Elements of Democratic Justice: Ian Shapiro Yale University
Elements of Democratic Justice: Ian Shapiro Yale University
Elements of Democratic Justice: Ian Shapiro Yale University
IAN SHAPIRO
Yale University
579
This content downloaded from 131.175.12.9 on Sat, 02 May 2020 03:57:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
580 POLITICAL THEORY / November 1996
and that the apparent tensions between democracy and justice need to be
rethought along lines that have more in common with popular expectations
than with academic orthodoxy. On my view, although democracy is not
sufficient for social justice, arguments about democracy and social justice are
more deeply entwined with one another than the conventional opposition
suggests. The mutual dependence of these two ideals is signaled by the fact
that, on the one hand, most arguments for democracy rest at bottom on
intuitions about what is just, and, on the other, if we dig deeply enough into
arguments about social justice we frequently discover that they rest on
appeals to democratic moral intuitions. This is not to say that commitments
to democracy and to social justice entail one another; it is to say, however,
that no account of either that undermines one's moral intuitions about the
other is likely to be judged satisfactory.3
Drawing out the implications of this observation, I have sought to develop
a view of social justice in which democratic considerations play a three-part
foundational role: in the definition of social goods, in the determination of
principles by which conflicts over goods should be resolved, and in the
appropriate stance toward implementing principles of justice in the actual
world of day-to-day politics.4 These three ways to be a democrat set the basic
terms of the view that I characterize as democratic justice, in contrast to
liberal, socialist, conservative, and communitarian views that are in wide
academic currency today. Although my view is conceived of as an alternative
to these, I mean to make it attractive to many of their proponents because it
depends less on alternative sets of assumptions about social justice and more
on making explicit the implications of democratic moral intuitions to which
many of them, on reflection, will find themselves committed. My earlier
defenses of democratic justice have been ground-clearing and programmatic,
amounting to a downpayment, at best, on a positive argument for democratic
justice. My aim here is to deliver on the first installment of the construc-
tive account.
Three preliminary points: First, democracy as I defend it is a subordinate
good. By this I mean that although democracy is necessary for ordering social
relations justly, we should resist every suggestion that it is sufficient, that it
is the highest human good, that it is the only human good, or that it should
dominate the activities in which we engage. Democracy operates best when
it sets the terms for our civil interactions without thereby determining their
course. Our lives require much else as well to be satisfactory, and it is wrong-
headed to expect democracy to deliver those other things. This conception
follows from the thought that because power relations form part-but not
all-of most collective activities, democracy appropriately conditions those
activities but it does not appropriately displace them. Although we should
This content downloaded from 131.175.12.9 on Sat, 02 May 2020 03:57:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Shapiro / ELEMENTS OF DEMOCRATIC JUSTICE 581
This content downloaded from 131.175.12.9 on Sat, 02 May 2020 03:57:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
582 POLITICAL THEORY / November 1996
however, life goes on and we need grounds for preferring some institutio
arrangements over others. Second, although it is common to think that we
should start with general matters because people are more likely to agree
them and then move to more specific and divisive matters-to the details
wherein the devil is thought to lurk-exactly the opposite is often true, as
Cass Sunstein has usefully noted. A faculty may be able to reach agreement
that a particular person should be granted tenure even though its members
could never agree on the reasons why. By extension, in arguing about the
merits of different political arrangements, it is often wise to avoid-or at least
minimize-attention to controversial questions of higher order interests and
ultimate justification.6 That is the assumption behind the present discussion.
Last, because no one can do everything, it behooves practitioners in different
disciplines to reflect on where they are most likely to make a useful contri-
bution. In my view normative political theorists best devote attention to
analyzing how to structure the power-dimensions of human interaction,
leaving to psychologists, moral philosophers, and metaphysicians full analy-
sis of higher order interests and issues of ultimate justification. Although
every intellectual division of labor will be unsatisfactory from some defen-
sible point of view, choices inevitably have to be made in this regard. The
reader must judge whether I have made the right ones here.
Democrats are committed to rule by the people. They insist that no arist
crat, monarch, bureaucrat, expert, or religious leader has the right, in virt
of such status, to force people to accept a particular conception of their pro
.common life. People should decide for themselves, via appropriate proce-
dures of collective decision, what their collective business should be. The
may reasonably be required to consult and take account of one another, a
of others affected by their actions, but beyond this no one may legitimate
tell them what to do. The people are sovereign; in all matters of collectiv
life they rule over themselves.
Although this is less often commented on in the academic literature,
democracy is as much about opposition to the arbitrary exercise of power
it is about collective self-government. In this connection Barrington Mo
remarks that historically democracy has been a weapon "of the poor and
many against the few and the well-to-do." Those who have actively soug
it in organized political movements "have wanted it as a device to increas
their share in political rule and weaken the power and authority of those w
This content downloaded from 131.175.12.9 on Sat, 02 May 2020 03:57:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Shapiro / ELEMENTS OF DEMOCRATIC JUSTICE 583
Collective Self-Government
This content downloaded from 131.175.12.9 on Sat, 02 May 2020 03:57:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
584 POLITICAL THEORY / November 1996
good; their proponents resist the idea that values should be imposed on peopl
against their wishes in the name of some greater social good. The reasons for
affirming this antivanguardist stance vary: they can range from commitmen
to variants of philosophical skepticism, pragmatism, and antifoundational-
ism, to beliefs in the psychological value of critical reflection and contested
authority, to the conviction that a degree of pluralism about values is socio-
logically or politically desirable. Liberals and democrats do not divide predict-
ably over these foundational matters, but for most of both some combination
of them issues in a principled resistance to moral vanguardism.'0
Liberals and democrats do divide predictably, however, over the institu-
tional implications they draw from their moral antivanguardism. Liberals,
who typically regard individual freedom as the greatest good, characteristically
focus on devices to protect the individual from the realm of collective action.
Democrats, by contrast, try to structure collective action appropriately to
embody the preferences of the governed. Liberals characteristically resist
this logic on the grounds that no procedure can fairly embody the preferences
of all the governed. For liberals, democratic decision rules all too readily
become devices by which phantom majorities-sometimes even manipulat-
ive minorities-tyrannize over individuals."
Although there is merit to the liberal argument, it rests on flawed assump-
tions about the nature of politics and about the limits of collective action.
Concerning the first, the characteristic liberal mistake is to focus on the forms
of tyranny performed by and through government as the only-certainly the
principal-kind of tyranny that should worry political theorists. Liberal
commitments to negative freedom, conventional constructions of public/pri-
vate dichotomies, and arguments for limited government are all shaped by
this governmentalist view of politics. Governmental power is one potential
site of domination, but there are many others that permeate the different domains
of "private" life. Government can be an instrument for mitigating domination
as well as a source of its generation. As a result, the choices and tradeoffs that
can minimize domination throughout society will likely defy such simplify-
ing formulae as "the government that governs least governs best."
