the seventeenth
century to exceed Puteanus’s number. The poem had been discussed in John
Wallis’s Tractatus de Algebra, and, although Wallis had not given a number for
the possible hexametric permutations, one reviewer of that work had suggested
2, 580. This reviewer is thought to have been Leibniz, who had discussed this
and other examples of such “proteus verses” in Dissertatio de Arte
Combinatoria.34 Leibniz here, however, gave no indication of how this number
had been estimated, and the issue was later taken up by Jacob Bernoulli, who
estimated the number at 3, 312 and showed how this number could be arrived at
from the classical laws governing the prosodic structure of hexametric verse.35
The problem of finding the principles for the generation of such proteus verses
represents a clear example of the search for a “syntactic engine” that can
generate an output of well-formed sentences according to entirely syntactic
laws. Here the relevant properties of the units are not their semantic ones, but
those nonsemantic ones that determine whether or not the “output” will scan in
the appropriate way. The convergence of computational and poetic principles
here is not coincidental.
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Mathematics, Computation, Language, and Poetry
only with itself....If it were only possible to make people understand that it is the
same with language as it is with mathematical formulae—they constitute a world
in itself—their play is self-sufficient, they express nothing but their own
marvelous nature.”36 It is this, seemingly “postmodern” aspect of Hardenberg’s
approach that denies some extralinguistic referent that is apparent in his Fichte
Studies, especially in relation to his criticism of Fichte’s account of the “I.”
In Kant, the concept “I” had been thought as a special type of concept that
captures the “transcendental unity of apperception.” It is a representation that
in the form of “I think” accompanies all of my representations, and that is
ultimately responsible for their unification into representations of a single
world.37 But the exact status of representations like this, Reinhold complained,
had never been clearly spelled out in Kant. Reinhold, as we have seen, treated
such mental “representations” as standing in a certain relation to both the
subject and the object of consciousness. Schulze (Aenesidemus) had interpreted
“representation” as referring to something like a sign or image—a typical
external representation that can be individuated without appeal to its
representational content. The skeptical question could then be put: how do we
know that such representations refer to any objects in the external world? As
Burge points out, this question cannot be posed in the “traditional view” as there
mental representations have no extrarepresentational properties that would
allow them to be individuated so that this question could be asked.38 Fichte’s
response to Schulz was then to reassert the traditional idea of the transparency
of a concept, at least for the case of the “I.” A thinker can recognize her own
thoughts as her own directly without any need for some intervening “sign.” Self-
consciousness does not depend on one’s ability to represent oneself with the sign
“I.” But this is just the view that Hardenberg challenges in his Fichte Studies.
Hardenberg’s notes here are nothing more than that, but the general drift of the
thought is the thesis that all “signifieds” of signs, the mental contents expressed
in signs, are, contrary to the traditional view, dependent for their identities on
the signs expressing them. But at the same time, the signs themselves, it would
seem, are identifiable as the signs they are only in that they express a mental
content: “The relationship of the sign to the signified. Both are in different
spheres that can mutually determine each another.”39 Given that Hardenberg’s
“sign” effectively translates what Ferdinand de Saussure was to later call
“signifier,” Hardenberg’s picture here approaches Saussure’s complex holistic
and differential account of language where differences among signifiers (p.230)
and differences among signifieds determine each other, ruling out the idea of
words expressing “concepts” as understood in the “traditional view.”40 Applied
to Fichte’s account of self-consciousness, this suggests that a being could only
be determinately conscious of itself to the extent that it could expresses itself
with the token “I,” suggesting that to be capable of intentionality, of mental
contents, the subject needs to be in some kind of communicative relation to
other subjects. Over a decade later, Hegel was to draw a similar lesson from
Page 9 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Mathematics, Computation, Language, and Poetry
It might be thought that with this Hardenberg has reverted to something like
Hamann’s idea that mental representations have the properties of “external”
representations, actual language. However, Hardenberg’s account is developed
in ways that, seemingly paradoxically, retain elements of the traditional
“transparency” view of mental content. The relation between sign and mental
content (sign and “signified”) will be different regarding whose mental state one
is considering in a communicative event. The suggestion clearly seems to be that
while for the speaker, at least considered in a particular way, the words
somehow do directly express essentially transparent thoughts, this cannot be the
case from the point of view of the person communicated to. “To the extent that
the signifying person is completely free either in the effect of the signified or in
the choice of signs, and not even dependent on his internally determined nature
—to that extent, the two [sign and signified] are interrelated for the signifying
person alone...[while] they are completely separate for a second signifying
person.”41 What I take this to mean is that from the first-person perspective,
speech must be considered as in the traditional view, with signs expressing
thoughts (signifieds) that are themselves somehow transparent and directly in
touch with the world, while for the other person this cannot be the case. For the
interlocutor, signs uttered by the other must be regarded first as elements of a
language, which has some sort of priority in the determination of the thought
being communicated. From the external point of view, language has to be taken
as a system in which the identity of each of the parts is determined by the way it
functions within the system. Our inner states must be expressed in language to
gain determinacy, but the determinacy found there can never be adequate to the
feel of those inner states themselves.
This complex account in which both elements of the traditional view and its
linguistic criticism are apparent in the later so-called logological fragments
where Hardenberg makes this point explicit, distinguishing between concepts
and words—a distinction that he describes as crucial for understanding the
nature of metaphysics and logic, and for the difficulty in bringing these two
disciplines together. Metaphysics, as the “pure dynamics of thinking” is
“concerned (p.231) with the soul of the philosophy of mind,” and metaphysical
concepts “relate to each other like thoughts, without words.”42 Hardenberg is
clearly aware as to the metaphysical strain that the idea of such wordless
thoughts commits one, as is revealed in the comment from the Fichte Studies:
“What kind of a relation is knowledge? It is a being outside of being that is
nevertheless within being....Consciousness is consequently an image of being
within being.” But then he corrects “image” with “sign,” and the theory of signs
Page 10 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Mathematics, Computation, Language, and Poetry
Page 11 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Mathematics, Computation, Language, and Poetry
In 1677 Leibniz was to write a dialogue on this very dispute, accepting Hobbes’s
view of the existence of mental characters with no intrinsic similarity to what
they signify, using the mathematical example of the lack of any resemblance
between “0” and nothing.53 But he wanted of course to avoid the type of
semantic skepticism of which Descartes accused Hobbes, and used a version of
Descartes’s appeal to clear and distinct ideas, but now such that these coincided
Page 12 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Mathematics, Computation, Language, and Poetry
with the final products of logical decomposition. But as Maat has pointed out,
Leibniz was himself troubled by doubts about the coherence of the notion of an
essentially thinkable atomic terminus of analysis. If a notion, call it A, is
essentially thinkable, then it would seem that it must be capable of further
analysis: it must be able to be analyzed into a component specific to its being A,
and the concept “thinkability” that it will have in common with all other
concepts.54 It would be considerations such as these that were behind later
idealist critiques of what is now known as the “Myth of the Given” and that has
its prototype in Kant’s insistence, noted above, that all representations, in order
to be representations, be accompanied by the concept “I,” the concept of the
thinker for whom they are representations.55
Page 13 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Mathematics, Computation, Language, and Poetry
Fichte Studies, “sign” (or for Saussure, “signifier”) and signified are “in different
spheres that can mutually determine each another.”58 Signs do not have
meaning in as much that they express “concepts” and thereby determinately
apply to “things” in the world. They have meaning to the extent that stoffliche
differences among them can determine differences within the realm of meaning
and use. Such words can be “played” according to their identities as signifiers so
as to transform the system of signifieds. Thus the idea of poetry as
“meaningless” melody does not capture the sense in which the elements are
words and not notes, elements that cannot be entirely stripped of semantic
properties and have only a syntax. For this reason we might be skeptical of those
(such as Dalhaus)59 who place “Novalis” here in the tradition of other romantics,
such as Ludwig Tieck and E. T. A. Hoffman, who are seen as pointing to a
conception of poetry as aspiring “towards the condition of music” (as Pater later
put it),60 and a conception of music as “absolute music”—music totally freed
from the constraints of language and representation.
Notes:
(1) . Hardenberg’s personal loss had been doubled by the death of a brother,
Erasmus, a month later.
Page 14 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Mathematics, Computation, Language, and Poetry
(4) . For a systematic treatment of this theme in the work of Novalis, see John
Neubauer, Symbolismus und symbolische Logik (Munich: Wilhelm Fink Verlag,
1978).
(5) . In general, positive reception of Leibniz’s work among the romantics had
centered on its quasi-vitalistic, antimechanistic dimensions. Frederick Beiser,
The Romantic Imperative: The Concept of Early German Romanticism
(Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2003), 143–44. Those aspects of
Leibniz’s work celebrated by the proponents of contemporary computationalist
approaches to the mind seem very different.
(6) . Thus Hobbes, in a work of 1656, declares that “by ratiocination, I mean
computation. Now to compute, is either to collect the sum of many things that
are added together, or to know what remains when one thing is taken out of
another. ... all ratiocination is comprehended in these two operations of the
mind, addition and subtraction.” Hobbes, “Elements of Philosophy,” in The
English Works of Thomas Hobbes of Malmesbury, ed. Sir William Molesworth,
vol. 1 (London: John Bohn, 1839), 3.
(7) . See George Dyson, Turing’s Cathedral: The Origins of the Digital Universe
(New York: Random House, 2012); Ronald Hausser, Computational Linguistics
and Talking Robots (Berlin: Springer, 2011), and Martin Davis, The Universal
Computer: The Road from Leibniz to Turing (New York: Norton, 2000).
(12) . Donald Knuth, The Art of Computer Programming, vol. 4, Generating All
Trees: History of Combinatorial Generation (Upper Saddle River, NJ: Pearson
Education, 2006); Paul J. Nahin, The Logician and the Engineer: How George
Page 15 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Mathematics, Computation, Language, and Poetry
Boole and Claude Shannon Created the Information Age (Princeton: Princeton
University Press, 2013).
(14) . Hans Niels Jahnke, “Mathematics and Culture: The Case of Novalis,”
Science in Context 4 (1991): 279–95.
(19) . Jere Paul Surber, ed. Metacritique: The Linguistic Assault on German
Idealism (Amherst: Humanity Books, 2001), 58.
(20) . Questions of who influenced whom in these regards are complex and
contested. See, for example, Katie Terezakis, The Immanent Word: The Turn to
Language in German Philosophy, 1759–1801 (New York: Routledge, 2007) and
Michael Forster, After Herder: Philosophy of Language in the German Tradition
Page 16 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Mathematics, Computation, Language, and Poetry
(25) . Immanuel Kant, Prolegomena To Any Future Metaphysics ed. and trans.
Gary Hatfield (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004, §39
(26) . Novalis, Fichte Studies, ed. and trans. Jane Kneller (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2003), no. 226.
(28) . In Kant’s account, the application of concept to thing is never direct but
always mediated by an intuition.
(32) . Cf., “A poem should not mean / But be.” Archibald MacLeish, Ars Poetica,
in Collected Poems 1917–1982 (Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1985 [1926]), 106.
(33) . The work was, Pietatis Thaumata in Bernardi Bauhusii e Societate Jesu
Proteum Parthenium.
(34) . Donald Knuth (The Art of Computer Programming) discusses this in the
context of the evolution of computer science. Neubauer notes that Novalis was
interested in the similar phenomenon of “Bouts-rimé” (Neubauer, Symbolismus
und symbolische Logik, 140).
Page 17 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Mathematics, Computation, Language, and Poetry
(39) . Novalis, Fichte Studies, no. 11. Hardenberg’s concept of “sign” effectively
equates to what Saussure was to call the “signifier”, i.e., the sign grasped in
terms of its nonrepresentational properties. The striking similarities between the
views of Saussure and Hardenberg are pursued in Gasparov, Beyond Pure
Reason.
(40) . Saussure, Course in General Linguistics, trans. Wade Baskin, ed. Perry
Meisel and Haun Saussy (New York: Columbia University Press, 2011 [1916]).
(42) . Novalis, Philosophical Writings, trans. and ed. Margaret Mahony Stoljar
(Albany: State University of New York Press, 1997), 51.
(45) . Hilary Putnam, Representation and Reality (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1988),
21.
(48) . Maat, Philosophical Languages, 313. Cf., “In Leibniz’s view, the power of a
symbolism does not reside in the individual symbols, but in the systematical
relations the symbols have to each other and to the things they designate. Hence
Leibniz’s central concern in his efforts to construct a philosophical language is
to establish a perfect conformity between its semantic and syntactic
aspects” (Maat, 309–10).
Page 18 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Mathematics, Computation, Language, and Poetry
(52) . Descartes opposition to the idea that “ideas” would have their own
nonrepresentational properties is, of course, consistent with his mind-body
dualism.
(57) . For example, some languages such as English will distinguish word-types
according to whether they start with the sounds distinguished in English as “p”
and “b,” but in other languages this “voicing” of the consonant will not
differentiate meanings at all and so be inaudible.
(59) . Carl Dalhaus, The Idea of Absolute Music, trans. Roger Lustig (Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 1989), 145.
(60) . Walter Pater, The Renaissance: Studies in Art and Poetry (Berkeley:
University of California Press, 1980), 106.
(61) . I wish to thank Dalia Nassar for helpful feedback on an earlier version of
this essay. My thanks also go to Frances Massey, with whom I have had many
illuminating discussions on topics touched on here.
Page 19 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Friedrich Schlegel’s Romantic Calculus
John H. Smith
DOI:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199976201.003.0014
Page 1 of 20
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Friedrich Schlegel’s Romantic Calculus
Page 2 of 20
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Friedrich Schlegel’s Romantic Calculus
Page 3 of 20
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Friedrich Schlegel’s Romantic Calculus
Calculus) of 1755 Euler argued for a deep ambivalence: infinitesimals are both
nothing and something. In the preface to his book he claims first:
As Sandifer points out, Euler seems to want it both ways. Indeed, this was the
way differentials were often treated, for example, by Newton and Leibniz: as
existing quantities so that they could be manipulated in equations, but then
disregarded as equivalent to zero in order to produce the final results.
Lazarus Ben David (often also Bendavid, 1762–1832) comes down on the side of
Euler in seeing infinitesimal magnitudes as equal to zero but also grapples with
the problem of representation and intuition.6Although he wrote on a variety of
philosophical topics, of particular interest here is his Versuch einer logischen
Auseinandersetzung des mathematischen Unendlichen (Essay on the Logical
Analysis of the Mathematical Infinite) of 1789. Maimon must have been aware of
it prior to its publication since, as we shall see, he responds to it already in his
own Versuch. Like so many others, Ben David addresses the awkwardness of the
situation in which a science like calculus rests on a concept that has no clear
definition. Indeed, the more successful calculus is, the greater the need to
understand its fundamental principles: “the greater the advantages are that
calculus affords us, and the more its results concur with those that had been
found by other means, the more desirous we become to establish the principles
out of which this calculus and its results emerge.”7 The problem with the
particular concept of the infinite is that it cannot be intuited or represented, its
Evidenz is not constructed as in geometry; therefore it requires logical analysis
(Bendavid xxx–xxxi).8 He proceeds by looking at the nature of numbers and
defining them as manifolds that are gathered in a unity (Bendavid §18).
Whatever is finite (“endlich”) can be measured, is “meßbar” (Bendavid §19). An
infinite magnitude, therefore, is one for which no number can be found that can
be a measure for it, and he concludes that “the mathematician calls every
magnitude, which cannot be expressed through numbers, infinite” (Bendavid
§18). Since neither the infinitely small nor infinitely large “can be given in terms
of number or measure; and it cannot be represented using any means that we
Page 4 of 20
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Friedrich Schlegel’s Romantic Calculus
(p.243)
The infinite has only the quality of being an immeasurable quantity, but is used
analogously in calculations as if it were a quantity (Bendavid §44). The infinite is
thus like an intensive magnitude that cannot be increased or decreased as such
(although something else can be measured, like the rise of mercury in a
thermometer) (Bendavid §48–49).
