Do Cases Make Bad Law
Do Cases Make Bad Law
Do Cases Make Bad Law
FrederickSchauert
"It is the merit of the common law," Oliver Wendell Holmes ob-
served, "that it decides the case first and determines the principle af-
terwards."' That the decision of a particular case holds pride of place
in common law methodology is largely uncontroversial. And indeed so
too is the view that this feature of the common law is properly de-
scribed as a "merit." Treating the resolution of concrete disputes as the
preferred context in which to make law-and making law is what
Holmes meant in referring to "determin[ing] the principle" - is the
hallmark of the common law approach.2 It is true that the common
law's methods and theory were developed at a time when most com-
mon law judges understood themselves to be discovering the law
rather than making it, but Holmes knew better. He fully appreciated
that common law judges made law in the process of deciding cases,
and nowadays few think otherwise. Common law method is not simply
the discovery of immanent law, but rather an approach in which the
decision of live disputes in concrete contexts guides the lawmaking
function. Moreover, so it is said, making law in the context of deciding
particular cases produces lawmaking superior to methods that ignore
the importance of real litigants exemplifying the issues the law must
resolve. Indeed, this belief in the virtue of a crystallized dispute be-
t Frank Stanton Professor of the First Amendment, John F. Kennedy School of Govern-
ment, Harvard University, and Daniel R. Fischel and Sylvia M. Neil Distinguished Visiting Pro-
fessor of Law (Fall 2005), The University of Chicago Law School. Earlier versions of this Article
were presented as a Faculty Enrichment Lecture at the Rogers College of Law of the University
of Arizona, as a Faculty Colloquium at the Chicago-Kent College of Law, and at the Harvard
Law School Seminar on Law and Economics. I am grateful for the comments of Yael Aridor Bar-
Ilan, Elizabeth Chorvat, Richard Fallon, Louis Kaplow, Richard Posner, Steven Shavell, Matthew
Stephenson, David Strauss, Peter Strauss, Mark Tushnet, Adrian Vermeule, Lloyd Weinreb, Mi-
chael Wells, Kenneth Winston, and Ernest Young; for valuable research suggestions from Iris
Bohnet, Alan Ferrell, Jack Goldsmith, and Christine Jolls; and for the generous research support
of The University of Chicago Law School and the Joan Shorenstein Center on the Press, Politics
and Public Policy.
1 Oliver Wendell Holmes, Codes and the Arrangement of the Law, 5 Am L Rev 1 (1870),
reprinted in Sheldon M. Novick, ed, 1 The Collected Works ofJustice Holmes 212 (Chicago 1995).
See also Louis Menand, The Metaphysical Club 338 (Farrar, Straus, and Giroux 2001).
2 "In short, as Professor Eisenberg has reminded us in his book on the common law, courts
are legitimately in two businesses: deciding individual disputes and enriching our body of legal
norms." Todd D. Rakoff, The Implied Terms of Contracts:Of "Default Rule" and "Situation-Sense,"
in Jack Beatson and Daniel Friedmann, eds, Good Faith and Fault in Contract Law 191, 195 (Clar-
endon 1995), citing Melvin Aron Eisenberg, The Nature of the Common Law 4-7 (Harvard 1988).
The University of Chicago Law Review [73:883
6 See, for example, John Austin, 2 Lectures on Jurisprudence 634 (Murray 5th ed 1885)
(Robert Campbell, ed) (noting "the childish fiction employed by our judges, that judiciary or
common law is not made by them, but is a miraculous something made by nobody, existing, I
suppose, from eternity, and merely declared from time to time by the judges"). See also Allen v
Jackson, 1 Ch D 399, 405 (C A 1875) (Mellish) (observing that "the whole of the rules of equity,
and nine tenths of the rules of common law, have in fact been made by the Judges"); John Chip-
man Gray, The Nature and Sources of the Law 285 (Macmillan 2d ed 1921) (referring to law
being "made by the judges").
7 "The orthodox Blackstonian view, however, is that judges do not make law, but only
declare what has always been law." R.W.M. Dias, Jurisprudence151 (Butterworths 5th ed 1985).
See also Willis v Baddeley, 2 QB 324,326 (C A 1892) (Esher) ("There is, in fact, no such thing as
judge-made law, for the judges do not make the law, though they frequently have to apply exist-
ing law to circumstances as to which it has not previously been authoritatively laid down that
such law is applicable."); In re Hallett's Estate, 13 Ch D 696, 710 (C A 1879) (Jessel) (announcing
that "the rules of Courts of Equity are not, like the rules of the Common Law, supposed to have
been established from time immemorial").
8 Anyone who thinks the statement in the text to be an inaccurate caricature would be
well advised to examine Eugene Wambaugh, The Study of Cases §§ 74-79 at 74-80 (Little, Brown
2d ed 1894) (admitting competing views of the law as either discovered or judge-made but advo-
cating a universal "legal reasoning [that] is the same everywhere"). To the same effect is John M.
Zane, German Legal Philosophy, 16 Mich L Rev 287, 338 (1918) ("The man who claims that
under [the United States'] system the courts make law is asserting that the courts habitually act
unconstitutionally.").
The University of Chicago Law Review [73:883
9 See Gerald J. Postema, Classical Common Law Jurisprudence (Part 1), 2 Oxford U
Commw L J 155, 166 (2002) ("Classical common law judges did not regard themselves as 'mak-
ing' law ...any more than rules of English grammar are [ ]made."); J.H. Baker, The Law's Two
Bodies: Some Evidential Problems in English Legal History 3 (Oxford 2001) (noting that "a
problem is presented by the fact that there is often a disparity between what courts do ... and
what they say they are doing"); Morton J. Horwitz, The Transformationof American Law 1780-
1960 16-17 (Oxford 1992) (describing "[d]eduction from general principles" as a nineteenth-
century tool to allow judges to "distinguish the legal from the political").
10 See Jeremy Bentham, Of Laws in General166-68, 184-95 (Athlone 1970) (H.L.A. Hart,
ed); Jeremy Bentham, An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation 8 (Athlone
1970) (E.H. Bums and H.L.A. Hart, eds). See also Gerald J. Postema, Bentham and the Common
Law Tradition 197 (Clarendon 1986) (noting Bentham's belief that precedent ought not be
viewed as binding); Nancy L. Rosenblum, Bentham's Theory of the Modern State 94-98 (Harvard
1978); James Steintrager, Bentham 20, 20-43 (Cornell 1977) ("Bentham's diagnosis of the sick-
ness of the English body politic centred on his analysis of the English common law.").
11 This is the best understanding of Holmes's claim that "[t]he life of the law has not been
logic: it has been experience." Oliver Wendell Holmes, The Common Law 5 (Belknap 1967)
(Mark DeWolfe Howe, ed). See also William Twining, Karl Llewellyn and the Realist Movement
16 (Weidenfeld 1973) ("[Holmes] recognized that judges can and do make law.").
12 Thus, the word "formalism," when not serving simply as a catchall term of jurispruden-
tial abuse, may denote a belief, indeed a highly plausible one, in the possibility and/or desirability
of rule-based constraint. Alternatively, "formalism" may be the vice of denying the extent of
judicial choice or discretion when that choice or discretion actually exists. See Frederick Schauer,
Formalism, 97 Yale L J 509,509-11 (1988). It is this latter version of formalism, formalism as the
denial of choice, that I discuss in the text.
13 Benjamin Cardozo wrote that:
The theory of the older writers was that judges did not legislate at all. A pre-existing rule
was there, imbedded, if concealed, in the body of the customary law. All that the judges did,
2006] Do Cases Make Bad Law?
was to throw off the wrappings, and expose the statute to our view. Since the days of Ben-
tham and Austin, no one, it is believed, has accepted this theory without deduction or re-
serve, though even in modern decisions we find traces of its lingering influence.
