Critical Thinking - The Basics, 2nd Edition
Critical Thinking - The Basics, 2nd Edition
CRITICAL THINKING
THE BASICS
THE BASICS
The Basics is a highly successful series of accessible guidebooks
which provide an overview of the fundamental principles of a sub-
ject area in a jargon-free and undaunting format.
Intended for students approaching a subject for the first time,
the books both introduce the essentials of a subject and provide
an ideal springboard for further study. With over 50 titles span-
ning subjects from Artificial Intelligence to Women’s Studies, The
Basics are an ideal starting point for students seeking to under-
stand a subject area.
Each text comes with recommendations for further study and
gradually introduces the complexities and nuances within a subject.
AMERICAN PHILOSOPHY BIOETHICS (SECOND EDITION)
NANCY STANLICK ALASTAIR V. CAMPBELL
EVOLUTION ATHEISM
SHERRIE LYONS GRAHAM OPPY
CRITICAL THINKING
THE BASICS
Second Edition
Stuart Hanscomb
vi
CONTENTS
List of Boxes xi
Preface and Acknowledgements xiii
Introduction 1
0.1 What is critical thinking? 3
0.2 Critical thinking and the spirit of philosophy 6
0.3 The historical and academic context of critical
thinking as a discipline 12
0.4 Alternative approaches 16
0.5 Critical thinking and ethics 17
0.6 This book’s approach (1): Overview of contents 19
0.7 This book’s approach (2): The use of examples 20
Further reading 23
viii CONTENTS
CONTENTS ix
Conclusion 246
Glossary 251
References 261
Index 267
ii
xi
BOXES
PREFACE AND
ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS
INTRODUCTION
My husband says I’m argumentative. He’s wrong though, and here are
three reasons why … (Sacha T. Burnstorm, pers. comm.)
DOI: 10.4324/9781003247944-1
2
2 INTRODUCTION
INTRODUCTION 3
ARGUMENTS
4 INTRODUCTION
INTRODUCTION 5
6 INTRODUCTION
Advice with respect to how this book can facilitate the second of these
can be found at the end of this chapter (and I would urge you to read
this section carefully, since to get the most from this subject it is vital to
combine what textbooks offer with external experiences and materials).
With respect to the third point, although critical thinking is about
avoiding errors in our reasoning and assessing the quality of argu-
ments, in a very important sense it is also about us. It is about us as
human beings, vulnerable to biases in our thinking, to moods and
emotions that can cloud our judgement, and to character dispositions
that entrench these tendencies. And it is about us as individuals with
a desire to know more about our strengths and weaknesses and how
to eliminate, mitigate, and improve upon them.
This book, then, is about how we can improve our thinking so that
we become better disposed to making good judgements, and it is also
therefore about self-knowledge: greater awareness of the aspects of
psychology and character that are relevant to constructive delibera-
tion and improved decision-making. Put another way, critical thinking
can contribute to self-improvement, and knowing about the self can
help improve critical thinking. This book considers the importance
of critical thinking as part of the wider question of how to live well.
INTRODUCTION 7
since based on such insecure principles could only be most doubtful and
uncertain; so that I had undertaken seriously once in my life to rid myself
of all the opinions I had adopted up to then, and to begin afresh from the
foundations. (1968, p.95)
Descartes is expressing not just a desire for truth, but recognition that
the search for it must involve self-examination. In the eighteenth
century, Enlightenment thinking championed reason over supersti-
tion and tradition in politics and ethics as well as science. Reason was
regarded not just as the route to the truth, but as a virtue that benefits
the individual and society. Through reason comes progress, and to be
willing to apply rational thinking to all issues is to take responsibil-
ity for one’s destiny; to grow up. In his 1784 essay An Answer to the
Question:What is Enlightenment? Immanuel Kant emphasised freedom
from ‘self-incurrent tutelage’ – the ‘resolution and courage’ to think
for ourselves ([1784] 1963, p.3).
These are examples of great philosophers and scientists challeng-
ing established knowledge, such as religious dogma and ancient sci-
entific assumptions. Most of us are not going to be the authors of
world-changing theories, but the lesson from philosophy for most
individuals concerns the attitude we take to our own lives and the
issues that define them. Basic to this is the importance of thinking
through our beliefs rigorously, testing them out where possible, and
taking responsibility for them. In this vein, the nineteenth-century phi-
losopher Søren Kierkegaard observed in The Present Age:
There are handbooks on everything, and generally speaking education
will soon consist of knowing letter-perfect a larger or smaller compen-
dium of observations from such handbooks, and one will excel in propor-
tion to his skill in pulling out the particular one, just as the typesetter
picks out letters. ([1846] 1979, p.104)
8 INTRODUCTION
exactly does this claim mean?’, What can we infer from it?’, ‘How do
I know it is the truth?’, ‘Why is it important to know about?’, and
‘What difference might knowing about it make to my life?’ While
critical thinking is not proposing the impossible task of understand-
ing everything, it is proposing that there are dispositions or attitudes
we can develop that make us less susceptible to error; that enable us
to ask the right questions and, perhaps most importantly, to have a
reflective awareness of what we, as individuals, do and do not know.
Features of what is now called critical thinking are foundational to
the mood and practice of modern philosophy, but the prototypical
critical thinker is the ancient Athenian, Socrates (469–399 BCE). He
did not write anything, but his ideas, personality, and philosophi-
cal approach, as presented in Plato’s dialogues, are hugely influential.
Socrates (like his pupil Plato, and Plato’s pupil Aristotle) was con-
cerned about the level of ignorance he encountered in those around
him, including teachers and statesmen. More importantly, he was
exercised by people’s ignorance of their own ignorance. For example,
in the Apology, after engaging a politician with a reputation for wis-
dom in dialogue he concludes:
It is only too likely that neither of us has any knowledge to boast of; but
he thinks he knows something that he does not know, whereas I am quite
conscious of my ignorance. … I am wiser than he is to this small extent,
that I do not think that I know what I do not know. (Plato, 1993, p.42)
INTRODUCTION 9
10 INTRODUCTION
INTRODUCTION 11
12 INTRODUCTION
INTRODUCTION 13
14 INTRODUCTION
More recently there has been growing interest in the links between
critical thinking and psychology, and in particular the now extensive
and quite well-understood range of biases that can affect judgement
and decision-making. If there are identifiable kinds of widespread
mistakes in reasoning that are consistently revealed in informal
argumentation – for instance seeing causal relationships where they
do not exist, making hasty generalisations, or determining the quality
of an argument by reference to irrelevant attributes of the arguer –
then it is reasonable to expect that there are underlying cognitive
biases that predispose us to make these errors. Researchers in the
fields of philosophy and psychology have tended to follow parallel
paths in their investigations of reasoning, but convergence is now
happening that is substantially enriching the interdisciplinary field of
critical thinking (e.g., Halpern, 2014).
The motivation of critical thinking scholars is to make logic use-
ful and have direct, practical application to daily life so that someone
who took a course in it would not only be better at logic, but a better
deliberator on worldly affairs, and show improvement in general aca-
demic abilities. Similar desires inspired the education-oriented ‘criti-
cal thinking movement’ in the US in the 1980s. Prime movers such
as Richard Paul and Robert Ennis (who were also instrumental in
developing informal logic) were critical of the standards and standing
of critical thinking in American school curricula and sought, with
some success, to raise its profile and generate materials and tech-
niques for its teaching. ‘Our overemphasis on rote memorization and
recall of facts’ says Richard Paul:
does not serve us well. We must exchange our traditional picture of knowl-
edge and learning for one that generates and rewards active, independent,
self-directed learning so that students can gather and assess data rigor-
ously and critically. We need to abandon methods that make students pas-
sive recipients of information and adopt those that transform them into
active participants in their own intellectual growth. (1995, p.45)
INTRODUCTION 15
16 INTRODUCTION
INTRODUCTION 17
18 INTRODUCTION
INTRODUCTION 19
20 INTRODUCTION
INTRODUCTION 21
With this in mind I will make a few points about the examples and
exercises found in this book:
22 INTRODUCTION
INTRODUCTION 23
FURTHER READING
24 INTRODUCTION
NOTE
1 Known as just Informal Logic since the mid-1980s.
25
RATIONALITY AND
COGNITIVE BIASES
1.1 RATIONALITY
In an investigation of critical thinking, two forms of rationality are
important to distinguish: ‘cognitive’ and ‘practical’ (or ‘functional’).
DOI: 10.4324/9781003247944-2
26
TWO SYSTEMS
A lot has been written about echo chambers in recent years, and it
is fairly straightforward to see how being overly exposed, through
our news and social media preferences, to people who share our
views can only exaggerate the effect of the confirmation bias (see
also social proof, below).
Unfortunately, confirmation bias is not limited to informal
reasoning – the academic reporting of research findings is prone to it
as well. In theory though, avoiding it in this context is relatively sim-
ple. One method, especially common in medicine and other areas of
applied science research, is known as a ‘systematic review’. This puts
in place rules for unbiased selection of previous findings on a subject,
along with questions to guide their assessment. It is designed to avoid
bias caused by non-rigorous searches or a lack of open-mindedness
on the part of the researcher. Crucially, although the original research
of the scientist is peer reviewed in academic journals, the review part
of it (i.e., a summary of the findings to date) is not always subject
to the same scrutiny. The systematic review approach insists on peer
review of this aspect and thus requires transparency with respect to
the scientist’s method of selection and evaluation.2
In order to protect ourselves from the confirmation bias in eve-
ryday thinking we need to develop the habit of looking for disconfirm-
ing evidence. This is made all the harder, however, if we consider that
our worldviews are themselves partly the product of the other biases
and heuristics that will be discussed in this section. In other words,
the confirmation bias will amplify beliefs that are already under the
influence of a range of other distorting effects.
33
The ‘pleasant illusions’ Paul refers to have become known as the self-
serving bias (Taylor and Brown, 1988): an automatic and systematic
tendency to overestimate those features of ourselves and the world
that are core to our sense of self-esteem and our motivation to suc-
ceed. These include our positive attributes (traits and abilities), the
amount of control we have over events that affect us, and how bright
our future will be in comparison to the futures of our peers. A gen-
eralised bias that serves these illusions sees us taking too much credit
for successes and not enough responsibility for our failures. And in
case you’re wondering, we also tend to self-servingly see ourselves as
less susceptible to cognitive biases than other people – what has been
termed the ‘bias blind spot’ (Pronin, Lin, and Ross, 2002).
Not everyone is subject to these self-serving illusions, but it seems
that the majority of us are. The implication of this research is that
we are not particularly good at dealing with reality square on, and
34
Most complied, and once the deed was done these participants were
then asked to rate the actual interestingness of the experiment, and
one group rated it much more highly than the others. You might
think it was the $20 group – perhaps because their elevated mood
caused by the not insubstantial payment had transferred to the expe-
rience as a whole – but it was the $1 group.The (now well-accepted)
reasoning goes that telling a lie to a peer for the sake of $1 is typi-
cally incompatible with a person’s self-image (as decent, honest, etc.);
$20, on the other hand, appears to be an acceptable trade-off. Self-
deception is thus enlisted by the $1 participants to preserve their
integrity, but as it is a psychological stretch to deny they had accepted
the money or told the lie, they instead subconsciously altered their
opinion on how engaging the task was.
This is an example of cognitive dissonance; a term coined by
psychologist Leon Festinger in the 1950s referring to the discom-
fort we feel when we become aware of an inconsistency among our
beliefs, attitudes, and actions. Faced with this tension, ego-defensive
strategies can be enlisted to help maintain a belief or attitude that is
important to us (often one that is associated with our self-image).
Rather than reappraise what’s important, we instead reinterpret other
features of the event so as to suppress the contradiction.
Cognitive dissonance is an aspect of a broad set of theories, now
well established, that point to a profound need for self-consistency.
Once we commit to something (a cause, a belief, a course of action)
‘we will encounter personal and interpersonal pressures to behave
consistently with that commitment’ (Cialdini, 2007, p.57). ‘Personal
pressure’ because most of us desire the character integration and
rationality that consistency is so central to; ‘interpersonal pressure’
because our need to rely on people being true to their word makes
us highly condemning of promise-breakers. For this reason, public
declarations or pledges are extremely powerful techniques for ensur-
ing that intentions are carried out.
The strength of this need for consistency is demonstrated by a
range of persuasion techniques which induce compliance in people
with respect to a trivial commitment, and then use this to leverage
more significant, but apparently consistent, behaviours. Known as the
‘foot-in-the-door’ technique, if I answer ‘yes’ to the telesales person’s
trivial question ‘Would you like a better deal on your phone?’, I’m
36
RECIPROCATION
grimace, for example, looks a lot like a human smile, so short of the
necessary specialist knowledge this heuristic might well lead us to
conclude they are happy when quite the opposite is the case. (More
will be said about stereotyping when we discuss generalisations in
Chapter 8.)
The other kind of mistake caused by the representativeness heu-
ristic is the overlooking of other critical questions we should be
asking in certain situations. A famous example used by Tversky and
Kahneman (1983) is the ‘Linda Problem’, which goes like this:
Linda is 31 years old, single, outspoken, and very bright. She majored in
philosophy. As a student she was deeply concerned with issues of dis-
crimination and social justice, and also participated in antinuclear dem-
onstrations. Please [indicate] the most likely alternative:
a) Linda is a bank teller
b) Linda is a bank teller and is active in the feminist movement
were lucky to have him, and it turned out he was probably right.
Stoke were even worse under Hughes’s replacement and ended up
relegated.
Another twist on base rates is the fallacy of suggesting false back-
ground rates in order to minimise or normalise a situation that is
in fact not trivial or normal at all. In a speech after the Charleston
church shooting in June 2015, President Obama addressed just this
fallacy:
Let’s be clear: at some point, we as a country will have to reckon with the
fact that this type of mass violence does not happen in other advanced
countries … with this kind of frequency.4
Anchoring and the contrast effect are examples of how the con-
textualizing of information can influence our perceptions and inter-
pretations. Anchoring happens when our judgement of a quantity
(or other value) is biased by an initial piece of information. Asked,
for example, to estimate the exact length of the Mississippi River
(which is around 2,300 miles), experimental participants who had
previously been asked if it was ‘more or less than 200 miles long’
guessed on average that it was around 1000 miles. By comparison, the
average estimate of participants who had previously been asked if it
was ‘more or less than 20,000 miles long’ was much larger – around
8,000 miles (McElroy and Dowd, 2007).