The liberal view is flawed also because its proponents tend to think that
whether or not our lives should be governed by collective institutions is an
intelligible question about politics. Hence Robert Nozick's remark that the
fundamental question of political theory "is whether there should be any state
at all."''2 This view is misleading because the institutions of private property,
contract, and public monopoly of coercive force that its proponents charac-
teristically favor were created and are sustained by the state, partly financed
by implicit taxes on those who would prefer an alternative system. In the
modern world, Nozick's assertion makes as much sense as would a claim that
This content downloaded from 131.175.12.9 on Sat, 02 May 2020 03:57:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Shapiro / ELEMENTS OF DEMOCRATIC JUSTICE 585
This content downloaded from 131.175.12.9 on Sat, 02 May 2020 03:57:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
586 POLITICAL THEORY / November 1996
sive decision rules, though not necessarily simple majority rule, and indeed,
within this class, different majorities might be agreed on as optimal for
different purposes. "The number of categories, and the number of decision-
making rules chosen, will depend on the situation which the individual
expects to prevail and the 'returns to scale' expected to result from using the
same rule over many activities." 15
This story is intuitively plausible only if we take the contractualist meta-
phor on which it rests seriously, assuming a prepolitical status quo where
there is no collective action and then a series of consensual moves that lead
to the creation of what we know of as political society. But, as Brian Barry,
Douglas Rae, and others have pointed out, once this assumption is jettisoned
there is no particular reason to regard unanimity rule as the most appropriate
default decision rule.'6 In the real world of ongoing politics, if I assume that
I am as likely to oppose a given policy as to support it regardless of whether
it is the status quo, then majority rule or something close to it is the logical
rule to prefer. Once we move from majority toward unanimity rule, we begin
to privilege the status quo. This will rightly seem arbitrary in a world that has
not evolved cooperatively from a precollective condition. In short, other
things being equal tyranny of the majority is something that people should
rationally fear, but not as much as they should fear tyranny of the minority."7
The preceding discussion reinforces the suggestion that there is no single
best decision rule for democratic governance. In domains of social life where
relations really do tend to approximate the contractualist story-in that they
are both created ex nihilo by the participants and are basically cooperative in
character-a presumptive commitment to unanimity rule is defensible. One
might think of marriage in contemporary America as a paradigm case. It is
created consensually, usually with the expectation that in important matters
day-to-day governance will also be consensual. (Indeed, with the advent of
no-fault divorce since the 1970s, we see an unusually strong form of the
unanimity requirement at work. In most American states either spouse can
insist-subject to a brief waiting period-on a divorce unilaterally: the
marriage continues only so long as both parties agree. Far from privileging
the status quo, this variant of unanimity rule makes it perpetually vulnerable,
since the rule is not defined by reference to the status quo but by in effect
recreating the conditions antecedent to it at the wish of either party.)'8
Many social relationships do not approximate the contractualist ideal; they
are not created ex nihilo in the sense that contemporary American marriages
usually are, and they are to a high degree structured by forces other than the
wills of the participants. Even childless marriages involve the generation of
reliances and externalities that can undermine their exclusively consensual
character. These are questions of degree, however. Social relations are often
This content downloaded from 131.175.12.9 on Sat, 02 May 2020 03:57:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Shapiro / ELEMENTS OF DEMOCRATIC JUSTICE 587
not contractualist to anything like the extent that marriage is, even when su
reliances are taken into account; most obviously, think of parent-child rel
tions. Constitutional political arrangements are often pointed to as presum
tively contractualist because of their foundational character and their pl
in the social contract tradition. Such arrangements might once have been
consented to by the relevant parties, although even in the American foundin
a narrowly circumscribed class agreed in fact-and then not unanimously.
Generations later, whatever contractualist element these arrangements on
exhibited has receded into the mists of time. In such circumstances (and n
doubt there are others) there is no evident reason to regard unanimity rule
best on the grounds that it embodies the consent of the governed.
Nor are there good reasons to think that some alternative decision rule
should appropriately govern all relations where a contractualist element is
either missing or overdetermined by other factors. As the examples just
mentioned indicate, this is a heterogeneous class. In some domains, the sort
Rae evidently has in mind, majority rule is prima facie the best decision rule.
These include relations typically characterized by arms-length transactions,
where substantial aspects of the collective action in question are competitive
rather than cooperative, and where there are no obvious reasons to counte-
nance paternalistic decision making. They are also often circumstances in
which people are either born into structural relations that cannot easily be
escaped, or, if there is a contractualist element to their participation, it is
accompanied by a good deal of what Marxists like to think of as "structural
coercion." Whatever the surface appearances, the relations in question are
not substantially voluntary. Arguments for workplace democracy in which
majority rule plays a substantial role generally appeal to some combination
of these characteristics in justifying their appeal; Rae's logic supplies us with
reasons for accepting them."9
Not every noncontractualist or minimally contractualist form of associa-
tion should be governed by majority rule, however. Both Buchanan and
Tullock's and Rae's reasoning take it for granted that, ceteris paribus, deci-
sion-making costs should be minimized, for which they have sometimes been
criticized by participatory democrats.20 Rather than follow the participatory
democrat's reasoning (which creates difficulties of its own),2' the argument
here is that participation must itself be thought about in a context-sensitive
way. In some circumstances participation is no more than a cost to be
minimized, subject to achieving or preventing a particular outcome. Anyone
who has sat through enough faculty meetings will know what at least one of
those circumstances is. In other situations, institutions may reasonably be
structured to maximize participation. Juries are an obvious example. Una-
nimity is generally required just because it forces discussion and joint
This content downloaded from 131.175.12.9 on Sat, 02 May 2020 03:57:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
588 POLITICAL THEORY / November 1996
This content downloaded from 131.175.12.9 on Sat, 02 May 2020 03:57:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Shapiro / ELEMENTS OF DEMOCRATIC JUSTICE 589
This content downloaded from 131.175.12.9 on Sat, 02 May 2020 03:57:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
590 POLITICAL THEORY / November 1996
This content downloaded from 131.175.12.9 on Sat, 02 May 2020 03:57:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Shapiro ! ELEMENTS OF DEMOCRATIC JUSTICE 591
Institutionalizing Opposition
This content downloaded from 131.175.12.9 on Sat, 02 May 2020 03:57:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
592 POLITICAL THEORY / November 1996
This content downloaded from 131.175.12.9 on Sat, 02 May 2020 03:57:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Shapiro / ELEMENTS OF DEMOCRATIC JUSTICE 593
can happen when permissive freedoms are not honored. Democrats would be
unwise ever to think them dispensable.