Benjamin N. Cardozo, The Nature of the JudicialProcess 124-25 (Yale 1921).
14 217 NY 382, 111 NE 1050,1054-55 (1916) (Cardozo). For discussion and elaboration, see
Eisenberg, The Nature of the Common Law at 58-61,132-35 (cited in note 2).
15 1932 App Cas 562,566,622-23 (HL 1932). For an analysis of Donoghue v Stevenson and
other cases as decisions choosing among alternative legally justifiable outcomes, and thus making
law, see Neil MacCormick, Legal Reasoning and Legal Theory 69-70,234-35,246-58 (Clarendon
1978) ("[T]here may be more than one set of normative generalizations which can be advanced
in rationalization of the rules which 'belong' to the [legal] system."). As is well known, the most
prominent contemporary defender of the view that judges find law and do not make it is Ronald
Dworkin, especially in Ronald Dworkin, Law's Empire 410-12 (Belknap 1986), and Ronald
Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously xi (Harvard 1977). But although Dworkin wishes to under-
stand as "finding" or "interpreting" what others would call "making," those differences have little
pertinence to the themes of this Article. Even if we understand Dworkin to be correct and his
opponents mistaken, my central point about the distorting dominance of the particular case
before the judge would be no less applicable.
16 15 USC § 1 (2000).
17 See, for example, United States v Socony-Vacuum Oil Co, 310 US 150,228 (1940).
18 See, for example, United Shoe Machinery Corp v United States, 258 US 451,457 (1922).
19 US Const Art I, § 8.
20 US Const Amend I.
21 Id.
22 US Const Amend V; US Const Amend XIV, § 1.
23 US Const Amend XIV, § 1.
24 US Const Amend IV.
The University of Chicago Law Review [73:883
decision that the reason is a reason for,35 any reason (or any statement
of a reason) that has precedential force in future cases operates in
largely rule-like fashion. Once a court announces a reason for its deci-
sion, and once that stated reason is something that future or lower
courts are expected to take seriously as a reason,6 then the troubling
question still arises as to whether the general statement that is the
reason is better or worse by virtue of it having been initially an-
nounced in the context of a concrete dispute that a court is expected
to resolve.
subsequent litigation, see Edward A. Hartnett, A Matter of Judgment, Not a Matter of Opinion,
74 NYU L Rev 123, 126 (1999)-is stunningly at odds with the realities of actual legal practice.
For the three-month period from October 1, 2004, through December 31, 2004, for example, 222
briefs were filed in the Supreme Court of the United States, and every one of those briefs quoted
from a previous Supreme Court decision (Lexis Supreme Court Briefs database, search con-
ducted on Feb 9, 2005). This would be an odd practice indeed unless the writers of those briefs
had reason to believe that what the Court had said in previous cases might make a decisional
difference in subsequent ones. Consequently, one traditional understanding of common law
decisionmaking, in which opinions are seen as highly transient and highly defeasible, appears
these days to be in substantial decline. The less that particular decisions exert force on the future,
the less my argument tells against common law method. But the more that particular decisions
genuinely constrain the future-and that is the whole point of precedent-the more the phe-
nomenon I address here is genuinely problematic.
37 The static model is artificial if we are considering the essentially continuous nature of
the common law itself But the static model begins to resemble reality whenever we consider the
numerous contexts-rulemaking in families, private associations, and often in administrative
agencies, for example-in which, realistically, a single discrete event or decision prompts the
process of rule creation.
38 This account of rule-based decisionmaking is developed at length in Schauer, Playing By
the Rules at 17-37 (cited in note 32).
39 I ignore the interesting phenomenon of person-specific "special" legislation. Special
laws, typically granting some privilege or exemption to (or prohibition on) an identified individ-
ual or entity, and commonly prohibited by state constitutions although not by the Constitution of
20061 Do Cases Make Bad Law?
ciding presumptively how not one but a class of future events or con-
troversies ought to be determined or regulated.
Our question is then one of comparing the lawmaker who sets
forth a rule for a multiplicity of future particulars in the context of
deciding one concrete dispute right now with the lawmaker who also
makes a rule for a multiplicity of future particulars, but who does so in
the abstract, divorced from the obligation to resolve a dispute be-
tween real parties. Plainly the case-based rulemaker, paradigmatically
the common law judge, will perceive her task in terms of determining
both how this case and also other cases of this kind ought to be de-
cided, while the non-case-based rulemaker will also have to decide
how cases of some kind-some set of future cases-ought to be de-
cided, but unencumbered (or unguided) by the necessity of deciding
one of those cases right now. Put differently, the common law judge
has before her a concrete token of the type of case for which she is
making a rule, while other rulemakers make their rules without having
before them in the same immediate way a particular token of the
case-type that the rule will encompass. Our task, therefore, is to com-
pare these two different approaches to and methods of lawmaking.
The contrast between the two types of lawmaking is often pre-
sented as a contrast between common law and statute law, between
common law and civil law," or between common law and codifica-
tion. 2 But however we characterize the difference, I mean to pose a
the United States, are not general and are not rules. See Norman J. Singer, 2 Statutes and Statu-
tory Construction § 40.01 (Clark Boardman Callaghan 5th ed 1993) (noting that the Alabama
Constitution is representative in prohibiting legislation "[e]xempting any individual, private
corporation, or association from the operation of any general law").
40 See, for example, Richard A. Posner, The Problems of Jurisprudence 247-61 (Harvard
1990) (devoting a chapter to contrasting common law versus statute law). But see Paul H. Rubin,
Common Law and Statute Law, 11 J Legal Stud 205,222 (1982) (arguing that the "sharp distinc-
tion[] between statute and common law.., is often overdrawn").
41 See, for example, Thomas Lundmark, Book Review, 46 Am J Comp L 211,214-15 (1998)
("One of the classic differences between civil-law and common-law jurisdictions is that the for-
mer ...do not recognize judicial precedent as an independent source of law."), reviewing D. Neil
MacCormick and Robert S. Summers, eds, Interpretive Precedents:A Comparative Study (Dart-
mouth 1997). But see Katharina Pistor and Chenggang Xu,Incomplete Law, 35 NYU J Intl L &
Polit 931, 946-47 (2003) (noting that although many believe civil law judges interpret law and
common law judges make law, "[tihe line between lawmaking and law interpretation [ is often
difficult to draw").
42 See, for example, Robert W. Gordon, Book Review, 36 Vand L Rev 431, 431 (1983)
("[M]odern historians have turned the debates over codification into a 'movement' ... resisted
by a countermovement to preserve the common law."), reviewing Charles M. Cook, The Ameri-
can Codification Movement: A Study of Antebellum Legal Reform (Greenwood 1981); Samuel
Stoljar, Codification and the Common Law in S.J. Stoljar, ed, Problems of Codification 1, 1 (Aus-
tralian Natl U 1977) (describing a longstanding split between "common law traditionalists and
aficionados of [codification]"). See also Charles M. Cook, The American CodificationMovement:
A Study of Antebellum Legal Reform ix-x (Greenwood 1981) (arguing that nineteenth-century
The University of Chicago Law Review [73:883
debates over common law and codification resulted in compromises that shaped a distinctive,
hybridized American legal system).
43 It is worth emphasizing that I am concerned here largely with the soundness (or lack
thereof) of a particular argument for case-based rulemaking. There are other arguments for it,
and there are arguments against it other than the one I offer here. Thus, my claim, even if sound,
cannot be considered a conclusive or all-things-considered argument against case-based rule-
making. Still, if I am right, one of the most prominent arguments for the case-based approach will
be significantly weakened, and the overall argument for that approach will be weakened pro tanto.