Anchoring is known to be a pervasive and powerful phenomenon
in a range of real-life as well as laboratory settings; so much so that
one of the few books written by the acclaimed psychology of per-
suasion academic and practitioner Robert Cialdini, is almost entirely
devoted to it (see Cialdini, 2017). It is most effective in situations
where attention is lower and people have limited knowledge of the
subject, but it can influence experts’ judgements as well. In nego-
tiations, for example, there can be an advantage in making the first
move because even a demand expected to be excessive will have a
42
SOCIAL PROOF
1.3 FRAMING
A generalised idea that can be applied to most examples of persuasive
communication is framing. The basic meaning of framing is cap-
tured by expressions like ‘frame of reference’, or ‘frame of mind’. In
communication it refers to a way of looking at things, of putting an
‘angle’ or ‘spin’ on a particular issue. In essence it involves emphasis-
ing some aspects of the issue at the expense of others.
Whereas some might say that my Uncle Vance is an alcoholic, oth-
ers would say he’s a ‘party animal’. Views on the ‘partygate’ scandal
that contributed to Boris Johnson’s declining credibility as UK prime
minister rested in part on whether boozy gatherings in Downing
Street during Covid lockdowns could be convincingly framed as
‘work meetings’. When Vladimir Putin characterised Russia’s actions
toward Ukraine in February 2022 as a ‘special military operation’
(rather than an invasion or a war) it was part of a frame that presented
the conflict as justified self-defence in the face of NATO expansion-
ism (rather than as unprovoked aggression).
Frames are selected by communicators to enhance the effective-
ness of messages, but the filters we automatically apply to informa-
tion also function as frames. All heuristics and biases frame situations
because they are systematically selective in what they lead us to take
from them. As we have seen, there are many ways communicators can
compose messages to take advantage of this.
There are two purposes, broadly speaking, to which framing is put:
Things become more interesting when both sets of needs are rel-
evant. In his Letter from Birmingham Jail, Martin Luther King, Jr.
is attempting to convince an audience, otherwise sympathetic to
his cause, of the value of non-violent civil disobedience. He has
been accused of being an ‘extremist’, a label he at first rejects, but
then accepts with a caveat. He lists various radicals and lawbreak-
ers from history and the Bible – including Jesus, Paul, Lincoln,
and Jefferson – who are foundational to American values. He then
reframes the issue:
The question is not whether we will be extremist, but what kind of extrem-
ists we will be.12
He has selected his argument and the examples he uses with great
care; these are extremists for ‘love’ rather than extremists for ‘hate’. It
is by no means a balanced picture, but at the same time it will pro-
vide a potentially helpful angle for an educated audience to engage
with his argument. Unlike propaganda, it is part of a respectful
dialogue.
As this example also illustrates, an important method of framing
is the use of figurative language. Metaphors, analogies, and allegories
try to explain or illuminate some aspect of the world by compar-
ing it with something recognisable to an audience. Arguments from
analogy work in a similar way, and this will be the subject matter of
Chapter 9.
48
EXERCISES
1. From what you have read in this chapter, draw up a list of things
we could do to protect ourselves from the negative effects of
heuristics and biases. This will include ways to prevent poor
decision-making in groups; protection from those who will
deliberately deploy persuasion techniques to influence us; and
of course protection from our own motivated reasoning.
Some recommendations have been explicitly included in the
chapter and some are implied, but there will be others that
you will be able to think of yourselves based on the chapter’s
content.
2. A good way to gain a better understanding of these biases and
how they operate is to explore their use in contextualized
examples of persuasive communication. Several are mentioned
in this chapter, including speeches by Martin Luther King, Jr.
and Barak Obama. These fall under the neutral definition of
rhetoric, but Twelve Angry Men (see this book’s Introduction)
is full of instances of how dangerous or unconstructive these
biases can be. Other examples can be found across subsequent
chapters, but it is also straightforward enough – and advanta-
geous since you can choose ones that are especially relevant to
your situation – to find your own.
FURTHER READING
• For a review of the anchoring effect see Furnham and Boo (2011);
and there’s an excellent discussion of it in Kahneman (2012, Ch.11).
• For an informative analysis of the components of groupthink see
Baron (2005).
• Largely for reasons of space the ‘exponential growth bias’ is not
covered in this book (it also has fewer connections to other biases,
dispositions, and fallacies than the ones I have included). However,
and not least because it helps explain responses to the Covid
pandemic, it is worth exploring. There are quite a few academic
articles linking the two topics, and a good introduction can be
found in Steven Pinker’s book Rationality (2021, pp.10–12).
NOTES
1 Roads to Freedom (Routledge, 1996), p.116.
2 There is a lot of helpful literature in this area, but one good guide to con-
ducting systematic reviews in healthcare see Khan, K.S., Kunz, R., Kleijnen,
J., and Antes, G. (2003) Five steps to conducting a systematic review. Journal
of the royal society of medicine, 96(3), 118–21.
3 For an excellent (and entertaining) example of negotiation skills, including
the art of concession-making, see Better Call Saul, Season 1, ep.2 (approx. 18
minutes in, but best to watch from the start to appreciate what’s going on).
4 For a transcript see www.theguardian.com/us-news/2015/jun/18/obama-
on-charleston-ive-had-to-make-statements-like-this-too-many-times. Joe
Biden made a similar point after the Robb Elementary shooting in Texas in
May 2022.
5 See, for example, https://climateoutreach.org/reports/ipcc-communications-
handbook/
6 I won’t cite specific sources, but there are many and they are easy to find in
an academic search engine.
7 www.ipsos.com/en-uk/public-hugely-overestimate-how-much-land-uk-
densely-built
8 See, for example, www.bbc.co.uk/news/uk-42554635
9 Discussed in Brown (1986), pp.165–7.
10 Klein, N. This Changes Everything (Penguin, 2014).
11 Wisdom, Information and Wonder (London: Routledge, 1991), p.48.
12 Available at: www.africa.upenn.edu/Articles_Gen/Letter_Birmingham.html
51
DOI: 10.4324/9781003247944-3
52
Quite often they are unpleasant to experience, but they always sig-
nify drama – a need is or is not being met, and thus desire, value, and
purpose are always in tow and encoded in these complex feelings.
The account of emotions I provide in this section should largely
align with our everyday experience of them, and is supported by
extensive psychological and philosophical research in this area. The
components of an emotional response have been unpacked in terms
of cognitive, physiological, and expressive aspects, along with asso-
ciated action-tendencies, but for our purposes vital aspects can be
categorised under cognition and feeling.
COGNITION
(1) something frustrating us; and (2) this being perceived as unfair
or unjust. So, if someone at work gets an undeserved promotion, or
when we witness or read about a legal or political injustice, some
degree of anger is expected.There is an intimate connection between
emotions and desires (and thus values): if we did not care then certain
things happening or not would not bother us and there would be no
emotional response. Emotions, then, imply judgements, and as will
be discussed in upcoming sections, these can be of the rapid System
1 variety, or the result of slower processing.
Along these lines relatively simple and recognisable situations can
be formulated for all emotions. And since responses come in degrees
of intensity, this we take to be related to the extent to which the
occurrence affects the person (e.g., tripping on a paving stone nor-
mally causes less embarrassment than forgetting your uncle’s new
girlfriend’s name who you’ve met twice before). Lastly, notice that
the cognitive element of emotions says nothing about what is in
fact going on in the world, only what we believe to be going on. As
psychotherapists well know, to understand the logic of someone’s
emotional response we need to understand what they care about and
how they interpret a situation in light of these cares.
FEELING
Few would dispute that emotions are feeling states, but there is much
more debate about what kind of feeling this is. Many emotions are
accompanied by felt physiological changes (e.g., body temperature,
the coursing of adrenalin), but when we talk about feeling a cer-
tain way towards something, we are also referring to a quality of the
thoughts that we have towards the object of our emotion. If I am
experiencing guilt because I still haven’t returned my friend Sacha’s
call this is more than a simple judgement of how I have wronged
them, it is a distinctive feeling that is inextricably linked to such a
judgement.
Moods share qualities of the feeling component of an emotion,
but usually without the cognitive aspect – there is no specific thing
that is their focus (at least not consciously). Affect is somewhat ill-
defined, but also important.Very broadly it refers to a wide range of
feelings – including sensations, moods, desires, and emotions – that
54
can be said to be rational when they correspond with our desires and
beliefs.
This line of thought can, however, lead to the claim that it is not
the emotion per se that is irrational, but the belief that causes it.
As philosopher Robert Solomon once put it: ‘emotions are not
irrational; people are irrational’ (2003, p.235). Emotions only appear
irrational because we fail to understand what the person is think-
ing, and often what we think – as the previous chapter helps to
demonstrate – is irrational. For Solomon, the emotions we feel when
we are being irrational simply correspond to these biases, or other
erroneous beliefs. So, when a small failure is pointed out to a narcissist
it is his false belief that he is generally superior to others that causes
his excessively strong reaction of anger. However, the claim here is
that the emotion – the strong reaction – is not the culprit, but rather
the distorted belief which underpins it. Put in this way, the emotion is
neither rational nor irrational, but better understood as non-rational.
This is of immense importance, but it is not the end of the story;
emotions have a reputation for being irrational because emotions and
beliefs do not always correspond. Consider the ‘red mist’ of uncon-
trolled rage, phobias, obsessive jealousy, or the dizzily disproportion-
ate rollercoaster of romantic love. Our emotions appear to make us
think and do bizarre things. Very strong emotions can lead to what
has been called ‘cognitive incapacitation’; a situation in which we are
unable to think clearly. Strong emotions in particular are associated
with:
• Exaggerated (disproportionate) thoughts and behaviour, such as
our perceptions of the other as ‘perfect’ or ‘the one’ when under
the spell of romantic love. In this chapter’s epigraph Taylor Swift
appears to concur. Attention tends to be narrowly focussed and
judgements tend to be black and white.
• Inappropriate or muddled thoughts and behaviour.
We find an example of this second type of distortion in a scene
from Rose Tremain’s novel Music and Silence. Set in 1629, landowner
George Middleton is throwing a New Year’s Eve party, and he’s a
very happy and relieved man. He is deeply in love with his fiancée
Charlotte, and has recently recovered, against the odds, from an oper-
ation to remove gall stones. In the kitchen the waiting coachmen,
56
now sloshed, have consumed a batch of the guests’ mince pies, and
George
knows nothing of all this, but he would nevertheless approve it, because
there is nothing, on this night, of which he is able to disapprove. Even
those neighbours of whom he is not particularly fond. When he looks at
them hopping in a jig or endeavouring to bow gracefully in a minuet his
heart forgives them their futile and irritating habits, their habitual dis-
putatiousness, their past attempts to marry him to their ugly daughters.
Indeed, he finds that he loves them. He even loves their daughters. He and
Charlotte pass from table to table and hands reach out to them, and they
seize these hands with an unconcealed show of affection. ‘[Charlotte]’
says George, ‘you have enabled me to adore the world!’ 1,2
Recall Solomon’s view that ‘emotions are not irrational; people are
irrational’. Should we say that George Middleton is irrational to want
to survive surgery and to marry Charlotte; or to feel relieved after
the operation? If not, then what’s irrational? Presumably it is the
effects of the emotion itself; an example of what is called ‘transferral
of affect’ where the feeling expands beyond its origins and attaches
itself to irrelevant and inappropriate objects and events.
Less well known but of great importance for critical thinking is
that mild emotions and other affective states have distorting effects
as well. Experiments have shown that a person’s emotional frame
of mind will affect their subsequent judgements. For example, if
individuals are induced into a positive or negative mood and then
asked to make judgements on crime or political figures, their mood
will condition the judgements they make.3 This effect is sometimes
referred to as emotional framing, and is a valuable persuasion tech-
nique (for more on framing in general, see Section 1.3). If a speech-
maker finds an angle on a topic that will predictably induce, say,
fear in their audience (e.g., a terrorist threat), they can then use the
resulting mood to elicit the response they want to other issues that
would be less persuasive were the audience not already in an anxious
frame of mind. For example, in many countries immigration is a con-
troversial topic that is associated with a range of emotions, includ-
ing anger, fear, pride, and compassion. An anti-immigration politician
will want to play on anger and fear, and will gain an advantage if
they can introduce the topic to an appropriately primed audience.To
put it another way, emotions and moods embody a confirmation
57
EMOTIONS AS HEURISTICS
they are less so. Discussing the heuristic function of feelings in what
is generally an excellent textbook on emotions Oatley, Keltner, and
Jenkins use this example:
many of the judgements we make are often too complex to review all the
relevant evidence. For instance, a comprehensive answer to the question
of how satisfied you are with your political leader might lead you to think
about current environmental policy, the state of health care, unemploy-
ment and inflation rates, what is being done about global warming …
Given this complexity of so many important judgements, we often rely
on a simpler assessment based on our current feeling, asking ourselves
‘How do I currently feel about this person?’ (2006, p.265)
marginalisation explains its reception might be, this is not what moti-
vated his criticism of the project and its creator. At the time he was
not consciously aware of his reasons, and as a result the efforts of his
rational system were corrupted:
I had used righteous anger as a smokescreen to conceal something more
self-serving. I had used the ‘working class’ as a Trojan horse to advance
my own personal agenda. And I did all of this while believing myself to be
well informed and deeply virtuous, unaware of how personal resentment
was subtly directing my thinking. (ibid, p.209)
news media across the world, and had a galvanising effect on attitudes
towards the Syrian refugee crisis in some countries.
The image of the dead body – dressed like any other little boy –
picked up on a beach and in the arms of a police officer, was unbear-
able. There was some controversy about papers printing the image,
but the Independent in the UK justified it in this way:
The Independent has taken the decision to publish these images because,
among the often glib words about the ‘ongoing migrant crisis’, it is all too
easy to forget the reality of the desperate situation facing many refugees.4
care about, and what we care about has inherent connections with
emotional responses (anger with injustice, compassion with suffer-
ing, fear with threat, guilt with responsibility, and so on). Also, in a
dialogue it is usually the case that we stand to lose or gain something
depending on how the discussion goes – we may perceive it as a
win or a loss, or a mutual exploration of an issue – and in each of
these variations our relationship with other discussants is potentially
affected.
The matter becomes more complex when we consider that emo-
tion is aroused by both the content of an argument and by the way
it is delivered. Language known to express emotion and arouse it in
audiences has been referred to as ‘emotionally charged’ (or sometimes
‘emotionally forceful’). Examples include extreme descriptors such
as ‘awful’, ‘dangerous’, ‘radical’, ‘wonderful’, ‘awesome’; and absolutist
terms such as ‘totally’, ‘completely’, ‘the greatest’, ‘the worst’, ‘always’,
‘never’, ‘eternal’ (forms of expression Donald Trump is fond of). As
we have seen, emotions tend to deal in crude categorisations, a sim-
plified and polarised world in which it is easier to make decisions.