Although permissive freedoms are often essential to securing the space
for opposition and fostering it, it would be a mistake to conclude that in
general they will be sufficient. To see why this is so, notice that permissive
freedoms can actually undermine the possibility of challenging the status quo,
as my earlier discussion of the proposed Clinton health care reform indicated.
Inequalities in control over the resources needed to transform permissive
freedoms into the service of effective opposition can mean that strategically
powerful groups, when committed to prevailing arrangements, may be able
to block all attempts to alter them. Thus, although permissive freedoms are
reasonably deemed valuable for their propensity to permit and even foster
opposition, they are not a panacea. When those committed to the status quo
have unmatched access to information, wealth, and organizational resources,
they may actually be able to use permissive freedoms to cement their
advantages in place.
Awareness of the combined impact of imperfect decision rules and differ-
ential control over political resources has led some commentators to defend
"substantive" conceptions of democracy over "procedural" ones, usually by
appeal to some variant of Justice Stone's celebrated fourth footnote in United
States v. Carolene Products Co. Noting that well-functioning democratic
processes might lead to the domination of "discrete and insular minorities,"
Stone countenanced the possibility that their operation might reasonably be
limited when this occurs. Stone dealt with a circumscribed class of cases. But
his point is a general one, and others have employed his reasoning more
expansively.29 For instance, John Hart Ely defended much of the judicial
activism of the Warren Court by reference to Carolene Products reasoning.30
Likewise, Charles Beitz has pressed the same considerations into an argu-
ment that the quantitative fairness of equal voting power will never ensure
substantively democratic outcomes.3' In Beitz's view, a truly democratic
system of "qualitative fairness" requires a prior system of "just legislation,"
since mere equal voting power can never be relied upon to produce fair
outcomes.32
Substantively democratic views merely have to be stated for the difficulty
with them to be plain: How can Ely know what democratic processes ought
to have achieved had they not been corrupted by the Carolene problem?
Whence the theory of just legislation against which Beitz will evaluate the
results of voting procedures? Writers like Ely and Beitz have little to say to
those who are unpersuaded by their respective conceptions of "equal concern
and respect" and "qualitative fairness." If, as I maintain, there is no criterion
for justice that is anterior to what democracy generates, this should not be
This content downloaded from 131.175.12.9 on Sat, 02 May 2020 03:57:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
594 POLITICAL THEORY / November 1996
This content downloaded from 131.175.12.9 on Sat, 02 May 2020 03:57:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Shapiro / ELEMENTS OF DEMOCRATIC JUSTICE 595
This content downloaded from 131.175.12.9 on Sat, 02 May 2020 03:57:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
596 POLITICAL THEORY / November 1996
community, which interfered with their (i.e., the parents') rights of free
religious exercise.34
Democratic justice also bids us to attend to the degree to which hierarchies
are ossified or fluid. We should distinguish self-liquidating hierarchies, as
when children become adults or students graduate, from non-self-liquidating
hierarchies such as caste systems and hierarchies constituted by hereditary
transmissions of wealth and power. We should also distinguish hierarchical
orders in which anyone can in principle ascend to the top from those where
that is not so. No woman can aspire to become Pope, a fact that makes the
Catholic religion less attractive than some others from the standpoint of
democratic justice on this score. In general the argument tells us to prefer
fluid hierarchies over ossified ones, other things being equal. Fluid hierar-
chies may not create permanently subordinated classes whereas ossified
hierarchies will. Of course other things seldom are equal; nonetheless the
requirement is a useful starting point. It tells us what the presumption is and
by whom the burden of persuasion should be carried.
Similarly, asymmetrical hierarchies are questionable whereas symmetri-
cal ones are not necessarily so. Polygamous marriages are generally asym-
metrical, for example, and as such suspect from the standpoint of democratic
justice: a husband can have many wives but a wife cannot have many
husbands.35 If these polygamous regimes were symmetrical, or had their
members practiced "complex marriage" as did the nineteenth-century Oneida
perfectionist community (in which any number of men could marry any
number of women), they would not be questionable by reference to this aspect
of the argument for democratic justice. Again, there may be other reasons
rooted in democratic justice for objecting to such arrangements, but their
symmetry would count in their favor.36
Closely related to questions about the relative fluidity and symmetry of
hierarchies are questions about the degree to which they are imposed. Did
the people who are subjected to them elect to be thus subjected? What were
their other realistic options at the time? Whether or not they chose to enter,
what degree of freedom to exit now exists? Generally nonimposed hierarchies
fare better than imposed ones, and less imposed hierarchies fare better than
more imposed ones. If someone elected to participate at the bottom of a hier-
archical relationship when she had alternative nonhierarchical (or less hier-
archical) options in front of her, the fact of her choice confers some presump-
tive legitimacy on the state of affairs. Analogously, if someone remains in a
hierarchical order when we are fairly confident that she has the resources to
leave, we have less reason to be troubled from the standpoint of democratic
justice than when this is not the case.
This content downloaded from 131.175.12.9 on Sat, 02 May 2020 03:57:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Shapiro / ELEMENTS OF DEMOCRATIC JUSTICE 597
This content downloaded from 131.175.12.9 on Sat, 02 May 2020 03:57:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
598 POLITICAL THEORY / November 1996
This content downloaded from 131.175.12.9 on Sat, 02 May 2020 03:57:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Shapiro / ELEMENTS OF DEMOCRATIC JUSTICE 599
This content downloaded from 131.175.12.9 on Sat, 02 May 2020 03:57:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
600 POLITICAL THEORY / November 1996
This content downloaded from 131.175.12.9 on Sat, 02 May 2020 03:57:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Shapiro / ELEMENTS OF DEMOCRATIC JUSTICE 601
Yet other potential tensions arise, for democratic justice, out of the fact
that it is simultaneously concerned with many domains of civil society. It may
be the case that pursuing democratic justice in one domain makes it more
difficult, perhaps even impossible, to pursue it in other domains. For instance,
participating in governance is part of what democratic justice requires. Yet
there are limits to how much time people have available, so that increased
participatory involvement in one domain may mean diminished participation
in others. This is what Carmen Sirianni has characterized as the "paradox of
participatory pluralism." It arises for anyone who both values democratic
participation and embraces a view of politics that ranges throughout civil
society. We cannot simultaneously maximize participation over all domains.43
The paradox is inescapable for participatory democrats like Sirianni (who
offers no solution to it), but the argument for democratic justice suggests
avenues for dealing with it. Participation is not valuable for its own sake on
my view; rather, it is valuable only as it is pursued in conjunction with the
goods that it conditions. Collective self-governance is important in every
domain of civil society but it is never the most important thing; adherents of
democratic justice should thus always be open to timesaving and other novel
devices to conserve participatory resources. For instance, since the 1970s a
number of writers have explored the use of "deliberative polls": randomly
This content downloaded from 131.175.12.9 on Sat, 02 May 2020 03:57:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
602 POLITICAL THEORY / November 1996
selected groups that are paid to debate public issues from the selectio
presidential candidates to the governance of school districts.44 Exp
with deliberative polls suggests that they may provide useful mechanis
both exerting democratic control and solving the difficulty, pointed to
Sartori and others, that "knowledge-cognitive competence and control-
becomes more and more the problem as politics becomes more and more
complicated."45 Randomly selected lay groups, that have no particular vested
interest in the outcome in a given area, can invest the time and energy needed
to make informed decisions. Such groups can gather data and listen to expert
witnesses, making use of esoteric knowledge without being held hostage to
it. The decisions they render could be advisory or even binding, at least for
certain matters. From the standpoint of democratic justice the possibilities
offered by deliberative polls are worth exploring because they provide a
potential way out of Sirianni's paradox: they combine citizen control with
the possibility of sophisticated decision making in a complex world, and they
do it in a way that takes account of the economy of time.46
Earlier I suggested that from the standpoint of democratic justice partici-
pation should be seen neither in purely instrumental terms nor as the point of
the exercise in politics. Such devices as the deliberative poll are attractive
because they are an example of a creative institutional response to the goal
of trying to occupy a middle ground between these two views. Everyone
might be expected to participate in some deliberative polls, just as everyone
is expected to sit on some conventional juries. Everyone would know that,
in the bodies they are not involved in, other randomly selected bodies were
sitting with no particular agendas or interest groups of their own that were
being advanced. Everyone would also know that no matter how complex and
technical decisions were becoming, a meaningful element of lay control
would nonetheless be present in all collective decision making. This is
essential for democratic justice.