44 "[L]itigants, after all, are the ones who actually experience the effects of legal rules."
Steven Shavell, The Appeals Process as a Means of Error Correction,24 J Legal Stud 379, 417
(1995) (noting that "appeals courts sometimes can learn about opportunities for lawmaking only
from disappointed litigants").
45 The claim is frequently part of a larger appeal for context and on the importance of
seeing particular litigants as a way to understand the context. See, for example, Wendy Anton
Fitzgerald, Maturity, Difference, and Mystery: Children's Perspectives and the Law, 36 Ariz L Rev
11, 107 n 577 (1994) (arguing that courts that focus on "the concrete context of the litigants" do
not "launch forth on a sea of indeterminacy and lawlessness"); Martha Minow, The Supreme
Court 1986 Term: Foreword: Justice Engendered, 101 Harv L Rev 10, 89 (1987) (arguing that
courts should avoid "insulating themselves in abstractions").
46 See note 1 and accompanying text.
47 See Eisenberg, The Nature of the Common Law at 12 (cited in note 2) (arguing that "the
particular case" is one of "two basic arenas" in "which the courts are obliged to be responsive");
Guido Calabresi, A Common Law for the Age of Statutes 165 (Harvard 1982) ("[Courts'] main
job would still be to give us continuity and change by applying the great vague principle of treat-
ing like cases alike."); Edward H. Levi, An Introduction to Legal Reasoning 3 (Chicago 1948)
(noting that "it cannot be said that the legal process is the application of known rules to diverse
facts... [Riules are discovered in the process of determining similarity"). See also Cass R. Sun-
stein, One Case at a Time: JudicialMinimalism on the Supreme Court ix (Harvard 1999) (advo-
cating "jiudicial minimalism," in which a "court settles the case before it, but it leaves many
things undecided").
20061 Do Cases Make Bad Law?
48 See, for example, Flast v Cohen, 392 US 83, 100 (1968) (reviewing precedent standing for
the idea that federal courts do not have to review cases that fail to present a concrete contro-
versy). As the Supreme Court put it in Baker v Carr, 369 US 186 (1962), concreteness "sharpens
the presentation of issues upon which the court so largely depends for illumination of difficult
constitutional questions." Id at 204. And in Valley Forge Christian Coil v Americans United for
Separation of Church and State, Inc, 454 US 464 (1982), the Court observed that "a concrete
factual context" is likely to produce "a realistic appreciation of the consequences of judicial
action." Id at 472. See also William A. Fletcher, The Structure of Standing, 98 Yale L J 221, 222
(1988) (noting that one common rationale for standing is that it "ensur[es] that a concrete case
informs the court of the consequences of its decisions"). Compare Susan Bandes, The Idea of a
Case, 42 Stan L Rev 227, 318-19 (1990) (arguing that the Supreme Court's standing jurispru-
dence "uses contorted logic and tortured language to fit a public rights problem into the private
rights mold").
49 I want to make clear that my challenge is to the very requirement of a concrete contro-
versy. and not to the interesting question of whether the standing requirement fosters concrete-
ness. As to the latter, see the important argument in David M. Driesen, Standing for Nothing: The
Paradox of Demanding Concrete Context for Formalist Adjudication, 89 Cornell L Rev 808, 811
(2004) (noting that courts do not have to adjudicate based on a case's specific facts, though
standing requires those facts to exist).
The University of Chicago Law Review [73:883
trying to get a sense - and it is rarely much more than this - of what
the array of future acts, events, disputes, and decisionmaking occasions
will look like.
The problem, however, is that in attempting to gauge the distribu-
tion of future events that will be encompassed by a rule, there is a sub-
stantial risk that the common law rulemaker will be unduly influenced
by the particular case before her. More specifically, the rulemaker,
seeing a concrete case before her, is likely to believe that this case is
representative of the larger array. If that is so then there is no prob-
lem. But if the immediate case is not representative, it may still be mis-
takenly thought to be representative, a mistake generated precisely by
the fact that this case is before the decisionmaker while other cases
within the class are not.
Thinking rationally, we understand that the case that happens to
be before a court or other case-based rulemaker is not exactly the
same in all respects, and not even in all relevant respects, as others
that might be members of the same larger and generally described
class. And rationally we can understand as well that some of the rele-
vant differences between this case and other members of its class are
such that the right decision for this case might not be the right deci-
sion for some, many, or even almost all of the other members of the
class. A judge acting rationally, therefore, would assess as systemati-
cally and as objectively as she could the extent to which the case be-
fore her was representative of the larger class of which it is a member.
The rational judge creating a rule would create a rule based on an as-
sessment of the nature and preferred resolution of the full set of ac-
tual acts and events encompassed by that rule, and would conse-
quently create the rule producing the best aggregate outcomes for the
entire class. The process would thus necessarily involve determining
the extent to which the larger class did or did not resemble the par-
ticular class member whose immediate presence before the decision-
maker prompted making the rule.
Unfortunately, however, decisionmakers often act with less than per-
fect rationality in making just this kind of assessment. They are mesmer-
ized by the case before them, and consequently often believe that the
most proximate member of a class is representative of the class. The
problem, however, is that decisionmakers make this (mis-)assessment not
on the basis of a rational survey of the class, and not on the basis of sys-
tematic empirical examination, but instead largely on the basis of the
usually irrelevant factors of proximity or ease of recall. This phenomenon
of being overinfluenced by proximate examples is commonly called, in
2006] Do Cases Make Bad Law?
the heuristics and biases literature, the "availability heuristic."'" Less often
it goes by the names "salience heuristic" or "vividness heuristic,"" but the
basic idea is the same: when decisionmakers are in the thrall of a highly
salient event, that event will so dominate their thinking that they will
make aggregate decisions that are overdependent on the particular event
and that overestimate the representativeness of that event within some
larger array of events." So if when buying insurance I am making a prob-
abilistic decision about the likelihood of, say, a hurricane over the next
ten years, I will make a different decision had there been a hurricane last
week than I would otherwise have made. Although the presence of a hur-
ricane last week ought not rationally to make a difference in predicting
the probability of a hurricane over the next ten years,53 in practice the
50 The original insight is in Amos Tversky and Daniel Kahneman, Judgment under Uncer-
tainty: Heuristics and Biases, 185 Science 1124, 1127 (1974) ("[P]eople assess the frequency of a
class or the probability of an event by the ease with which instances or occurrences can be
brought to mind."), and there is now a voluminous literature, some of the key items being con-
tained in Daniel Kahneman, Paul Slovic, and Amos Tversky, eds, Judgment under Uncertainty:
Heuristics and Biases 11-14 (Cambridge 1982) (noting that "the reliance on availability leads to
predictable biases," such as those stemming from "retrievability," "the effectiveness of a search
set," "imaginability," and "illusory correlation"), and Thomas Gilovich, Dale Griffin, and Daniel
Kahneman, eds, Heuristics and Biases: The Psychology of Intuitive Judgment 19-119 (Cambridge
2002) (presenting five articles discussing the representativeness and availability heuristics).
51 See Scott Pious, The Psychology of Judgment and Decision Making 125-26, 178-80
(McGraw-Hill 1993) (noting the similarities between availability, salience, and vividness). See
also Robert M. Reyes, William C. Thompson, and Gordon H. Bower, Judgmental Biases Resulting
from Differing Availabilities of Arguments, 39 J Personality & Soc Psych 2, 5-12 (1980) (finding
that concrete and vivid information has greater effect on decisionmaking than abstract information).