Different audiences will be moved by different words and phrases
associated with linguistic and cultural norms – often connected with
moral values – and a persuasion specialist will know what these are.
And as we also found out in this chapter, ‘charged’ doesn’t necessarily
mean obvious.The unconscious priming of audiences can take many
forms, including the employment of words that will bias readers’ or
listeners’ subsequent judgements.
We should also remind ourselves that a range of non-verbal cues
are associated with emotions, including facial expression, posture,
gesture, and paralinguistic aspects such as volume, pitch, and pace of
delivery. We are typically highly sensitive to these cues when used by
others, and they are notoriously hard for us to control. Even when
trying hard to conceal our feelings, non-verbal signals will leak from
us, perhaps subtly, but still noticeably, for attentive others.
The preceding exploration of emotion and cognition is impor-
tant preparation for formulating, receiving, and assessing arguments.
We are constantly vulnerable to error if we lack self-awareness and
allow strong feelings to bias our judgements. And this is especially
important since some of those who try to persuade us will seek to
undermine our critical thinking in just this way. With this in mind,
66
2.6 CONCLUSION
It is important for an approach to critical thinking that emphasises
cognitive biases, character dispositions, and constructive dialogues to
pay some attention to emotions. In this chapter I have attempted to
formalise some of the, often familiar, ways they are linked to irrational
thinking and biased perceptions, but also to the broad functioning
70
EXERCISES
1. In the introduction to this book I named the film and play
Twelve Angry Men as the best text I know for applying the ideas
of critical thinking. It is essentially a ninety-minute dialogue in
which the twelve jury members argue about a murder case. As
the name suggests, everyone gets angry at some point – even
the impressively temperate Juror 8 – and among many learning
opportunities it affords, it demonstrates the effects of emotions
on dialogue.
Juror 8’s appeal to pity was discussed in this chapter, but
there are countless further examples of emotion playing either
a constructive or (most likely) destructive role in the delibera-
tion. Find examples of:
• Emotion playing a constructive role
• Displays of emotion causing emotional responses in oth-
ers (with positive or negative outcomes)
• Emotion causing others to disengage
• Emotional expression reflecting negatively on the arguer
• A person’s emotional delivery forcing them into a more
extreme position than they might have otherwise settled
for
• Emotion as a distraction, or as a means for avoiding truth
• Constructive or unconstructive handling of emotions in
others
2. In line with what has been discussed in this chapter, monitor
your emotional responses in various contexts, and especially
dialogues that involve the exchange of arguments.
71
FURTHER READING
Many important sources are found in this chapter, all of which are
in the reference list at the end of the book. I must though highlight
Epstein (2014). Also, for a very good philosophy book on emotion
and rationality see Brady (2013); and an equally good psychology
source is the chapter ‘Emotions and Cognition’ in Keltner, Oatley,
and Jenkins (2013).
NOTES
1 Tremain, R. (2000) Music and Silence.Vintage, p. 299. Reproduced by permis-
sion of The Random House Group Ltd.
2 There’s a nice moment in Jonathan Franzen’s recent novel Crossroads that
presents a similar, though less euphoric, transfer of affect (see pp.44–5).
3 For an experiment along these lines, see DeSteno et al. (2004).
4 Withnall, A. (2015) [Article]. Available at: www.independent.co.uk/news/
world/ europe/if-these-extraordinarily-powerful-images-of-a-dead-syrian-
child-washed-up-on-a-beach-dont-change-europes-attitude-to-refugees-
what-will-10482757.html.
5 www.irishexaminer.com/world/arid-30645119.html
72
It is not enough to have a good mind, rather the main thing is to apply it
well. (Rene Descartes, [1641] 1968)
My husband says I’m overly sensitive to criticism. BUT WHAT DOES
HE KNOW? WHO IS HE TO CRITICISE ME? HE’S LUCKY I DON’T
DIVORCE HIM! (Sacha T. Burnstorm, pers. comm.)
Learning about heuristics and biases is not the same thing as learn-
ing to think in ways that avoid their negative effects. Critical think-
ing is something that we need to do, not just know about. However,
the doing is particularly challenging because of the automaticity of
System 1 thinking. We need to develop the habit of critical think-
ing in order to counteract the powerful tendency to think quickly
in situations where thinking slowly would be more beneficial. The
skills of critical thinking thus aim to instil more constructive habits
of thought.
A further level is added, though, in which these skills are moti-
vated by dispositions to think critically. To be a critical thinker in
this sense is having what Ennis calls an ‘inclination’ to think critically.
According to this approach we don’t just ‘do’ critical thinking, but
‘become’ a critical thinker. ‘Becoming’ a critical thinker, however,
does not mean some cultish, full-blooded transformation in your
DOI: 10.4324/9781003247944-4
73
COMMITMENT TO TRUTH
OPEN-MINDEDNESS
MODESTY
SELF-KNOWLEDGE
METACOGNITION
DIALOGICAL DISPOSITIONS
COURAGE
STAYING FOCUSSED
DELIBERATIVE WIT
and about your sleepless nights. Then they will be listening carefully, if
only to try to figure out where you will end up on this question. And when
you tell them, they will understand why. (1991, p.29)
The initial premise has already been explained, but the second
requires some elaboration. One reason constructive dialogue is less
likely if we are not respectful towards other participants is that it
could provide an incentive for them to disengage. A person detecting
signs of disrespect might leave the discussion entirely, or be reluctant
to contribute their full energy, or to be entirely open about their
position and grounds for holding it.
This point brings us to a second argument for why concern for
others is so important for critical thinking. The reasoning here is less
about the functioning of the dialogical process, and more about our
ability to understand the positions that others hold. It has already
been established that open-mindedness is fundamental to critical
thinking, but this is not just a matter of being able to detach our-
selves from our commitments in order to objectively assess alterna-
tives, it is also the ability to really listen to those alternatives with the
right degree of attentiveness. Often the bases of people’s beliefs are
subtle and highly contextual, and in order to truly understand them
86
Sadly, the way that critical thinking is taught (and how its aims and
methods are communicated) too often runs counter to this attitude.
In his article ‘Argument is War … and War is Hell’ (1995) Daniel H.
Cohen is critical of the adversarial, combative way in which argu-
mentation tends to be understood. This, he says, risks creating ‘not
just able arguers, but argumentative arguers: proficient, pedantic and
petty’ (ibid, 180–1). Taking pleasure in argument for argument’s sake,
or seeing the aim as winning the argument rather than establishing
truth, is all part of the dispositional profile of an adversarial approach.
It is something that is readily apparent in the practice of formal
debates, and in the way court cases in many countries are conducted.
As many social media exchanges demonstrate, it can seep more
widely into a culture as well. An upshot, Deborah Tannen (1998, p.9)
points out in her book The Argument Culture, is that ‘you’re usually
not trying to understand what the other person is saying, or what in
their experience leads them to say it. Instead, you’re readying your
response: listening for those weaknesses in logic to leap on.’
In place of the ‘war’ metaphor, Cohen suggests various alternatives,
including collaborative frames such as brainstorming. In place of lis-
tening in order to defeat there is listening motivated by inquisitiveness.
In place of me against you, there is me and you trying to sort out a
problem, the solution to which we might not have been able to reach
alone, and which could end up being a hybrid or synthesis of our
initial, individual positions.
A side-effect of this attitude to dialogues can be a kind of inti-
macy that is profoundly rewarding. The careful, respectful listening,
and thus opening up to the other’s world, is one reason for this.
Another is that the sharing of ideas in a dialogue towards new, mutu-
ally generated, important insights is an excellent basis for bonding.2
Philosopher Bertrand Russell describes his meeting with novelist
Joseph Conrad in a way that demonstrates this potential:
We talked with continually increasing intimacy. We seemed to sink
through layer after layer of what was superficial till gradually both reached
the central fire. It was an experience unlike any other that I have known.
We looked into each other’s eyes, half appalled and half intoxicated to
find ourselves together in such a region. The emotion was as intense
as passionate love, and at the same time all-embracing, I came away
88
bewildered, and hardly able to find my way among ordinary affairs. (Cited
in Yalom, 1980, p.396)
This is an example of what has come to be known as ‘flow’: the
experience of focussed engagement with an intrinsically rewarding
task that you are skilled at and in control of, but which is suitably
challenging and provides immediate feedback. It is associated with
an experience of timelessness (being lost in the moment), non-
self-consciousness (the boundaries of the ego are more supple than
usual), and calmness. According to the concept’s originator – Mihaly
Csikszentmihalyi (2002) – it can be elicited by a range of activities,
including sport, creative work, and one-to-one social encounters.
A non-dialogical variation of flow is what Dewey (1910) calls
‘wholeheartedness’. In contrast to the perseverance needed to main-
tain concentration in some deliberative situations, wholeheartedness
is an intellectual absorption in a subject where ‘the material holds
and buoys [the] mind up and gives an onward impetus to thinking’
(ibid). It is complex, reflective thinking with its own momentum, and
in which questions and ideas arise ‘spontaneously’.
To return to the central point, care for the well-being of others is
an important disposition for a critical thinker to possess, but it should
also be apparent that the practice of critical thinking, if encouraged
in the right ways, can itself serve as a gateway to understanding and
compassion. Critical thinking can thus be motivated not just by
truth-seeking, but by connection and intimacy.
DON’T BE A SMARTARSE
For Ennis, then, the ideal critical thinker will ‘take into account
others’ feelings and level of understanding, avoiding intimidating
or confusing others with their critical thinking prowess’ (ibid). In
other words, don’t be a smartarse. Since their primary intention is
to entertain rather than to seek the truth, caution is needed when
assessing arguments in comedy routines.3 I am, however, going to
consider a story from comedian Stewart Lee. It is an example that
I believe is justified because the comedian’s own published reflec-
tions seem to make it clear that this was a real event and that this
is how he felt about it. During one of his shows, Lee is making a
point about intolerance, and the context is a cab driver who says
to him, out of the blue, ‘all homosexuals should be killed’. Lee asks
him for his reasons.
And then there was a pause, because he’d never had to go to the next
level of the argument … after a moment he said ‘Well, because homo-
sexuality is immoral.’
Offering the example of the ancient Greeks, Lee then explains to
him that ‘morality is not a fixed thing’ and therefore not the best basis
from which to argue this point. The cabbie’s response is:
‘Well, you can prove anything with facts, can’t you?’
Lee continues:
For a minute I went, ‘Yeah.’ And then I thought, ‘Hang on! That’s the
most fantastic way of winning an argument I’ve ever heard! ‘… I’m not
interested in facts. I find they tend to cloud my judgement. I prefer to rely
on instinct and blind prejudice.’4
As abhorrent as the cabbie’s stated view is, Lee is being a smartarse
because the argument he presents is bound to cause confusion. It
deals in historical facts and abstract concepts like moral relativism
that the cabbie probably will not be familiar with. Lee is talking
over his head, and so understood more charitably the response ‘you
can prove anything with facts’ should not be taken literally. Instead,
it should be interpreted along the lines of ‘I don’t understand what
you’re talking about’, or ‘displaying familiarity with technical terms
and giving the appearance of clever arguments can fool some people,
but not me’, or perhaps simply ‘I know when I’m being patronised.’5
90
3.3 CONCLUSION
Dispositions are fundamental to critical thinking because the skills
taught in the next two chapters should be rightly motivated, and
because their effective employment will invariably require wise
judgement. While a wide range of dispositions or virtues can be seen
as relevant to critical thinking, this chapter has identified and dis-
cussed ones that are closer to its heart, such as open-mindedness and
commitment to truth. I also take the position that, since construc-
tive dialogues are basic to the discipline, dispositions relating to care
for others, as well as the practical facilitation of these interactions,
are of great relevance. Finally, the importance of self-knowledge is
an important theme from the opening chapters of this book: the
cognitive and motivational biases that typify human thought, and
the ways emotions can interfere with or enable rational decision-
making. All critical thinking dispositions and skills help us counter-
act or enhance these features, but the self-knowledge derived from
reflection on our personal preferences, priorities and prejudices is
vitally important too.
EXERCISES
1. A particularly valuable exercise I have used in class involves
watching (and/or reading) Twelve Angry Men and assessing the
critical thinking dispositions of some or all the characters in
the play/film. The quality of the content of their arguments,
and especially the way they interact with one another, will
serve as clues to the presence or otherwise of dispositions and
behaviours that have been the subject of this chapter.The same
approach can of course be applied to characters from other
stories or from real-life contexts (such as political debates) as
well. A good example is Cathy Newman’s infamous interview
with Jordan Peterson in 2018 (originally Channel 4, now easily
locatable online).
2. A good way to develop our open-mindedness is through
what’s known as ‘counter-attitudinal advocacy’. This means to
write or speak in favour of a position that you do not hold
93
FURTHER READING
Aside from the in-text references to the ideas of people like Ennis
and Facione, the following sources are particularly relevant to some
of the ideas discussed in this chapter:
• For an interesting discussion of flexibility see Tiberius (2008, Ch.3).
• For a review of research on need for cognitive closure see Webster
and Kruglanski (1997).
• A very useful source of advice for constructive dialogues can again
be found in Robert Ennis (1996a, pp.371–5), and for or a more
in-depth look at the nature of dialogues (including ‘Rules for a
Critical Discussion’) see Walton (2006, Ch.5).
• An excellent source on constructive conversations, including
politeness, is Deborah Tannen (1992); and her later work (1998),
directly about argumentation, offers a wide range of insights into
problems resulting from an excessive emphasis on combative
approaches to disagreements.
NOTES
1 Diana Beech, Attitude is Everything, Times Higher Education, 21.5.15.
2 Cohen and Miller’s (2016) notion of ‘compathy’ in argumentation shares sev-
eral features with what is being discussed here.
3 Although there are of course genuine hybrids, such as Comedy Central’s The
Daily Show, and the performances, writings, and podcasts of people like John
Oliver, Rachel Parris, and Matt Forde.
94
4 How I Escaped My Certain Fate: The Life and Deaths of a Stand-up Comedian
(London: Faber & Faber, 2011) pp.80–2.
5 I should point out that Stewart Lee is not usually a comedian who mocks any-
one vulnerable, such as inarticulate people. Much of what he says and seems
to stand for is actively promoting fairness and non-prejudicial attitudes. (And
of course, what’s astonished/angered him here is the cab driver’s prejudicial
statement.)
