Solution To Problem Set Five - Demand: Consumer Choice
Solution To Problem Set Five - Demand: Consumer Choice
Consumer Choice
Lecture Notes in Microeconomic Theory by Ariel Rubinstein
Last Update: Oct 30, 2007
P
1. Calculate the demand function for the utility function k αk ln(xk ).
The consumer’s problem is:
X X
max αk ln(xk ) st pk xk ≤ w and xk ≥ 0 for all k ∈ {1, . . . , K}.
{xk }
k k
2. Verify that when preferences are continuous, the demand function x(p, w)
is continuous in prices and in wealth (and not only in p).
Choose an arbitrary convergent sequence of price/wealth pairs (pn , wn ) →
(p, w) such that (p, w) (0, 0). Since x(p, w) is homogeneous of degree
zero, this implies n
n n p
x(p , w ) = x ,1 .
wn
Since demand is continuous in p, then
n
p p
x ,1 → x , 1 = x(p, w),
wn w
1
3. Show that if a consumer has a homothetic preference relation, then his
demand function is homogeneous of degree one in w.
Assume that % is homothetic, and let λ > 0 and (p, w) ∈ <K+1 ∗
++ . Let y ∈
∗ 1 ∗ 1 ∗
B(p, λw), ie py ≤ λw. Clearly, λ y ∈ B(p, w), and thus x(p, w) % λ y .
By homotheticity, it follows λx(p, w) % y ∗ .
Since y ∗ was arbitrarily chosen from B(p, λw), it follows that λx(p, w) % y
for every y ∈ B(p, λw). Moreover, λx(p, w) ∈ B(p, λw), and therefore
λx(p, w) = x(p, λw) since it is the optimal bundle in B(p, λw).
r6x(p, w)
@
@
@
@
@r z
@
@ @
@ r x(p, w0 ) @r y
@ @
@ @
@ @-
Clearly, x(p, w) % y, and thus by strict convexity z y. But then
0
0
(0, w
p2 ) x(p, w ) by quasi-linearity, a contradiction.
2
• x1 (p, w) > 0, w < w0 ⇒ x1 (p, w0 ) = x1 (p, w) + [w0 − w].
Proof: By contradiction, assume x(p, w0 ) 6= x(p, w) + e1 [w0 − w].
Since x(p, w) % y for all y ∈ B(p, w), then
0 0
x1 (p, w) + [w − w], x2 (p, w) % y1 + [w − w], y2
6
@
@
r z @ r x(p, w0 )
@
@
@ Preferred to bold line directly by q-linearity
@ @@
@ r x(p, w) @@r x(p, w) + e1 [w0 − w]
@ @@
@ @
@
@ @-
3
Since (pn , xn ) ∈ G(w), then pn xn ≤ w for every n. It readily follows that
6. Determine whether the following behavior patterns are consistent with the
consumer model:
2w w
(a) The consumer’s demand function is x(p, w) = 2p1 +p2 , 2p1 +p2 .
Yes, x(p, w) can be rationalized by the monotonic preference rela-
tion represented by u(x) = min{x1 , 2x2 }. Since % is monotonic, the
consumer will always set
i. p1 x1 + p2 x2 = w by Walras’ Law, and
ii. x1 = 2x2 by the functional form of u(x).
Substituting (ii) into (i), it follows
w 2w
2p1 x2 + p2 x2 = w ⇒ x2 (p, w) = ⇒ x1 (p, w) = .
2p1 + p2 2p1 + p2
(c) The consumer chooses a bundle (x1 , x2 ) which satisfies xx21 = pp12 and
costs w. Does the utility function u(x) = x21 + x22 rationalize the
consumer’s behavior?
No, u(x) = x21 +x22 does not rationalize the behavior. Since u(x) is not
quasi-concave, the maximization approach that we used in Question
1 is not appropriate. If 0 < p2 < p1 , then a consumer maximizing
u(x) would set x(p, w) = (0, pw2 ). Nevertheless, the consumer actually
chooses
x1 p1
= > 0 ⇒ x1 (p, w) > 0.
x2 p2
4
Moreover, the behavior violates the WA and therefore is not ratio-
nalizable. Consider the choices from the following budget sets:
x((2, 1), 5) = (2, 1) and x((1, 2), 5) = (1, 2).
Note that each of the bundles is affordable at the other bundle’s
prices:
(1, 2) · x((2, 1), 5) = (1, 2) · (2, 1) = 4 < 5
(2, 1) · x((1, 2), 5) = (2, 1) · (1, 2) = 4 < 5,
which is a violation of the WA.
5
(c) Is this demand procedure rationalizable?
Yes, it can be rationalized by the monotonic utility function
if u(x) < u0
u(x)
v(x) =
u0 + x1 if u(x) ≥ u0 .
(e) Show that in the domain of (p, w) for which there is a feasible bundle
yielding utility of at least u0 the consumer’s demand function for
commodity 1 is decreasing in p1 and increasing in w.
Let (p, w) be such that maxx∈B(p,w) u(x) ≥ u0 , and define p0 = p−γe1
for some γ > 0. Since p0 x(p, w) < w, then x1 (p, w) < x1 (p0 , w), as
the agent can afford strictly more of commodity 1 under B(p0 , w)
while maintaining utility u0 . Consequently, x1 (p.w) is decreasing in
p1 .
Similarly, define w0 = w + γ, and note px(p, w) < w0 . As before,
it must be that x1 (p, w) < x1 (p.w0 ), as the agent can afford strictly
more of commodity 1 under B(p, w0 ), and thus x1 (p.w) is increasing
in w.
w
and note that xni ≤ m for every i = 1, ..., K and every n. Conse-
n w K
quently, {x } is contained in the compact hypercube [0, m ] . There-
n
fore, without loss of generality we can assume that x → y. Moreover,
note that py = limn→∞ pn xn ≤ w, and thus y ∈ B(p, w). There are
two cases to consider:
Case 1: u(y) < u0
Since x is unique by (b), then u(y) < u(x). By continuity, there
exists a point z x such that pz < w and u(y) < u(z). Then
6
for n large enough, pn z ≤ w and u(xn ) < u(z), a contradiction
to xn being the optimal bundle in B(pn , w).
Case 2: u(y) ≥ u0
Since x is unique by (b), then u(x) ≥ u0 and x1 > y1 . Define
z = 21 x + 12 y, and note that z1 > y1 , z ∈ B(p, w) and u(z) > u0
by strict convexity. By continuity, there exists an > 0 such
that z1 − > y1 , p[z − e] < w and u(z − e) > u0 . Then for n
large enough, pn [z − e] ≤ w and z1 − > xn1 , a contradiction to
xn being the optimal bundle in B(pn , w).
and consider the price/wealth pairs (pA , wA ) = ((1, 2), 8) and (pB , wB ) =
((2, 1), 8). Note that
xA
1 = (4, 2) xB
1 = (4, 0) xA
2 = (0, 4) xB
2 = (2, 4).
7
Proof of Lemma: Let |X| = N . By contradiction, assume that for every
x ∈ X, there is a y ∈ X such that y x. Choose any element in X,
say x1 . Then there exists another element in X, say x2 , such that
x2 x1 . Again, there exists an x3 ∈ X such that x3 x2 and so
on. Thus we can find a sequence such that xN +1 xN ... x1 .
Since |X| = N , then for some i ∈ {1, ..., N − 1}, xN +1 = xi . But
then xN +1 ... xi+1 and xi+1 xN +1 , a contradiction to being
acyclic.