Apart from the extremes of limiting cases like slavery, the general a
ment for democratic justice does not provide conclusive assessments of
particular decision rules or mechanisms of opposition. Instead, as we have
seen, it generates presumptions and distributes burdens of persuasion in
various ways. That is as it should be. Since the general argument is a
semicontextual, particularities of context are needed to decide when burdens
have been appropriately carried and when presumptions have been rebut-
This content downloaded from 131.175.12.9 on Sat, 02 May 2020 03:57:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Shapiro / ELEMENTS OF DEMOCRATIC JUSTICE 603
This content downloaded from 131.175.12.9 on Sat, 02 May 2020 03:57:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
604 POLITICAL THEORY / November 1996
was a part-time activity for the wealthy. But these improvements have
brought with them new brands of ossified power in the form of professional
politicians with lifetime career aspirations in government. In the United
States, electoral politics have become dependent on money to such a degree
that political elites manage to maintain themselves in positions of power for
life in ways that are at odds with democracy's hostility toward entrenched
hierarchy.49 As a response to this, new democratic reforms are being called
for, geared toward limiting the number of terms politicians can serve and
better regulating the role of money in electoral politics.50
It defies credulity to suppose that in any of these instances democratic
reformers could have understood social processes profoundly enough, or
seen sufficiently far into the future, to have anticipated all the problems and
possibilities that lay ahead. Yet these cases are not exceptional; life has more
imagination than we do, and it will often defeat our best efforts and present
unexpected obstacles and opportunities. The fabric of social life and the
dynamics of historical change are complex and little understood; that is the
reality with which we have to live. Designing democratic institutional con-
straints is thus bound to be a pragmatic business, best pursued in context-sen-
sitive and incremental ways. New activities come into being, technological
change, experience, and the evolution of other causally linked activities all
present fresh problems and generate novel possibilities for democratic gov-
ernance. There are good reasons to be skeptical of anyone who denies this,
whether they harbor a hidden agenda that is being obscured by their van-
guardist pretensions or they are acting out of misplaced faith in their own
prescient abilities.
Means/ends dichotomies are suspect, also, for the normative reason that
they undermine the spirit of democratic justice. Although I have argued that
we should resist the participatory democrat's contention that participation is
valuable for its own sake, we should be no less wary of purely instrumental
conceptions of democracy. Democratic means are never the point of the
exercise, but they are usually of more than mere instrumental value. There is
value to doing things democratically, and there is value to struggling with
how to do things democratically while still achieving one's other goals.
Democratic habits of self-restraint and attention to the needs and aspirations
of others have to be learned through democratic practice; succumbing to the
authoritarianism inherent in means/ends dichotomies should be expected to
undermine it. In this connection, Dewey penned the right maxim for demo-
cratic justice over half a century ago: "Our first defense is to realize that
democracy can be served only by the slow day by day adoption and conta-
gious diffusion in every phase of our common life of methods that are
identical with the ends to be reached."51
This content downloaded from 131.175.12.9 on Sat, 02 May 2020 03:57:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Shapiro / ELEMENTS OF DEMOCRATIC JUSTICE 605
The principled refusal to impose solutions from above can provoke the
argument that unless this is done they will not be implemented at all, an
there are, indeed, at least three important classes of exceptions to the in
presumption against vanguardism. The first concerns the provision of pu
goods. As my earlier discussion of education revealed, when the provisio
of public goods is at issue and there are differential capacities for exit, n
local decision rule will likely be effective in diminishing injustice. This
amounts to saying that effective policies will have to be imposed from
above.52 Proponents of "shock therapy" in the transition from communism to
capitalism seem often to take an analogous view. Adam Przeworski argues,
for example, that during transitions from authoritarianism to democracy
unless economic reforms are rammed through from above, those who are
adversely affected by them will mobilize their opposition to them through
the democratic process, scuttling the reforms. Consequently, fledgling demo-
cratic governments "face the choice of either involving a broad range of
political forces in the shaping of reforms, thus compromising their economic
soundness, or trying to undermine all opposition to the [reform] program."