95
In this chapter we turn our attention away from the arguer’s cog-
nitive biases, emotions, and dispositions, and towards the nature
of arguments themselves. The majority of the chapter is devoted
to explaining argument reconstruction: the practice of extracting
the essential content and structure of someone’s argument from
the everyday language in which it is expressed or implied. Here
we will encounter concepts and techniques such as ambiguity and
vagueness, straw man arguments, implicit premises, and the prin-
ciple of charity. Prior to this, I will provide a reminder of what an
argument is, and explain how the sentences which comprise the
premises and conclusions must be what are called ‘propositions’ or
‘statements’.
DOI: 10.4324/9781003247944-5
96
Premise 1:
Premise 2:
Conclusion:
P1:
P2:
C:
This would be the structure of a simple two premise argument, such as:
Anything that intensifies racial discrimination should be outlawed.
Capital punishment intensifies racial discrimination. Therefore capital
punishment should be outlawed.
Often arguments are more complex that this, involving many more
premises (some of which might be ‘implicit’), more than one conclu-
sion, and what are known as ‘sub-conclusions’. These variations will
be explored shortly.
You will become better at making these judgements the more you
become familiar with the subject matter of critical thinking, but
more importantly it is a matter of practice. As indicated, argument
reconstruction is primarily a skill. There are a number of guiding
principles and recommendations (set out below), but mastering it
requires doing it, and doing it really quite a lot. This can be tedious
for sure, but with perseverance your improvement will be very appar-
ent, as will the way in which this ability transfers itself to improved
questioning and comprehension in any part of life where arguments
are found.
The basic aim of argument reconstruction is simple enough: distil
the essence of the argument that is being made. It can be understood as
a form of summarising. Critical thinking has been defined as mini-
mising errors in our reasoning by improving our ability to generate
99
Holmes responds:
I say that’s one version of how some people saw her. … As George Bernard
Shaw … said, there were only two views about her, either that she was
miraculous or that she was unbearable. That’s the unbearable version …
REWORDING
The passage below is from Martin Luther King, Jr.’s Letter from
Birmingham Jail. As you will recall from Chapter 1, the overall aim
of the letter was to justify King’s method of non-violent (but some-
times illegal) direct action against forms of white oppression in the
southern states of America. The letter, though published in the press
nationwide, was ostensibly written to members of the white clergy
in Alabama who, though supportive of his cause, were critical of his
methods. One of many arguments he makes is this:
In your statement you asserted that our actions, even though peace-
ful, must be condemned because they precipitate violence. But can this
assertion be logically made? Isn’t this like condemning the robbed man
103
Premises 1–3 could be grouped into a single, very long, premise, but
separating them in this way makes the argument easier to analyse. For
example, we might want to contest the strength of King’s analogy
with the robbed man, but be more satisfied with the Socrates and
Jesus analogies.
In summary then: questions and other non-statements must be
reworded if they are to form part of the reconstruction; but if in any
doubt as to whether significant rewording or condensing of sentences
might lose important content, then leave them in their original form.
The third aim of rewording is to clarify, where relevant and pos-
sible, ambiguous and vague sentences. An ambiguous sentence is one
that has more than one possible meaning, for example:
After the bar room brawl the tables were turned.
This can imply that these ethnic groups are not US children, whereas
what the author intends to say is that ‘19 per cent of US as a total
population are poor’. (This has since been corrected.)
In his Guardian newspaper column Giles Fraser wrote a piece
called ‘Assisted suicide is the equivalent of a zero-hours contract
with life’. He argued that a recent trend for suicide in the UK is
a symptom of excessive individualism. Everything has become an
individual choice (rather than a community responsibility), includ-
ing when we die.
Maud lives round the corner from me in south London. She remembers
a time when everyone knew everyone else, and when there was genu-
ine community solidarity. Nowadays people come and go, she says, and
young people can’t be bothered with the elderly. She is often lonely. ‘Even
the doctor came round to see me and asked me if I wanted to commit
suicide,’ she says.7
Some very black humour flirts with this example because I do not
believe for a second that the doctor was offering Maud suicide as an
option (as he might offer her forms of medication or counselling).
Considering her loneliness or depression, I imagine he was trying to
ascertain if she was a suicide risk. In this example it is hard to know
whether it is the doctor, Maud, or Giles Fraser that has caused the
mix-up. Let’s hope it is Fraser, but whichever is the case what we are
presented with is ambiguous.
When teasing out the premises and conclusion of a person’s argu-
ment, ambiguous sentences must be disambiguated. In a dialogue we
can ask the person for clarification, but if they are not available for
questioning we can either:
• Do our best to suppose their intended meaning, applying the
‘principle of charity’ (see below); or
• Reconstruct more than one version of the argument, applying
alternative meanings of ambiguous sentences in each case.
106
If an ambiguous sentence is one which can mean more than one thing,
a vague sentence lacks precision. In many contexts an absence of preci-
sion is entirely appropriate so long as the communicator and their audi-
ence share relevant cultural and linguistic norms:‘give me a moment’,‘I’ll
be there soon’,‘just a few potatoes’. (The process of learning these norms
was highlighted a few years ago when my then 4-year-old asked me, in
all innocence and with no agenda, how long a ‘moment’ is.)
It has been suggested that the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate
Change (IPCC) should change its style of reporting probabilities to
the media because of a mismatch between the vague terms it uses and
what these are taken to mean by the general public. For example, in
statements like ‘Ice-free Arctic Ocean summers are very likely at levels
of global warming higher than 2°C’8 they use ‘very likely’ to mean
>90% certainty, but it has been found that the public’s understanding
of ‘very likely’ is >70% certainty.9 This represents a significant dis-
crepancy that will not help the already tough task of communicating
urgency and motivating climate-related behaviour change.
Vague statements can signal the beginning of a dialogue in which
a relatively unformed belief about an issue achieves sharper focus:
‘You say that it’s “very likely” that … But what exactly do you mean
by this?’ But in non-dialogical communication vagueness can be
problematic where it causes (1) misunderstanding (as in the IPCC
example), and (2) imprecision that is inappropriate for the context in
question, leaving us unable to respond until we know exactly what is
meant by, for example, ‘the train is delayed’; ‘the airport is quite close
to the city’; ‘their actions were borderline illegal’; ‘Lou was talking
about you the other day’; or ‘it was a fairly innocent flirtation’.
Unlike ambiguous sentences, vague statements can form premises
and conclusions in arguments where (1) and (2) above do not rep-
resent a problem (‘I’ve only got a couple more things to do, there-
fore I will be there in a short while’). Where (1) or (2) is a problem,
the issue is similar to the one caused by ambiguity. Vague sentences
become, in effect, ones that cannot be determined to be true or false,
and therefore cannot function as propositions. When reconstructing
arguments we therefore need to make these meanings more pre-
cise, either through an educated guess or through further research. As
with the rewording of ambiguous sentences, the ‘principle of charity’
should also be applied (see below).
107
P1: History shows that prime ministers have regularly used war
abroad to distract from constitutional matters or problems at
home.
108
Premise (1)
Premise (2)
Conclusion (1)
Premise (3)
Conclusion (2)
Premise (4)
Etc.
Overall conclusion
Mexico in 2010. Quoting from BP’s risk assessment prior to the spill
she says,
Best of all, should a major spill occur, there is, apparently, ‘little risk of con-
tact or impact to the coastline’ because of the company’s projected speedy
response (!) and ‘due to the distance [of the rig] to shore’ – about 48 miles
(77km). This is the most astonishing claim of all. In a gulf that often sees
winds of more than 70km an hour, not to mention hurricanes, BP had so
little respect for the ocean’s capacity to ebb and flow, surge and heave, that
it did not think oil could make a paltry 77km trip. None of this sloppiness
would have been possible, however, had BP not been making its predic-
tions to a political class eager to believe that nature had indeed been mas-
tered. Some, like Republican Lisa Murkowski, were more eager than others.
The Alaskan senator was so awe-struck by the industry’s four-dimensional
seismic imaging that she proclaimed deep-sea drilling to have reached the
very height of controlled artificiality. ‘It’s better than Disneyland in terms of
how you can take technologies and go after a resource that is thousands of
years old and do so in an environmentally sound way,’ she told the Senate
energy committee just seven months ago.12
P1:
P2:
P3:
Etc.
C:
Reconstructed:
4.4 SUMMARY
The art of argument reconstruction involves several skills: identify-
ing premises and conclusions; rewording (e.g., of relevant information
not originally provided in the form of propositions, or of ambigu-
ous or vague claims); teasing out implicit premises and conclusions;
reordering of premises and identifying sub-conclusions. All of this
should be carried out in the spirit of charity because the objectives
are truth, honest agreement, and constructive dialogues, rather than
113
DISCUSSION QUESTION
The case is made in this chapter for straw man arguments always
being fallacious, but is this necessarily the case? Are there circum-
stances in which it is acceptable to distort someone else’s position in
order to make it easier to argue against? Two short articles that make
a case for this view are by Aikin and Casey (2011, 2016).
EXERCISES
Making use of the techniques explained in this chapter, reconstruct
the following arguments:
FURTHER READING
• For exercises on visual arguments see Morrow and Weston (2011);
and Lunsford and Ruszkiewicz (2010).
• For an instructive article about straw man and iron man arguments
see Aikin and Casey (2016); and for some important insights into
the motivations behind straw man arguments see Tannen (1998),
especially Ch.1.
NOTES
1 The good-natured and informative Start the Week, BBC Radio 4, 14.9.20.
2 Hooven, C. Testosterone (Cassell, 2021).
3 Saul Goodman knows a thing or two about iron manning his clients. Be
aware that the term ‘steel manning’ has also been coined; not as an alterna-
tive to ‘iron man’ but with the same meaning as the principle of charity (see
above).
4 Some good examples are Johnson and Blair (2006); Scriven (1976); Bowell
and Kemp (2015); and Morrow and Weston (2011).
5 Available at: www.africa.upenn.edu/Articles_Gen/Letter_Birmingham.
html
6 Berk, L. Infants, Children, and Adolescents, 7th Ed. (Pearson International
Edition, 2010), p. 74.
7 The Guardian, 29.8.15
115
[Fallacies] are like bad habits. They are hard to break. (John Woods,
2013, p.5)
In books on logic, and some books on critical thinking, you will find
discussion of deductive and inductive arguments. My view (and also
the view of Scriven (1976) and Johnson and Blair (2006), among oth-
ers) is that learning about this distinction is of limited value outside
DOI: 10.4324/9781003247944-6
117
P1: Either the Earth has remained in a static state, or it has changed
form due to tectonic shifts.
P2: The Earth has not remained in a static state.
C: Therefore the Earth has changed form due to tectonic shifts.
P1: Donald Trump says that voter fraud lost him the 2020 presi-
dential election.
P2: Everything Donald Trump says is true.
C: Therefore voter fraud lost Donald Trump the 2020 presidential
election.
But since the second premise is not true, the truth of the conclusion
cannot be guaranteed. If presented with this argument we wouldn’t
challenge its logic, but rather the truth of its premises.
A valid deductive argument with true premises (and therefore a
true conclusion) is known as a sound argument, and it is the strongest
118
type of argument there is. If you can convince someone of the truth
of your premises, and the argument has a valid deductive structure,
then they have no option but to accept your conclusion.
An inductive argument on the other hand lacks this airtight
quality. An inductive version of the above argument might be:
P1: Either the Earth has remained in a static state, or it has changed
form due to tectonic shifts.
P2: As far as the evidence goes, it seems the Earth has not remained
in a static state.
C: Therefore the Earth has changed form due to tectonic shifts.
In this form the conclusion does not necessarily follow from the
premises – unlike valid deductive arguments it would not be a con-
tradiction to reject the conclusion whilst accepting the premises.
The reason why I and other critical thinking scholars are not
inclined to take this distinction too seriously, however, concerns the
ease with which an inductive argument can be turned into a deduc-
tive argument, and vice versa. As Michael Scriven says,
A slight juggling of the premises (by adding some unstated ones) and the
conclusions can always convert an inductive argument into a deductive
one without any essential loss of the ‘point of the argument’. (1976, p.34)
Take this argument:
Rather than use the first version we are better off using the second,
but in both cases we know that the strength of the argument depends
on the truth or falsity of the premises.
119
We can accept that if the premises are true then the conclusion must
also be true, but this is trivial. What matters, again, is the truth or
otherwise of the premises, and we will demand (or seek) evidence of
this before we accept that Lassie is dead.
A more pressing concern for critical thinking is appreciating the
context in which an argument is put forward. Scientific discovery
is usually seen as a process whereby careful observations are used to
predict outcomes in similar situations towards developing a theory to
explain the phenomenon in question. However, no matter what the
theory’s current success is in predicting results, scientists recognise
that it is possible for it to be proven wrong by subsequent find-
ings. In this sense it has been known as an inductive approach; the
kind of deductive proofs available to mathematicians and logicians
do not apply to empirical investigations. Assessment of the inductive
approach is often linked to an analysis of generalisations, and more
will be said on this in Chapter 8.1
PLAUSIBLE ARGUMENTS
P1: If your dog looks unwell and there is at least some reason to
believe its water source is poisoned then the best course of
action is to rush it to the vet.
P2: Lassie looks unwell and there’s a rumour that toxins from frack-
ing fluid have been polluting the local groundwater.
C: Therefore the best course of action is to rush her to the vet.
Fallacies are, in short, poor arguments of certain kinds that are used
frequently and are liable to be convincing to those not thinking criti-
cally. A bad argument that conforms to a certain pattern but that is
not particularly deceptive is still a fallacy, but the ‘liable to be con-
vincing’ clause remains an important component of the definition.
One reason is that we often argue fallaciously without realising we
are doing so, indicating that, in the moment at least, we think the
argument is strong. And if we are deceived, some of our audience
are likely to be as well. A second reason is that, since there are many
fallacies, any given class or textbook must make choices about what
to include and what to prioritise. A sensible criterion for inclusion
is a fallacy being ‘characteristically deceptive’ since these will be the
more disabling ones in processes of decision-making.
123
GENERAL QUESTIONS
P1: X is similar to Y.
P2: Z is true of Y.
P3: Therefore Z is also true of X.
Applied to Neil’s argument the likely answers – i.e., the basis for
further research, or what we would put back to him if we were in
Portillo’s shoes – are these:
The first three critical questions tend to be where our basic rational-
ity will take us when encountering arguments from analogy, but I
think that the fourth one is slightly less intuitive, and it is also the
hardest one to answer since it involves a lot of imaginative work.
However, even if all four are relatively obvious, familiarity with a list
like this – questions that have been broadly agreed upon by a range
of scholars – gives us some confidence that these are the angles we
need to pursue in the discussion.