52 There is a dispute in the literature between those who take availability as an often reli-
able indicator of class characteristics, see Gary Klein, The Fiction of Optimization, in Gerd Gig-
erenzer and Reinhard Selten, eds, Bounded Rationality: The Adaptive Toolbox 103, 114 (MIT
2001) (positing that instead of being seen as biases, heuristics are better viewed "as strengths that
permit skillful decision making in field settings"), and those opposed to the view that availability
is often a biased indicator of an actual frequency distribution, see Amos Tversky and Daniel
Kahneman, Extensional versus Intuitive Reasoning: The Conjunction Fallacy in Probability
Judgment, in Gilovich, Griffin, and Kahneman, eds, Heuristics and Biases 19, 20-21 (cited in note
50) (noting extensive data that show heuristics to be "errors of judgment"). Some of the dispute
can be disaggregated by understanding availability solely in terms of ease of recall, independent
of the extent to which people may recall on the basis of reliability and not ease. And there is
evidence that when we control for the content of the recall, ease of recall itself is often a deter-
minant of judgment. Norbert Schwarz and Leigh Ann Vaughn, The Availability Heuristic Revis-
ited: Ease of Recall and Content of Recall as DistinctSources of Information,in Gilovich, Griffin,
and Kahneman, eds, Heuristicsand Biases 103,118-19 (cited in note 50) ("[I]ndividuals are likely
to rely on ease of recall when the judgment task is of low personal relevance."). Understood as
ease of recall itself, availability is especially likely to be biased. As shall become clear, there is
reason to believe not only that the availability of the immediate case is an unreliable indicator of
the array of disputes of that type, but also that, when litigation incentives are taken into account,
it may be an especially unreliable indicator.
53 This may or may not be true, but I assume that for certain weather events like for many
disasters, the occurrence of such an event at Time 1 is causally unrelated to the probability of a
similar event at Time 2.
The University of Chicago Law Review [73:883
58 See Chris Guthrie, Jeffrey J. Rachlinski, and Andrew J. Wistrich, Inside the JudicialMind,
86 Cornell L Rev 777, 787-94 (2001) (describing how the damage determinations of parties,
jurors, and judges are anchored by initial information); Fritz Strack and Thomas Mussweiler,
Explaining the Enigmatic Anchoring Effect: Mechanisms of Selective Accessibility, 73 J Personal-
ity & Soc Psych 437, 438 (1997) (noting that anchoring occurs regardless of whether the given
anchor falls inside or outside a range of neutrally acceptable values); Pious, The Psychology of
Judgment and Decision Making at 144-52 (cited in note 51) (noting that "unusually high or low"
values are "most likely to produce biases in judgment"); Tversky and Kahneman, 185 Science at
1128-30 (cited in note 50) (finding that cognitive "adjustments" from the anchor value "are
typically insufficient").
59 See Francisca Farifia, Ram6n Arce, and Mercedes Novo, Anchoring in Judicial Decision-
Making, 7 Psych in Spain 56,61-62 (2003) (finding anchoring effects in judicial determinations of
guilt and judicial imposition of sentences in criminal cases).
60 See Gretchen B. Chapman and Eric J. Johnson, Incorporatingthe Irrelevant: Anchors in
Judgments of Belief and Value, in Gilovich, Griffin, and Kahneman, eds, Heuristics and Biases
120, 138 (cited in note 50) (describing anchoring as "both prevalent and robust" and observable
"in numerous real-world contexts"); Timothy D. Wilson, et al, A New Look at Anchoring Effects:
Basic Anchoring and Its Antecedents, 125 J Exp Psych: Gen 387, 400 (1996) (finding "anchoring
effects even when people were blatantly provided with anchor values and explicitly told not to
use these values when answering subsequent questions").
61 See Pious, The Psychology of Judgment at 97-98 (cited in note 51) (describing how
framing an outcome as a "gain" rather than a "loss" shapes decisionmakers' risk-aversion); Amos
Tversky and Daniel Kahneman, Rational Choice and the Framing of Decisions, 59 J Bus S251,
S260-61 (1986) (giving the example of how framing the difference between two prices as either a
surcharge or a discount impacts preferences); Daniel Kahneman and Amos Tversky, Choice, Values,
and Frames,39 Am Psych 341,343 (1984) (noting that "two versions of a choice problem that are
recognized to be equivalent when shown together should elicit the same preference even when
898 The University of Chicago Law Review [73:883
shown separately" but that "the requirement of invariance ... cannot generally be satisfied");
Amos Tversky and Daniel Kahneman, The Framing of Decisions and the Psychology of Choice,
211 Science 453, 457 (1981) (noting that "seemingly inconsequential changes in the formulation
of choice problems caused significant shifts of preference").
62 James N. Druckman, Political Preference Formation: Competition, Deliberation,and the
(Ir)relevanceof Framing Effects, 98 Am Pol Sci Rev 671,672 (2004).
63 Much of this literature is cited in Druckman, 98 Am Pol Sci Rev at 685--86 (cited in note 62).
2006] Do Cases Make Bad Law?
64 Jerome Frank, Law and the Modern Mind 102-04 (Brentano's 1930).
65 To the same effect, see Joseph C. Hutcheson, Jr., The Judgment Intuitive: The Function of
the "Hunch" in Judicial Decision,14 Cornell L Q 274,278 (1929) ("[Tlhe judge, being merely on
his way with a roving commission to find the just solution, will follow his hunch wherever it leads
him."); Herman Oliphant, A Return to Stare Decisis, 14 ABA J 71, 75 (1928).
66 See Brian Leiter, American Legal Realism, in Martin . Golding and William A. Ed-
mundson, eds, The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Law and Legal Theory 50, 58-59
(Blackwell 2005).
67 Karl Llewellyn, The Common Law Tradition:DecidingAppeals 121 (Little, Brown 1960)
(arguing that judges draw "on more than 'common knowledge' to decide cases; they draw on
"'horse sense,' the balanced shrewdness of the expert in the art"). See also William Twining, Karl
Llewellyn and the Realist Movement at 209 (cited in note 11).
The University of Chicago Law Review [73:883
68 Llewellyn's celebration was far less frequent and far more qualified than Frank's, for
Llewellyn was most concerned with urging judges to base their decisions on situation types
rather than case-specific litigant characteristics. See Leiter, American Legal Realism at 55 (cited
in note 66) ("[W]hat more typically determines the course of the decision is the 'situation-type,'
that is, the general pattern of behavior."). In this context, it is important to note that the thor-
ough-going particularist-Jerome Frank, perhaps-would not be troubled by the issue I raise
here, for the particularist would not suppose that the "law" that is made in one case would have
much, if any, effect on the decision of subsequent cases. I use the Realist observations about
particularism, therefore, not totally to enlist the Realists in my case, but simply to draw on their
highly plausible observations about the way in which the necessity of decision might focus judi-
cial attention more on a particular case than would occur in a less distorted lawmaking process.
69 Reaching the wrong result in order to announce the right rule is the best understanding
of Herbert Wechsler's call for decision according to "neutral principles." Herbert Wechsler, To-
ward Neutral Principles in Constitutional Law, 73 Harv L Rev 1, 34-35 (1959). The word "neu-
tral" is unnecessary and distracting, see Frederick Schauer, Neutrality and JudicialReview, 22 L
& Phil 217, 217 (2003), but the basic idea is that a rule announced in the first case should be one
a court is willing to follow in subsequent ones. Kent Greenawalt, The Enduring Significance of
Neutral Principles,78 Colum L Rev 982, 983 (1978); M.P. Golding, Principled Decision-Making
and the Supreme Court, 63 Colum L Rev 35, 35 (1963). The implication is that if a court is not
willing to follow in future cases the rule necessary to decide the first case properly, then deciding
the first case improperly would be preferable to having a bad rule, a rule that precisely because it
is a bad rule will decide some number of subsequent cases improperly.