In Przeworski's view, any government "that is resolute must proceed in spite
of the clamor of voices that call for softening or slowing down the reform
program." Because reformers "know what is good" all political conflicts
become no more than a waste of time. Przeworski goes on to point out that
every instance of successful market reform during democratic transitions on
record was implemented by executive decree, remarking that "[t]his potential
is inherent in the very conception of market reforms."53
From the standpoint of democratic justice, the critical question is whether
the reformers really do "know what is good" and pursue it in fact. Much of
what is presented by economic reformers as uncontroversially good might in
fact be controversial, and many economic reforms that are described as public
goods do not meet the technical criteria that require both joint supply and
nonexcludability.54 Whether the sorts of privatization and stabilization poli-
cies that such political economists as Przeworski, Janos Kornai, Jeffrey
Sachs, and others advocate lead to the supply of public goods in this sense is
debatable. No doubt parts of what is provided are public goods, but other
aspects of these policies may amount to little more than mechanisms for
raiding public treasuries by strategically well-placed groups, generating little
or no benefit for anyone else. In such instances, the pursuit of private benefit
may be cloaked in the language of public goods, and opposition to them that
is really a reflection of zero-sum distributive conflict will masquerade as a
collective action problem. What are billed as solutions to it will actually be
partisan policies that help some sectors and hurt others. Democrats who
suspect this is the case with substantial parts of postcommunist privatizations
This content downloaded from 131.175.12.9 on Sat, 02 May 2020 03:57:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
606 POLITICAL THEORY / November 1996
are bound to find themselves ambivalent, at least, about the "bitter pil
strategies that depend on "initial brutality, on proceeding as quickly as
possible with the most radical measures," and implementing reforms either
by administrative fiat or ramming them through legislatures.55
In circumstances where one does not doubt that a public good is being
supplied, one's democratic moral intuitions are not troubled by decisive
action from above. For instance in the South African constitutional negotia-
tions that led up to the April 1994 elections, it gradually became clear that-
desirable as multiparty roundtable negotiations sounded-they were not
going to produce an agreement on a democratic constitution. Too many groups
had too many incentives to pursue private agendas at the expense of ensuring
that the public good was provided. Consequently, it became evident that, if
a democratic political order was to be put in place, it would have to be
hammered out as an elite pact and then imposed on the society. This is what
transpired in fact, and the reason that democrats the world over applauded as
opponents to the transition were so effectively either marginalized or co-opted
was that almost no one doubted that what the elites proposed to impose-a
democratic constitutional order-was in fact a public good.56
Distinguishing the provision of genuine public goods from spurious ones
is a difficult and controversial business. Often the two will be mixed, making
it even more difficult, as is almost certainly the case with most privatization
plans. Even in the case of the South African constitution it seems clear that
the elites who committed themselves to providing the public good in question
sprinkled in a few benefits for themselves, notably a system of electoral and
parliamentary rules that greatly weakens backbenchers vis-a-vis leaderships,
as well as bribes to particular interest groups to insulate them from the new
political order.57
From the standpoint of democratic justice, the extent to which policies
may legitimately be imposed from above varies with the degree to which
genuine public goods are being provided. As the preceding remarks indicate,
this will often be hotly disputed and ideologically charged, not least because
there will be those who have an interest in obscuring the matter. It may also
be genuinely unclear in certain circumstances. When either of these things is
the case, what we are witnessing is not a failure in the argument for
democratic justice. Rather, it is a failure in understanding of, or agreement
about, whether or not something constitutes a public good. This is not to
diminish the normative importance of the matter, it is only to say that it would
be to expect the wrong kind of thing from any political theory to ask of it that
it resolve contentious empirical questions of political economy. The argument
for democratic justice can be expected to counsel what to do when a certain
fact pattern obtains; it cannot be expected to tell us whether or not the fact
This content downloaded from 131.175.12.9 on Sat, 02 May 2020 03:57:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Shapiro / ELEMENTS OF DEMOCRATIC JUSTICE 607
pattern really does obtain. The general argument does, however, counsel us
to regard claims to be providing public goods with suspicion, and to subject
them to what lawyers think of as "strict scrutiny." American courts typically
subject legislative action to this most demanding level of constitutional
scrutiny when the proposed action interferes with a "fundamental" liberty,
usually a freedom protected by the Bill of Rights. Strict scrutiny requires a
showing that the governmental objective is unusually important-that a
"compelling" state interest is at stake-and that it cannot be accomplished in
a less intrusive way.58 By analogy we might say that the undemocratic
imposition of a public good is justified only when the good in question is
essential to the operation of a democratic order and cannot be attained in any
other way. Because those who claim to provide public goods may have
ulterior motives, and because private goods can often masquerade as public
goods, the strong presumption should always be against their imposition
from above.
A second class of exceptions to the general presumption against vanguard-
ism arises when illegitimate hierarchies have been maintained by the state.
For example, in the West the disadvantaged status of women in family life
was sustained.by the common law and other active policies of the state for
centuries. One dramatic legacy of this history is that as recently as the 1950s
throughout the United States a husband could not be prosecuted for raping
his wife. By the mid- 1990s spousal rape was a prosecutable felony during an
ongoing marriage in well over a third of American jurisdictions, the product
of a concerted feminist campaign in state legislatures and courts.59 It would
have been impossible for such changes to have come about without the state's
active involvement, since it is the policies of the state that were at the root of
the injustice in question. Likewise, it took the passage of the married women's
property acts (the first wave of which began in the 1840s) to destroy the
common law rule that had given the husband control, and sometimes title, to
the wife's property and possessions during marriage.'
In such circumstances it will be necessary, and justifiable from the
standpoint of democratic justice, for the state to be centrally involved in
dismantling the unjust system it has created. Women would have been
morally misguided as well as politically shortsighted had they not sought to
enlist public institutions in this struggle to refashion the terms of their
domestic association. Since the unjust hierarchies to which they had been
subjected were direct products of state policies and sustained by the legal
order, it was reasonable to require the state to play an active role in disman-
tling the injustices in question. Likewise, the effects of the Group Areas Act
in South Africa, which led to the forced removals of millions of blacks from
viable communities to desolate deserts, are properly responded to by remedial
This content downloaded from 131.175.12.9 on Sat, 02 May 2020 03:57:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
608 POLITICAL THEORY / November 1996
action from a democratic South African state.61 The general point here
the more antidemocratic practices have been underwritten by the sta
more powerful is the case for the involvement of state institutions in re
dying the unjust status quo.62
A third class of exceptions arises when domination within a domain is
a direct product of state action, but it is nonetheless sustained by for
external to that domain that can be removed only by state action. This i
Michael Walzer has described as "dominance," the transfer of power
domain of social life where it may be legitimate into another where it i
Walzer contends, for instance, that economic inequality is not objecti
as such, and that it may be justified in the sphere of production for its inc
and other efficiency effects. What is objectionable is that disparities in i
and wealth are all too easily translatable into disparities in the political
domain, the domestic domain, the educational domain, and other areas where
they have no evident rationale.63 This happens because the resources neces-
sary to exercise power tend to be fungible across domains, and Walzer sees
it as one of the appropriate tasks of a democratic state to limit this fungibility.
On this view, laws against buying and selling votes for money can be
defended, for example, even though such laws are inefficient in the econo-
mist's sense. Similarly, refusals by courts to enforce antenuptial agreements
that leave divorcing spouses destitute amount to a refusal by the state to allow
economic disparities that may be justifiable outside the domestic domain to
set the terms of life within it.
From the standpoint of democratic justice Walzer's intuition about this
class of cases is defensible, if for different reasons than those that he supplies.
Whereas for Walzer the reason for trying to prevent domination within a
sphere by those who control goods external to it is rooted in shared meanings
about which goods are appropriate in which domains, from the present
standpoint the justification is rooted in considerations drawn from the politi-
cal economy of power.64 I said earlier that the shape of decision rules should
follow the contours of power relations, not those of memberships. It follows
that when obstacles to democracy within a domain are externally sustained,
it is an appropriate use of state power that it be used to remove such obstacles.