Clearly this is just the start of a long debate (which is itself just one
part of the discussion around fox hunting), but knowing the basic
questions to pose once an argument from analogy has been identified
is a good start, and one that has the potential to lead the exchange
along constructive lines.
Returning to the ARS criteria, notice that critical question Q1
for arguments from analogy is a form of the acceptability criterion;
Q2 concerns relevance; and Q3 and Q4 question the sufficiency of
the premises.
P1: Richard Dawkins says that the world would be a better place
without organised religion.
P2: Richard Dawkins has relevant expertise on the history, politics,
and ethics of organised religion.
C: Therefore it is likely that the world would be a better place
without organised religion.
P2 is the implicit premise that, when made explicit, clearly reveals the
argument as an argument from authority. With respect to the guid-
ance on reconstructing enthymemes offered in Chapter 4, it might
well be unnecessary or inadvisable to fully reconstruct the argument
in this way in many situations, but it can certainly be helpful to the
process of making clear one’s critique of a position that relies on
Dawkins’ authority on this matter.
131
EXERCISES
My view is that there is limited value in applying the ARS questions
to relatively unfamiliar and decontextualised arguments, so instead of
132
providing some of these (as I did at the end of the last chapter), my
recommendation is to select passages that involve arguments from
topics and texts you are familiar with and apply the ARS critical
questions to them. This could include:
• Other disciplines you are studying;
• Topical events and debates;
• Extended texts such as those recommended in this book;
• Essays and other assignments that you have written.
FURTHER READING
NOTES
1 Also, certain forms of deductive argument, and their associated fallacies, fea-
ture in Chapter 10.
2 This Week, 2.7.15
133
DOI: 10.4324/9781003247944-7
134
part of a larger system with which the responsibility lies. The impli-
cation of the second is that there are reasons for thinking authority
X is indeed the right authority to base our beliefs on, and it is this
reasoning that turns out to be the most important consideration for
critical thinking.
Since we cannot become experts in all the fields that are relevant
to the decisions we make in our personal and professional lives, reli-
ance on authority is unavoidable. There are also plenty of circum-
stances where an unquestioning approach to authority is usually the
best approach. The crucial thing is for us to know why this is the
case; why X is the right kind of authority to help inform our beliefs
on a particular topic, or why circumstance Y (a battlefield, medical
emergency, restaurant kitchen during peak demand, etc.) is the place
and time not to question orders. Modern analyses of arguments from
authority recognise the limitations of an individual’s knowledge and
powers, and the critical questions they generate embody this under-
standing. In Johnson and Blair’s words, ‘we are urged to be filters of
opinions rather than sponges who soak them up indiscriminately’
(2006, p.167).
The flipside of appealing to authority in support of our positions
is attempting to discredit those who oppose our beliefs. This can be
because of their lack of expertise, their biased view on the subject,
inconsistency between what they advocate and how they behave,
or simply because of their undesirable character (or associations
with other undesirable characters). All these forms of argument are
known as ad hominem arguments, and are a main focus of the
next chapter.
This chapter is about arguments in which either characteristics of
the arguer, or people that the arguer refers to, constitute the main
premise. It will stretch its net wider than arguments that appeal to or
discredit expert authority, addressing several argument forms that rely
on what has been called ‘social power’. The concept of social power
is a broad one, but generally refers to the ability of one person (or a
collection of people) to influence another person (or collection of
people). By influence is meant a change in behaviour and/or beliefs
and attitudes.
In their widely employed analysis of the subject, social psycholo-
gists John French and Bertram Raven (1959) identified five types of
135
of others through rewards has reward power, which extends this cat-
egory beyond the positional and normative reach of legitimate power.
Coercive power: The power of someone who is able to punish someone
who does not comply with a request or command. It is the opposite of
reward power, but similar to it in so far as it can be held by someone
without legitimate power.
Referent power: In contrast to the relatively impersonal legitimate and
expert power, referent power is held by a group or person who you
personally connect to. They demonstrate values and other qualities
that are – or you would like to be – an important part of your identity.
Without the need for requests, orders, or threats, you thus have a
desire to conform to a group’s or a person’s norms, and in this way
those norms have power over you.
Is the authority cited an expert in their field, and is this field relevant
to the issue under discussion? If someone is a medical doctor and
they are giving their opinion on a common bodily ailment, then we
can say yes to Q1 and Q2. If they are making a claim about a psy-
chological condition, then we need to be more cautious. This much
is obvious, but if we are not concentrating we can easily be fooled.
Not every historian is an expert on Scottish history, and not every
Scottish historian is an expert on the Jacobite Risings, so if some-
one commenting on the Battle of Culloden is only introduced as a
139
Consensus
In a radio programme3 interviewing the world famous entomologist
and founder of sociobiology, E.O.Wilson,Wilson defended his theory
of group selection over the selfish gene theory of cooperative behav-
iour.4 In this peak hour broadcast it was instructive to see how this
complex debate was defended by both Wilson and his rival Richard
Dawkins (who had also been interviewed on the subject). Most of
the listeners would lack the expertise to be convinced one way or
the other by the scientific arguments, so both relied significantly on
arguments from authority. Wilson made the point that mathemati-
cal modelling disproved the selfish gene theory. He had little option
but to spare us the maths, but did stress that his co-researchers were
two well-respected Harvard mathematicians: Martin Nowak and the
‘genius’ Corina Tarnita.
Beyond this, it should be added, Wilson went some distance to
explaining and defending his theory without reference to authority,
but Dawkins was quite explicit about needing to use an argument
from authority (something he said he generally dislikes doing) and
simply pointed out that a reply to Wilson’s paper elicited a damming
response in the form of a letter to the journal Nature (who published
Wilson’s article) from 140 eminent evolutionary biologists. His argu-
ment came down to numbers: yes, Wilson is a leading authority in
evolutionary biology, but on this issue he is vastly outnumbered by
other experts. Who are you going to trust? The first part of Wilson’s
141
With climate change, if the experts are right then the consequences
will be catastrophic, so we ignore them at our peril. For most of us at
143
least, the same cannot be said for authoritative views on the surface
temperature of Venus, or the history of cricket.
are current examples). The puzzle is that the intuitive answer – that
such people are less scientifically literate or rational – is at best only a
small part of the explanation. Research is now filling in the gaps, and
some of this relates to a subsection of the cognitive biases and social
dynamics discussed in this book. To go deeper into this complex and
fascinating area there are references included in exercise 2 at the end
of this chapter.
are located. Examples of position to know range from our local geo-
graphical and cultural knowledge (where the local library is, the best
place to find job ads, how much, if at all, should we tip bar or res-
taurant staff) and basic procedures and norms of the workplace (who
to send expenses forms to, how to address senior staff in an email),
through to the boss who withholds or distorts information gathered
at high-level committee meetings in order to maintain control over
subordinates.7 Altogether juicier examples include revelations about
love affairs, corruption, illegal parties, and other immoral or criminal
behaviours that are found in autobiographies, shared in confidence,
haplessly revealed in TV interviews, leaked by whistle-blowers, or
obtained through computer hacking.
Examples of position to know arguments are endless, and take
us directly to some deep issues in ethical and political philosophy.
Information power is employed by governments in undemocratic
acts of propaganda, by civil servants who keep government ministers
in the dark, and it exists in the unavoidable agenda-setting that goes
on in news media. Information power can also be used benignly,
and on occasion – like those who wish not to know the full details
and extent of their terminal medical conditions – we can justifiably
choose to remain ignorant.
An important consideration for the position to know argument is
the difference between expertise and experience. Contrast, for exam-
ple, knowing all about cancer from a scientific perspective and living
through cancer; or between knowing about heartbreak from a liter-
ary and psychological point of view and having your heart broken.
One way of appreciating the significance of this difference is in terms
of the knowledge that qualitative research often seeks out. In its quest
for expert knowledge it finds out about the first-hand accounts of
people who have had certain experiences. Alternatively think of how
news reporting typically combines the experiences of people at the
sharp end of, say, welfare cuts or health service reforms, with expert
economic or political analysis. It is important not to view accounts of
experiences as provisional or otherwise inferior to theoretical under-
standing. For a number of reasons – including contextual and ‘felt’
qualities – it offers a distinctive insight into an issue, rather than one
that is simply waiting to be replaced by a theoretical account.
147
Witness testimony
For certain kinds of news stories (including extreme weather events
and terrorist attacks) news media rely heavily on witness testimony.
Witness testimony differs from position to know in that it refers to
situations where people experience an unusual event first-hand, and
thus become valuable for establishing the truth about it. Position
to know as a corollary of information power implies a degree of
stability in the information’s availability so that it is available to any-
one who happens to be in a ‘position to know’. The eyewitness, in
148
contrast, happens upon something through luck (or ill luck) rather
than anything about them or their station in life. And that thing is in
important senses a one-off, rather than something we can (or would
want to) recreate.
As well as news reporting, eyewitness testimony can of course be
important in court cases (it plays a pivotal role in Twelve Angry Men),
the school playground (‘Who saw what happened to Rory’s lunch
box?’), and many other circumstances. It is, however, notoriously
unreliable in two interrelated respects:
• Mistaken beliefs: cognitive psychology has demonstrated that
there tends to be a substantial gap between what we confidently
believe we have seen and what actually happened.
• Lying: in circumstances were a person stands to gain from an event
to which they are the only witness, the temptation will be there
to distort or fabricate the truth. This can of course work at a sub-
conscious level as well (see rationalisation and cognitive dis-
sonance in Chapter 1), with the outcome of creating distinctly
convenient mistaken beliefs (‘The cat was already dead when I
ran over it’;The person I saw with that good looking stranger in a
dimly lit restaurant looked too young to be my wife’.)
In David Hume’s famous essay ‘On Miracles’8 motivations like this
are among the reasons he gives for why a sole witness to a supposed
miracle should never be believed. In short, it will always be more
likely that the person is mistaken or lying than that a law of nature
has been contravened.
Miracles aside, and despite these problems, witness testimony
remains important because it is sometimes all we have to go on. In
order for us to have greater confidence in witness accounts, the fol-
lowing critical questions can be posed (based on Walton, Reed and
Macagno, 2008, p.91):
P1: X believes/advocates Y.
P2: X is biased in a way that could prejudice their beliefs/advocacy
of Y.
P3: We should disregard/be cautious about the views of someone
who could be biased in this way.
C: Therefore, we should disregard/be cautious about X’s views
on Y.
The UK’s now concluded (in 2022) Independent Inquiry into Child
Sex Abuse provides a noteworthy example. Provoked by the Jimmy
Savile scandal, it was a wide-ranging investigation that included gov-
ernmental level suspects stretching back at least to the 1970s. When
it was set up in 2014 it was proving so difficult to find someone not
linked to possible suspects for the role of chair that it was neces-
sary to bring in a judge from New Zealand (Lowell Goddard). In
this instance a series of strong circumstantial ad hominem arguments
righty delayed the process by over a year.9
Rather less convincing was the foundational accusation of the
documentary The Great Global Warming Swindle (Martin Durkin,
2007) that the scientists who have found evidence for anthropo-
genic global warming have, in fact, known for a long time that
their views have been disproved. They maintain their defence of
this view, though, in order to keep their lucrative positions on the
Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change. (Their view has, of
course, not been disproved, and their position on the IPCC is vol-
untary and unpaid.)
150
Towards the end of Martin Luther King, Jr.’s Letter from Birmingham
Jail11 is a circumstantial ad hominem attack that is harder to judge
than the previous two examples. Here he pricks the conscience of
America’s white moderates by offering a theory for their lack of sup-
port for his methods. After explaining his reasons for the necessity of
non-violent direct action he says:
I had hoped that the white moderate would see this. Maybe I was too
optimistic. Maybe I expected too much. I guess I should have real-
ized that few members of a race that has oppressed another race can
understand or appreciate the deep groans and passionate yearnings of
those that have been oppressed, and still fewer have the vision to see
that injustice must be rooted out by strong, persistent, and determined
action.
The ad hominem argument in this passage, reconstructed in a sum-
marised form, seems to be this:
King, Jr. is leading, and as a result the right kind of belief or response
is not to be expected.
If we apply the critical questions, Q2 can be answered in the
affirmative since not being in a position to know (in the form of life
experience), if true, is relevant to King, Jr.’s conclusion. Whether it
is true though (Q1) is another matter; quite possibly it is, but this is
not something that can be answered easily from a layperson’s point
of view. Since much of the rest of the speech is dealing with the
white moderates’ arguments, then this ad hominem attack cannot be
rejected as simply crude or dismissive, and nor can the conclusion
he draws from it. If the entire message had been based around an ad
hominem argument of this type, however, then it would be fair to
regard his, quite firm, conclusion as inappropriate (Q3).
The implication is that this is not what the subject signed up for;
that the experimenter no longer has legitimate power over him. If
the subject refuses to continue, all the experimenter can say is that
the experiment must come to an end, highlighting the limits of his
power. Nevertheless, prior to this the barrier of anxiety that so many
156
subjects were unable to overcome was the result of fear of the experi-
menter’s disapproval, which itself – Milgram plausibly speculates – is
in large part caused by a generalising of an internalised association,
beginning in childhood, between doing what’s right and the power
of legitimate authorities to reward and punish (ibid, p. 138).
ARGUMENT 1
ARGUMENT 2
P1: If you complain again about unpaid overtime, then I will see to
it that you are fired.
P2: You want to avoid being fired.
C: You should stop complaining about unpaid overtime.
REWARD POWER
Critical questions:
Q1: Can the person genuinely provide the reward in question, and
are they likely to?
Q2: Are you able to do what is required to receive the reward
offered?
Q3: Are you (or should you be) willing to pay the necessary price?
6.4 SUMMARY
This chapter has examined the strength of arguments based on expert,
information, legitimate, reward, and coercive power. In each case they
can form the basis of strong arguments, but, as the Milgram experiments
demonstrate, the deep and complex motivations behind obedience and
compliance is such that an enormous amount of caution – assisted by
self-awareness, courage, and a willingness to take responsibility for our
beliefs and actions – is needed when confronted by authority-based
appeals. The next chapter continues the themes of social power and
message source, exploring ethotic authority, further types of ad homi-
nem argument, and arguments appealing to referent power.
EXERCISES
1. Since appeals to the forms of power and authority discussed in
this chapter are so common, a worthwhile exercise is to find sev-
eral examples of such appeals from news stories, opinion pieces,
political commentaries, exchanges on social media, etc. Apply
the appropriate critical questions to them, assess their poten-
tial persuasiveness, their impact on the dialogue, and what they
might reveal about the dispositions of the people who use them.