A somewhat different position was represented by one of the more widely read
mathematicians—in part because of his textbooks—of the second half of the
eighteenth century, Abraham Gotthelf Kästner (1719–1800).9 He points out in his
Anfangsgründe der Analysis des Unendlichen (Foundations of the Analysis of the
Infinite) that the “mysteries” and “inconsistencies” that so many authors have
produced around the concept of infinity arise “whenever one views an infinite
magnitude as something really existing”; instead, one needs to conceive
“magnitudes that grow or diminish [as] undetermined/indefinite [unbestimmt]”
and thus, strictly speaking, as not a number.10 And indeed he refers positively to
Euler in the preface to the second edition of 1770 (Kästner xvi). In a manner that
will lead in the nineteenth century to a formulation of the foundations of calculus
that does away with infinitesimals altogether, he understands the infinitely small
or large relationship between dx and dy in terms of limits (Kästner 52–54).
However, he refers to Leibniz’s expression “toleranter vera” (a tolerable truth)
that does permit us to speak of “the infinite as something real” (Kästner 52).
That is, Kästner is referring to the fact that although given his metaphysics of
monads Leibniz had argued for the reality of infinitesimal magnitudes, he later
came to see them as “necessary fictions.” Thus, though using somewhat
different arguments than Euler, Kästner also ends up revealing the paradox of
the mathematical infinite—it exists and does not exist—which leads him to
suggest accepting the “manner of speaking” (“Redensart”) which is “tolerably
true” (“erträglich wahr”): “The relationship between infinitely small magnitudes,
which can be given in terms of finite magnitudes” (Kästner 54). The
unrepresentable (infinitely small or large magnitudes) can be represented as
necessary fictions and tolerable truths.11
Page 5 of 20
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Friedrich Schlegel’s Romantic Calculus
But to see how Schlegel could make such an extraordinary claim, we should
return to Maimon, for his response to basic problems in Kant introduced the
mathematical infinite into consciousness itself.12 Maimon’s argument is, indeed,
very difficult to grasp at times, for he himself was aware of his limitations as an
autodidact in philosophy and as a nonnative speaker of German (since he came
from a Jewish family in Lithuania). At its core, his argument seems to be a
rethinking of Kant with a commitment to the reality of the infinitesimal, and to
the infinitesimal nature of reality for consciousness. We can state it this way: the
act of synthesizing that Kant had considered consciousness’s contribution to the
production of knowledge is interpreted by Maimon in terms of the twin notions
of the differential and the integral. While for Kant, knowledge as experience
comes about by the two steps of first subsuming the manifold of sense data
under the forms of intuition to make representations and then subsuming these
representations under the categories provided by the understanding, Maimon
argues in a way more consistent with Leibniz and Wolff that there is an infinite
gradation of consciousness. At the “lower end” of the continuum—and it is a
continuum in a mathematical sense—we have the “primitive consciousness of a
constituent part of a synthesis” (which he calls a “presentation” [Vorstellung])
and at the “upper end” we have the “consciousness of the completed
synthesis” (Maimon 181). These two are “limit concepts” or “mere
ideas” (Maimon 181) in that by definition there would be no object of knowledge
whatever if there were no consciousness, that is, if consciousness were reduced
to zero; and likewise, only an “infinite consciousness” (God) could possibly attain
full knowledge of how any object could be synthesized (p.245)
Page 6 of 20
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Friedrich Schlegel’s Romantic Calculus
Page 7 of 20
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Friedrich Schlegel’s Romantic Calculus
the variables x and y as dx and dy, each of which may be considered = 0 but in
their relations have determinate values and thus give rise to the gradation of
experiences: “These differentials of objects are the so-called noumena; but the
objects themselves arising from them are the phenomena. With respect to
intuition = 0, the differential of any object in itself is dx = 0, dy = 0 etc.;
however, their relations are not = 0, but can rather be given determinately in
the intuitions arising from them” (Maimon 21). Consciousness is constantly
active in constructing reality out of, or perhaps better, as, relations between
perceptions. The greater the conscious activity, the more we are aware of our
contribution to this construction. As consciousness diminishes or approaches
zero we do not recognize our own activity at the level of perception. While it is
still a synthesis “in” us, it appears to come from the “outside”—a term that is not
to be understood spatially but as “not part of our consciousness,” since the
conscious activity approaches zero. That sense of something “beyond” our
consciousness as a limit idea would be the “thing in itself.” But because it makes
no sense for us to talk about our consciousness ever reaching that zero point,
the perceptions can always be “added up” (integrated) so that we become
increasingly aware of them. Maimon makes the comparison with physics and one
of the primary uses of calculus: “Just as, for example, with an accelerated
movement, the preceding velocity does not disappear, but ever joins itself onto
the following ones, so that an ever increasing velocity arises, so equally the first
sensible representation does not disappear, but ever joins itself onto the
following ones, until the degree necessary for consciousness is
reached” (Maimon 20–21). This “joining” of minimal sensations by consciousness
is understood as the integrating of an infinity of infinitesimal differential
relations.15 Maimon has thereby defined consciousness as an entity that
synthesizes a reality across a continuum ranging between the limits of zero
(receptivity) and infinity (totality of all relations in thought), without ever
reaching them. Although finite in nature, consciousness nonetheless works with
the infinitely small and infinitely large in paradoxical yet powerful ways in order
to produce conceptual knowledge. In a sense, consciousness is like the
mathematicians who depend on notions of the infinitesimal and infinity to
produce effective results even though, from the perspective (p.247) of their
discipline around 1800, they cannot fully explain them in terms of their finite
tools.
Page 8 of 20
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Friedrich Schlegel’s Romantic Calculus
he undoubtedly heard a good deal about it), or delved deeply into calculus, or
employed its concepts rigorously, we can see how it permeates and frames his
thought.
The key problematic for Schlegel, namely the relationship of the absolute and
the individual, is captured in his questions “on the answer to which everything
depends”: “Why has the infinite come out of itself and made itself finite?—that is
in other words: Why are there individuals?—Or: Why does the play of nature not
run itself out in an instant, so that nothing would exist?” (KA 12, 39).18 He is in
many ways the romantic thinker of the infinite, or, to state the inverse, the
infinite is the key issue that he attempts to capture. While undoubtedly this
concept enters into his thought via Spinoza and Fichte, we can hear clearly in
these questions Leibniz, and with him then enters the mathematical infinite.19
That is, the questions he is posing are versions of the debate about the
continuous and the discrete, the infinitely large and the infinitely small, and the
emergence of reality out of differentials, which seem to both exist and not exist
at the same time. By considering the introduction of the mathematical infinite
into philosophy not as a cause for reason’s dialectic with itself but as an
explanation of consciousness’s construction of reality, we can understand how
Schlegel can offer an answer to his questions: The infinite has entered into, or is
always already within, the finite just as calculus employs differentials,
infinitesimals, and their infinite integration in order to explore the world of
constant change. The paradoxes of the ill-defined or at least highly ambivalent
methods of the new mathematics resonate for Schlegel and make the infinite in
his thought productive. It has consequences for his considerations of method,
consciousness, the task of overcoming dualisms, and the nature of philosophy
itself.
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Friedrich Schlegel’s Romantic Calculus
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Friedrich Schlegel’s Romantic Calculus
besides the point here, since we do not make use of infinity to think the
object, but merely to think the way it arises.
(Maimon 143)22
Page 11 of 20
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Friedrich Schlegel’s Romantic Calculus
If both being and consciousness, and their relationship, are constructed out of
the infinite gradations of and between the zero and the one, this has
consequences for the nature of philosophy itself. Thus, we encounter the
dialectic of the one and the many in a familiar form. On the one hand, “All
knowing is infinite. It is an indivisible totality.” But on the other, “[Philosophy’s]
divisibility is arbitrary,” by which he does not so much mean random as, rather,
infinite, or, perhaps more precisely, indeterminate in degree (KA 12, 10). In a
way that anticipates Hegel, Schlegel here does not so much “resolve” a Kantian
antinomy as embrace it thanks to a turn to the mathematical infinite. The “one”
of infinity can also be approximated by the infinite synthesis (integration) of
infinitesimals. That he is indeed thinking in terms of “magnitudes” we can see
from the otherwise odd formulation that philosophy is infinite in the sense of
Page 12 of 20
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Friedrich Schlegel’s Romantic Calculus
“intensive as well as extensive” (KA 12, 9). And this has the further consequence
“that the most perfect/complete system can only be by approximation” (KA 12,
9). If philosophy is infinite, as knowledge is infinite, then we are also driven by
an infinite skepticism (KA 12, 9; recall his praise of Maimon). The longing and
striving for the infinite (“Streben” or “Sehnsucht nach dem Unendlichen,” KA
12, 8, 11) that drive the philosopher and that the philosopher must awaken in
others, is therefore closer to discussions of irrational numbers than antirational
feelings.
Thus, for Schlegel the way to address the fundamental dualisms that preoccupy
his, and indeed all post-Kantian, thought—dogmatism and empiricism, reality
and consciousness, absolute and individual—is through the tools of
mathematical thinking (not necessarily the rigors of mathematical proof). This
conclusion is rooted in the nature of such thinking, for just before the previous
quote on the elements of mathematics he states: “If one combines dualism and
theory, a science would emerge that does not have phenomena as its point of
departure but, rather, elements. This is mathematics. It is so to speak a dualism
a priori” (KA 12, 15). Mathematical reasoning about the infinite is so important
to him because it allows him to think through the dualism in its pure
relationality. “All reality is the product of opposing elements” (KA 12, 8) in the
sense of the infinitely small and the infinitely large that, then, converge with
each other. Thus we can understand how Schlegel arrives at what he calls “our
formula now (p.252) from a positive perspective”: “the minimum of the I is
equal to the maximum of nature; and the minimum of nature is equal to the
maximum of the I. That is, the smallest sphere of consciousness is equal to the
largest of nature, and vice versa” (KA 12, 6). What might sound like a playful
paradox coming from the philosopher of irony is rooted in the discussions
around the antinomies associated with the infinitesimal. He formulates the task
of idealism in terms that echo fully Maimon’s uses of the differential relation to
explain Kant’s anticipations of perception and reality: “The philosopher
(idealism) deals with the minimum and the maximum, and physics with the finite
members between reality and the elements of an infinite progression of
proportions” (KA 12, 17).
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Friedrich Schlegel’s Romantic Calculus
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Friedrich Schlegel’s Romantic Calculus
Notes:
(1) . Salomon Maimon, Essay on Transcendental Philosophy, trans. Nick Midgley,
Henry Somers-Hall, Alistair Welchman, and Merten Reglitz (New York:
Continuum, 2010), 19 n. 1. Hereafter cited as “Maimon” in the body of the text.
In his Logic (1812) Hegel also argues for the significance of the mathematical
infinite in terms that echo Maimon’s: “But in a philosophical respect the
mathematical infinite is important because underlying it, in fact, is the notion of
the genuine infinite and it is far superior to the ordinary so-called metaphysical
infinite on which are based the objections to the mathematical infinite.” Georg
Friedrich Wilhelm Hegel, Wissenschaft der Logik, in Werke in zwanzig Bänden,
ed. K. Michel E. Moldenhauer (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1969), 280.
Hereafter cited as “Hegel” in the body of the text.
Page 15 of 20
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Friedrich Schlegel’s Romantic Calculus
(7) . Lazarus Ben David, Versuch einer logischen Auseinandersetzung über das
mathematische Unendliche (Berlin: Petit und Schöne, 1789), 23. Hereafter cited
as “Bendavid” in the body of the text.
(11) . This is just a very small sampling of the wealth of work done in these years
on the topic. In addition to the separate textbooks, there was also the 1786
Preisfrage of the Prussian Academy to provide a clear and precise treatment of
the mathematical infinite. Related to this issue was also the Preisfrage of 1782 to
derive notions of calculus from Euclidean geometry. The concern there was the
central one of whether the new notions of the infinite could be grasped with
intuition (like geometry) or needed to be “constructed.”
Page 16 of 20
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Friedrich Schlegel’s Romantic Calculus
(12) . The contribution that Maimon made to the history of modern philosophy
has been well documented over the last twenty years. Manfred Frank devotes
over two lectures to him in his Unendliche Annäherung but he makes no mention
of the mathematics in his otherwise excellent discussion. Beiser claims that
Maimon’s work is “of the first importance for the history of post-Kantian
idealism,” and he offers a brief discussion of the “difficult” theory of
differentials. Frederick Beiser, The Fate of Reason: German Philosophy from
Kant to Fichte (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993), 286. A number
of Maimon scholars have argued that he be considered seriously in his own right
and not just as a middle figure (S. H. Bergman, The Philosophy of Solomon
Maimon [Jerusalem: Magnes, 1967]; Jan Bransen, The Antinomy of Thought:
Maimonian Skepticism and the Relation between Thoughts and Objects
[Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1991]). However, few address why the
notion of the mathematical infinite can shift our perspective on fundamental
problems in philosophy. And while others address his use of the differential, no
one has sought to locate him within the discussions of the period. Exceptions are
recent discussions by Simon Duffy and Daniel W. Smith (in Sjoerd van Tuinen
and Niamh McDonnell, eds., Deleuze and the Fold: A Critical Reader [New York:
Palgrave Macmillan, 2010]), spurred by interest in Deleuze’s work on Leibniz
and mathematics. The one commentator to devote a monograph on Maimon and
mathematics is Buzaglo, who offers a very brief discussion of the pertinent
sections of Chapter 2 of the Versuch, only to claim that the notion of the
differential is not relevant. See Meir Buzaglo, Solomon Maimon: Monism,
Skepticism and Mathematics (Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press, 2002),
125. Freudenthal provides a very rich reading, recognizing at the outset that
“Maimon’s philosophy is imbued with mathematics.” Gideon Freudenthal,
“Maimon’s Philosophical Program. Understanding versus Intuition,”
Internationales Jahrbuch des Deutschen Idealismus/International Yearbook of
German Idealism 8 (2010), 83.
Page 17 of 20
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Friedrich Schlegel’s Romantic Calculus
(15) . Given his position that the differential is an infinitely small quantum,
which can never be zero but is only a “limit concept” of consciousness and the
activity of consciousness in constituting reality, it is not by chance that Maimon
offers a spirited critique of his friend and supporter, Ben David, for mistakenly
taking Euler’s position that dx = 0. In the first part of the appendix to his
Versuch, Maimon includes an essay “On Symbolic Cognition and Philosophical
Language” (Maimon 139–72) that demonstrates the role of the mathematicians
we have explored in his philosophical investigations. Differentials constitute a
particular kind of “nothing that mathematicians nevertheless make into an
object of their cognition because of the universality of their calculus” (Maimon
150). They must be thought of as infinitely small, “but this does not make them
any less real” (Maimon 152). Ben David, in defining “the infinitely small = the
infinitely large = 0” fails “to distinguish precisely these different types of
nothing from one another” (Maimon 152). Instead, Maimon suggests, one should
turn to another mathematician, for “it is only necessary to read a
Kästner” (Maimon 150). See below on parallels between Maimon and Schlegel
on such “symbolic cognition” of such nonrepresentables as infinitesimals.
Furthermore, Maimon’s argument makes use of Kant’s later discussions in the
Critique of Pure Reason of the “anticipations of perception” and reveals the
power of the mathematical infinite beyond what Kant himself could see.
(17) . Brauers and Zeuch explore Schlegel and the infinite, also in relation to the
Western tradition. Chaouli discusses Schlegel and chemistry. See Claudia
Brauers, Perspektiven des Unendlichen. Friedrich Schlegels ästhetische
Vermittlungstheorie (Berlin: Ernst Schmidt Verlag, 1996) and Ulrike Zeuch, Das
Unendliche: Höchste Fülle oder Nichts? Zur Problematik von Friedrich Schlegels
Geist-Begriff und dessen geistesgeschichtlichen Voraussetzungen (Würzburg:
Königshausen und Neumann, 1991).