To deny this would amount to abandoning democratic justice in particular
domains to those who have imperial control of fungible resources. In short-
pace Walzer-because causal effects rather than shared membership within
a domain are decisive in legitimating a right to democratic control, it follows
that state action that crosses the boundaries of domains can be justified when
this is necessary to achieve democratic justice within a domain.65
Action by the state to advance democratic reform can be justified, then,
but not as part of any missionary quest on democratic justice's behalf. There
This content downloaded from 131.175.12.9 on Sat, 02 May 2020 03:57:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Shapiro / ELEMENTS OF DEMOCRATIC JUSTICE 609
This content downloaded from 131.175.12.9 on Sat, 02 May 2020 03:57:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
610 POLITICAL THEORY/ November 1996
emerged from the democratic process unacceptable and insist that the parties
try anew to find an accommodation. Thus in contrast to what many have seen
as the altogether too timid approach taken by the U.S. Supreme Court in the
school desegregation cases of the 1950s and after, on Burt's view the Court
took the right stand. In Brown v. Board of Education the justices declared the
doctrine of "separate but equal" to be an unconstitutional violation of the
equal protection clause, but they did not describe schooling conditions that
would be acceptable.67 Rather, they turned the problem back to Southern state
legislatures, requiring them to fashion acceptable remedies themselves.68
These remedies came before the Court as a result of subsequent litigation,
were evaluated when they did, and were often found to be wanting.69 But the
Court avoided designing the remedy itself, and with it the charge that it was
usurping the legislative function.
Ginsburg, too, has made the case that when courts try to step beyond a
reactive role they undermine their legitimacy in a democracy. Although she
thinks that it is sometimes necessary for the court to step "ahead" of the
political process to achieve reforms that the Constitution requires, if it gets
too far ahead it can produce a backlash and provoke charges that it is
overreaching its appropriate place in a democratic constitutional order.70 She
and Burt both think that the sort of approach adopted by Justice Blackmun
in Roe v. Wade exemplifies this danger.7' In contrast to the Brown approach
in Roe the Court did a good deal more than strike down a Texas abortion
statute. The majority opinion laid out a detailed test to determine the condi-
tions under which any abortion statute could be expected to pass muster. In
effect, Justice Blackmun authored a federal abortion statute of his own. As
Ginsburg put it, the court "invited no dialogue with legislators. Instead, it
seemed entirely to remove the ball from the legislators' court" by wiping out
virtually every form of abortion regulation then in existence.72
On the Ginsburg-Burt view, the sweeping holding in Roe diminished the
Court's democratic legitimacy at the same time as it polarized opinion about
abortion and put paid to various schemes to liberalize abortion laws that were
under way in different states. Between 1967 and 1973 statutes were passed
in nineteen states liberalizing the permissible grounds for abortion. Many
feminists had been dissatisfied with the pace and extent of this reform. This
is why they mounted the campaign that resulted in Roe. Burt concedes that
in 1973 it was "not clear whether the recently enacted state laws signified the
beginning of a national trend toward abolishing all abortion restrictions or
even whether in the so-called liberalized states, the new enactments would
significantly increase access to abortion for anyone." Nonetheless, he points
out that "the abortion issue was openly, avidly, controverted in a substantial
number of public forums, and unlike the regimen extant as recently as 1967,
This content downloaded from 131.175.12.9 on Sat, 02 May 2020 03:57:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Shapiro / ELEMENTS OF DEMOCRATIC JUSTICE 611
it was no longer clear who was winning the battle."73 Following the Brown
model, the Court might have struck down the Texas abortion statute in Roe
and remanded the matter for further action at the state level, thereby setting
limits on what legislatures might do in the matter of regulating abortion
without involving the Court directly in designing that regulation. On the
Ginsburg-Burt view, this would have left space for democratic resolution of
the conflict, ensuring the survival of the right to abortion while at the same
time preserving the legitimacy of the Court's role in a democracy.74
Although the tensions that arise within democratic justice differ from
those that motivate Burt and Ginsburg, in three important respects their view
of the appropriate role for courts in a democratic order fits comfortably within
the general argument developed here. First, they articulate an appropriate
institutional response to the injunction that rather than impose democracy on
collective activities the goal should be to try to structure things so that people
will find ways to democratize things for themselves. By placing courts in a
nay-saying stance of ruling out practices as unacceptable when they violate
the strictures of democratic justice, courts can force legislatures and the
conflicting parties they represent to seek creative solutions to their conflicts
that can pass constitutional muster. Second, the Ginsburg-Burt view is
attractive because it is reactive but directed; it exemplifies the creative
pragmatism that motivates democratic justice. It involves accepting that there
is an important-if circumscribed role for courts in a democracy, yet it does
not make the unmanageable administrative demands on courts that accom-
pany more proactive views of adjudication. On this view a court might
reasonably hold that a given policy should be rejected without stating (indeed,
perhaps without having decided) what policy would pass muster. "This is
unacceptable for reasons a, b, c . . . ; find a better way" is seen as an
appropriate stance for a constitutional court. Finally, by recognizing the
relatively greater legitimacy of legislatures and treating courts as institutional
mechanisms for coping with legislative failure, the Ginsburg-Burt view takes
account of the fact that no decision-making mechanism is flawless. Yet it does
so in a way that is rooted in the idea that democratic procedures should be
made to operate as well as possible, and, when they fail, remedies should be
no more intrusive on the democratic process than is necessary to repair them.
Some will object to this as too minimal a role for reviewing courts, but
democrats have to concern themselves not only with courts that aspire to
advance the cause of democratic justice, as they might reasonably be thought
to have done in Brown and Roe, but also with courts that do not, as was the
case in Dred Scott, the Civil Rights Cases, and Lochner v. New York.7s
Insulated from any further review and lacing, at least in the American context,
in democratic accountability, courts can put decisions of this kind in place
This content downloaded from 131.175.12.9 on Sat, 02 May 2020 03:57:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
612 POLITICAL THEORY / November 1996
that may not be reversed for decades or even generations. Although it may
thus be wise from the standpoint of democratic justice to embrace an activist
role for a constitutional court, it is equally wise to limit courts to a circum-
scribed and negationist activism.
CONCLUDING REMARKS
My aim in this essay has been to render plausible the case for a demo
conception of social justice. This I have sought to do by building on the
popular view, in which considerations of democracy and justice are inti-
mately linked, rather than conventional academic views of them as funda-
mentally distinct and mutually antagonistic. The account that I offer rests on
the twin commitments to government and opposition in democratic theory,
suggesting that there should always be opportunities for those affected by the
operation of a collective practice both to participate in its governance and to
oppose its results when they are so inclined. These two injunctions should
reasonably be expected to have different implications in different cultures
and, within the same culture, to evolve over time and play themselves out
differently in different domains. They are best thought of as conditioning
constraints, designed to democratize social relations as they are reproduced,
rather than as blueprints for social justice.