2. The focus of this chapter has been the application of criteria
for avoiding and guarding against weak appeals to authority.
A separate phenomenon is the chronic distrust of experts in
areas where there is scientific consensus, with climate science
and vaccinations as outstanding recent examples.There is now
a large body of literature that seeks to explain the psychologi-
cal and political causes of this: Levy, 2019, and Baghramian
and Croce, 2021 are excellent starting points, as is the web-
site of PERITIA, the EU project on public trust in exper-
tise: https://peritia-trust.eu. To initiate your own thinking on
the issue a helpful exercise is to hypothesise reasons based on
some of the ideas discussed in this chapter and elsewhere in
this book (especially Chapters 1–3, 7, and 8.)
FURTHER READING
As with other chapters, use the in-text references as a guide to fur-
ther reading on specific aspects of what has been discussed here. Also,
164
NOTES
1 A modern advocate of this, drawing on Aristotle’s and Seneca’s ideas on vir-
tues and rhetoric, is Alan Brinton. (See, for example, Brinton, 1986)
2 For example, Johnson and Blair (2006, pp.168–72) have four, Douglas Walton
(2006, p.88) has six, and Christopher Tindale (2007, pp. 134–43) seven.
3 The Life Scientific, BBC Radio 4, 28.7.15.
4 Group selection is the idea that evolution works, at least in part, at the level
of the adaptive fitness of groups rather than genes. Thus, a group in which
individuals are more cooperative and willing to self-sacrifice for the sake of
the collective will fare better than one in which individuals are more selfish.
The selfish gene theory, on the other hand, states that cooperative tendencies
(reciprocal and kin altruism) are only selected to the extent that they benefit
the individual and those who share their genes.
5 Pennisi, E. (2011) Researchers Challenge E.O. Wilson over Evolutionary
Theory [Article]. Available at: www.science.org/content/article/researchers-
challenge-e-o-wilson-over-evolutionary-theory
6 My analysis of these issues has been significantly influenced by Heather
Battaly’s article ‘Attacking Character’ (2010).
7 You know who you are!
8 This essay can be found in numerous places, including Stump, E. and Murray,
M. (eds) Philosophy of Religion:The Big Questions (Blackwell, 1999).
9 See Mason, R. (2014) Fiona Woolf resigns as chair of government’s child
abuse inquiry [Online article]. Available at: www.theguardian.com/
politics/2014/oct/31/fiona-woolf-resigns-chairman-child-abuse-inquiry.
(For other r easons Lowell resigned (or was sacked) in 2016, and was replaced
by Prof Alexis Jay.)
10 Adapted from Douglas Walton (2006, p.123) and Christopher Tindale
(2007, p.89).
11 Available at: www.africa.upenn.edu/Articles_Gen/Letter_Birmingham.html
12 Described and analysed in Hannah Arendt’s book Eichmann in Jerusalem:
A Report into the Banality of Evil (Penguin, 1965).
13 Klein, N. The Shock Doctrine (Penguin, 2008).
14 For an insightful discussion of this, and ad baculum arguments in general, see
Woods (1995).
165
In the broadest sense then, ethotic arguments employ the moral char-
acter of the person upholding a position to help establish the plausi-
bility of that position. As you can see from the scheme above, this can
refer to good or bad aspects of that character, depending on whether
the arguer’s aim is to support or reject a particular conclusion. In this
section I am going to use ‘ethotic authority’ to refer to arguments
appealing in a positive way to moral character, and ‘abusive ad homi-
nem’ for arguments that appeal to it in a negative way.
ETHOTIC AUTHORITY
Chances are it is Annie, even though the same traits are listed for
both, and you are not told that they are listed in order of prominence.
This is taken from a classic set of experiments by Solomon Asch in
the 1940s;1 he proposed that the halo effect causes the first entry to
influence the interpretation of what follows so that ambiguous quali-
ties such as being critical or impulsive attain a positive or negative
spin depending on what comes before them. The net evaluation is
thus reliably skewed by the initial piece of information we receive.
170
TU QUOQUE ARGUMENTS
Q2. Is this attack relevant to the claim that the argument makes?
Al Gore received criticism for flying the world to promote his eco
film An Inconvenient Truth (2006), but this is not relevant to the con-
clusion that he is hypocritical or otherwise lacks credibility. Al Gore’s
choosing not to fly might have sent some kind of message (as Greta
Thunberg’s carbon neutral sailing across the Atlantic to attend cli-
mate events in 2019 did), but not if his film is not making an impact
on publics and policymakers in the first place. Very likely it was his
174
presence in these places, plus the commitment to the cause that his
touring demonstrated, that made people pay attention.4
On the other hand, the Church of England criticising payday loan
companies, whilst at the same time investing in one of them (Wonga)
looks like a stronger tu quoque argument.5 The same goes for the list
of politicians and advisers who broke Covid lockdown restrictions in
the UK in 2020 and 2021 and were consequently (though notori-
ously not in all cases) forced to resign.
In the spousal dialogue at the top of this section things are more
complicated. It is possible that the husband’s response is entirely
defensive and that his counteraccusation is simply a means of deflect-
ing the discussion away from the fact that he does need to be friend-
lier towards his in-laws. It is also possible that, even if true of the
husband, the wife’s accusation is indeed mirrored by her own behav-
iour. Under these circumstances cool heads are needed (the very cool
heads that ad hominem arguments tend not to encourage). Other
things being equal, both parties should, ideally, reflect on their own
behaviour and reach a joint conclusion that (1) both need to improve
in this way and, importantly, (2) that one cannot reasonably expect
the other to do this unless they do it themselves.
Underpinning this is the need for reciprocation in so many social
encounters (see Chapter 1). Since we cannot expect perfection in
our moral and social behaviour, our standards tend to be relative to
the norms that surround us. In other words, if our peers demand
things of us, we expect them to demand the same of themselves.
It is, however, this same rule of reciprocation that can cause a group
(or couple-based) conspiracy of silence. In order not to provoke the
rows and fallings-out that criticisms tend to generate, and in order
to avoid the critical spotlight being turned in our direction, we can
find ourselves not criticising others when we should be. In terms of
personal development and group deliberations, tu quoque responses
could have a detrimental long-term impact because people become
unwilling to offer constructive feedback that would otherwise serve
us, or the group, well. It is easy to imagine the role that this kind of
response could play in groupthink; if a critical suggestion is met
with the messenger being shot, fewer messengers will be turning up,
a greater number of poor arguments will go unchallenged, and the
‘illusion of unanimity’ will be strengthened.
175
GUILT BY ASSOCIATION
Morton’s fish and chips are the best in town. Other examples serve as
an extension of this idea; the practiced, and hopefully reflected-upon,
experience that justifies jury-based decision-making, consulting with
employees when deciding organisational codes of conduct, and the
democratic election of governments.
More often a carefully worded ad populum will give rise to a con-
clusion that is plausible, or at least indicates that a position is worthy
of a closer look. Some will be variations of position to know argu-
ments where we are told that something is true because everyone
who has had certain experiences (relating to their job or other life
experience) gets it. This can be the basis of an important argument
when those who are not in that position tend not to agree.
Or we might just answer ‘no’ to Q2, and religious belief is an
outstanding example. It could be true, but millions believing that it
is should not count as a reason for a neutral person to believe that it
is. Also, in science there are numerous cases where what the public
believes and what experts believe are clearly at odds. Climate change
denial among the American Christian right is a specific and serious
example, and the exposing of commonly held beliefs as myths is
common in popular science forums.6
Overall, we need to be aware that potentially momentous changes
can occur in scientific or moral knowledge which contradict but fail
to dislodge traditional beliefs.This inertia could be a simple matter of
ignorance and the time it takes for knowledge to seep into a culture,
but some beliefs remain common because they are comforting or
otherwise useful.
Q3 is covered by previous analyses of position to know argu-
ments. Q4 is directed at dogmatic, lazy, fearful, antagonistic, or com-
petitive group mindsets that create the dangerous biases and unreliable
communication that is so depressingly common on social media.The
self-fulfilling deliberations that impede critical thinking in Twelve
Angry Men serve as an example. We also need to be careful not to
conflate witness testimony type cases with straightforward examples
of ad populum position to know arguments, since immersion in situ-
ations can come with its own biases. We can have some sympathy for
‘You weren’t there, man!’ or ‘You can’t handle the truth!’ defences of
dubious military practices, but they are not going to be the last word
on the matter.
178
Twelve Angry Men is also helpful for illustrating the important dif-
ference between ad populum arguments that refer to actions and those
that refer to beliefs. As discussed in Chapter 1, as a bargaining tool
to persuade the other jury members to talk about the case, Juror 8
proposes that if he cannot change their opinion after an hour of dis-
cussion then he would change his vote to guilty. He is not suggesting
that he will have changed his mind about the case, but is offering,
rather, a practical solution. This is of course quite common; it is basic
to democracies and, in general, to situations in which going along
with the majority – despite not agreeing with them – can be the
best or right thing to do.These kinds of deliberation come with their
own critical questions (e.g., even in a democracy a case can be made
for it not always being right to go along with majority decisions), but
the main point here is that basing one’s action on the popular view is
very different from basing one’s belief on it.
‘Social dilemmas’ are situations in which a certain rational perspec-
tive can dictate that what we believe to be the right thing to do is
not what we should do, because we have reasons to believe that not
enough others will also be doing it. Either we do not want to be the
‘sucker’ who makes the sacrifice when others aren’t, or, as with reduc-
ing carbon emissions, if not enough people/countries commit then
the efforts of a few will not make any difference.There is not the space
to pursue this topic any further here, but there is a vast literature to seek
out if you are interested (see Further reading at the end of the chapter).
Some recent cases of social media based ‘mob pressure’ or ‘witch
hunts’ raise some intriguing questions concerning the power of ad
populums. The forced resignation of Nobel laureate Sir Tim Hunt
from his academic post at UCL in 2015 after making sexist com-
ments (in the form of a joke) at a conference is one example. UCL’s
decision was regarded as controversial, and some, including high-
profile astrophysicist and TV presenter Brian Cox blame a ‘trial by
social media’ for forcing their hand. Commenting on the story, an
editorial in The Guardian concludes that:
Twitter is loud, shouty and mainly male. It is rubbish at nuance, detail
or ambivalence but it is perfect for rushing noisily to judgment, some-
times … in a downright threatening way. The experience of UCL is another
warning that a Twitterstorm is a digital riot, and that is how it should be
treated.7
179
Widely held ethical views are rightly taken more seriously than sci-
entific ones because they are value judgements that emerge from a
culture; experts are describing our sensibilities as much as they are
shaping them. However, if we assume that social media is able to
amplify what appear to be popular moral views in a way that can have
this kind of impact, then the helpfulness of the critical questions for
guiding our analysis is plain. The answer to each of them is not obvi-
ous and requires not only an investigation of the details of the case,
but philosophical questioning about the appropriate role of popular
opinion in the making of moral and political judgements.
7.3 SUMMARY
We saw in the previous chapter that appeals to authority are unavoid-
able, and handled with care they can be strong arguments. Even more
care is needed with ad hominem arguments – they can be lazy decision-
making shortcuts, and seductive for this and other reasons. However, a
person’s circumstances, behaviours, or general character can sometimes
be relevant to how we go about assessing their arguments. So long
as the conclusions we draw are proportionate – rarely is a personal
attack enough by itself for an outright rejection – then they are by no
means always fallacious. The same, from a positive perspective, applies
to arguments appealing to ethotic authority.The social proof and refer-
ent power that ad populum arguments court helps explain their appeal,
but they too are not always weak, especially in circumstances where we
are deciding what to do rather than what to believe.
EXERCISES
1. Assess the following tu quoque argument (from Roger Scruton,
On Hunting (London: Yellow Jersey, 1999), pp.139–40) by
applying the ad hominem critical questions to it (see Ch.6,
section 6.2).
182
FURTHER READING
Make use of the in-text references as a guide to further reading on
specific aspects of this chapter, and a further recommendation is
Douglas Walton’s book Ad Hominem Arguments (2009).
To find out more about social dilemmas a classic early text is
Robert Alexrod’s The Evolution of Cooperation (Penguin, 1984); there
is an enlightening and accessible chapter on it in Peter Singer’s How
Are We to Live? (Oxford University Press, 1993); and for a good book
applying this dilemma to climate change see Stephen Gardiner’s The
Perfect Moral Storm (Oxford University Press, 2011).
183
NOTES
1 Asch, S. (1946) Forming impressions of personality. The Journal of Abnormal
and Social Psychology, 41(3), 258–90.
2 For two excellent examples of charismatic leadership (as well as a range of
rhetorical techniques) see the character Andreas Wolf in Jonathan Franzen’s
novel Purity (Fourth Estate, 2015), p.262, and Forest Whitaker’s portrayal of Idi
Amin in the film The Last King of Scotland (Kevin MacDonald, 2007) – most
notably the section where Amin is persuading the young Scottish doctor to be
his personal physician (between approx. 24 and 36 minutes).
3 A very good book devoted to this subject is Miranda Fricker’s Epistemic
Injustice (Oxford University Press, 2007).
4 See Hoffman, A. (2011) Talking past each other? Cultural framing of skep-
tical and convinced logics in the climate change debate. Organization &
Environment, 24(1), 3–33.
5 www.reuters.com/article/wonga-church-stakesale-idUSL4N0PL5O420140710
6 For example, Discovery Channel’s Mythbusters, the Fortean Times column
‘Mythconceptions’.
7 The Guardian view on theTim Hunt affair: an explosive combination of science,
sexism and social media (2015) [Editorial].Available at: www.theguardian.com/
commentisfree/2015/jun/30/the-guardian-view-on-the-tim-hunt-affair-
an-explosive-combination-of-science-sexism-and-social-media
8 See Payne, O. Inspiring Sustainable Behaviour (Earthscan, 2012), pp.97–99.
9 Kahan, D. et al. (2011) The tragedy of the risk-perception commons: Culture
conflict, rationality conflict, and climate change. Temple University legal studies
research paper, 2011–26.
184
CAUSAL ARGUMENTS,
GENERALISATIONS, ARGUMENTS
FROM CONSEQUENCES, AND
SLIPPERY SLOPE ARGUMENTS
Since we are all such absolutists by instinct, what in our quality as students
of philosophy ought we to do about this fact? Shall we espouse and endorse
it? Or shall we treat it as a weakness of our nature from which we must free
ourselves if we can? I sincerely believe that the latter course is the only one
we can follow as reflective [people]. (William James, ‘The Will to Believe’)
Generalisations … never right, always fun. (Henry Rollins, Talk is Cheap
Vol.3)
If people start using slippery slope arguments, where will it end?