70 As with a court that goes out of its way to emphasize the uniqueness of a unique case, as in
Bush v Gore, 531 US 98,109 (2000) ("Our consideration is limited to the present circumstances.").
71 See Sunstein, One Case at a Time at 5 (cited in note 47) ("[A] minimalist path usually ...
makes a good deal of sense when the Court is dealing with a constitutionalissue of high complex-
ity about which many people feel deeply and on which the nation is divided.").
20061 Do Cases Make Bad Law?
particular case even though that rule will produce erroneous outcomes
in future cases.
The way in which the obligation to decide the immediate case can
distort a rulemaker's perception of the class of cases to be covered by a
putative rule is again compatible with recent work in the social sciences.
As with airline pilots who fail to see other airplanes because they are
focusing on operating the controls,72 people often ignore that which is
plainly "visible and available" to them because their ability to perceive
the readily available is "competing with a task requiring other atten-
tional resources."73 So when people have a particular task that requires
doing, the focus on the task may increase even further any tendency to4
is in theory available.
fail to perceive or to misperceive even that which
For the typical judge, deciding this case may be just that kind of task,
and thus the obligation to decide may well increase even further the
proclivity to be unduly influenced by the facts of the immediate case.
C. Some Examples
Consider, for example, New York Times Co v Sullivan."' Other
76
than to say that libel was not covered by the First Amendment, the
Supreme Court had never before even considered a defamation case.
Yet despite the Court's lack of experience with the topic, in Sullivan it
was compelled to make a decision in the context of a case in which
protection of the civil rights movement against crippling civil judg-
ments was seen to be important, in which the plaintiff was a powerful
public official using civil litigation as a way of wielding official power,
and in which the verdicts embodied little other than the jury's (and Ala-
bama's) desire to punish what were perceived to be so-called Northern
Agitators. These dimensions of the actual litigation were at the fore-
front of the Court's thinking," and thus it is useful to ask whether, if
72 Arien Mack, Inattentional Blindness: Looking without Seeing, 12 Curt Dir in Psych Sci
180, 180 (2003) (noting the same phenomenon "even may account for many car accidents"). See
also Arien Mack and Irvin Rock, InattentionalBlindness 250 (MIT 1998) ("[T]hat the absence of
attention causes apparent blindness, deafness, and numbness and perhaps even insensitivity to
extreme pain [indicates] that attention is necessary for conscious perception.").
73 Chugh and Bazerman, Bounded Awareness at 5 (cited in note 55) (noting that "signifi-
cant laughter and disbelief' result when inattentive subjects are alerted to a novel stimulus that
passed through their visual fields).
74 See Daniel J. Simons and Christopher F. Chabris, Gorillas in Our Midst: Sustained Inat-
tentional Blindness for Dynamic Events, 28 Perception 1059, 1072 (1999) (finding that "'directed
ignoring' could inhibit perception of not just the ignored event but of all unattended events").
75 376 US 254 (1964).
76 See Beauharnaisv Illinois,343 US 250,266 (1952).
77 See Anthony Lewis, Make No Law: The Sullivan Case and the First Amendment 147
(Random House 1991) (noting that the Court applied its new test to the instant facts, a rare
event, in order to prevent the same outcome on remand); Harry Kalven, Jr., The Negro and the
The University of Chicago Law Review [73:883
FirstAmendment 53 (Ohio State 1965) ("On its facts, the Times case seems to have been put
together by the Devil himself in order to embarrass the legal system.").
78 See Frederick Schauer, The Exceptional First Amendment, in Michael Ignatieff, ed,
American Exceptionalism and Human Rights 29, 30 (Princeton 2005) ("[T]he American First
Amendment ...remains a recalcitrant outlier to a growing international understanding of what
the freedom of expression entails."); Michael Chesterman, Freedom of Speech in Australian Law:
A Delicate Plant 101 (Ashgate 2000) ("[In Australia,] the defendant [in an action for libel] must
normally prove that ...reasonable grounds warranting belief in the truth of the defamatory
imputation existed at the time of publication."); Ian Loveland, PoliticalLibels: A Comparative
Study 4 (Hart 2000) (noting that in England, the plaintiff in a libel case must only "prove that the
publication complained of was libellous"); Leonard Leigh, Of Free Speech and Individual Repu-
tation: New York Times v. Sullivan in Canada and Australia, in Ian Loveland, ed, Importing the
FirstAmendment: Freedom of Expression in American, English, and European Law 51, 66 (Hart
1998) ("In neither [Australia nor Canada] do courts welcome the American extension [of libel]
from matters of a political nature ... to matters of public interest.").
79 I do not claim that Sullivan was wrongly decided, nor that the Sullivan actual malice rule
was the wrong rule. Both of those might be true, see Richard Epstein, Was New York Times v.
Sullivan Wrong?, 53 U Chi L Rev 782, 784-85 (1986) (noting that the post-Sullivan period has
brought increased numbers of libel suits and increasing unease about libel law), but my point is
only that the particular facts of the case produced a rule almost certainly different from what the
same justices of the same Court would otherwise have done were they asked simply to make a
public figure libel rule, and different from what every other open liberal democracy in the world
has subsequently decided to do. Sullivan may be a fortuitously distorted decision, but the distor-
tion seems nevertheless plain.
80 462 US 919,967 (1983) (White dissenting).
81 Id at 974.
82 379 US 294 (1964) (upholding the Civil Rights Act of 1964 as a valid congressional exer-
cise of the Commerce Power even as applied to primarily local entities).
83 383 US 131 (1966) (upholding the First Amendment right to protest, even in a public
library).
2006] Do Cases Make Bad Law?
84 526 US 137 (1999) (increasing the degree of judicial scrutiny over the qualifications of
expert witnesses).
85 509 US 579,597 (1993) (holding that "the Rules of Evidence ... assign to the trial judge
the task of ensuring that an expert's testimony both rests on a reliable foundation and is relevant").
86 To be exact, 83 out of 7781 in the Supreme Court's October 2003 Term. The Supreme
Court 2003 Term: The Statistics, 118 Harv L Rev 497,504-05 (2004) (excluding fifty cases summa-
rily decided from the eighty-three decided by full opinion).
87 See Shavell, 24 J Legal Stud at 416-17 (cited in note 44) (noting that appellate courts
that screen their own caseload may be able to engage in lawmaking with less attention to the
error correction process).
The University of Chicago Law Review [73:883
Collins" may have led the California Supreme Court, and other courts
dealing with the issue after Collins,' to express a principle of skepti-
cism about statistical evidence that would be justified were Collins
representative of all statistical evidence cases, but much less so if the
case were an aberration. Similarly, the purest and ultimately diluted °
versions of so-called interest analysis in conflicts of law may have
been based on the belief that the seeming irrationality of the tradi-
tional rules when applied to a small number of unusual guest statute
scenarios was typical of choice of law issues." And to the same effect is
the indication that larger principles of criminal intent were distorted
by a series of nineteenth century decisions in which the judges' views
about the issues of sexual morality involved in statutory rape cases led
them to say things about mens rea that they would not have said in
other types of cases."
I emphasize again that all of these cases may be unrepresentative
of the full array of case-based rulemaking decisions, and thus provide
94 Insofar as the cases arriving in an appellate court are systematically heterogeneous with
respect to the classes of which they are members, see Gillian K. Hadfield, Bias in the Evolution
of Legal Rules, 80 Georgetown L J 583, 592 (1992), the phenomenon identified here would be
amplified. But even if outliers arrive in appellate courts in their proper proportion, the tendency of
decisionmakers to see the outliers as nonoutlying exemplars would itself create a substantial problem.
95 As should be apparent, all of this also applies to the original perception of a court that
an existing rule needs to be changed. A rule that gets it right 99 percent of the time is, usually, a
pretty good rule, but if only the 1 percent gets litigated then courts are likely to believe that the
existing rule is far worse than it in fact is. I discuss this issue at greater length in Part IV.A.
96 1 return to these comparative issues in Part V.
99 Omychund v Barker,26 Eng Rep 15,23 (Ch 1744) (Mansfield) ("[Tlhe common law, that
works itself pure by rules drawn from the fountain of justice, is for this reason superior to an act
of parliament."). See Lon L. Fuller, The Law in Quest of Itself 140 (Foundation 1940) (adopting
Mansfield's phrase in saying that "[tihe common law works itself pure and adapts itself to the
needs of a new day").
100 The literature, sometimes more or sometimes less supportive of evolutionary explana-
tions, includes Todd J. Zywicki, The Rise and Fall of Efficiency in the Common Law: A Supply-
Side Analysis, 97 Nw U L Rev 1551, 1553 (2003) (proposing that changes in the institutional legal
framework "have made the common law more susceptible to rent-seeking pressures, which have
undermined the common law's pro-efficiency orientation"); Douglas Glen Whitman, Evolution
of the Common Law and the Emergence of Compromise,29 J Legal Stud 753,755 (2000) (using a
model of legal process to derive conditions under which the common law will produce conver-
gence on a single rule rather than oscillation between rules); Herbert Hovenkamp, Evolutionary
Models in Jurisprudence,64 Texas L Rev 645, 646 (1985) ("Today every theory of jurisprudence
worth contemplating incorporates a theory of change."); R. Peter Terrebonne, A Strictly Evolu-
tionary Model of Common Law, 10 J Legal Stud 397, 398 (1981) (importing "tools of evolution-
ary analysis from biology" to test the efficiency of law); William M. Landes and Richard A. Pos-
ner, Adjudication as a Private Good, 8 J Legal Stud 235, 284 (1979) (arguing that the common
law trends towards economic efficiency in some areas but that its overall efficiency is generally
"overstated"); John C. Goodman, An Economic Theory of the Evolution of Common Law, 7 J
Legal Stud 393, 394 (1978) (proposing that the litigants drive the evolution of the common law
towards economic efficiency); Paul H. Rubin, Why Is the Common Law Efficient?, 6 J Legal Stud
51, 51 (1977) (arguing that inefficient legal rules will lead to more litigation, and thus greater
potential change, than efficient legal rules).
20061 Do Cases Make Bad Law?
prompt change are thought, for the very reasons we are considering
here, to be more representative than they in fact are. Because rules are
necessarily actually or potentially both under- and overinclusive,''
even the best rules will in their normal operation on occasion produce
the wrong results. Precise speed limits will sometimes overconstrain
good drivers under perfect conditions, just as they may unduly em-
power poor drivers in bad conditions. The rule prohibiting vehicles in
the park may keep out benign ceremonial vehicles and also fail to ex-
clude noisy or dangerous instrumentalities that are not vehicles.'O'And'
Act of 1934 3
precise rules such as § 16(b) of the Securities Exchange
may fail to reach inside-trading owners of 9.99 percent of the stock of
a registered company while at the same time the rule constrains the
owner of 10.01 percent of the stock who seeks to sell within six
months of buying even though she possesses no inside information
whatsoever.
Yet although this under- and overinclusion is a necessary feature
of rules, a process that focuses disproportionately on the instances of
under- or (especially) overinclusion may be inclined to take every
such instance as an occasion for changing a rule. A rule that gets it
right 99 percent of the time may well be a very good rule, but a proc-
ess that focuses only on the remaining 1 percent may be a process in-
fluenced to believe that some of these very good rules are in need of
modification. In a variation on the common phenomenon of hindsight
bias, " and also as a manifestation of the common tendency to overes-
101 See Schauer, Playingby the Rules at 34-35 (cited in note 32).
102 This well-known example comes from H.L.A. Hart, Positivism and the Separation of
Law and Morals, 71 Harv L Rev 593, 607 (1958) (positing that rules create "a penumbra of de-
batable cases" surrounding "a core of settled meaning"), and H.L.A. Hart, The Concept of Law
123 (Clarendon 2d ed 1994) (arguing that "[alll rules involve recognizing or classifying particular
cases," some of which are easily classified and some of which are ambiguous). The supposed
counterexample comes from Lon L. Fuller, Positivism and Fidelity to Law-A Reply to Professor
Hart, 71 Harv L Rev 630, 663 (1958) (arguing that the distinction between the core and the pe-
numbra cannot be determined without reference to purpose).
103 15 USC § 78p(a) (2000) (establishing that "[e]very person who is directly or indirectly
the beneficial owner of more than 10 percent of any class of any equity security" is required to
file statements in accordance with the statute).
104 See Baruch Fischhoff, Learningfrom Experience: Coping with Hindsight Bias andAmbi-
guity, in J. Scott Armstrong, ed, Principlesof Forecasting:A Handbook for Researchersand Prac-
titioners 543, 544 (Kluwer 2001) (defining hindsight bias as "the tendency to exaggerate in hind-
sight what one [would have been] able to predict in foresight"); Paul Slovic and Baruch
Fischhoff, On the Psychology of Experimental Surprises, 3 J Exp Psych: Hum Perception & Per-
formance 544,561 (1977) (finding "people to be wrong too often when they are certain that they
are right"); Baruch Fischhoff, Hindsight 7 Foresight:The Effect of Outcome Knowledge on Judg-
ment under Uncertainty, 1 J Exp Psych: Hum Perception & Performance 288, 298 (1975) (finding
that subjects with outcome knowledge believed the probability of the known occurrence was
higher than subjects without outcome knowledge). For the view that hindsight bias is adaptive
and not irrational, see Ulrich Hoffrage, Ralph Hertwig, and Gerd Gigerenzer, Hindsight Bias: A
The University of Chicago Law Review [73:883
By-Product of Knowledge Updating?, 26 J Exp Psych: Learning, Memory & Cognition 566, 579
(2000) ("[W]e do not view hindsight bias as a bias in the first place but as a consequence of
learning by feedback.").
105 See Bernt P. Stigum, Econometrics and the Philosophy of Economics: Theory-Data Con-
frontations in Economics 431-33 (Princeton 2003) (noting, however, that "[bly how much per-
ceived and objective probabilities differ and how this difference varies with . .. individuals are
less well documented").
106 See, for example, Paul H. Rubin, Common Law and Statute Law, 11 J Legal Stud 205,
207 (1982) (arguing that the increased efficiency of the common law may be more historical
correlation than methodological causation); Richard A. Epstein, The Static Conception of the
Common Law, 9 J Legal Stud 253, 275 (1980) ("The simple dichotomy between statutory and
common law rules explains nothing.").
2006] Do Cases Make Bad Law?
107 See generally Larry Alexander, Constrainedby Precedent, 63 S Cal L Rev 1, 3 (1989)
(naming precedent "one of the core structural features of adjudication in common-law legal
systems"); Frederick Schauer, Precedent,39 Stan L Rev 571,572 (1987) ("Reliance on precedent
is part of life in general."). For an economic analysis of why the common law might have incor-
porated a strong system of precedent, see Ronald A. Heiner, Imperfect Decisions and the Law:
On the Evolution of Legal Precedent and Rules, 15 J Legal Stud 227, 227 (1986) (arguing that
"uncertainty due to imperfectly using information" drove "certain major procedures that have
evolved in the law").
108 The requirement that the constraint be independent of the wisdom of the constraining
case is a necessary feature of any nontrivial account of precedent. See Alexander, 63 S Cal L Rev
at 4 (cited in note 107) (examining "constraint by incorrectly decided precedents"); Schauer, 39
Stan L Rev at 571 (cited in note 107) ("The previous treatment of occurrence X in manner Y
constitutes, solely because of its historicalpedigree, a reason for treating X in manner Y if and
when X again occurs."). Precedents that exert decisional force only when they are perceived to
be correct have no weight qua precedents. Only if the essence of precedential constraint is un-
derstood to be content independent, and thus only if precedents constrain (even if only presump-
tively) even when they are perceived as mistaken by the subsequently deciding court, does the
force of precedent have genuine bite.
109See Mark J. Roe, Chaos and Evolution in Law and Economics, 109 Harv L Rev 641,643-
44 (1996) (noting that cultural practices may remain static even after the historical forces that
provoked those practices have changed).
110 The literature is vast and growing. Seminal work on the basic phenomenon includes
Theodore Eisenberg, Litigation Models and Trial Outcomes in Civil Rights and PrisonerCases, 77
Georgetown L J 1567, 1569 (1989) (noting a selection effect when "cases tried are [ ]a skewed
The University of Chicago Law Review [73:883
selection effect, the likelihood that any dispute will wind up in an ap-
pellate court is significantly a function of the existence of two parties
holding mutually exclusive positions each believing that they have a
realistic possibility of prevailing. In such cases-we call them hard, or
indeterminate -the likelihood of litigation and appeal is higher than
the likelihood of litigation and appeal when only one side has a plau-
sible possibility of prevailing. On the strong view of the selection ef-
fect it is only the cases balanced on the knife edge of existing doc-
trine - the fifty-fifty cases, if you will - that go to trial and appeal, but,
even on a weaker view, the cases that a previous decision renders
moderately clear, even if wrongly clear, are systematically less likely to
go to trial and appeal. And as long as this is so, then most cases pre-
senting an opportunity to modify an erroneous rule will simply not
arise, or if they arise will settle before judgment at trial, or if they do
not settle before judgment will settle after judgment but before the
appeal that might modify the erroneous rule. Correcting an erroneous
rule made at Time 1 requires a case at Time 2, but if the cases at Time
2 are unlikely even to reach judgment precisely because of the rule
made at Time 1, then the common law's ability to correct its own mis-
takes will be systematically less than its ability to make them in the
first instance.
From this vantage point, then, we can see that the possibility of
correcting in a subsequent case the lawmaking error in a previous case
sample of cases filed"); George L. Priest, Reexamining the Selection Hypothesis: Learningfrom
Wittman's Mistakes, 14 J Legal Stud 215,216-17 (1985) (showing how an all-or-nothing legal rule
affects parties' willingness to settle); George L. Priest and Benjamin Klein, The Selection of
Disputesfor Litigation, 13 J Legal Stud 1, 2 (1984) (noting that the very low proportion of cases
that go to trial makes it "very difficult to infer specific characteristics" about all litigants);
George L. Priest, Selective Characteristicsof Litigation,9 J Legal Stud 399, 400 (1980) (examining
"the effect on the common law process of ...the decision of parties to litigate or settle their
dispute"); George L. Priest, The Common Law Process and the Selection of Efficient Rules, 6 J
Legal Stud 65, 65 (1977) (noting that if "transaction costs in the real world are positive," "ineffi-
cient legal rules will impose greater costs" and be more likely to be litigated). Subsequent discus-
sion, analysis, and empirical work includes Daniel Kessler, Thomas Meites, and Geoffrey Miller,
Explaining Deviationsfrom the Fifty-Percent Rule: A Multimodal Approach to the Selection of
Cases for Litigation, 25 J Legal Stud 233, 235 (1996) (suggesting a multimodal approach to rec-
oncile observed data with the predictions of selection effect); Robert E. Thomas, The Trial Selec-
tion Hypothesis without the 50 Percent Rule: Some Experimental Evidence, 24 J Legal Stud 209,
211-12 (1995) (noting that "the relative difference between the two sides' estimates" of fault, as
well as how close the dispute is to the legal rule, determines whether the parties will litigate);
Keith N. Hylton, Asymmetric Information and the Selection of Disputesfor Litigation,22 J Legal
Stud 187, 188 (1993) (arguing that "win-rate patterns can be explained by the informational
requirements of the relevant legal standard"); Theodore Eisenberg, Testing the Selection Effect: A
New Theoretical Framework with Empirical Tests, 19 J Legal Stud 337, 338-39 (1990) (proposing
the "50 percent hypothesis," which is an assumption that plaintiffs and defendants will each win
half the time). For an excellent analysis of the issues and a more comprehensive survey of the
literature, see Leandra Lederman, Which Cases Go to Trial?:An EmpiricalStudy of Predictorsof
Failureto Settle, 49 Case W Res L Rev 315,318 (1999).
2006] Do Cases Make Bad Law?
111 Relatedly, consider Judge Calabresi's famous argument advocating that common law
courts either already have or, if not, be given the authority to update clear but obsolete statutes.
Calabresi, A Common Law for the Age of Statutes at 170 (cited in note 47) (contending that
courts have "authority to interpret statutes honestly, but in ambiguous cases also functionally").
Without coming to a final conclusion on the matter, we would at least want to inquire into the
possibility that common law courts considering updating statutes would update statutes (and not
just find particular exceptions for particular cases) somewhat more than necessary because of a
proclivity to take aberrational but litigated cases as more indicative of a deeper statutory prob-
lem than was in fact the case.
The University of Chicago Law Review [73:883
V. IMPLICATIONS
A. Questions of Justiciability
As I noted at the outset of this Article, the alleged informational
advantages of having a single concrete case before a court have often
been thought to provide a reason for vigorous enforcement of the ex-
isting requirements for standing,16 and, by extension, for ripeness.. as
factual components fleshed out"); Abbott Laboratories v Gardner,387 US 136, 148-49 (1967)
(holding that the ripeness doctrine prevents courts from resolving abstract disagreements). See
also Gene R. Nichol, Jr., Ripeness and the Constitution,54 U Chi L Rev 153,155-56 (1987).
118 See Raines v Byrd, 521 US 811,819-20 (1997) (making a separation of powers argument
for a strict standing requirement); United Public Workers of America v Mitchell, 330 US 75, 89
(1947) (alluding to an Article III basis for the ripeness doctrine).
119 See Rescue Army v Municipal Court of Los Angeles, 331 US 549,583-85 (1947) (refusing
a preliminary judgment on the legal issue until a concrete case came before the Court); United
Public Workers, 330 US at 89 ("For adjudication of constitutional issues, 'concrete legal issues,
presented in actual cases, not abstractions,' are requisite."); Abner J. Mikva, Why Judges Should
Not Be Advicegivers: A Response to Professor Neal Katyal, 50 Stan L Rev 1825, 1826 (1998)
(arguing that nothing "in judges' status or stature [ ] qualifies them to give such advice to elected
officials"); Felix Frankfurter, A Note on Advisory Opinions, 37 Harv L Rev 1002, 1003 (1924)
("Every tendency to deal with [facts] abstractedly, to formulate them in terms of sterile legal
questions, is bound to result in sterile conclusions.").
120 See, for example, Mich Const Art III § 8 (2005) ("Either house of the legislature or the
governor may request the opinion of the supreme court ...as to the constitutionality of legisla-
tion."); Mass Const Art LXXXV (2004) ("Each branch of the legislature, as well as the governor
or the council, shall have authority to require the opinions of the justices of the supreme judicial
court.").
121 See, for example, Wolfgang Zeidler, The Federal Constitutional Court of the Federal
Republic of Germany:Decisions on the Constitutionalityof Legal Norms, 62 Notre Dame L Rev
504, 505-06 (1987) (noting that constitutional challenges in Germany require neither standing
nor ripeness).
2006] Do Cases Make Bad Law?
dictions in which the issue is still open, the sympathy to advisory opin-
ions might be somewhat greater.'22
The same considerations play out in legal doctrine as well, even
after the hurdles of justiciability have been cleared. Courts determin-
ing whether to entertain facial (as opposed to as-applied) challenges
are engaged in a process by which they must imagine the array of
events that will be encompassed by the allegedly unconstitutional
law.", If a court's assessment of that array is likely skewed by the par-
ticular case before it, however, the arguments for entertaining a facial
challenge become weaker, and the arguments for dealing with uncon-
stitutionality on a case-by-case as-applied basis become stronger. So
too with overbreadth. 1' If the basis for determining that a statute is
unconstitutionally overbroad is based, in large part, on a judicial pre-
diction of its likely applications,"' then, again, some reason to believe
that such predictions will be systematically distorted would be one
reason for encouraging reluctance to rely too heavily on overbreadth.
122 See William M. Landes and Richard A. Posner, The Economics ofAnticipatory Adjudica-
tion, 23 J Legal Stud 683,684-86 (1994) (examining the costs and benefits of anticipatory adjudi-
cation regimes).
123 See Richard H. Fallon, Jr., As-Applied and Facial Challenges and Third-Party Standing,
113 Harv L Rev 1321, 1324 (2000) (concluding "that there is no single distinctive category of
facial, as opposed to as-applied, litigation").
124 See Richard H. Fallon, Jr., Making Sense of Overbreadth, 100 Yale L J 853, 855 (1991)
("First Amendment overbreadth is largely a prophylactic doctrine, aimed at preventing a 'chill-
ing effect."); Henry P Monaghan, Overbreadth, 1981 Sup Ct Rev 1, 2 (noting that the "various limit-
ing conceptions" of the overbreadth doctrine cause it to be perceived as "erratic and confusing").
125 See. for example, New York v Ferber, 458 US 747, 749, 774 (1982) (holding that a state
anti-child-pornography statute was not overbroad because there was no indication that it would
be applied to material that did not explicitly depict sexual conduct); Broadrick v Oklahoma, 413
US 601, 616-18 (1973) (upholding state laws restricting the public, but not the private, political
speech of state employees).
The University of Chicago Law Review [73:883
court would then know about exemplars of the problem beyond the
case at hand, thus likely reducing the distorting effect of that case.
This process of delaying can even take place when jurisdiction is
not discretionary. A court deciding a case might decide the case with-
out any opinion at all, as is the common practice in the federal courts
of appeals, or if it decided a case with opinion it could make a choice to
decide narrowly rather than broadly, and in adjudicative mode much
more than rulemaking mode. Virtually any decision can be more or
less narrowly justified, and in that sense genuine common law rule-
making is in some respects itself discretionary. To the extent that a
court was inclined to make a rule, therefore, knowledge of the biases
produced by concrete cases might militate in favor of deciding the first
case narrowly and delaying rulemaking until the court's experiential
base was considerably larger."' And this applies to the practice of giv-
ing reasons as well. As noted above,v the very practice of giving rea-
sons has a rulemaking aspect, and thus a court deciding to delay its
rulemaking can do this not only by not deciding, but also by giving no
reasons for its decision, or giving narrower rather than broader rea-
sons. The arguments here are all ones that, ceteris paribus, will counsel
delay in judicial rulemaking, but the devices of delay turn out in fact
to be quite numerous.
126 There remains the risk, however, that subsequent cases will still be seen through the lens
of the first case because of anchoring and framing effects, and to the extent that this is so then no
amount of delay in rulemaking will totally eliminate the distortion of seeing all cases after the
first through the lens of the first case. See Matthew Rabin and Joel L. Schrag, FirstImpressions
Matter: A Model of Confirmatory Bias, 114 Q J Econ 37, 38 (1999) (describing "confirmatory
bias" as a tendency "to misinterpret ambiguous evidence as confirming [one's] current hypothe-
ses about the world").
127 See text accompanying note 35.
2006] Do Cases Make Bad Law?
more suited to engage in the "large n" empirical assessment that effec-
tive rulemaking would require. This would then constitute an argu-
ment, for example, albeit not the only argument and not necessarily a
conclusive argument, for administrative agencies making rules in the
context of formal rulemaking rather than as an adjunct to adjudica-
tion. For the same reasons it would constitute an argument for insti-
tutions such as the Federal Rules of Evidence and the Federal Rules
of Civil Procedure (and the standing committees that take the lead in
their revision) as opposed to letting the rules develop over time in
common law fashion. And it might even counsel congressional hesi-
tance when it considered, as it did in enacting the Sherman Act, for
example, relying on a common law process to develop an entire area
of law as opposed to charging an expert agency with the job, or per-
haps, for all of its own pathologies, even doing it itself.
VI. CONCLUSION
My aims here are modest. They are not to claim that civil law le-
gal regimes are better than common law ones, that statute law is better
than common law, that codification is better than case-by-case deci-
sionmaking, that the "case or controversy" requirement is fundamen-
tally confused, or that it is generally better to make decisions under a
"veil of ignorance."' All of these may well be true, but a full compari-
son between common law method and its alternatives would require a
thorough consideration of all of the virtues and pathologies of the
common law as a process and all of the virtues and pathologies of all
of its alternatives, and would need to do so in a multiplicity of institu-
tional contexts. It may well be, after all, that these various virtues and
pathologies would appear in different ways and with different conse-
quences depending on various other institutional features. All of these
considerations, therefore, and more, make the all-things-considered
comparison between common law method and any of a number of
alternatives far more than can possibly be tackled by one person, or in
any one article.
128 See the prescient (from my perspective) analysis in David L. Shapiro, The Choice of
Rulemaking or Adjudication in the Development of Administrative Policy, 78 Harv L Rev 921,
972 (1965) ("[Aldministrative efforts to give content to general statutory provisions ... should be
encouraged rather than thwarted."). See also Peter L. Strauss, The Common Law and Statutes, 70
U Colo L Rev 225,225 (1999).
129 John Rawls. A Theory of Justice 11 (Belknap rev ed 1999) ("[The veil of ignorance]
ensures that no one is advantaged or disadvantaged in the choice of principles by the outcome of
natural chance or the contingency of social circumstances."). See also John C. Harsanyi, Cardinal
Utility in Welfare Economics and in the Theory of Risk-Taking, 61 J Pol Econ 434, 434-35 (1953)
("[A] value judgment on the distribution of income would show the required impersonality ... if
the person [chose] in complete ignorance of what his own relative position... would be.").
The University of Chicago Law Review [73:883
130 There are, of course, dissenters. See, for example, Frederick Schauer, Profiles,Probabili-
ties, and Stereotypes ix (Belknap 2003) ("My aim in this book is to challenge the primacy of the
particular.... [T]hat this particular case, or this particular event, is what is most important.").
131 See Landes and Posner, 23 J Legal Stud at 685 (cited in note 122) (favoring anticipatory
adjudication but admitting that "[tihere is greater risk of deciding a case incorrectly when there
is little or no factual record").
132 One such distortion, and one I have not dealt with directly here, is the way in which the
common law may simply see too narrow a range of policy options and policy problems, a failing
neatly captured in the complaint that the common law "feeds too much upon itself." James
McCauley Landis, Statutes and the Sources of Law, in Roscoe Pound, ed, Harvard Legal Essays
213,213 (Harvard 1934).