This view contains internal tensions, to be sure, but I have tried to show
that these come with the territory in reflecting about the justness of social
arrangements, and to indicate something about how these tensions might best
be coped with consistent with the spirit of the general argument. Beyond this,
I have sought to indicate the main outlines of a view of the state that follows
from my view, and to develop some of its implications for the provision of
public goods and for the state's appropriate role in advancing democratic
justice more generally. I have sketched the basic principles that should guide
state action, as well as the fitting nature and place for judicial review in the
argument for democratic justice. No doubt these arguments raise as many
questions as they settle, but I hope, nonetheless, that I have characterized
the central argument and its motivation sufficiently fully to cast it in an
attractive light.
In 1918 Dewey remarked that any philosophy animated by the striving to
achieve democracy "will construe liberty as meaning a universe in which
there is real uncertainty and contingency, a world which is not all in, and
never will be, a world which in some respects is incomplete and in the making,
and which in these respects may be made this way or that according as men
This content downloaded from 131.175.12.9 on Sat, 02 May 2020 03:57:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Shapiro ! ELEMENTS OF DEMOCRATIC JUSTICE 613
judge, prize, love and labor. To such a philosophy any notion of a perfec
complete reality, finished, existing always the same without regard to t
vicissitudes of time, will be abhorrent."76 Democratic justice is conceive
in a similar contingent and pragmatic spirit. Just as there are no blueprin
there are no final destinations. Social practices evolve, as do technologies of
government and opposition, often presenting fresh injustices and novel
possibilities for dealing with them. The challenge is to confront the injustices
and take advantage of the possibilities in a principled and satisfying way.
Democratic justice is intended to help in that endeavor.
NOTES
1. John Dewey, The Public and Its Problems (New York: Henry Holt, 1927), 84-5.
2. See, for example, Guiseppe Di Palma, To Craft Democracies: An Essay on Democra
Transitions (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1990), 23, for defense of the view that th
democratic ideal should be disengaged "from the idea of social progress" if it is to endure, a
Samuel P. Huntington, The Third Wave: Democratization in the Late Twentieth Century (N
man: University of Oklahoma Press, 1991), 165-9, for the argument that political leaders w
sell out on their constituents' demands for social justice are more likely to succeed in conso
dating democratic institutions than those who do not.
3. See my "Three Ways to Be a Democrat," Political Theory 22 (February 1994): 124-
4. I should say at the outset that by using the term foundational I do not mean to take up a
position here in debates about the nature of knowledge and existence. In describing a comm
ment to democracy as foundational, I mean only to suggest that no prior or more basic polit
commitment rightly commands our common allegiance.
5. John Rawls, "Faimess to Goodness," Philosophical Review 82 (1973): 228, and "Justic
as Fairness: Political not Metaphysical," Philosophy and PublicAffairs 14, no. 3 (1985): 223-
esp. 223-6.
6. See Cass Sunstein, "On Legal Theory and Legal Practice," in Nomos XXXVII: Theory
and Practice, ed. Ian Shapiro and Judith Wagner DeCew (New York: New York University Press,
1995), 267-87.
7. Barrington Moore, Jr., Liberal Prospects under Soviet Socialism: A Comparative
Historical Perspective (New York: The Averell Harriman Institute, 1989), 25.
8. Nelson Mandela, "Address to Court before Sentencing," in Ideologies of Liberation in
BlackAfrica 1856-1970, ed. J. Ayo Langley (London: Rex Collins, 1979), 665. On the Chartists,
see Dorothy Thompson, The Chartists (London: Temple Smith, 1984). Generally see Elie
Halevy, The Growth of Philosophic Radicalism (New York: Kelley, 1972).
9. Langley, Ideologies of Liberation, 664.
10. Nor do all liberals agree with one another, any more than all democrats do, over which
of these, combinations of these, or combinations of these and other, reasons they invoke for
adhering to antivanguardist conceptions of the good.
11. For one conventional statement of this view, see William Riker, Liberalism against
Populism (Prospect Heights, IL: Waveland, 1982). It might be objected that the depiction of
liberalism in the text is something of a caricature in that it deals with academic rather than popular
This content downloaded from 131.175.12.9 on Sat, 02 May 2020 03:57:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
614 POLITICAL THEORY / November 1996
This content downloaded from 131.175.12.9 on Sat, 02 May 2020 03:57:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Shapiro / ELEMENTS OF DEMOCRATIC JUSTICE 615
Tom Hamburger and Ted Marmor, "Dead on Arrival: Why Washington's Power Elites
Consider Single Payer Health Reform," The Washington Monthly (September 1993): 27
24. Liberals take the basic unit of the nation state for granted, treating it as a kind of
voluntary association writ large, as has often been pointed out in criticism of Rawls. S
Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971), 371-82,
"The Law of Peoples," Critical Inquiry 20 (Autumn 1993): 36-68. No doubt this is often a
consequence of the liberal proclivity for thinking in contractualist terms. For an illustration of
the communitarian view of membership as the basic trumping good, see Walzer, Spheres of
Justice, 29, 31-63.
25. My contention that the causally based view is more defensible than the going alternatives
is compatible with a number of recent arguments whose purpose is to decenter membership-
based sovereignty as the decisive determinant of participation, and to replace it with systems of
overlapping jurisdiction in which different groups of persons are seen as sovereign over different
classes of decisions. See Thomas Pogge, "Cosmopolitanism and Sovereignty," Ethics 103
(October 1992): 48-75; Alexander Wendt, "Collective Identity-Formation and the International
State," American Political Science Review 88, no. 2 (June 1994): 384-96; and William Antholis,
"Liberal Democratic Theory and the Transformation of Sovereignty" (Ph.D. diss., Yale Univer-
sity, 1993).
26. Barrington Moore, Jr., Liberal Prospects, 8. See also Archibald S. Foord, His Majesty's
Opposition 1714-1830 (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1964).
27. Even before the advent of the modern literature on public choice, Schumpeter had
exposed the logical flaws in the Rousseauist idea of a general will, concluding that "though a
common will or public opinion of some sort may still be said to emerge from the infinitely
complex jumble of individual and group-wise situation, volitions, influences, actions and
reactions of the 'democratic process,' the result lacks not only rational unity but also rational
sanction." Joseph Schumpeter, Capitalism, Socialism and Democracy (New York: Harper and
Row, 1942), 253.
28. Huntington regards at least two turnovers of power following elections as necessary for
a country's being democratic. See The Third Wave, 6-7. See also Robert Dahl, Polyarchy:
Participation and Opposition (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1971).