(18) . See Dalia Nassar, “Schelling und die Frühromantik: Das Unendliche und
das Endliche im Kunstwerk,” http://www.academia.edu/656856/
Schelling_und_die_Fruhromantik_Das_Unendliche_und_das_Endliche_im_Kunstwerk
Page 18 of 20
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Friedrich Schlegel’s Romantic Calculus
(accessed April 20, 2013), for a discussion of Schlegel on the absolute in relation
to Schelling and poetry.
(19) . Consider the footnote near the end of the introduction to his lectures:
“Zwischen Spinoza und Fichte liegt Leibnitz in der Mitte” (KA 12, 30). Also John
H. Smith, “Leibniz Reception around 1800: Monadic Vitalism and Harmony in
Schleiermacher’s Reden über die Religion and Schlegel’s Lucinde,” in Religion,
Reason, and Culture in the Age of Goethe, ed. Elizabeth Kimmerer and Patricia
Simpson (Rochester, NY: Camden House, 2013).
(20) . See also the many variation on this formula, such as: “√χα/0 = Gott” (the
square root of chaos divided by zero, i.e. infinite chaos; KA 18, 238, no. 540) or
even wilder: “Gott = 1/0 √χα1/0/0” (the infinite root of chaos to the infinite power
divided by 0; KA 18, 277, no. 999). Or also: “Der Monolog ein 1/0√Dialog1/0” (KA
18, 199, no. 34).
(24) . See also the fragment from the time of the lectures: “Continuity is the
character of all that is idealist [alles Idealistischen]” (KA 18, 363, no. 504).
(26) . As Thiel reminds us: “In terms of the history of philosophy and of
mathematics it is noteworthy that out of notions of the infinitesimal, which were
often attacked as imprecise, a philosophy of the mathematics of the infinite
arose in the eighteenth century, a ‘metaphysics of infinitesimal calculus.’ And a
rich body of literature was produced that argued often in the style of its
founders, like Leibniz, who....saw through infinitesimals as fictions and yet,
rather than eliminate them, justified them by analogies.” Christian Thiel,
Page 19 of 20
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Friedrich Schlegel’s Romantic Calculus
Page 20 of 20
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
The “Mathematical” Wissenschaftslehre
David W. Wood
DOI:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199976201.003.0015
Page 1 of 16
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
The “Mathematical” Wissenschaftslehre
For a romantic figure, one could ask: why was Novalis interested in these
abstract and complex fields of thought? As we will see with Fichte, the late
fragments of Novalis show his interest to have been much more of a
philosophical (p.259) one, and he above all attempted to grasp the reciprocal
interactions between the symbolic languages and methods of philosophy and
mathematics. Or in the words of the historian of mathematics, Hans Niels
Jahnke, it was mathematics as the “symbol of a higher unity of knowledge” that
appealed to Novalis.5
Page 2 of 16
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
The “Mathematical” Wissenschaftslehre
exposed certain lacunae, such as the lack of critical attention paid to the later
philosophical writings of Novalis.
Although Novalis’s encyclopedia project remained incomplete and was put aside
in March 1799, its guiding philosophical idea of a single universal science can
still be found in Novalis’s postencyclopedia writings, including the 1799 essay
“Christendom or Europe”.10 It is similarly present in 1800 toward the end of the
final “Fragments and Studies”, where philosophy only becomes “truly visible”
within the finished system of all the sciences: “[Philosophy] is the undetermined
science of the sciences—a mysticism of the drive for knowledge on the whole—
the spirit of science as it were....Thus all the sciences are interrelated—and
philosophy will never be completed. Only in the perfect system of all the
sciences will philosophy become truly visible” (NS 3, 666). This final systematic
form of philosophy for Novalis is therefore a regulative ideal in the (p.260)
Kantian sense, because we can approach it but never fully attain it. Or it can be
conceived as similar to the Fichtean idea of a vocation (Bestimmung): philosophy
can never be completed, nor can it ever appear in concreto. Hence in addition to
the terms “romantic philosophy,” or “magical idealism,” Novalis’s system of
thought in these later fragments may also be characterized as a form of
“encyclopedic philosophy.” Comparing his idea with Fichte’s goal to make the
Wissenschaftslehre into a “science of the sciences” or with Hegel’s
Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences we see that Novalis likewise shares
this striving for a system of universal knowledge with the German idealists.
Unlike philosophy, which only becomes visible after the unification of all the
sciences, mathematics is already a visible and useful instrument, because the
objects of mathematics are initially found in the visible sense world. This
Page 3 of 16
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
The “Mathematical” Wissenschaftslehre
Page 4 of 16
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
The “Mathematical” Wissenschaftslehre
This question could be preceded by another one: did Fichte himself think the
Wissenschaftslehre to be mathematical? One has to give an affirmative answer
to this question. In fact, beginning with the discovery of the Wissenschaftslehre
in the winter of 1793–94, where he saw himself as a sort of modern Euclid, right
up until his final lectures in the winter of 1813–14, Fichte repeatedly argued for
the Wissenschaftslehre’s close affinity and even at times its identity with
mathematics.19 Why did Fichte equate his philosophy with mathematics? This is
because for him they shared a number of crucial “distinctions” or characteristics
in common. First, he considered the first postulate of his system, like those in
geometry, to be wholly self-evident to the unprejudiced thinker. Second, genuine
intellectual intuition for him was similar to mathematical intuition because the
act of thinking about oneself possesses a universal validity that holds for every
rational being, regardless of the language, signs, or symbols we choose to use.
The language or signs are only external assistances to arrive at an internal
intuition of the self. Third, again like in Euclidean geometry, Fichte’s starting
point or first postulate was unprovable and therefore logically “irrefutable”; that
Page 5 of 16
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
The “Mathematical” Wissenschaftslehre
is because for Fichte all refuting and disproving are confined to the sphere of
conceptual operations.
Apart from Kant and Spinoza, Fichte rarely compared his philosophy directly to
other systems in philosophical history; yet on account of its similarly profound
commitment to idealism, he saw Plato’s philosophy as a forerunner to his own:
“Among the Greeks, Plato was on this path to the Wissenschaftslehre....among
the ancient philosophers Plato may have had an inkling [of our view]” (GA 1/9,
73, 110). This Platonist component of Fichte’s thought is particularly evident in
his theory of “original” geometry from 1805, which is based on absolute, ideal,
and infinite elements that have to be grasped in geometric intuition, and which
he set in opposition to the “ordinary” geometry of Euclid.23 Novalis was one of
the first thinkers to detect this Platonist or Neoplatonist heritage in the Fichtean
system, when in 1798 he briefly cited the “idealistic similarity” between Fichte
and Plotinus.24 Fichte’s idealistic proximity to the Platonic stream was finally
Page 6 of 16
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
The “Mathematical” Wissenschaftslehre
Page 7 of 16
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
The “Mathematical” Wissenschaftslehre
Page 8 of 16
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
The “Mathematical” Wissenschaftslehre
Of course, Novalis and Fichte realize there are limits to our problem-solving
abilities in mathematics and philosophy. The unknown is not always attained (p.
266) from out of the known, and sometimes we fail to uncover the right answer,
or a problem simply cannot be solved. We therefore need a science to
consciously reflect on these methodological limits, whose origin lies in a
reflection on the limits and nature of the activity of problem-solving itself. This is
entirely in the spirit of Kant’s critical philosophy, which is a science reflecting on
the limits and boundaries of pure thought. This critical approach should be
adopted with regard to mathematics, resulting in a discipline that takes over
where ordinary mathematics leaves off, a transcendental or meta-discipline
explaining why ordinary mathematics reaches and runs up against certain limits,
as well as explaining the very conditions of its possibility. In other words, there
is a necessity for a genuine philosophy of mathematics, a discipline that had not
yet been sufficiently established during the idealistic and romantic period. With
his cognitive reflections on the nature and possibility of mathematical activity it
is obvious that Fichte considered the Wissenschaftslehre as being able to
contribute to such a disciple. Fichte writes in 1804,
One could argue that what is particularly “Fichtean” about some of the late
fragments of Novalis is that he seems to agree with Fichte that the methods of
the Wissenschaftslehre could provide a framework for a kind of proto-philosophy
of mathematics. Novalis here made a direct comparison between Fichte and the
French mathematician Georges-Louis Le Sage, who was trying to introduce
rigorous “speculative” and mechanistic models into physics: “The
Wissenschaftslehre is nothing more than a proof of the reality of logic—its
harmony with the rest of nature and [it is] completely analogous to mathematics
with regard to its discoveries, its rectifications—and to what it can achieve. (Le
Sage has accomplished something similar in mathematics)” (NS 3, 559). For
Novalis, the Wissenschaftslehre’s method of inwardly directing one’s attention to
the activities of the mind during the constructing of the self could serve as a
Page 9 of 16
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
The “Mathematical” Wissenschaftslehre
Attempt to prove and solve this [i.e., the functions of the analytic and
synthetic methods in mathematics]—to construct what mathematics fails to
prove or solve—the Wissenschaftslehre of mathematics. The application of
problems and theorems—combining them—the scientification of
mathematics.
(NS 3, 175)34
Hence, among contemporary philosophers, it is above all Novalis who saw the
Wissenschaftslehre’s potential for contributing to a scientific discipline
reflecting on the problems, activities, and limits of mathematics. However, here
one should keep in mind a number of other things. Firstly, one has to be careful
about overinterpreting these late fragments on the need for a philosophy of
mathematics, or attributing too much value to what are admittedly only
scattered remarks on Fichte’s mathematical Wissenschaftslehre. Novalis’s ideas
remain brief indications and are not fully developed.35 Second, one should not
forget Novalis’s cutting criticisms of the presentation of Fichte’s system in the
late fragments: the Wissenschaftslehre is a “frightful convolution of
abstractions” that is not yet “complete or presented precisely enough” and
“absolutely unpoetic” (NS 4, 230).36 Finally, Novalis’s utterances on the
deficiencies in the presentations of Fichte’s system should not be taken in turn
as rejections of the Wissenschaftslehre as a whole. For Fichte had made exactly
the same criticisms about the presentation of his philosophy. He too was not
satisfied with its external form, and continually revised and recast his system in
an attempt to assist the understanding of his readers. As Fichte remarked to
Reinhold in 1797: “Your evaluation of my presentation, as it has appeared so far,
is much too favorable. Or perhaps the content has allowed you to overlook the
deficiency of the presentation. I consider it to be most imperfect. Yes, I know
that it gives off sparks of spirit; but it is not a single flame.”37
Page 10 of 16
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
The “Mathematical” Wissenschaftslehre
Hermann Weyl and Jules Vuillemin. Neither of these later thinkers directly refers
to Novalis’s remarks on the mathematical nature of Fichte’s philosophy, yet they
too argue for a positive mathematical reading of the Wissenschaftslehre. Hence,
like the above-mentioned example of Andreas Speiser’s research on the Platonic
elements of Fichte’s thought, one could also consider the work of Weyl and
Vuillemin to have provided an independent confirmation of some of Novalis’s
original insights. In conclusion, we will outline two specific instances of this.
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
The “Mathematical” Wissenschaftslehre
14.5. Conclusion
To summarize: as we saw above, Novalis did not just write lovely poetic hymns to
mathematics, but had also engaged in serious mathematical studies, which (p.
270) led him in turn to reflect on the relationship between this discipline and
philosophy. Like Fichte, the late Novalis saw mathematics as a scientific ideal
and argued for the need for a genuine philosophy of mathematics. Writing in the
1799 Freiberg Natural-Scientific Studies, Novalis remarks: “All the sciences
should become mathematics. Up to now, mathematics has merely been the first
and simplest expression or revelation of true scientific spirit....Poetics of
mathematics. Grammar of mathematics. Physics of mathematics. Philosophy of
Page 12 of 16
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
The “Mathematical” Wissenschaftslehre
In the field of German philosophy the question is often asked: “Did the
Romantics really understand Kant and Fichte?” With regard to the mathematical
pretensions of the Wissenschaftslehre the first elements of an answer may now
be provided. In contrast to the outdated view that Novalis had at most a
“poetically inspired” grasp of Fichte’s system, one could argue that he was only
able to attain his insights on account of his extensive mathematical and
philosophical studies. This background allowed him to actually understand the
Wissenschaftslehre better than many of his contemporaries, and to perceive
mathematical aspects in it which have only been grasped by more recent
research. In terms of relevance it therefore seems that scholars of German
idealism and philosophical romanticism can still benefit from a closer
examination of Novalis’s reflections on Fichte, especially those found in his final
philosophical fragments.
Notes:
(1) . I would like to thank the Fritz Thyssen Stiftung for their generous
assistance during the period of writing this essay. On Novalis and mathematics,
see among others: Martin Dyck, Novalis and Mathematics (Chapel Hill:
University of North Carolina Press, 1960); Käte Hamburger, “Novalis und die
Mathematik,” in Philosophie der Dichter: Novalis, Schiller, Rilke (Stuttgart:
Kohlhammer, 1966), 11–82; Howard Pollack, “Novalis and Mathematics
Revisited: Paradoxes of the Infinite in the Allgemeine Brouillon,” Athenäum:
Jahrbuch für Romantik 7 (1997), 113–140; and more recently, Benoît
Timmermans, “Novalis et la réforme des mathématiques,” in Modernité
Romantique, ed. Augustin Dumont and Laurent van Eynde (Paris: Éditions Kimé,
2011), 73–88.
Page 13 of 16
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
The “Mathematical” Wissenschaftslehre
(2) . Wilhelm Dilthey, Das Erlebnis und die Dichtung: Lessing, Goethe, Novalis,
Hölderlin, in Gesammelte Schriften, vol. 26 (Göttingen: Vandenhoeck &
Ruprecht, 2005), 196.
(3) . The Historical-Critical edition was begun in 1960 and completed in 1988.
(7) . For an English translation of this text see Novalis, Notes for a Romantic
Encyclopaedia: Das Allgemeine Brouillon, ed. and trans. David W. Wood
(hereafter Romantic Encyclopedia) (Albany: SUNY Press, 2007).
(9) . Cf. Manfred Frank’s summary of his differences with Beiser in his Auswege
aus dem Deutschen Idealismus (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 2007), 16–19.
See also Chapter 1 of this volume.
(10) . Here Novalis speaks of how philosophy can assist in the unification of the
sciences. See “Christenheit oder Europa”, 1799 (NS 3, 521).
(14) . Ibid.
(18) . See Friedrich Schlegel’s letter to Novalis, May 5, 1797 (NS 4, 482). On
this romantic notion, see my “From ‘Fichticizing’ to ‘Romanticizing’: Fichte and
Page 14 of 16
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
The “Mathematical” Wissenschaftslehre
(19) . For more details of this, see David W. Wood, “Mathesis of the Mind”: A
Study of Fichte’s Wissenschaftslehre and Geometry (hereafter “Mathesis of the
Mind”) (New York: Rodopi, 2012).
(22) . Ibid.
(23) . For a discussion of Fichte’s theory of original geometry and its relation to
Platonism, as well as a translation into English of the key text, see my “Mathesis
of the Mind,” esp. 79–120, 275–90.
(24) . As he also did with Kant. See Novalis to Friedrich Schlegel, December 10,
1798 (NS 4, 269). Cf. Werner Beierwaltes, Platonismus und Idealismus
(Frankfurt am Main: Klostermann, 1972; reprint 2004), 84–85.
(27) . Cf. Lisa Shabel, Mathematics in Kant’s Critical Philosophy (New York:
Routledge, 2003), 115.
Page 15 of 16
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
The “Mathematical” Wissenschaftslehre
(39) . Hermann Weyl, Das Kontinuum (Leipzig: Veit & Comp., 1919), 2.
(43) . See Jules Vuillemin, La philosophie de l’algèbre (Paris: PUF, 1962, reprint
1993), 116.
Page 16 of 16
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Irritable Figures
Irritable Figures
Herder’s Poetic Empiricism
Amanda Jo Goldstein
DOI:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199976201.003.0016
Page 1 of 24
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Irritable Figures
Page 2 of 24
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Irritable Figures
Under particular, and particularly romantic, pressure in this essay will be the
line of demarcation between science (Wissenschaft, scientia) and poetry (poesis,
production), as well as the fate of stimuli so plural and so slight that they hardly
cross the threshold into sensation. I will explore the subversion of that line of
demarcation and the fate of those obscure stimuli in two essays by Johann
Gottfried Herder (1744–1803), one that argues for the physiologically poetic
relation between sensation and thought, and another for the veracity of poetic
figures. (p.275) Herder’s “On the Cognition and Sensation of the Human Soul
[Vom Erkennen und Empfinden der menschlichen Seele]” (1778) and “On Image,
Poetry, and Fable [Über Bild, Dichtung, und Fabel]” (1787) anticipate many of
the challenges that have come to define “postpositivist” problems in the
philosophy of science: the interimplication of history and philosophy, the
instability of the “fact/value” distinction, the “theory-ladenness” of observation,
and the constitutive role of linguistic and technological apparatus in the
“discovery” and representation of scientific facts and theories.4 Herder develops
an empiricist epistemology profoundly sensitive to the historicity, social-
situatedness, and asymmetrical relations of power inherent in the process of
studying nature through experimental enquiry—and yet, as I will try to argue,
this philosophy of science does not issue in sheer linguistic or social
constructivism, as some of its postmodern analogues seem to do. Here the
ineradicable contingency and anthropomorphism of the knowledge humans
make neither derealizes the objects of scientific inquiry nor severs that
knowledge finally from the world of (other) things. For Herder, I will argue, the
“all too human” contingency of knowledge in fact describes its scientifically
indispensible zone of contact with other natures. And Herder moreover
rehabilitates poetry—specially understood as the joint product of observer and
observed—as the mode of representation adequate to this contact: a neglected
resource for a science capable of resisting radical skepticism in both its
empiricist and idealist flavors.5
“Not ashamed to run after images,” as he puts it, Herder’ revalues poetry for, or
better, as natural science in unapologetically figurative style (CS 189). Drawing
on contemporary physiology to explore the relays required to transform
“obscure irritations” into something as polished and unitary as a conscious
sensation, Herder concludes that our sense organs are constantly “translating,”
“allegorizing,” and “schematizing” (CS 189–90, IPF 359). He thus sees poetic
Page 3 of 24
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Irritable Figures
In this essay’s first part, “Revisionary Empiricism and the Science of Sensation,”
I take a step back in order to set out how Herder’s philosophy of science derives
and departs from the legacies of New Scientific experimentalism and classical
empiricist psychology, as well as to touch on its engagement with the emergent
sciences of life. In the second, longer part, “The Physiology of Tropes,” I delve
deeper into the irritable fibers of Herder’s romantic observer, exploring how his
provocative account of the physiology of sensation as a seriously figurative
process serves to valorize poetry as a privileged technique of empirical inquiry
and representation.
Page 4 of 24
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Irritable Figures
Jonathan Crary has influentially posited the camera obscura as the epitome of
classical empiricist protocol: presuming both a “pre-given world of objective
truth” and an autonomous subject capable of observing this world from the
sequestered space of his own interiority, this optical apparatus figured
knowledge as a “kind of askesis” through which the observer purified and
regulated the world’s disorderly advance.8 At the beginning of the nineteenth
century, Crary argues, the science of vision abandoned these pristine mechanics
of light and descended into the observer’s complex physiology: the visible
“escaped from the timeless order of the camera obscura” to “lodg[e] in another
apparatus...the unstable physiology and temporality of the human body.”9
Crary’s sketch is broad-brush, but Herder wittily affirms the caricature (albeit
two decades earlier than Crary’s periodization scheme would allow). The author
of “On the Sensation and Cognition of the Human Soul” describes his own essay
as a descent into the body that would have made prior philosophers blush:
“Often there lie under the diaphragm causes which we very incorrectly and
laboriously seek in the head...in the face of this sort of deep abyss of obscure
sensations...our bright and clear philosophy is horrified” (CS 196). Herder
delights to ridicule those abstemious philosophers, “standing firm and secure,”
in “happy ignorance” of the uncouth abyss of “obscure forces and irritations”
from which their luminous ideas actually arise (201).
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Irritable Figures
the mind,” Locke affirms, “enter by the senses simple and unmixed,” and
“nothing can be plainer to a man than the clear and distinct perception he has of
those simple ideas.”10 Famously, these “simple ideas of sensation” impress a self
of correspondent uniformity and simplicity: “white paper, void of all characters,
without any ideas,” and Locke explicitly declined to examine “by what motions of
our spirits or alterations of our bodies we come to have any sensation by our
organs, or any ideas in our understandings.”11 Herder, then, and Crary after him,
is astute to (p.278) notice that the rise of experimental physiology, a science
precisely devoted to how “we come to have any sensation by our organs,” has
the potential to transform empiricist psychology. For better or worse, this
science could restore the “body full of sensations, full of irritations” to the
“vaporous skeleton” common to both rationalist metaphysics and empiricist
philosophy (CS 182).
At the very moment that he sees, he also hears, and unconsciously enjoys,
through all the organs of his manifold machine, external influences that,
though they remain largely obscure sensations, nevertheless secretly
cooperate on the sum of his whole condition at all times. He floats in a sea
of impressions of objects, in which one wave laps against him softly,
another more perceptibly.
(633)
Ideas of sense are late glosses on the “sea of impressions” registered within the
thousand-fold weave of his body. Moreover, the whole method of distillation that
an individual unconsciously performs—the method of producing sensations from
Page 6 of 24
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Irritable Figures
That is, regardless of sensory stimulus, Herder argues, “we would grope about
in deep night and blindness if instruction [Unterweisung] had not early on
thought for us and, so to speak, imprinted in us ready-made thought-formulas
[fertige Gedankenformeln uns eingeprägt hätte]” (CS 212 [358]). We require the
prosthetic of instruction—“the support of staffs that were reached to us in
earliest childhood”—to bind sensations to cognitions and, indeed, to sense
coherently at all. In an important formulation, Herder writes that familial and
(p.279) cultural indoctrination forge an armature of “secret bonds [geheime
Bände]” through which any “object has to come to us,” if it is to take sensible
shape at all (212 [358], emphasis added). The present members of any given
society have their very eyes “accustomed, tied, limited” to the “viewpoint”
characteristic of their context; any sensed object arrives by way of prepared and
permissible paths.12 For Herder, then, it is not particularly fruitful, even
heuristically, to conceive of sensation as simple or the self in originary
blankness: “Man is such a complex, artificial being [ein so zusammengesetztes,
künstliches Wesen] that despite every effort he can never achieve a wholly
simple state” (IPF 357 [633]). Herder instead exposes philosophical pretenses of
purity and autonomy as attempts to suppress the real “birth of our reason” in
circumstances of physical and psychic dependency (CS 212). Dependency on
women, no less: from the very womb forward, Herder points out embryonic
philosophers float in a maternal matrix of communicated “impressions and
irritations” (CS 207); “the nursemaids who form our tongues are our first
teachers of logic” (F 48); the best human inventions emerge from “the husks of
human need, in a cradle of childhood, in swaddling clothes” (F 55); and “in this
matter women are our philosophers, not we theirs” (CS 207).
What Herder strikingly calls the “sense of an alien which imprints itself in us
[dieser Sinn eines Fremden, der sich in uns einprägt]” thus shapes our
profoundest interiority and is perpetuated in each instance of movement,
Page 7 of 24
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Irritable Figures
(p.280) Having sketched the way Herder’s thought intensifies its classical
empiricist inheritance by bringing historical contingency to bear at the level of
sensation, I want to underscore a second, characteristically romantic revision of
that legacy. Perpetuating the Cartesian truth criteria of “clarity and
distinctness,” previous empiricist psychology had emphasized the obscurity and
heterogeneity inherent in sensuously derived knowledge primarily in order to
target such imperfections for elimination. Herder and like-minded romantics
viewed sensory impurity less as an epistemic impediment (whose removal would
adequate knowledge to truth) than as a neglected cache of true experience
(awaiting transformation into knowledge by philosophically unorthodox means).
Thus Herder inverts the philosophical virtue of clarity and distinctness with
mischievous precision: “what,” he asks, “does that clear, luminous,
encompassing cognition lack so that it is not and does not become sensation?”13
Here, the distillation of sensation into “so called pure thinking” enforces a loss of
information and accuracy prior philosophy splendidly “reveals the unity in
everything...but does it also reveal as distinguishingly the eachness in each
thing?” (CSd 180, CS 242). Herder regrets that a “broad region of sensations,
drives, affects...gets called body, obscure ideas, feelings”—and systematically
ignored. He therefore sets out to track and redeem the “rich traces [reiche
Spuren]” of bodily interaction with the world that thinking must bear, “despite
all distillation [Trotz aller Destillation]” (CS 181, 242 [392]).
For such revisionary empiricism, the mixed “abyss” of “obscure forces and
irritations” that do not cross the threshold into discursive clarity constitutes a
critical, corporeal register of interactions with the objects of scientific curiosity
(CS 201). Its “rich traces” are essential to any empirical effort to document
these objects’ efficacy and ours. Attending to the subtle, divergent, near-
imperceptible impressions, impressions that “touch him softly,” “whose sounds
get lost in each other more obscurely,” will advance the description of nature,
without and within (CS 192).
Page 8 of 24
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Irritable Figures
Maschine]” (190 [333]). But we ought no longer assume that such romantic self-
scrutiny relinquishes natural curiosity in favor of the purely introspective work
of subjective genius. Indeed, Herder dismisses as “puerile hysteria” and
“abstract egoism” the contemporary cult of genius that was pressing philosophy
—natural, aesthetic, and moral—towards idealism: “inspiration; creative force;
originality; heaven- aspiring, independently self-developing original power; and
so forth” (239, 209, 235). The “soul”—which Herder’s essay invites us to
interpret as the “nerve structure” personified, if not the power of nerves to
conjure up our very sense of personhood—“spins, knows, cognizes nothing out of
itself...it must use the (p.281) irritations, the senses, the forces and
opportunities which became its own through a fortunate, unearned
inheritance” (209). Like the natural body, from which it ought no longer be
separated, the psyche resourcefully assimilates chance materials that condition
its coming.
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Irritable Figures
stuff as the basic material of the cosmos and the most alluring target of
experimental and philosophical inquiry.17
The rise of experimental physiology goes some way toward explaining the
bewildering crossing of subjects and objects of experimental observation, and
indeed of methodological essays and experimental findings, in the texts of the
romantic period. With biological life under scrutiny, the living observer, no less
than the live animals subject to inspection (embryonic chicks, freshwater polyps,
microscopic animalculae), becomes an object of interest and a (p.282)
physiological variable at the scene of empirical investigation.18 It is perhaps
Goethe, writing in his journal On Morphology, who provides the most economical
gloss on this conundrum and the prospects for turning it to advantage: “Every
new object, well seen, opens up a new organ in us [Jeder neue Gegenstand, wohl
beschaut, schließt ein neues Organ in uns auf].”19 Revisionary empiricism is
abbreviated in this astonishing phrase, which transforms “us” from observing
subject to observed object, and back again: keen observers of metamorphosis,
Goethe suggests, cannot but metamorphose in the act of observation; we cannot
but open an “organ” adjusted to the metamorphic object that occasioned this
opening, ourselves the objects of a transformative process whose outcome is to
produce us as observing subjects once again. Sensation is here understood as a
process of bilateral physical transformation, and the living “metamorphoses”
that are the object of life scientific enquiry begin to implicate observing subjects
and their empirical methods, as well.
In the next section, we will see Herder splendidly elaborate the other end of this
rigorous confusion between the subjects and objects of live observation,
exploring the way the observer’s sensorium transforms objects to fit its habits
and needs. Clearly needful, in the romantic period, were forms of empiricism
that would confront, and even cultivate, the methodologically untidy likelihood
that neither subject nor object emerges unchanged from the scene of sensory
observation. Both, Herder will suggest, are transfigured in a way that only
poetic figures can mark.
Page 10 of 24
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Irritable Figures
(p.283) And since for Herder, as we will see, the sensory basis of empirical
knowledge is poetic down to its very nerves and fibers, the epistemological
status of poetic language changes: the tropes, figures, images, and metaphors
formerly thought to veil the simple evidence of experience may instead manifest
underappreciated forms of veracity. Herder concedes that any truth
communicated in such poetic science will be “human truth, certainly,”
ineluctably anthropomorphic in shape (CS 188). But for him, this condition,
though necessary, is neither tragic nor debilitating for knowledge.21 Instead, the
contingencies that delimit human knowledge also demarcate its points of contact
with other natures.22 Indeed, part of what makes Herder’s stance so difficult to
re-inhabit today is his thoroughgoing attempt to philosophize not about nature,
but as one nature among others, one body among many bodies—without letting
go his prescient grasp on the historicity and the species-specificity (to speak
redundantly), of this effort.
“Our whole life,” Herder argues in “On Image, Poetry, and Fable,” “is to a
certain extent poetics.” It turns out that “life” here is physiologically meant, and
that Herder sees sensation as the primary site of coextension between life and
poetics. No neutral register of the influx of the external world, Herder presents
sensation as the active and selective process through which we “separat[e]
objects from others,” “giving them outline, dimension, and form [Umriß, Maß
und Gestalt]” (IPF 358 [635]). Receptive only to those aspects of an “infinite”
object that approach in a specific medium—and, as we have seen, by socially
sanctioned paths—our sense organs parse and transform “the interwoven tangle
of obscure irritations [zusammen geflochtner Knäuel dunkler Reize],” into the
consistent and manageable phenomena of a “world-structure
[Weltgebäude]” (CS 202–3 [348]).
[W]e do not see, rather we create images for ourselves [wir sehen nicht,
sondern wir erschaffen uns Bilder]....For the image that is projected on the
retina of your eye is not the idea that you derive from its object; it is
merely a product of your inner sense, a work of art created by your soul’s
faculty of perception [ein Kunstgemälde der Bemerkungskraft deiner
Seele].
Page 11 of 24
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Irritable Figures
In real and absolute terms, the human being can neither poeticize nor
invent, for otherwise in doing so he would become the creator of another
world. What he can do is conjoin images and ideas, designate them with
the stamp of analogy, thus leaving his own mark on them;...For everything
that we call image in Nature becomes such only through the reception and
operation of his perceiving, separating, composing, and designating soul.
(IPF 365)
Eigentlich und absolut kann der Mensch weder dichten, noch erfinden; er
würde damit der Schöpfer einer neuen Welt. Was er tun kann, ist, Bilder
und Gedanken paaren, sie mit dem Stempel der Analogie, insonderheit aus
sich selbst, bezeichnen;...Denn alles was Bild in der Natur heißt, wird
solches nur durch die Empfängnis und Wirkung seiner bemerkenden,
absondernden, zusammensetzenden, bezeichnenden Seele.
(645)
The “stamp of analogy” invoked in this passage and its cognates—“stamp of our
consciousness,” “stamp of my inner sense”—recur frequently in Herder in order
to defamiliarize the image of an object, to reveal its appearance “in Nature” as
the outcome of a prior assimilation. At stake in sensation is a “reception and
operation” between observer and observed for which the image must be
understood not as the raw or simple datum but the final “mark.”
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Irritable Figures
unilateral imaginative act: as we saw above, the very capacity to sense in this
way, to fashion sensory experience into coherent subjectivity (one’s “own
mark”), is contingent upon the ingress of “an alien which imprints itself in us.”
(p.285) One asset of this account of “sensuous cognition,” a feature that would
appeal to Nietzsche and to Foucault, is that it brooks no illusion of a sensory
transaction that does not leave its mark, no pretense at impartial observation
(aesthetic or scientific) uncontaminated by relations of power and appropriation.
“Only a fool,” Herder explains, “forgets the having [das Haben]” in thinking,
severing thought from the needy and desirous, “receiving and giving,” body that
“draws in and exudes” (CS 213 [359], 191). Both the consequential ingress of
the object into the body of the observer, and the selecting and assimilating force,
which, like a customs officer, conditions that “reception,” are openly expressed
through Herder’s “stamp of analogy,” a figure of assimilation that renders the
object perceptible, licit, legitimate, but only by occulting or excluding aspects of
its difference from the perceiving self.
Sensation, as we have seen, is a bilateral act of figuration (from the Lat. fingere)
in the material sense of to fashion, form, or shape: sense organs physically
fashion “obscure irritations” into assimilable images, sounds, or scents. But as
he uncovers the “image” and “analogy” producing capacities of the sense
organs, Herder connects this physical meaning of figure to its other, rhetorical
meaning: the deviation from proper use and arrangement usually reserved for a
work on words. Stressing the radical differences between the “chaos” of sensible
objects and the fibrous irritations they induce, between those irritations and
visible images they occasion, between those visible images and thoughts to
which they are yoked by “secret bonds,” and between the different sensory
systems that simultaneously admit an object, Herder describes the activity of
sensuous perception as allegorizing, schematizing, translating work. He thus
insists that the tropic operations typically consigned to verbal ornamentation are
moving non- and pre-verbally within the very physiology of sensation:
Page 13 of 24
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Irritable Figures
Hence it follows that our soul, like our language, allegorizes constantly
[beständig allegorisiere]. When the soul sees objects as images, or rather
(p.286) when it transforms them into mental images [in Gedankenbilder
verwandelt], according to rules that are imprinted [eingeprägt] on it, what
is it doing but translating [übersetzen], metaschematizing
[metaschematisieren]? And if the soul now strives to illuminate these
mental images—which are its work alone—through words, through signs
[Zeichen] for the sense of hearing, and thereby to express them to others,
what is it doing once again but translating, alloisizing [alläosieren]?
A careful reading makes it clear that here the work of sensation is a poetic work
that is “like our language,” but not exclusive to it. The “translation” that finally
produces “words” in this passage is but the latest in a series of transfigurative
relays that render the object differently, “alloisizing” or “othering” it at each
turn. The passage’s subtle shift from the soul allegorizing, “speaking otherwise
than one seems to speak,” to the more general alloisizing, “changing, altering,”
encapsulates our point about a poetics not limited to words: Herder
etymologically revises the figural action from “other-speaking” to a broader
sensory “othering” of which verbal language would be but one outcome and
instance. Herder does not further explain the emphatic term
“metaschematizing” upon which the above passage’s account of sensation and
speech seems to hinge.24 But to prefix meta to “schema”—Greek for form and
shape, which Latin translated to figura—drives home the central Herderian
insight that any word or image that attains to consciousness, let alone to
language, is already a meta-figure that glosses a complex of preverbal figurative
events: “cloth[ing],” as Herder puts it elsewhere, “a thousand beings with one
robe for me” (CS 203).
The object has so little in common with the image, the image with the
thought, the thought with the expression, the visual perception with the
name, that they, as it were, touch one another only by virtue of the
sensibility of our complex organization, which perceives several things
through several senses at the same time. Only the communicability among
our several senses... [constitutes] the so-called perfectibility of man. If we
had but one sense and were connected with Creation only by a single
aspect of the world, as it were, there would be no possibility of converting
Page 14 of 24
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Irritable Figures
objects into images and images into words or other signs. Then we should
have to bid farewell to human reason!
(p.287) Herder’s astonishing final claim is this: the advanced semiotic practice
distinctive of “human reason” stems from the copresence of plural sensory
systems within the confined space of the human body, where their divergent,
modes of “converting objects” overlap. Tropological communications within a
body that senses “a thousandfold and a thousandfold differently” set the pattern,
and condition the possibility, for the verbal version of “language” as we usually
mean it. Such language, then, must be conceived fundamentally as metaphor
(meta, over/beyond + pherein to bear or carry) and its near synonym,
translation, both figures of transport that deviate as they represent.
Remarkably, Herder declares the poetic quality that marks sensuous experience
not a symptom of fictitiousness, but a “seal of truth [Siegel der Wahrheit]” (CS
189 [331]). This figured mark is truthful in at least two ways: it attests, first, to
the fact of real, physical contact between perceiver and perceived, and it makes
plain, second, the anthropomorphic shape that any fact perceived by a human
truth-seeker will bear. For Herder, the kind of truth that manifests this figurative
“seal,” that is, the kind of truth that neither conceals its “analogy to the human
being,” nor pretends to transcendent validity, is the best possible truth:
Page 15 of 24
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Irritable Figures
Again, if the very portals of empirical experience are poetic, poetic language
might be doing the work of high-resolution representation, rather than
inessential adornment. Indeed, Herder praises poetic language in terms we
frequently reserve for the scientific and journalistic prose genres that now
monopolize objective description. Poetry excels in “accuracy,” “faithfulness,”
“truth” and “minor detail”:
Our inner poetic sense is able to bind together the manifold features of the
sensation so faithfully and accurately [so wahr und genau zusammen zu
knüpfen] that in its artificial world [Kunstwelt] we feel once more the
whole living world, for it is precisely the minor details [kleinen Umstände]
—which the frigid understanding might not have noticed...[or] omits as
superfluous [als Überfluß wegstreichet]—that are the truest lineaments
[wahresten Striche] of the peculiar feeling, and that precisely because of
this truth, therefore, possess the most decided efficacy [dieser Wahrheit
wegen von der entschiedensten Wirkung].
Above all, poetry is the “truest” representation of the panoply of noticed and
unnoticed interactions that amount to a given sensation; its empirical truth
consists in unstinting reproduction of all “the diversity of that which we felt all
at once” upon sensing an object (“der Mannigfaltigkeit dessen, was wir beim
Genuß dieses Gegenstandes damals auf Einmal fühlten” (IPF 362 [640–41]).
Such a reproduction rejects no detail as “superfluous,” and therefore presents a
Page 16 of 24
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Irritable Figures
thorough record of both the perceiver’s sensibility and the manifold “efficacy” of
the perceived (IPF 362).
Might poetic and fictional texts, then, provide access to those “rich traces” of
embodied experience unavailable to science while “clarity and distinctness”
remain the criteria of sound knowledge? By now it will come as no surprise (p.
289) that Herder’s essays answer this question with multiple “yeses” and a
flurry of metaphors. That Shakespeare “is no physiologist,” he writes, “no one
could say who had seen Hamlet and Lear”: “without knowing it, he depicts the
passion right down to the deepest abysses and fibres from which it
sprouted” (CS 199). The logical complement to this view is equally important to
Herder. Scientific discovery, he argues, is disavowed poetics:
Newton in his system of the world became a poet contrary to his wishes
[wider Willen en Dichter], as did Buffon in his cosmogony... for the most
part it was a single new image [Bild], a single analogy [Analogie], a single
striking metaphor [auffallendes Gleichnis] that gave birth to the greatest
and boldest theories. The philosophers who declaim against figurative
language [Bildersprache], and themselves serve nothing but old, often
uncomprehended, figurative idols [unverstandnen Bildgötzen], are at least
in great contradiction with themselves.
At stake is an observation akin to the one that would open Hans Blumenberg’s
“Prospect for a Theory of Non-Conceptuality” (1960) some two hundred years
later. Metaphors, Blumenberg observes, form the cutting edge of “experimental
theoretical conceptions,” preceding and leading the consolidation of technical
terminology.25 But more than mere placeholders for incipient concepts,
metaphors demonstrate a theoretical efficacy that attests to their “authentic way
of grasping...connections with the life-world”—connections that, for
Blumenberg, form “the constant motivating support (though one that cannot be
constantly kept in view) of all theory” (81). For Herder, too, figures issue from
couplings with the world that conceptual philosophy is structurally ill-equipped
to see; in his case, from the subtle, opaque, and erotic interactions that define
our physiological being: “in the face of this sort of deep abyss of obscure
sensations our bright and clear philosophy is horrified” (CS 196). Expressing
real-physical interactions that conceptual decorum needs to leave unknown,
metaphors know more than knowledge cares to acknowledge.
In the context of a given conceptual system, then, this form of poetic and
theoretical expression can easily take on the elevated, prophetic, and mystified
character of genius (CS 199). Herder will ground it firmly in terrestrial
experience instead. In an extraordinary passage, he likens poetics to animal
instinct, deriving the prophetic power of each from their link to the “unknown
Page 17 of 24
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Irritable Figures
Here Nietzsche’s strikingly Herderian essay, “On Truth and Lying in a Non-
Moral Sense [Über Wahrheit und Lüge im außermoralischen Sinne],” aids
interpretation.26 After affirming that preverbal sensation is already metaphor
—“The stimulation of the nerve is first translated into an image: first
metaphor!”—Nietzsche explains metaphor exactly in terms of a leaping motion
between “spheres” of being: “each time there is a complete leap from one
sphere into the heart of another, new sphere” (144). Echoing Herder’s “drive to
make analogies,” Nietzsche designates “the drive to form metaphors [Trieb zur
Metapherbildung]” as the “fundamental human drive” (150).27 For Nietzsche
here, as Sarah Kofman has argued, metaphoric activity “is not just a drive like
any other; it could be called the general form of all drives.”28
Herder’s easy oscillation between the prophetic transports of poetry and those
of fibrous irritation seems to agree that to speak of a metaphor-forming drive is
nearly tautological. Indeed, Andrea Christian Bertino has argued in this context
that the fundamentally relational notion of a “drive” signals a movement towards
something not contained or containable in its concept: drives in Herder and
Nietzsche advert to their own conceptual limits and even, he argues, to “the
uncontrollable necessity of metaphorical carrying-over.”29 Terms like “drive” and
Page 18 of 24
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Irritable Figures
So we might close by stressing again how Herder’s interest in the poetic quality
of empirical knowing and representing does not aim, as Nietzsche’s essay does,
primarily to uncover our role as “artistically creative subjects,” unwitting
linguistic producers of the world that our science purports to “discover” (148).
At stake instead is a now unfamiliar understanding of physical bodies as
fundamentally tropic, enmeshed in a multitude of figurative transactions and
displacements of which human rhetoric is but one outcome and instance. Indeed,
from his prize-winning essay On the Origins of Human Language (1772) forward,
Herder strenuously advocated a natural origin for human language, synecdoche
in the period for a naturalism so thoroughgoing that it would account for even
the most intellective, apparently immaterial aspects of the universe (languages)
without recourse to divine causes.30
In asserting the figurative status of human sensation and language, then, Herder
does not subordinate “nature” to our verbal metaphorics, but renders those
metaphorics derivative of a broader category transfigurations and transports
already and everywhere underway. Similarly, when Herder notices that
metaphors and organic drives share a formal structure, his aim is not to unmask
physiological theory as “mere” metaphor, “mere” product of human speech. Like
many of his contemporaries, Herder finds in Haller’s “irritable” fibers—“these
obscure stamens of irritation towards sensation” (CS 190 [133])—scientific
confirmation that material nature tends towards changes of shape, form, and
figure, and the metaphoric leaping between levels of which language is only the
most flagrant example. Irritation, an effect akin to mechanical expansion and
contraction, nonetheless tends “towards sensation,” effecting a transport that
shuttles “dead nature” toward animate life, physics toward physiology, bodily
toward mental activity. In Herder’s hands, irritations and drives participate in
the epochal shift towards a naturalistic conception of life’s origins: the
conviction that “life in swift flight” could spring up from inert materials was
Page 19 of 24
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Irritable Figures
In “On the Cognition and Sensation of the Human Soul,” poets and scientists
demonstrate a conspicuously reciprocal ignorance of the fact that “for (p.292)
us all of physics remains a kind of poetics for our senses,” a fact that, as we have
seen, Herder regards as both ineluctable and fortuitous for knowledge.
Shakespeare was a “physiologist” “without knowing it,” Newton a poet despite
himself. Herder’s is romantic philosophy of science insofar as it seeks the
knowledgeable form of representation that would result if we could cultivate the
poetic aspect of scientific representation as a key source of its truth, and the
scientific aspect of poetic representation as a key source of its pleasure. “Oh,
what a work of strangely fine developments and observations,” he muses, could
a “thinking and feeling physiologist” write: it would capture “this noble string-
play in its structure, in its conducting and knotting, entwining and
subtilizing” (206). And what an unvarnished “offprint of a living human soul
[Abdruck einer lebendigen Menschenseele]” could be produced by a poet who
cultivated his writing’s function as “betrayer” of “how he received images, how
he ordered and adjusted them and the chaos of his impressions” (217–19 [366]).
The assumption that literature has no science and science no poetics, Herder
thinks, inhibits the truth and efficacy of each.
Notes:
(1) . Robin Valenza, Literature, Language, and the Rise of the Intellectual
Disciplines (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009), 1–33; Raymond
Williams, Culture and Society, 1780–1950 (New York: Columbia University Press,
1983), 30–48; Lorraine Daston and Peter Galison, Objectivity (New York and
Cambridge: Zone Books and MIT Press, 2007), 37, 242–47.
(2) . For a pithy, like-minded account of the alternative Herder posed to the
(ultimately victorious) formation of the disciplines, and of the frequent
misprision of this alternative in historical retrospect, see Eva Knodt,
“Hermeneutics and the End of Science: Herder’s Role in the Formation of Natur-
and Geisteswissenschaften,” in Johann Gottfried Herder: Academic Disciplines
and the Pursuit of Knowledge, ed. Wulf Koepke, (Columbia, SC: Camden House,
1996), 1–12. Notice how the characterization “monstrous” arises in works as
diverse as Denise Gigante’s Life: Organic Form and Romanticism (New Haven:
Yale University Press, 2009) and Bruno Latour’s We Have Never Been Modern
(Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993). After decades of careful
scholarship on the scientific “contexts” of romantic-era literature, as well as new
histories of romantic-era science, it is now safe to conclude that natural
scientific reading, writing, and research were the rule, rather than the
exception, among even the most canonically literary romantics, productive of the
Page 20 of 24
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Irritable Figures
texts, not just the contexts, of romantic era literature. Fine emblems of this now
vast bibliography include Jocelyn Holland, German Romanticism and Science:
The Procreative Poetics of Goethe, Novalis, and Ritter (New York: Routledge,
2009), Noel Jackson, Science and Sensation in British Romanticism (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2008), and Safia Azzouni, Kunst als praktischer
Wissenschaft: Goethes “Wilhelm Meisters Wanderjahre” und die Hefte Zur
Morphologie (Köln: Böhlau Verlag, 2005).
(4) . Herder, “On the Cognition and Sensation of the Human Soul,” in Herder:
Philosophical Writings, ed. and trans. Michael N. Forster (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2002), 187–243; and “On Image, Poetry, and Fable,”
in Selected Writings on Aesthetics: Johann Gottfried Herder, ed. and trans.
Gregory Moore (Princeton, NJ and Oxford: Princeton University Press, 2006),
357–82. These two essays are abbreviated CS and IPF in what follows. Citations
from the German, when given, refer to HW 4, 329–93 and 633–77; page
references to this edition appear in square brackets. My summary of cruxes in
postpositivist philosophy of science is heavily indebted to Zammito, A Nice
Derangement of Epistemes: Post-positivism in the Study of Science from Quine
to Latour (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2004).
(5) . See Beiser, The Fate of Reason: German Philosophy from Kant to Fichte
(Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993).
(6) . Berlin, The Roots of Romanticism, ed. Henry Hardy (Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press, 1999), 57.
(7) . See, for instance, Zammito, Kant, Herder, and the Birth of Anthropology
(Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2002), Peter Hanns Reill, Vitalizing
Nature in the Enlightenment (Berkeley: University of California Press, 2005),
Anne C. Vila, Enlightenment and Pathology: Sensibility in the Literature and
Medicine of Eighteenth-Century France (Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins
University Press, 1998), Kevis Goodman, Georgic Modernity and British
Romanticism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004), and Maureen
McClane, Romanticism and the Human Sciences: Poetry, Population, and the
Discourse of the Species (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000).
(8) . Jonathan Crary, Techniques of the Observer: On Vision and Modernity in the
Nineteenth Century (London: October/MIT Press, 1990), 39.
Page 21 of 24
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Irritable Figures
(13) . “On Cognition and Sensation, the Two Main Forces of the Human Soul,” a
1775 draft of Herder’s published essay; in Forster, Philosophical Writings, 178–
86, 180. Abbreviated CSd hereafter.
(14) . See Anne C. Vila, Enlightenment and Pathology, and Shirley A. Roe, Matter,
Life, and Generation: 18th-Century Embryology and the Haller-Wolff Debate
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981).
(17) . For a most lucid and nuanced account of this process that, in my view,
opens up continuities between “high and late Enlightenment” and “romantic”
sophistications of early Enlightenment rationalism and mechanism, see Reill,
Page 22 of 24
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Irritable Figures
(19) . Goethe, “Bedeutende Fördernis durch ein einziges geistreiches Wort,” Zur
Morphologie 2.1, in MA 12, 306.
(20) . Nietzsche, “On Truth and Lying in a Non-Moral Sense,” in The Birth of
Tragedy and Other Writings, ed. Raymond Guess and Ronald Speirs, trans.
Speirs (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999), 139–53.
(22) . As per their shared Latin etymon con + tangere, to touch together.
Page 23 of 24
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Irritable Figures
(26) . Nietzsche, “On Truth and Lying in a Non-Moral Sense.” in The Birth of
Tragedy and Other Writings, ed. Raymond Guess and Ronald Speirs, trans.
Speirs (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 199), 139–153 On Niezsche’s
debts to Herder on the question of the tropic origin of thought, see Andrea
Christian Bertino, “Vernatürlichung”: Ursprünge von Friedrich Nietzsches
Entidealisierung des Menschen, seiner Sprache und seiner Geschichte bei
Johann Gottfried Herder, (Berlin: De Gruyter, 2011), esp. 170–203. See also
Borsche, “Bildworte,” 63–64.
(28) . Kofman, Nietzsche and Metaphor, trans. Duncan Large (Stanford, CA:
Stanford University Press, 1993), 25.
(29) . Bentino, Vernatürlichung, 172. I disagree that Herder uses the notion of
figurative drive as a “non-biological” heuristic: Bertino bases this conclusion on
the assertion that this drive surfaces in discussions of poetry and language,
rather than in biological natural scientific contexts—but the “Sensation and
Cognition” essay is biological indeed.
Page 24 of 24
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Romantic Empiricism after the “End of Nature”
Dalia Nassar
DOI:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199976201.003.0017
It has been almost two decades since the publication of Bill McKibben’s book,
The End of Nature (1989), which, as the title proclaims, announced the end of
that which we have, for many centuries, called nature. McKibben’s claim is that
the increasing influence of human activity on the natural environment has led
not only to unprecedented transformations in an extremely short amount of time,
but also to the complete elimination of a reality that is outside of or independent
of the sphere of human activity. “The idea of nature,” he writes, “will not survive
Page 1 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Romantic Empiricism after the “End of Nature”
the new global pollution—the carbon dioxide and CFCs and the like....We have
changed the atmosphere, and we are changing the weather. By changing the
weather, we make every spot on earth man-made and artificial....The world, the
whole world, is touched by our work even when that work is invisible.”1
Over the last decade, McKibben’s claim that nature has come to an end has been
reiterated and, in many cases, reconfigured. Thus, although environmental
philosophers have generally agreed with the view that the idea of nature is
problematic or implausible, their reasoning often differs from McKibben’s.
Timothy Morton is a case in point. In his recent book, Ecology without Nature
(2007), Morton argues that ecology and ecological thought must rid itself of the
idea of nature. This is not, however, because we have destroyed nature such that
it no longer exists. Rather, Morton’s claim is that nature is an idealized reality—
an idea—that does not describe material reality or specify phenomena. (p.297)
The idea of nature, he argues, “hinders authentic ecological politics, ethics
philosophy and art” because it is “transcendental term in a material mask.”2
Page 2 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Romantic Empiricism after the “End of Nature”
In light of the critiques of the idea of nature, the interest in romanticism seems
perplexing and perhaps even problematic. Does the romantic idea of nature not
also suffer from the kinds of problems that McKibben and Morton point out? In
fact, Morton’s rejection of the idea of nature begins with a critical assessment of
romanticism, and it is precisely the romantic view of and approach to nature that
he considers to be the source of the problem. Nonetheless, one is left to wonder
whether the (or a) romantic conception of nature can contribute to
contemporary debates, and whether the critical challenges to the idea of nature
have either overlooked or misunderstood certain aspects of romanticism.
Page 3 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Romantic Empiricism after the “End of Nature”
In Jena, Weimar, and Berlin, the generation of philosophers after Kant was
concerned with overcoming the various oppositions that resounded throughout
his corpus: the opposition between sensibility and the understanding (intuition
and intellect), noumena and phenomena, necessity and freedom, matter and
mind, passivity and activity. Although in the Critique of Judgment (1790) Kant
promised to bridge the gulf between these distinct domains, his concluding
claim that nature and freedom can only be unified in a hypothetical and
unknowable “supersensible substrate” did not ultimately achieve this end. So
long as the unity between nature and freedom (matter and mind) remained
hypothetical, there was no way by which to establish the connection necessary
for, on the one hand, overcoming skepticism, and, on the other, developing an
adequate philosophy of nature.9 At this time, I will not delve into the specific
difficulties of Kant’s position, or the criticisms it received.10 Rather, I will only
briefly mention the romantic response to the Kantian project.
Page 4 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Romantic Empiricism after the “End of Nature”
Yet, even within the larger German romantic tradition, one finds distinctive
directions with diverse methods and perspectives. Schelling is exemplary in his
attempt to construct a “system of nature.” This construction begins by positing
an original premise, an absolute or necessary first principle. This principle,
however, contains a contradiction, a duality, which must be resolved. The
resolution of this duality occurs in the so-called process of construction, in which
one intuition is generated after the other, until finally, an “absolute synthesis” is
achieved. That is, a synthesis of all the previous intuition is realized in one
culminating insight—an insight that also demonstrates the validity of the original
premise.12 In the philosophy of nature, the different intuitions that are
successively generated through the internal contradiction of the first premise
are nothing other than the stages of natural development: from magnetism and
electricity, to chemistry and organisms, and, finally, to the specific evolutionary
relationships between different organisms, Schelling constructs the history of
nature.13 While Schelling undertook experiments and emphasized the
significance of experience for the adequate construction of a system of nature,
his method and aims were determined by his systematic ideals. More
specifically, his goal was to establish the theoretical foundations of a system of
nature.
Page 5 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Romantic Empiricism after the “End of Nature”
Goethe’s interest in nature and the natural sciences commenced during his
tenure as an administrator in Saxe-Weimar Eisenach. One of his first tasks in
Weimar was the reopening of the mines in Ilmenau, which led him to the study of
minerals and the development of his own mineral collections.
During this time, Goethe began to study botany, reading Carl Linneaus, working
with the Jena professor August Johann Batch, and developing a garden for his
research. For Goethe, reading Linneaus was both exciting and disappointing.
Linneaus had attempted to organize the world; however, Goethe surmised, not
one of his attempts was a success. Linneaus’s system led to a fragmentary and
superficial taxonomy because it was based on a few visible parts. In contrast,
Goethe argued that knowledge must seek to grasp and present the unity of the
phenomena—that is to say, discern how the different parts and stages of
development participate in the phenomenon as a whole. Only by grasping the
integrated character of the plant, he maintained, can we go on to recognize it as
a member of a particular species or kingdom (a plant as plant, an animal as
animal). The question for Goethe, then, was not whether plants exhibit a
distinctive unity, but rather what this unity involves, and how it can be
recognized and articulated.
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Romantic Empiricism after the “End of Nature”
knowledge, Goethe argues, Kant was also, and necessarily, transgressing them.
He writes,
Goethe’s critique, which Hegel also leveled against Kant’s methodology, applies
most directly to Kant’s claim that knowledge of natural ends or organisms is
beyond our cognition. How, Goethe asks, was Kant able to draw these limits if he
(Kant) did not have any access to what is beyond them? This was not, however,
the only reason that Kant’s framework appeared perplexing to Goethe. The very
thing that Kant had denied—cognition of organic beings—Goethe believed
himself to have achieved. Thus, he goes on, “had I myself not ceaselessly
pressed forward to the archetype, though at first unconsciously, from an inner
drive; had I not even succeeded in evolving a method in harmony with Nature?
What then was to prevent me from courageously embarking upon the adventure
of reason, as the old gentleman of Königsberg himself calls it?” (MA 12, 99).
Goethe agreed with Kant that there is always a “gap” between idea and
experience. For Kant, this gap is due to an incongruity between the singularity
of the perceived (the individual this) and the generality or universality of
concepts. This incongruity, according to Kant, results in a “contingency” in our
knowledge: “our understanding is a faculty of concepts, i.e., a discursive
understanding, for which it must of course be contingent what and how different
might be the particular that can be given to it in nature and brought under its
concepts” (AA 5: 406). For Goethe, by contrast, the gap between idea and
Page 7 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Romantic Empiricism after the “End of Nature”
In 1786, Goethe travelled to Italy with the aim of immersing himself in the visual
arts and learning about plant physiology. It was during this time that he arrived
at his idea of an “Urpflanze” or archetypal plant. In the garden in Palermo, he
was struck by both the diversity and unity of what he observed. He writes: “I
was confronted with so many kinds of fresh, new forms, I was taken again by my
old fanciful idea: might I not discover the Urpflanze amid this multitude? Such a
thing must exist after all! How else would I recognize this or that form as being
a plant, if they were not all constructed according to one model?” (MA 15, 327).
What is it, Goethe asks himself, that enables him to recognize the manifold
varieties of plants as plant. Or, what is the unifying principle of plants?
Importantly, he does not seek it outside of the multiplicity, but “amid the
multitude.”
In a letter to Herder, dated exactly one month following his visit to the garden,
Goethe writes that he has come very near to comprehending “the secret of plant
generation and organization” (MA 15, 393). He has realized, he reports to
Herder, that the unity he is after is inherently connected to growth and
generation. It was not until July of 1787, however, that Goethe more clearly
articulated his discovery. In a report in which he includes the two passages
quoted above, he adds the important conclusion: “it has become apparent to me
that in the plant organ we ordinarily call the leaf a true Proteus is concealed,
that can hide and reveal itself in all formations. From top to bottom, a plant is all
leaf, united so inseparably with the future bud that one cannot be imagined
without the other” (MA 15, 456). What distinguishes a plant, what makes it
Page 8 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Romantic Empiricism after the “End of Nature”
recognizable as a plant, are the formative relationships between its parts: the
way in which each of the parts appears to anticipate what comes after it and the
plant as a whole—or, as Goethe put it, each part anticipates “the future bud.”
Thus, by claiming that “all plant is leaf,” Goethe is not reducing the plant to the
leaf, but rather recognizing a morphological continuity between the parts,
wherein each part is a formative manifestation (“bildende Kraft”)16 of the “true
Proteus,” that is, of an underlying ideal that determines the parts and their
relations in (p.304) developmental terms. In other words, what unifies the
plant is not simply its structure, but its structure as its formative unity, that is, as
the developmental relations between the parts, as the way in which each part
realizes the plant’s continued development.
In his Essay on the Metamorphosis of Plants (1790) Goethe presents this insight
in greater detail. An observation of plants, he writes, reveals “that certain of
their external parts sometimes undergo a change and assume, either entirely or
in greater or lesser degree, the form of the parts adjacent to them” (MA 12, 29,
no. 1). This is most evident, he explains, in what might be called intermediate
parts, cases where stem leaves have taken on attributes of the calyx, or where
the calyx is tinted with the color of the blossom, or where petals show
resemblances to stamens and so on. In other words, if the plant’s parts are
perceived alongside one another, one begins to recognize morphological
continuity between the parts, and it becomes clear that each part assumes a
form that is a modification or progression of the other parts.
Page 9 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Romantic Empiricism after the “End of Nature”
form of each of the plant’s parts, that is, the way in which each part is both a
response to what precedes it and an anticipation of what is to come. Each part,
one can say, reflects the history of the plant and thereby contains within it the
whole plant. The unity of the plant is thus inherently connected to its growth,
and development, such that each part is a physical manifestation of a stage of
metamorphosis. It is a unity that emerges in time, and is realized in and through
the plant’s growth and transformation.
Thus, the very fact that organic beings grow and their parts represent stages of
development means that the different stages presuppose and anticipate one
another. That is, the possibility of future stages is already at work in earlier
ones. For example, just as the formation of the flower presupposes the formation
of the stem, so the possibility of the flower is already at work in the development
of pistil and stem. The structure of the organism can be thus distinguished from
the structure of casual observation in three ways. First, the parts grow in
relation to one another, and not independently of one another. Second, this
development reveals an anticipation of the future, such that the possibility of
“the future bud,” as Goethe put it, is already at work in the present. Finally, the
parts develop simultaneously (they grow together or at once).
Given the fact that, when we perceive, we see the parts independently of one
another, and, moreover, experience a temporal structure in which the past alone
determines the present, how are we to grasp the organizing principle that
Page 10 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Romantic Empiricism after the “End of Nature”
underlies plant development? The answer to this question lies in our ability to
perceive and grasp the continuity and relatedness between the different stages,
so as to be able to see the simultaneous and the successive as one.17 How is this
to take place?
The transitions, after all, are not given immediately to sensibility. For this
reason, Goethe surmises, the only way by which to grasp them is by visualizing
them in memory—and for this the imagination is necessary. Through the (p.
306) imagination I recreate in my mind what takes place in nature, and thereby
present to the mind’s eye what remains imperceptible to the physical eye. To
achieve this, Goethe writes, I must “consider all phenomena in a certain
developmental sequence and attentively follow the transitions forwards and
backwards. Only in this way do I finally arrive at the living view of the whole,
from which a concept is formed that soon will merge with the idea along an
ascending line” (LA 1/8, 74).
This involves two steps. First, I must discern the transitions between the parts,
and thereby see how each part relates to the one that precedes and the one that
follows it. Second, I must grasp these transitions as they occur simultaneously.
After all, the goal is not simply to arrive at an understanding of the continuity
between the parts and see how each part is a metamorphosis of the one that
preceded it, but also to grasp the unified activity of the plant. For only in this
way can one see all the parts as interrelated members of a living process. But
what does it mean to grasp the unified activity, or the underlying unity of the
distinctive parts? For Goethe this means nothing less than transforming what is
given to perception and imagination into an idea. He explains this
transformation as follows:
If I look at the created object, inquire into its creation, and follow this
process back as far as I can, I will find a series of steps. Since these are not
actually seen together before me, I must visualize them in my memory so
that they form a certain ideal whole.
At first I will tend to think in terms of steps, but nature leaves no gaps, and
thus, in the end, I will have to see this progression of uninterrupted activity
as a whole. I can do so only by dissolving the particularity without
destroying the impression itself.
The idea that is grasped in this way is not a static or abstract concept that is
divested of difference and particularity. Nor is it something that is imposed upon
the sensibly given by the understanding. Rather, it emerges out of an
engagement with the sensibly given, and thus provides, as Goethe puts it, an
impression of the whole that does not destroy the particular. The idea must
enable insight of the different parts and their relations—the continuity between
Page 11 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Romantic Empiricism after the “End of Nature”
them—and thus present the differences within the unity. Only in this way can I
grasp the unity of a living organism, that is, an internally differentiated unity.
Page 12 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Romantic Empiricism after the “End of Nature”
Second, his approach implies that knowledge involves the attempt to become
identical with the thing known. Goethe described his method as a “delicate
empiricism, which makes itself utterly identical with the object” (MA 17, 823).
This identity requires a transformation in the knower—a transformation that
takes place on two levels. On the one hand, the knower actively seeks to make
her thinking identical with her perceiving—and thus shifts the balance in her
cognition, so that concepts do not determine and grant meaning to inchoate (p.
308) sensibly given data, but rather, thought and ideas emerge from and in
light of what is perceived. On the other hand, perceiving must itself strive to
become identical with what is before it; it too must achieve a certain plasticity,
so as to be able to grasp the organism as an integrated unity. This double
transformation leads to what Goethe calls the “eye of the mind,” that is, a
thinking that emerges out of and is identical with perception.21
Page 13 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Romantic Empiricism after the “End of Nature”
As a substitute for the concept of nature and in order to answer this question,
several thinkers have developed new concepts or employed old ones in new
ways. Morton, for instance, speaks of the “coexistence” of things, and argues
that we should strive to exist with things.23 Coexistence, according to Morton,
describes a “pre-ontological level of ‘existence,’” in which we cannot speak (p.
309) about distinct ontological beings, but rather the “intimacy of all life
forms.” What he means, however, is never made clear. For one, he refuses to
distinguish between living and nonliving things, and at no point does he explain
what he means by “life forms.” Yet he often includes nonliving entities into his
schema of “coexistence.” Although Morton’s notion of coexistence has the
positive intention of offering an inclusive conception of reality, it ends up doing
exactly what Morton finds problematic in the idea of nature: it is a vague and
abstract concept that is imposed on the phenomena. It is, furthermore, a concept
that does not offer a concrete approach to the phenomena or disclose the
phenomena in their particularity: it does not tell us anything other than that
things stand next to one another. What they are, how they stand next to one
another, and what their relations are remain unclear. Thus, rather than seeking
to understand a phenomenon, the notion of coexistence eclipses phenomena in,
as Morton puts it, the “constant flux.”
Biodiversity is another idea that has been put forth as a replacement for the
notion of nature and is connected with the disappearance or extinction of certain
types. While Morton distinguishes his notion of coexistence from the idea of
biodiversity, where the goal is to save or maintain as many kinds of beings as
possible, in both cases the decisive idea is that of the existence or continuation
of existence—that is, the preservation of something that exists now. Biodiversity
rests on the idea that we must strive to maintain the greatest number of kinds.
Number, however, is not self-evidently healthy. Thus kinds must be understood in
accordance to their diverse and complex functions within an ecological niche.
This means that we must investigate and understand these niches, and to simply
speak in terms of the concept of “biodiversity” is just as vague and abstract as
the concept “nature.” Furthermore, the notion of biodiversity alone fails to offer
a concrete approach to the phenomena. Instead, just like the notion of
“coexistence,” it relies on a vague idea of preservation and continuity, which
does not provide adequate ways of discerning differences, recognizing
similarities, and drawing judgments. The unquestioned assumption in both is
that because all things are part of the general flux (coexist), they must continue
to exist.
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Romantic Empiricism after the “End of Nature”
My thesis is that Goethe and specifically his method offer a viable solution to the
lacuna in contemporary environmental theory. His approach to the natural world
allows him to discern differences, without however undermining or overlooking
similarities. For his goal was to grasp the unity in the multiplicity, and thereby
recognize the distinctive singularity of each thing through its relations and place
within a larger context. His Urpflanze, or archetypal plant, was indeed an idea.
As such, however, it was not separable from the phenomena of the plants; it was
neither an arbitrary abstraction derived from some apparent commonalities
between a set of plants, nor a purely mental construct generated through an
intellectual intuition. Rather, as an idea, the Urpflanze was achieved through
empirical investigation; it was verified through its ability to disclose the
distinctive character of plants, or as Goethe put it, the “secret of plant
generation and organization.” Thus, in Goethe we find an idealism that does not
imply antirealism, nor does it involve a shutting out of empirical phenomena.
The opposite is the case. As I have shown, for Goethe, knowledge can emerge
only through careful and arduous observation coupled with theoretical and
methodological consideration. The idea is never divorced from the phenomenon,
but rather is the phenomenon in the most immanent sense.
Page 15 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Romantic Empiricism after the “End of Nature”
The act of knowledge thus rests on an honest engagement with reality, with the
phenomena. While this is not a thorough and comprehensive environmental
ethics, the claim that we are under an epistemological obligation to what is
before us provides the first step in that direction. This obligation falls entirely on
the side of the knower, and, importantly, does not involve the ethicist in the
vicious circle of having to assume values or rights—precisely what she or he
seeks to justify.24
Notes:
(1) . Bill McKibben, The End of Nature (London: Viking, 1990), 54 and 56.
(3) . Kate Rigby, “Writing after Nature,” Australian Humanities Review 39–40
(2006). www.australianhumanitiesreview.org/archive/Issue-
September-2006.rigby.html.
(4) . Ibid.
(5) . See for instance, Jonathan Bate, Romantic Ecology: Wordsworth and the
Environmental Tradition (London: Routledge, 1991); Karl Kroeber, Ecological
Literary Criticism: Romantic Imagining and the Biology of Mind (New York:
Page 16 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Romantic Empiricism after the “End of Nature”
Columbia University Press, 1994); James McKusick, “Coleridge and the Economy
of Nature,” Studies in Romanticism 35 (1996): 375–92.
(6) . This is all the more astonishing when one sees that the key critics of the
idea of nature are also scholars of literary romanticism. This includes Timothy
Morton and Kate Rigby. Rigby’s book on European romanticism significantly
assesses the relevance of romantic thought for environmental philosophy. She
remains uncomfortable, however, with what she sees as an overarching (and
anthropocentric) holism in romanticism. See Topographies of the Sacred: The
Poetics of Place in European Romanticism (Charlottesville, VA: University of
Virginia Press, 2004). In this paper, I seek to emphasize a specific romantic
legacy—what I call “romantic empiricism”—that Rigby also discusses, but does
not specifically consider in relation to contemporary environmental thought.
(7) . Amanda Jo Goldstein’s chapter in this volume similarly traces the empiricist
tradition of romantic thought in the work of Herder. See chapter 15.
(9) . Shortly after the publication of the Critique of Pure Reason (1781), Kant’s
first critics accused him of skepticism. If things-in-themselves could not be
known, then how could we be sure that our knowledge actually reflects truth
and is not merely illusory? (The first review of the Critique, coauthored by
Johann Georg Heinrich Feder and Christian Garve, published in 1782 and known
as the “Göttingen Review” or the “Feder/Grave Review,” leveled precisely this
critique, arguing that Kantian philosophy was a full-blown idealism). Or, how can
a priori forms agree with or correspond to a posteriori matter? (This is the
principle critique of Salomon Maimon in his Versuch über die
Transcendentalphilosophie [1789].) Or, given Kant’s basic premises, how can we
know that sensibility was indeed receptive, and that things-in-themselves existed
at all? (This was the essence of Jacobi’s argument, in which he claimed that Kant
inconsistently argued that objects are the causes of our representations.) For a
complete account of the skeptical attacks on Kant’s philosophy, see Frederick C.
Beiser, The Fate of Reason: German Philosophy between Kant and Fichte
(Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1987). In turn, the possibility of a
philosophy of nature depends on the unification of two irreconcilable principles:
the mechanism that underlies nature “as the sum of all appearances,” and the
teleology that is presumed (and is thus only regulative) to explain those entities
that are inexplicable on mechanical principles. Although Kant seeks to reconcile
these two principles in the Antinomy of Teleological Judgment, it is difficult to
see how exactly his solution achieves reconciliation. For a comprehensive and
illuminating analysis of the difficulty of the task at hand, see Eric Watkins, “The
Antinomy of Teleological Judgment,” Kant Yearbook 1 (2009): 197–222.
Page 17 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Romantic Empiricism after the “End of Nature”
(10) . See my The Romantic Absolute: Being and Knowing in German Romantic
Philosophy 1795–1804 (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2013).
(12) . For an explication of how the first premise determines the development of
the system, see my The Romantic Absolute, Part 3.
(13) . For an account of Schelling’s derivations, see Eckart Förster, The Twenty
Five Years of Philosophy: A Systematic Reconstruction, trans. Brady Bowman
(Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2012), 233–34.
(15) . One of the more difficult aspects of the Critique of Judgment has to do with
the apparent distinction that Kant draws between our experience of organisms
and our cognition of them (as ends of nature or as purposive). For it seems that,
on the one hand, organisms “appear” to us in experience—such that we are able
to distinguish them from nonorganic beings and make claims about their
structure—while, on the other hand, they are deemed as ultimately
incomprehensible (see for instance, Peter McLaughlin, Kant’s Critique of
Teleology in Biological Explanation [Lewiston: Edwin Mellen Press, 1990], 56).
For Goethe, the kind of difference that Kant seems to want to draw between
experience and knowledge does not make sense—for insofar as a phenomenon
appears, then it is knowable.
(16) . In his work on animal morphology, Goethe describes the relations between
the parts of an animal as developing “according to a certain scheme, formed
[umgeformt] differently through the formative force [bildende Kraft] in the most
steady manner” (FA 24, 280).
(20) . In the same remark in Maxims and Reflections Goethe also states that “the
most important thing to grasp is that all fact is already theory” (MA 17, 824).
Page 18 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Romantic Empiricism after the “End of Nature”
(22) . It should be noted that this is a problem that specifically plagues thinkers
who claim that the idea of nature is incoherent and philosophically unjustifiable
(Morton, for instance). McKibben’s take, in contrast, is that nature once was but
no longer is, such that he is able to demand environmental activism that is
inspired by this historical reality. In other words, the idea of nature (although no
longer a reality) has a normative status in McKibben’s thought.
(24) . The research and writing of this paper was supported by the Australian
Research Council Discovery Early Career Research Award (DE120102402).
Page 19 of 19
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Texts by Authors from the Romantic Era
Forberg, Friedrich Karl. Fragmente aus meinen Papieren. Jena: J. G. Voigt, 1796.
Fries, Jakob Friedrich. Reinhold, Fichte und Schelling. Leipzig: Reineicke, 1803.
Page 1 of 6
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Texts by Authors from the Romantic Era
——. Über die Gegenstände der bildenden Kunst. Zurich: Artemis Verlag, 1961–
66.
Jacobi, Friedrich Heinrich. Ueber die Lehre des Spinoza in Briefen an Herrn
Moses Mendelssohn. Neue vermehrte Auflage. Breslau: Löwe, 1789.
——. Werke, vols. 1/1 and 1/2: Schriften zum Spinozastreit. Edited by Klaus
Hammacher and Irmgard-Maria Piske. Hamburg: Meiner; Stuttgart-Bad
Cannstatt: Frommann-Holzboog, 1989.
Page 2 of 6
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Texts by Authors from the Romantic Era
——. “Ueber den Unterschied zwischen dem gesunden Verstande und der
philosophierenden Vernunft in Rücksicht auf die Fundamente des durch beyde
möglichen Wissens.” In Beyträge zur Berichtigung bisheriger Mißverständnisse
der Philosophen, vol. 2, Die Fundamente des philosophischen Wissens, der
Metaphysik, Moral, moralischen Religion und Geschmackslehre betreffend. Jena:
Johann Michael Mauke, 1794.
Schelling, Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph von, and Johann Gottlieb Fichte. Fichte-
Schelling Briefwechsel. Edited with an introduction by Walter Schulz. Frankfurt
am Main: Suhrkamp, 1968.
Page 3 of 6
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Texts by Authors from the Romantic Era
——. “Bruchstücke aus einer Schrift über die Philosophie und ihre Principien.”
Philosophisches Journal einer Gesellschaft Teutscher Gelehrten 3, no. 2 (1795):
95–132.
English Translations
Fichte, J. G. “Review of Aenesidemus.” In Between Kant and Hegel: Texts in the
Development of Post-Kantian Idealism. Edited and translated with introductions
by George di Giovanni and H. S. Harris. Albany: State University of New York
Press, 1985.
Page 4 of 6
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Texts by Authors from the Romantic Era
(p.318) ——. Odes and Elegies. Translated by Nick Hoff. Middletown, CT:
Wesleyan University Press, 2008.
Kant, Immanuel. Critique of Pure Reason. Translated and edited by Paul Guyer
and Allen W. Wood. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998.
——. Critique of the Power of Judgment. Edited by Paul Guyer and translated by
Paul Guyer and Eric Matthews. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000.
Novalis. The Novices of Sais. Translated by Ralph Manheim. New York: Curt
Valentin, 1949.
——. Notes for a Romantic Encyclopaedia: Das Allgemeine Brouillon. Edited and
translated by David W. Wood. Albany: State University of New York Press, 2007.
Schlegel, Friedrich von. Lectures on the History of Literature. London: Bell and
Daldy, 1873.
——. Friedrich Schlegel: Dialogue on Poetry and Literary Aphorisms. Edited with
an introduction by Ernst Behler and Roman Struc. University Park: Pennsylvania
State University Press, 1968.
Page 5 of 6
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Texts by Authors from the Romantic Era
Page 6 of 6
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Other Texts and Secondary Literature
——. “Geselligkeit und Gesellschaft. Die Geburt der Dialektik aus dem Geist der
Konversation in Schleiermachers ‘Versuch einer Theorie des geselligen
Betragens.’” In Salons der Romantik. Beiträge eines Wiepersdorfer Kolloquiums
Page 1 of 23
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Other Texts and Secondary Literature
zu Theorie und Geschichte des Salons, edited by Hartwig Schultz, 45–61. Berlin:
Walter de Gruyter, 1997.
Bate, W. Jackson. The Burden of the Past and the English Poet. Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press, 1970.
Beiser, Frederick. The Fate of Reason: German Philosophy from Kant to Fichte.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993.
Page 2 of 23
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Other Texts and Secondary Literature
Bell, John. The Continuous and the Infinitesimal in Mathematics and Philosophy.
Milan: Polimetrica, 2006.
Berlin, Isaiah. The Roots of Romanticism. Edited by Henry Hardy. Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press, 1999.
Berman, Russell A., Christina Crosby, Frederick L. de Naples, et al. “Why Major
in Literature? What We Say to Our Students.” PMLA 117, no. 3 (2002): 487–521.
——. The Utopian Function of Art and Literature. Translated by Jack Zipes and
Frank Mecklenburg. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1993.
Bloom, Harold. The Anxiety of Influence. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1973.
Page 3 of 23
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Other Texts and Secondary Literature
Boyle, Nicholas. Goethe, the Poet and the Age. vol. 2, Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 2000.
Bransen, Jan. The Antinomy of Thought: Maimonian Skepticism and the Relation
between Thoughts and Objects. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1991.
Bubbio, Diego Paolo and Paul Redding, ed. Religion after Kant: God and Culture
in the Idealist Era. Newcastle upon Tyne, UK: Cambridge Scholars Press, 2012.
Budick, Sanford. Kant and Milton. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press,
2010.
——. Truth, Thought, Reason: Essays on Frege. Oxford: Oxford University Press,
2005.
Page 4 of 23
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Other Texts and Secondary Literature
——. Must We Mean What We Say? Updated Edition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press, 1969.
Chaouli, Michel. The Laboratory of Poetry: Chemistry and Poetics in the Work of
Friedrich Schlegel. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 2002.
Page 5 of 23
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Other Texts and Secondary Literature
——. The Faith of the Faithless: Experiments in Political Theology. New York:
Verso, 2012.
(p.322) Crone, Rainer, and Alexandra Von Stosch. Anish Kapoor. London:
Prestel, 2008.
Dalhaus, Carl. The Idea of Absolute Music. Translated by Roger Lustig. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 1989.
Daston, Lorraine, and Peter Galison. Objectivity. New York: Zone Books;
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2007.
Derrida, Jacques. The Post Card: From Socrates to Freud and Beyond.
Translated by Alan Bass. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1980.
——. Glas. Translated by John P. Leavey and Richard Rand. Lincoln: University of
Nebraska Press, 1990.
Diamond, Cora. “Losing Your Concepts.” Ethics 98, no. 2 (1988): 255–77.
——. Das Erlebnis und die Dichtung: Lessing, Goethe, Novalis, Hölderlin. In
Gesammelte Schriften, vol. 26. Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 2005.
Page 6 of 23
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Other Texts and Secondary Literature
Dyson, George. Turing’s Cathedral: The Origins of the Digital Universe. New
York: Random House, 2012.
——. “La tragédie du paysage: Caspar David Friedrich.” In L’espace pictural, 69–
90. Paris: Les Belles Lettres, 2011.
Page 7 of 23
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Other Texts and Secondary Literature
——. “Herders Beitrag zur Entstehung der Idee romantisch.” In Die Aktualität
der Romantik, edited by M. N. Forster and K. Vieweg. Berlin: LIT, 2012.
——. Das Sagbare und das Unsagbare. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1989.
——. Der kommende Gott: Vorlesungen über die Neue Mythologie. Frankfurt am
Main: Suhrkamp, 1982.
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Other Texts and Secondary Literature
Frank, Manfred, Ulrich Schnabel, and Thomas Assheuer. “Ein Gespräch mit dem
Tübinger Philosophen Manfred Frank über die Illusionen der Hirnforschung und
ihre zweifelhaften politischen Folgen.” Die Zeit, August 29, 2009. http://
www.zeit.de/2009/36/Hirnforschung
Page 9 of 23
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Other Texts and Secondary Literature
——. Truth and Method. Translated by Joel Weinsheimer and Donald G. Marshall.
New York: Continuum, 2003.
Gibson, John. Fiction and the Weave of Life. Oxford: Oxford University Press,
2007.
——. Wolfgang Huemer, and Luca Pocci, eds. A Sense of the World: Essays on
Fiction, Narrative, and Knowledge. New York: Routledge, 2007.
Gigante, Denise. Life: Organic Form and Romanticism. New Haven: Yale
University Press, 2009.
Page 10 of 23
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Other Texts and Secondary Literature
Gould, Timothy. Hearing Things: Voice and Method in the Writing of Stanley
Cavell. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1998.
Grave, Johannes. Caspar David Friedrich und die Theorie des Erhabenen.
Weimar: VDG-Verlag, 2001.
Heise, Urusla. Nach der Natur. Das Artensterben und die moderne Kultur.
Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 2010.
Henrich, Dieter. “Hölderlin über Urteil und Seyn: Eine Studie zur Entstehung
des Idealismus.” Hölderlin-Jahrbuch 14 (1965–66): 73–96.
Page 11 of 23
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Other Texts and Secondary Literature
Irmscher, Hans Dietrich. “Witz und Analogie als Instrumente des entdeckenden
Erkennens.” In “Weitstrahlsinniges” Denken: Studien zu Johann Gottfried
Herder von Hans Dietrich Irmscher, edited by Marion Heinz and Violetta Stolz,
206–35. Würzburg: Königshausen & Neumann, 2009.
Jahnke, Hans Niels. “Mathematics and Culture: The Case of Novalis.” Science in
Context 4 (1991): 279–95.
Page 12 of 23
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Other Texts and Secondary Literature
Jamme, Christoph, and Hans Schneider, eds. Mythologie der Vernunft. Hegels
ältestes Systemprogramm des deutschen Idealismus. Frankfurt am Main:
Suhrkamp, 1988.
Kapoor, Anish. “‘I Don’t Know Where I’m Going.’” Interview with Alastair Sooke,
The Telegraph, September 26, 2006. http://www.telegraph.co.uk/culture/art/
3655568/I-dont-know-where-Im-going.html
——. Mind in a Physical World: An Essay on the Mind-Body Problem and Mental
Causation. Cambridge: MIT Press, 2000.
Kittler, Wolf. “Falling after the Fall: The Analysis of the Infinite in Kleist’s
Marionettentheater.” In Heinrich von Kleist and Modernity, edited by Bernd
Fischer and Tim Mehigan, 279–94. Rochester, NY: Camden House, 2011.
Kroeber, Karl. Ecological Literary Criticism: Romantic Imagining and the Biology
of Mind. New York: Columbia University Press, 1994.
Page 13 of 23
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Other Texts and Secondary Literature
Lambert, Johann Heinrich. Neues Organon oder Gedanken über die Erforschung
und Bezeichnung des Wahren und dessen Unterscheidung vom Irrthum und
Schein. Leipzig: Johann Mendler, 1764. http://www.kuttaka.org/~JHL/
L1764a.html.
Larmore, Charles. The Romantic Legacy. New York: Columbia University Press,
1996.
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Other Texts and Secondary Literature
——. “Schiller and the Genesis of German Romanticism.” In Essays in the History
of Ideas, 207–27.
Martyn, David. “Figures of the Mean: Freedom, Progress, and the Law of
Statistical Averages in Kleist’s ‘Allerneuester Erziehungsplan.’” Germanic
Review 85 (2010): 44–62.
Millán, Elizabeth and John H. Smith, eds. Goethe Yearbook. vol. 18 (2011).
Page 15 of 23
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Other Texts and Secondary Literature
(p.329) Nahin, Paul J. The Logician and the Engineer: How George Boole and
Claude Shannon Created the Information Age. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press, 2013.
Nassar, Dalia. The Romantic Absolute: Being and Knowing in German Romantic
Philosophy, 1795–1804. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2013.
——. “Schelling und die Frühromantik: Das Unendliche und das Endliche im
Kunstwerk.” Accessed April 20, 2013. http://www.academia.edu/656856/
Schelling_und_die_Fruhromantik_Das_Unendliche_und_das_Endliche_im_Kunstwerk.
——. “Sensibility and Organic Unity: Kant, Goethe and the Plasticity of
Cognition.” Intellectual History Review (forthcoming 2014).
Page 16 of 23
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Other Texts and Secondary Literature
——. “On Truth and Lying in a Non-Moral Sense.” In The Birth of Tragedy and
Other Writings, edited by Raymond Guess and Ronald Speirs, translated by
Ronald Speirs, 139–53. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999.
Nuzzo, Angelica. Kant and the Unity of Reason. West Lafayette, IN: Purdue
University Press, 2005.O’Regan, Cyril. “Aesthetic Idealism and its relation to
theological formation: reception and critique.” In The Impact of Idealism. The
Legacy of Post-Kantian German Thought, vol. 4: Religion, edited by Nicholas
Adams, 142-66. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2013.
Pater, Walter. The Renaissance: Studies in Art and Poetry. Berkeley: University of
California Press, 1980 (1893).
Plantinga, Alvin, and Nicholas Wolterstorff. Faith and Rationality. Notre Dame,
IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1983.
Prager, Brad. “Kant in Caspar David Friedrich’s Frames.” Art History 25 (2002):
68–86.
Putnam, Hilary. Representation and Reality. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1991.
Page 17 of 23
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Other Texts and Secondary Literature
Roe, Shirley A. Matter, Life, and Generation: 18th-Century Embryology and the
Haller-Wolff Debate. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981.
——. Literature and the Touch of the Real. Newark: University of Delaware
Press, 2004.
Page 18 of 23
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Other Texts and Secondary Literature
Searle, John. The Rediscovery of the Mind. Cambridge: MIT Press, 1992.
Smith, John H. Dialogues between Faith and Reason: The Death and Return of
God in Modern German Thought. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 2011.
Speiser, Andreas. “Die Grundlagen der Mathematik von Plato bis Fichte.” Eranos
Jahrbuch 14 (1946): 11–38.
Page 19 of 23
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Other Texts and Secondary Literature
Stolnitz, Jerome. “On the Cognitive Triviality of Art.” British Journal of Aesthetics
32, no. 3 (1992): 191–200.
Surber, Jere Paul, ed. Metacritique: The Linguistic Assault on German Idealism.
Amherst, NY: Humanity Books, 2001.
Trabant, J. Apeliotes oder der Sinn der Sprache. Wilhelm von Humboldts
Sprachbild. Berlin: Akademie Verlag, 1986.
Tuinen, Sjoerd van, and Niamh McDonnell, eds. Deleuze and the Fold: A Critical
Reader. New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2010.
Page 20 of 23
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Other Texts and Secondary Literature
Wallace, David Foster. Everything and More: A Compact History of Infinity. New
York: Norton: 2003.
Page 21 of 23
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Other Texts and Secondary Literature
Wolfe, Charles T. “Why Was There No Controversy over Life in the Scientific
Revolution?” In Controversies within the Scientific Revolution, edited by V.
Boantza and M. Dascal, 187–221. Amsterdam: John Benjamins, 2011.
Page 22 of 23
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Other Texts and Secondary Literature
——. “Teleology then and now: The question of Kant’s relevance for
contemporary controversies over function in biology.” Studies in History and
Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 37 (2006): 748–770.
Zeuch, Ulrike. Das Unendliche: Höchste Fülle oder Nichts? Zur Problematik von
Friedrich Schlegels Geist-Begriff und dessen geistesgeschichtlichen
Voraussetzungen. Würzburg: Königshausen & Neumann, 1991.
——. “Gehört das Ich zur Natur? Geistige und organische Natur in Schellings
Naturphilosophie.” Philosophisches Jahrbuch 108 (2001): 41–57.
Page 23 of 23
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Index
(p.335) Index
absolute idealism. See idealism
absolute, the,
epistemological ground of, 24
experience of, 213, 250
definition of, 130–131
in Hölderlin, 130, 131–132, 136–137, 139–140
irrepresentability
as antinomial attempt, 150
as endless striving, 18, 28–29 (see also infinite striving)
and gap between finite and infinite, 190
and limits of language, 170, 173
magnitude, questions of, 188–189
and reason, 36
in relation to the subject, 210, 247
in Schlegel, F., 170
temporality of, 247
Adorno, Theodor W., 150, 159 n14
aesthetics
creativity in, 41
and Naturphilosophie, 41
romantic, 39
and the truth of art, 41
See also beauty; sublime
“annihilation of nature,” 203, 210, 215
antifoundationalism, 5, 23–25, 30, 37–38, 150. See also Schlegel, Friedrich von
Aquinas, Saint Thomas, 227
archetype, theory of, 33, 193, 302
Arnim, Achim von, 191
Athäneum (journal), 2, 9 n2, 10 n6, 10 n7, 114
Austin, J. L., 179
Bate, Jonathan, 298
Page 1 of 15
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Index
beauty
in art and nature, 122
as completion of science, 154–155
as harmony of parts, 162 n42
as intuition of perfection, 40
in Kant’s Copernican Revolution, 39
Neoplatonic vs. Kantian, 189
sublime, as opposed to, 188
truth, as not equivalent to, 162 n39
See also sublime
being
and consciousness, 27, 251
and identity, 19, 22
Beiser, Frederick
on freedom, 203–206
on Novalis, 259
Romantic Imperative, The, 202–203, 209, 210, 213
romanticism
interpretation of, 2–3, 259–260, 264–265
and politics, 205
and religion, 213
and Spinoza, 209
Ben David, Lazarus, 242–243
Berlin, Isaiah, 276
Bildung
alternative conceptions of, 93, 105–106
definition of, 92
(p.336) in Hegel, 105
in Schleiermacher, 99, 105–106
and science, 216
Bloch, Ernst, 215–216
Blumenberg, Hans, 289
Boeckh, August, 80
Brandt, Reinhard, 190
Brentano, Clemens, 191
Burge, Tyler, 161 n36, 227, 229–230
Cavell, Stanley, 152–153, 165, 167, 176
complementarity thesis, 151–155
computationalism, 222–228, 231–232
constellation research, 15–16, 18. See also Henrich, Dieter
Corngold, Stanley, 140
Crary, Jonathan, 277
Critchely, Simon, 150
De Man, Paul, 140
Diamond, Cora, 153
Diez, Carl Immanuel, 25
drives, 136–138, 290–291
emotion in fiction and reality, 174–175, 177. See also literature; poetry
empiricism, romantic
Page 2 of 15
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Index
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Index
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Index
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Index
“On the Cognition and Sensation of the Human Soul,” 275, 277, 281, 282, 291–292
his philosophy of language, 69
poetry
definition of, 275
and knowledge, 287, 288, 294–295n23
and language, 283, 289, 290, 291
on sensation, 282, 285–286
on translation, 81
Treatise on the Origin of Language, 68, 225, 291
hermeneutics
and philosophy, 95
in Schlegel, F., 77, 79, 80
in Schleiermacher
and circularity, 76, 101
and divination, 96
and Gadamer, 94, 107 n14, 108 n24
and history of discipline, 93, 100
and individuality, 94–96, 97, 98, 104
interpretations of, 74, 75, 96, 97
and philosophy, 108 n22
and preconceptions of interpreter, 102
and primary vs. secondary thoughts, 98–99
and psychology, 96;
of religious texts, 100
and Ricoeur, Paul, 107 n7
his rules for implementation, 75
social and ethical motivations of, 99
its universalization, 94
validity, question of 97
See also translation theory
Heidegger, Martin, 150
Henrich, Dieter, 15–16, 18. See also constellation research
Herbert, Paul von, 16
Hindenburg, Carl Friedrich, 224
history
circular view of, 48
chaotic view of, 51
Hegel’s view of, 49
and the “historical turn” in Germany, 57
Kant’s view of, 63 n4
linear view of, 50
paths of, romantic and elliptical, 47
romantic criticisms of views of, 52–53
value of its philosophical investigation, 54
Hoffbauer, Johann Christoph, 225
Hölderlin, Friedrich
absolute, conception of the, 130, 131–132, 136–137, 139–140
Diotma poems, 139
exteriority, experience of, 131, 132
Page 6 of 15
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Index
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Index
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Index
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Index
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Index
on sociability, 116–117
“symphilosophy,” concept of, 113, 120
on universal knowledge, 260
Wittgenstein, influence on, 153
Oetinger, Friedrich Christoph, 206, 215, 217 n5
“Oldest System Program of German Idealism,” 160 n24, 202, 214, 217 n13
painting. See Friedrich, Caspar David
Pantheism Controversy, 131
Pfau, Thomas, 134–135
philology, 148
philosophy of art. See aesthetics
philosophy of history. See history
philosophy of language, 68–71, 176–177, 225. See also Schlegel, Friedrich von
philosophy of mathematics. See mathematics
philosophy of science. See science
Pinkard, Terry, 132
Ploucquet, Gottfried, 22, 206, 224–225
poetry
classical vs. romantic, 78
in Herder, 275, 287, 288, 294–295n23, 283, 289, 290, 291
in Hölderlin, 59, 130, 136, 137, 138–144
and individuality, 95
and literature, 157 n8
in Novalis, 233–234
Plato’s criticism of, 147, 148, 151
progressive universal, 47, 48, 52, 114–116, 252, 257 n23
reality, in relation to, 175–179
and representation, 27, 140, 227, 233–234, 276, 288
in Schelling, 149
in Schlegel, F., 115, 163–165, 172–179, 179 n6, 183 n81, 184 n89, 252
and science, 149, 152, 274–275, 292, 292 n2, 294–295n23
translation of, 83
value of, 154, 156, 156 n1
See also literature
poststructuralism (postmodernism), 15
priority thesis, 151–155, 156 n1
Puteanus, Erycius, 228
Putnam, Hilary, 231
realism, 27, 35–36, 41
reflection, 19–20, 129–131, 133–140, 144
(p.342) Reinhold, Karl Leonard
Attempt at a New Theory of the Human Faculty of Representation, 20–21
on consciousness, 226
Diez’s criticism of, 25
Fichte as successor to, 16
Fichte’s criticism of, 226, 229–230
Jena romanticism, in relation to, 16–17
and Kant, 226, 229
and Novalis, 221
Page 11 of 15
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Index
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Index
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Index
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020
Index
Page 15 of 15
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2020. All
Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: University College London; date: 15 May 2020