(Sacha T. Burnstorm, pers. comm.)
When decisions are made they are often justified in terms of the con-
sequences they are intended to bring about: making these changes to
the criminal justice system will decrease reoffending; making these
cuts to renewable energy subsidies will help reduce the budget deficit;
introducing video assistant referee technology (VAR) in football will
make key decisions more accurate and not overly impede the flow of
DOI: 10.4324/9781003247944-9
185
the game; eating less processed meat will make us healthier; and so on.
But of course we, and those we are trying to convince, need to have
reasons for believing these consequences will occur. Sometimes these
reasons take the form of arguing for the causal relationship between
various phenomena, and this involves two kinds of reasoning:
will switch on’. I did this, but nothing happened for about 6 or 7
seconds. Because I’ve not always had the best experiences with tech-
nology I assumed that (typically) my MP3 player was a bit slow. It
otherwise worked fine though, so this wasn’t much of a problem, and
I would learn to love it anyway. I just developed the habit of holding
the button down for this length of time. Several months later I was
distracted by something whilst going through this ritual and let go
after a couple of seconds.When I looked back at the screen a few sec-
onds later I was surprised to see that it was on. The penny dropped. I
had been assuming that turning it on meant that something needed
to appear on the screen, but clearly that is not the case; holding down
the button for 2–3 seconds is indeed enough to activate it, but noth-
ing actually appears on the screen until after 6 or 7 seconds.
Apart from a need to reassess my relationship with technology, what
this illustrates is how the quick assumptions we make about cause
and effect can be both erroneous and habit-forming. Establishing
the cause of something can be very difficult indeed, and of course
attempts to do this are basic to the theory of the natural and social
sciences and to the work of historians. Each discipline will have dis-
tinctive criteria for establishing the strength of causal claims, and they
will share some general principles as well.
In the natural sciences a causally closed system is assumed in
which all phenomena adhere to the physical principles governing
the behaviour of matter. In the social sciences, explanations range
from the physical to the cultural and are entwined with philosophi-
cal debates about the nature of the mind’s relationship with the brain
and the meaning and existence of free will. How, for example, can a
thought – conceived of as a non-physical thing – cause changes to
the physical world? If the mind is essentially a physical thing, and thus
part of a chain of cause and effect, is free will possible? How are rea-
sons for acting in certain ways different in kind from the mechanical
causes of natural phenomena?
These are metaphysical questions, but more closely associated with
critical thinking are epistemological puzzles. As David Hume ([1748]
2008) pointed out, we do not directly observe the cause of an event;
the process by which X brings about Y. We observe that my golf club
making contact with the ball is perfectly correlated with the ball
moving (if not always the distance and direction I want it to go), but
187
the physical laws that we assume determine this are inferred rather
than evident to the senses. Kant ([1781] 1929) argued that the very
possibility of having experiences requires certain necessary condi-
tions, including causality, but that the actual basis of our experience
of causation is itself unknowable.
It is this limitation on our knowledge, combined with both the
complexity of the world and what Kahneman (2012, pp.74–8) sug-
gests is an innate tendency to ‘see’ causes where they do not exist, that
makes causal reasoning particularly vulnerable to error. The causes of
phenomena like climate change, educational attainment, and crimi-
nal behaviour; or of events like the Reformation, the American Civil
War, and the fall of apartheid in South Africa are multiple, complex,
and hard to establish with certainty. As we have seen, we have a ten-
dency to jump to conclusions about straightforward cases of cause
and effect, and with complex phenomena an added problem is to
oversimplify our explanations.
The specialisation of academics can present us with a variation of
this problem, and increasingly collaboration between disciplines to
improve accuracy in establishing causes is encouraged. For example,
the current obesity epidemic in parts of the developed world falls
into the domains of (among others) health and nutrition, sociology,
politics, psychology, and economics. Similarly, practitioners from a
range of professions (social work, medicine, mental health, educa-
tion) will work together to implement solutions for child abuse pre-
vention, community and clinical care for people with mental health
problems, or managing end of life care.
Everyday reasoning presents similar challenges. What caused Aunt
Eliza to divorce Uncle Vance? Were they ‘simply’ growing apart? Was it
the influence of her sister-in-law? Was she never truly able to forgive
him for what happened in Düsseldorf? Was it all of these things com-
bined, or some of them, or something else entirely? This is clearly not a
matter for a research project or a team of practitioners, but concerned
friends and family will often be mulling over causal explanations and
presenting arguments to one another in an analogous fashion.
It is outside the scope of this book to delve further into the sub-
tleties of the causal explanations that different situations present or
that different disciplines trade in. It is though important to survey
some general principles of causal reasoning. The aim here is to seek
188
CAUSAL FALLACIES
OVERLOOKING COINCIDENCE
If two events regularly occur together but are not causally related, the
chances are that they have a shared cause (see below). With singular
or unusual events there is a strong possibility of mistaking mere coin-
cidence for cause. My belief about my MP3 on button is an example
of this, as are many superstitions. Every so often in the news we hear
190
Yalom’s theory about Eve was that her underlying loneliness, created
by an inability or unwillingness to connect with others, caused her
drinking. Primarily, the drink was a means of coping with her isola-
tion, rather than her isolation resulting from the shame associated
with her drinking.
Although this headline does not necessarily state that being a goth
causes or contributes to depression, this is what is implied, presumably
because it makes for a better story. Read on and the issue of direc-
tion of cause is usually mentioned in press coverage, and the article
itself, though very cautious about causation, suggests that identifying
with the goth subculture does increase vulnerability to depression
and self-harm (rather than a reversal in which mental health issues
make it more likely that a person identifies as a goth). However, the
authors readily acknowledge that they are not in a position to rule
this out and, importantly, nor do they rule out shared causes such
as ‘stigma and social ostracism’ (a key aspect of the article that was
sometimes overlooked in the news). In other words, rather than ‘peer
contagion’ (hanging out with other goths) being the sole, or even
contributing, cause of these mental disorders, both the disorders and
the goth identification could have a shared cause in underlying con-
ditions such as social exclusion and bullying.
The visibility of the variables in question – in this case mental
disorders and being a goth – and the simplicity of certain causal
explanations (perhaps combined with certain stereotypes) is prime
System 1 candy. Shared causes are far less obvious and require more
imaginative hypothesising, and thus we are vulnerable to o verlooking
them.
Another example is found in an assessment by John Oliver (in
HBO’s Last Week Tonight) of the conspiracy theory that 5G masts are
spreading Covid.3 The theory is based on a correlation between the
siting of these masts and high rates of coronavirus, but Oliver points
out that these transmitters tend to be sited in areas of high population
density, which is also where Covid outbreaks are most likely. High
population density is, then, the reason behind both the existence of
5G masts and increased rates of Covid, rather than 5G masts being
responsible for spreading the disease.
193
Sod’s law means that things tend to go wrong at the most inconven-
ient time, and is essentially about bad luck. It is Sod’s law that my
boiler breaks down the very month that car and house insurance are
due for renewal, and all those things in Alanis Morissette’s song Ironic
are examples of Sod’s law (rather than being ironic). In the driving
example it is not Sod’s law that you ran someone’s dog down, it was
because you were driving too fast and couldn’t stop in time.To make
yourself feel better you infer an unfortunate coincidence of events
rather than accepting a causal relationship between your speed and
the accident occurring. In Boris Johnson’s resignation speech in July
2022 he famously said ‘them’s the breaks’. He was implying it was
bad luck that ended his tenure as prime minister rather the persistent
erosion of backbench MP’s and eventually his cabinet’s trust caused
by, among other things, his dishonesty and sense of entitlement. If
nothing else this parting phrase was true to form.
A somewhat different set of motivations lie behind this next
example. In October 2015 the singer and activist Charlotte Church
196
SUPERSTITION
8.2 GENERALISATIONS
Causal arguments are often generalisations, but not all generalisations
are causal arguments. Another type involves arguing from qualities
that characterise a particular class of things (bicycles, flowers, pol-
iticians, scientific theories, vegetables, and so on) to the expected
202
The remainder of this section will explain and discuss the main fal-
lacies associated with generalisations: hasty generalisations and
sweeping generalisations.
HASTY GENERALISATIONS
gives this response to the question: ‘How do you know this is the
cause?’
[Because] I see it around me, you know. I have friends who fail. They figure
it’s the right thing to do, and, you know, they just get lazy or want to hang
out with their friends. (Kuhn, 1991, p. 74)
SWEEPING GENERALISATIONS
The other topic Deana Kuhn used to study people’s everyday rea-
soning skills was criminals reoffending. In one example a participant
accounts for reoffending in the following way:
Human beings are very much creatures of habit, and I don’t think that
there’s such a habit as committing a crime, but everything that leads up
to committing a crime is probably habit. (Kuhn, 1991, p.60)
CRITICAL QUESTIONS
In light of the above discussions, the main critical questions that can
be applied to arguments involving generalisations are these:
POSITIVE FORM:
NEGATIVE FORM:
The context of the discussion is just war theory, and one of the crite-
ria for deciding if waging a war is just is whether it is a last resort. If
drone strikes are considered ‘actions short of war’, then their becom-
ing acceptable could corrupt the ‘avoiding violence’ impetus behind
this criterion.The negative argument from consequences concerning
this use of drones can satisfy Q1 and Q3, and there is possibly a case
for an affirmative answer to Q2. However, because there are a num-
ber of other arguments for and against drone strikes and their rela-
tionship to just war theory (e.g., greater precision leading to fewer
civilian casualties, but also less likelihood of surrender since the other
side do not feel that they are fighting a real enemy) then Q4 is com-
plicated to assess. We should be aware though that if, on balance, Q4
does not weigh against drone strikes, then greater certainty is needed
in response to Q2.
Q2a: Are there good reasons for thinking that a loss of control over
consequences will occur during the sequence of cause and
effect?
The door was later opened, and we have ended up with video replays.
It is (so far) not for throw-ins, and since many agree that on balance
the introduction of VAR is a good thing, it seems not to have landed
us with a catastrophic consequence (Q3).
by Brexit, but even if this is true the situation is not irreversible. For
example, if we need to rely on non-British people to be care workers
then there is a system for granting visas to fill these vacancies.
This is a controversial and emotive topic, and you can imagine this
argument against the preaching of extremist beliefs having some sup-
port in countries facing anti-government or terrorist threats. Before
218
8.4 SUMMARY
This chapter has highlighted the links between consequences, causes,
and generalisations.We need to gauge and evaluate, as best we can, the
consequences of different decisions.To help us do this we must avoid
mistakes in (1) reasoning about causation, and (2) how we generalise
from what is currently known to future events and to what has not
been directly investigated. These errors are in part the consequence
of psychological frailties – such as a liking for absolutes, or proneness
to superstition and fear appeals – that are now quite well understood.
Improvements in our critical thinking can be developed, not just
from learning about relevant argument forms and fallacies, but from a
reflective appreciation of these frailties and by continuing to develop
appropriate dispositions and constructive dialogical practices.
EXERCISES
1. Conspiracy theories are an excellent subject matter to apply
critical thinking to. One exercise is to generate a set of critical
questions designed to assess their plausibility. In conjunction
with this it would be useful to (a) read some philosophical
analysis of conspiracy theories (such as Cassam, 2019), and (b)
219
FURTHER READING
CAUSAL ARGUMENTS
GENERALISATIONS
NOTES
1 Fortean Times, Issue 305, Sept. 2013.
2 Bowes, L. et al. (2015) Risk of depression and self-harm in teenagers iden-
tifying with goth subculture: a longitudinal cohort study. Available at: www.
thelancet.com/psychiatry, Vol.2.
3 Season 7, Ep.18, July 2020.
4 McGrath, M. (2015) Global Warming Increases Food Shocks Threat [Article].
Available at: www.bbc.co.uk/news/science-environment-33910552, and Bailey,
R. et al. (2015) Extreme Weather and Resilience of the Global Food System
[Report]. Available at: www.cabdirect.org/globalhealth/abstract/20163135764
5 Skinner, B.F. (1948) ‘Superstition’ in the pigeon. Journal of Experimental
Psychology, 38, 168–72.
6 E.g., Brian, K. (1999) Of conspiracy theories. Journal of Philosophy, 96(1),
109–26.
7 See Goldacre, B. (2008) Bad Science. (London: Fourth Estate), pp. 97–9 and
165–70.
8 The Will to Believe in Selected Papers on Philosophy (New York: Dutton,1967),
p.110.
9 Talk is Cheap Volume 3 (Audio recording, 2004)
10 Mahoney, M. and Freeman, A. (eds), Cognition and Psychotherapy (New York:
Plenum, 1985).
11 Fortean Times, February 2015, p.39. To avoid this error Quassim Cassam
(2019) distinguishes between Conspiracy Theories (with caps) and con-
spiracy theories. The former are without any serious credibility and their
propagation linked to political agendas.
12 Brunstetter, D., & Braun, M. (2011). The implications of drones on the just
war tradition. Ethics & International Affairs, 25(3), 337–358.
13 IPCC (2022) www.ipcc.ch/report/ar6/wg2/
14 See, e.g., www.irishexaminer.com/sport/soccer/arid-30448950.html
15 www.theguardian.com/us-news/video/2022/jun/24/this-is-not-over-
kamala-harris-speaks-out-against-overturning-of-roe-v-wade-video
16 I am Ozzy (Sphere, 2009), pp.26–7.
17 See George Marshall (2014) Don’t Even Think About It. (Bloomsbury).
221
DOI: 10.4324/9781003247944-10
222
P1: X is comparable to Y.
P2: Z is true of Y.
C: Therefore Z is also true of X.
P3: Z is true of Y.
P4: Z is linked with features a, b, c, etc.
C: Therefore Z is also true of X.
Set in the 1970s, The Last King of Scotland (Keven MacDonald, 2007)
is a film about a young Scottish doctor (Nicholas) who, when volun-
teering in Uganda, ends up becoming Ide Amin’s personal physician.
Nicolas initially rejects Amin’s offer because he has come to Uganda
to help ordinary people, but Amin then argues that by helping the
president he will be helping the people by assisting the development
of a national health service. Nicholas again, politely, refuses. Amin’s
second argument is an analogy that can be reconstructed like this:
coming across a watch for the first time (in contrast to a stone)
would rightly believe that it is not a random occurrence (Q1). (Note
that with hypothetical analogies we can challenge the belief that is
assumed in the analogue – so in Thomson’s analogy we might want
to claim that we do not have the right to disconnect our self from the
violinist as she thinks we would – but in real-life analogies the facts
of the analogue can be challenged as well as our supposed attitude
towards those facts.) Arguably there are relevant similarities between
the watch and the workings of nature (Q2), but Q3 begins to reveal
weaknesses in the argument. Despite their complexity and function-
ality, living organisms and their component parts are noticeably dif-
ferent from man-made artefacts, and in many respects (irregularities,
shapes, textures, and so on) share more with the contrasting stone
than with watches and other devices. Also, a simple dissimilarity is
that we can observe watches and other machines being designed and
built, but have no such empirical evidence for the origins of nature.
Q4 is problematic for design arguments since an alternative anal-
ogy for the creation of nature is the creation of living organisms at
a result of procreation. A designer is not an observable or necessary
feature of the continuation of animal and vegetable species, so why
should it be for the world as a whole? In Hume’s words,
The world plainly resembles more an animal or a vegetable, than it does
a watch or knitting-loom. Its cause, therefore, it is more probable, resem-
bles the cause of the former. The cause of the former is generation or veg-
etation. The cause, therefore, of the world, we may infer to be something
similar analogous to generation or vegetation. (Hume, [1779] 1990, p.87)
From these examples we can see that the lone, carefully selected
metaphor helps keep messages coherent and memorable. Further use
of figurative language would risk creating linguistic clutter that would
interfere with this aim. In both speeches, however, the metaphor
appears closer to the middle of the speech than the beginning, and in
both cases the reason is that unrelated content was (for good reasons)
positioned prior to this. In the Obama case the speech naturally begins
with condolence rather than arguments, and with Brown other argu-
ments (concerning, for example, national (British) pride) were more
appropriate as openers. If a metaphor functions as a joker, it makes
sense that Brown would choose to play his on the economic theme.
have creative qualities, though, they are effective for generating dis-
cussion and catalysing stronger arguments and deeper understanding.
There is a cognitive reason for this, concerning stimulation of the
imagination, and a motivational reason as well. Several literary phi-
losophers, such as Søren Kierkegaard, Jean-Paul Sartre, Iris Murdoch,
and Martha Nussbaum, have written about the importance of stories
(including allegories) for depersonalising topics; their aesthetic distance
providing an engaging focus whilst helping to avoid some of the emo-
tional distortion that political and ethical debates can generate and that
frequently impede our real-life deliberations. Since the story is not ours,
we do not find ourselves caught up in the ‘vulgar heat’ of our personal
jealousies or angers or in the sometimes blinding violence of our loves.
(Nussbaum, 1990, p.48)
SUMMARY
draws out relevant (‘target’) features of the primary case that support
the conclusion. A strong argument from analogy impresses on us the
plausibility that since something is true of the analogue case it will
also be true of the primary case. A weak analogy should leave us
questioning the relevance of the connection between the two, and
searching for counteranalogies that further expose this flaw.
EXERCISES
1. There are quite a few examples of brief and extended analogies
in this chapter (such as Covid vaccine refusal being equated
to drink driving; the scene from The Last King of Scotland; the
documentary The Corporation; Thomson’s ‘famous violinist’;
the film Don’t Look Up; and Frank Skinner’s religion-football
comparison) which have been explained or cited, but not
analysed. This you could do by applying the critical questions
and the criteria for the persuasiveness of figurative language in
the ‘Psychology and rhetoric’ section. It is worth looking out
for your own examples as well – arguments from analogy are
used very frequently indeed.
2. As mentioned towards the end of the chapter, generating and
countering arguments from analogy is one of the most imagi-
native aspects of critical thinking. There are various activities
you can do around this, and one example is for a contentious
topic that interests you (or one agreed on by the class or set by
the teacher), devise an argument from analogy in support of
your position. To add realism (and perhaps make the task a bit
easier), determine in advance the type of person or audience
you are trying to convince with your argument.
FURTHER READING
Three sources on arguments from analogy that will help develop
your understanding of the subject and of some of the disagreements
within it are these:
• Bruce Waller (2013) ‘Classifying and Analysing Analogies’.
• Christopher Tindale (2007), Chapter 10.
• Trudy Govier (2013), Chapter 11.
233
NOTES
1 www.bbc.co.uk/news/av/uk-57146619
2 The choice of terminology is closest to Trudy Govier’s (2013), but ‘target
feature’ is Hughes, Lavery, and Doran’s phrase (2010), p.215.
3 Thomson, J.J. (1971) A Defence of Abortion, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 1 (1),
47–66.
4 The Play Book (Allen Lane, 2022), p.172.
5 On the Road (Arrow Books, 2009), pp.42–3.
6 Both of these speeches are easily located for viewing online.
234
10
FURTHER FALLACIES
The previous three chapters have been about argument forms, and
their associated fallacies, that warrant extended analysis and explora-
tion. The focus of this chapter is a selection of fallacies and rhetori-
cal techniques that could not be located among these analyses, but
which are also important to know about. These are affirming the
consequent (and denying the antecedent); circular arguments;
false dilemmas; the perfectionist fallacy; and red herrings and
equivocations.
P1: If X, then Y.
P2: X.
C: Therefore Y.
DOI: 10.4324/9781003247944-11
235
P1: If X, then Y.
P2: Y.
C: Therefore X.
So,
Many things can make us emotional in the way that Rovelli seems to
mean – such as walking in a mountainous landscape, or contemplat-
ing the night sky, or watching our team win an important match –
but these are not works of art.
A similar argument to modus ponens is modus tollens, which has this
structure:
P1: If X, then Y.
P2: Not Y.
C: Therefore not X.
If X is the case, then Y must also be the case; therefore if Y is not the
case then X cannot be the case:
P1: If you like all forms of music, then you must like jazz scat
singing.
P2: You don’t like jazz scat singing.
C: Therefore you don’t like all forms of music.
P1: If X, then Y.
P2: Not X.
C: Therefore not Y.
P1: If you like all forms of music, then you must like jazz scat
singing.
P2: You don’t like all forms of music.
C: Therefore you don’t like jazz scat singing.
237
Circular arguments are fairly common, and if you get the scent of
one it is worth pursuing it even if it takes some trial and error to
pin it down. If someone tries to prove God’s existence using the
Bible, for example, persistence can pay off because it is probably
circular:
If this seems pretty dumb, then that’s because, in the vast majority of
cases, it is. For example, after mass shootings in the US we usually
hear a variation on this argument:
P1: If the US changes its gun control laws then people will still be
able get hold of guns.
P2: If people can get hold of guns, then shootings and massacres
will be a possibility.
C: Therefore there’s no point in the US changing its gun control
laws.
242
from death or misery, the fact that there are many others I cannot res-
cue is irrelevant to the moral worth of doing this. Huge problems some-
times produce an irrational paralysis of the imagination. It is so terrible
to think of the poverty and starvation that will still exist in the world
whatever I do, that it is tempting to despair and do nothing. (Glover,
1986, p.126)
10.6 SUMMARY
This chapter has explained some common fallacies not discussed
elsewhere in the book and provided some reasons for why they are
important to know about. Lists of fallacies can be very long, and
there will never be a definitive set, so a book like this is inevitably
selective. If you explore other critical thinking textbooks you could
well uncover others that you think have equal or greater relevance to
the worlds in which you are responsible for making decisions.
EXERCISES
This is a good place to remind you of the recommendation in the
book’s Introduction that the best way to practise identifying and eval-
uating argument forms and fallacies is by analysing detailed examples
in which the context is familiar to you.
Aside from this, an exercise I use in my critical thinking classes to
enhance students’ understanding of these ideas is to provide a list of
argument forms and fallacies, and assign each student two or three to
research. Dividing the list among the class has various practical and
245
FURTHER READING
Most textbooks on informal logic and critical thinking will dis-
cuss the fallacies found in this chapter (as well as those featured in
other parts of the book). Some good examples are Bowell and Kemp
(2015), Chatfield (2018), Hughes, Lavery, and Doran (2010), Johnson
and Blair (2006), LeBlanc (1998), and Sinnott-Armstrong (2018).
NOTES
1 Today programme, BBC Radio 4, 28.9.15
2 Fatwa – 6. Are You With Us?, BBC Sounds. Available at: www.bbc.co.uk/
sounds/play/m0002g88
3 Klein, N. (2014) This Changes Everything. Penguin
4 Classic Rock, December 2015, p.22
5 Available at: www.youtube.com/watch?v=D2ScHyXs50Q
6 Available at: www.reuters.com/world/asia-pacific/taliban-say-female-afghan-
tv-presenters-must-cover-face-air-2022–05–19/
7 Jefferson, B. (2013) Jose Mourinho: Chelsea losing to Basel and Everton isn’t
a crisis, Syria is a crisis [Article]. Available at: www.express.co.uk/sport/foot-
ball/430957/ Jose-Mourinho-Chelsea-losing-to-Basel-and-Everton-isn-t-a-
crisis-Syria-is-a-crisis.
246
CONCLUSION
As set out in the introduction, and as hopefully this book has demon-
strated, the aim of critical thinking is to make us better deliberators
and decision makers through a frame of mind and a set of knowledge
and skills that:
1. Help us to identify, reconstruct and assess the arguments of
others.
2. Help us to construct, assess and improve our own arguments.
3. Educate us in the pitfalls associated with reasoning in terms of:
i. Fallacies and their associated psychological biases;
ii. Features of unconstructive dialogues; and
iii. Dispositions that make us prone to fallacious reasoning
and unconstructive dialogues.
CONCLUSION 247
248 CONCLUSION
CONCLUSION 249
But we’re not. Whatever our self-serving bias tells us, we too
are prone to the self-serving bias.
8. Become acquainted with the ways in which emotions can hin-
der (and help) argumentation. And notice the kinds of argu-
ments that are especially emotive, such as ad hominems, ad
baculums, and slippery slopes.
9. Consider the communication needs and limitations of your
audience. Make judicious use of enthymemes, take care with
your vocabulary, and avoid alienating others through smartars-
ery. Where permitted by the subject matter, choose authorities
and analogies that will be recognisable and appealing to your
audience.
10. If we listen carefully to the views of others, we might find that
we agree on more than we think we do; that disagreements are
caused by misunderstandings, or are superficial. To get there
we need to be willing to ask questions, and not with a view
to tripping people up. Thinking critically about beliefs and
courses of action means that our evaluations can be positive as
well as negative. To be oriented to the negative is a bias, and at
its worst it can make us ‘argumentative’. Don’t be argumenta-
tive, be a critical thinker.
ii
251
GLOSSARY
their health, rather than from any direct physical effects of the
treatment itself.
plausible argument A style of argument employed in delibera-
tions and other dialogues in which generally accepted assump-
tions act as the basis for reaching conclusions.They have practical
advantages, but are recognised as provisional in nature. See also
burden of proof, and defeasible generalisation.
pluralistic ignorance A socially based form of ignorance in which
indecision or inaction results from the mutual misinterpretation
of uncertainty as calmness or confidence.
position to know argument An argument based on informa-
tion power (but excluding witness testimony).
premise See argument.
premise and conclusion indicators When identifying and
reconstructing arguments, certain words and phrases can help to
indicate the presence of premises (e.g., ‘the reasons for this are’)
and conclusions (e.g., ‘therefore’).
principle of charity When reconstructing arguments, the princi-
ple of charity is the best reasonable interpretation of ambiguous,
vague, or otherwise unclear sentences or arguments.
proposition (statement) A sentence that (at least in theory) can
be adjudged to be true or false. These are contrasted with, for
example, sentences that are questions or directives (requests,
orders). All premises and conclusions in an argument must be
propositions.
psychology of persuasion The study of the psychological prin-
ciples underlying persuasive communication.
rational system See System 1/2 thinking.
rationalisation A type of ego-defence in which we uncon-
sciously provide a false reason for why something happened
because the real reason (which the rationalisation masks) causes
us psychological pain or discomfort
reciprocation A heuristic linked to the norm of equitable
exchange of favours, goods, and so on.
red herring An irrelevant argument with the potential to divert
other arguers away from the issue being discussed because
of its apparent relevance and often emotive content. See also
equivocation.
GLOSSARY 259
REFERENCES
Taylor, S.E. and Brown, J.D. (1988) Illusion and Well-Being:A Social Psychological
Perspective on Mental Health. Psychological bulletin, 103(2), 193–210.
Tiberius,V. (2008) The Reflective Life. Oxford University Press.
Tindale, C. (2007) Fallacies and Argument Appraisal. Cambridge University Press.
Tomić, T. (2013) False Dilemma: A Systematic Exposition. Argumentation, 27(4),
347–68.
Toulmin, S. (1958) The Uses of Argument. Cambridge University Press.
Tversky, A., and Kahneman, D. (1974) Judgment under Uncertainty: Heuristics
and Biases. Science, 185(4157), 1124–31.
Tversky, A. and Kahneman, D. (1983) Extensional Versus Intuitive Reasoning:
the Conjunction Fallacy in Probability Judgment. Psychological Review, 90(4),
293–315.
Waller, B.N. (2001) Classifying and Analysing Analogies. Informal Logic, 21(3),
199–218.
Walton, D. (1989) Informal Logic. Cambridge University Press.
Walton, D. (1992) The Place of Emotion in Argument. Penn State University Press.
Walton, D. (1995) A Pragmatic Theory of Fallacy. University of Alabama Press.
Walton, D. (2001) Abductive, Presumptive and Plausible Arguments, Informal
Logic, 21(2), 141–69.
Walton, D. (2006) Fundamentals of Critical Argumentation. Cambridge University
Press.
Walton, D. (2009) Ad Hominem Arguments. University of Alabama Press.
Walton, D. (2015) The Basic Slippery Slope Argument, Informal Logic, 35(3),
273–311.
Walton, D., Reed, C., and Macagno, F. (2008) Argumentation Schemes. Cambridge
University Press.
Weber, M. (1978) Economy and Society. University of California Press.
Webster, D. and Kruglanski, A. (1994) Individual differences in need for cognitive
closure. Journal of personality and social psychology, 67(6), 1049–62
Webster, D. and Kruglanski, A. (1997) Cognitive and Social Consequences of the
Need for Cognitive Closure, European Review of Social Psychology, 8(1), 133–73.
Willard, C.A. (1990) Authority. Informal Logic, 12(1), 12–22.
Woods, J. (1995) Appeal to Force. In H. Hansen and R. Pinto (eds.) Fallacies. Penn
State University Press.
Woods, J. (2013) Errors of Reasoning: Naturalizing the Logic of Inference. College
Publications.
Worth, L. and Mackie, D. (1987) Cognitive Mediation of Positive Affect in
Persuasion. Social Cognition, 5(1), 76–94.
Yalom, I. (1980) Existential Psychotherapy. Basic Books.
267
INDEX