29. Stone focused his attention on "statutes directed at particular religious ... or racial
minorities" and circumstances that tend "seriously to curtail the operation of those political
processes ordinarily to be relied upon to protect minorities," United States v. Carolene Products
Co., 304 U.S. 144 (1938), 152 n. 4.
30. John Hart Ely, Democracy and Distrust (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press,
1980). Ely described his argument as purely procedural, designed to repair defects of democratic
process. But as critics have pointed out and the discussion below makes clear, it is obviously a
substantive argument. See R. Smith, Liberalism and American Constitutional Law (Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press, 1985), 89-91, 170-4.
31. Charles Beitz, "Equal Opportunity in Political Representation," in Equal Opportunity,
ed. Norman E. Bowie (Boulder, CO: Westview, 1988), 155-74. It should not be thought that
Carolene Products logic is the exclusive preserve of the political left. For instance, Riker and
Weingast employ it to criticize taxation of property: "What protection is there against members
of today's majority from providing private, redistributive benefits to themselves under the guise
of public purposes and at the expense of some minority of owners and the efficiency of
production? Why is the abridgement of a minority's economic rights less troubling than an
abridgement of the same minority's political rights?" William H. Riker and Barry R. Weingast,
"Constitutional Regulation of Legislative Choice: The Political Consequences of Judicial
This content downloaded from 131.175.12.9 on Sat, 02 May 2020 03:57:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
616 POLITICAL THEORY / November 1996
This content downloaded from 131.175.12.9 on Sat, 02 May 2020 03:57:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Shapiro / ELEMENTS OF DEMOCRATIC JUSTICE 617
This content downloaded from 131.175.12.9 on Sat, 02 May 2020 03:57:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
618 POLITICAL THEORY / November 1996
57. As far as political elites sprinkling in benefits for themselves is concerned, the 1993
constitution requires that any member of parliament who ceases to be a member of his or her
political party will also cease to be a member of parliament, being replaced by someone else
from the party's parliamentary list. As for bribes, all civil service jobs and salaries were
guaranteed for at least five years following the transition, and in the last weeks before the election
President de Klerk transferred some three million acres of land to Zulu king Goodwill Zwelitini
in order to prevent their falling under the control of the new national government following the
April 1994 elections. New York Times, May 24, 1994, A6. For further discussion, see Courtney
Jung and Ian Shapiro, "South Africa's Negotiated Transition: Democracy, Opposition, and the
New Constitutional Order," Politics & Society 23, no. 3 (September 1995): 269-308.
58. See Laurence H. Tribe, American Constitutional Law, 2d ed. (New York: Foundation,
1988), 251-75.
59. On the changing law of marital rape in the United States, see Michael Freeman, "If You
Can't Rape Your Wife, Who[m] Can You Rape? The Marital Rape Exception Re-examined,"
Family Law Quarterly 15, no. 1 (Spring 1981): 1-29; Deborah Rhode, Justice and Gender
(Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1989), 249-51; Rene I. Augustine, "Marriage: The
Safe Haven for Rapists," Journal of Family Law 29, no. 3 (1990-1): 559-90; Sandra Ryder and
Sheryl Kuzmenka, "Legal Rape: The Marital Exception," John Marshall Law Review 24 (1992):
393-421. On the English evolution of the exception, see P. M. Bromley and N. V. Lowe, Family
Law, 7th ed. (Salem, NH: Butterworths, 1987), 109-12.
60. See H. H. Clark, The Law of Domestic Relations in the United States, 2d ed. (Saint Paul,
MN: West, 1988), 589.
61. For an account of the extent and effects of these policies, see Helen Suzman, In No
Uncertain Terms (New York: Knopf, 1993), 65-212.
62. This says nothing about which state institutions are most appropriate for the purpose,
whether courts, legislatures or executive agencies. See below.
63. Walzer, Spheres of Justice, 3-30.
64. I have noted elsewhere that the appeal to shared meanings fails because these are
invariably in contention. "Three Ways to Be a Democrat," 130-5.
65. It should be evident from my earlier discussion of public goods and state culpability that
I also think Walzer is mistaken in thinking that preventing dominance is the only legitimate basis
for the imposition of solutions by the state.
66. Robert A. Burt, The Constitution in Conflict (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press,
1992), 29.
67. Brown v. Board of Education 1, 347 U.S. 483 (1954).
68. Brown v. Board of Education II, 349 U.S. 294 (1955).
69. Burt, Constitution in Conflict, 271-3 10.
70. Ruth Bader Ginsburg, "Speaking in a Judicial Voice" (Madison Lecture, New York
University Law School, March 9, 1993, mimeo), 30-8. See also Nomination of Ruth Bader
Ginsburg to Be an Associate Justice of the United States Supreme Court: Report Together with
Additional Views, Exec. Report 103-6-93-1 United States Senate.
71. Roe v. Wade, 410 U.S. 113 (1973).
72. Ginsburg, "Speaking in a Judicial Voice," 32.
73. Burt, Constitution in Conflict, 348.
74. Ibid., 349-52. The Ginsburg-Burt approach was finally adopted by the Supreme Court
in Planned Parenthood of Pennsylvania v. Casey, 112 S. Ct. 2791 (1992). By affinming the
existence of a woman's fundamental constitutional right to an abortion, recognizing the legiti-
macy of the state's interest in potential life, and insisting that states may notpursue the vindication
of that interest in a manner that is unduly burdensome to women, the Court set some basic
This content downloaded from 131.175.12.9 on Sat, 02 May 2020 03:57:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Shapiro / ELEMENTS OF DEMOCRATIC JUSTICE 619
parameters within which legislatures must now fashion regulations that govern aborti
Casey dissenters are right to point out that there will be a degree of unpredictability and c
as different regulatory regimes are enacted in different states and tested through the cou
S. Ct. 2791, at 2866 (1992). On views of adjudication thatencourage efficiency and clarit
all else this will appear to be a reprehensible invitation to further litigation. On the Ginsb
view, however, that Casey invites litigation may be a cost worth paying. It places the b
coming up with modes of regulating abortion that are not unduly burdensome on democra
elected legislatures, and forces them to do this in the knowledge that the statutes they en
be tested through the courts and thrown out if they are found wanting. These issues are t
further in my introduction to Abortion: The Supreme Court Decisions (Indianapolis, IN: Ha
1995), 1-23.
75. Dred Scott v. Sandford, 60 U.S. 393 (1856); In re Civil Rights Cases, 109 U.S. 3 (1883);
and Lochner v. New York, 198 U.S. 45 (1905).
76. From an address to the Philosophical Union of the University of California in November
1918, reprinted in Dewey, The Political Writings, 44.
Ian Shapiro is professor of political science at Yale. His new book, Democracy's Place,
will be published by Cornell University Press this fall.
This content downloaded from 131.175.12.9 on Sat, 02 May 2020 03:57:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms