Bab 1 - 5
Bab 1 - 5
1. Introduction
The main purpose of this chapter is to expound and criticize the dominant
epistemological perspective of mathematics. This is the absolutist view that
mathematical truth is absolutely certain, that mathematics is the one and perhaps the
only realm of certain, unquestionable and objective knowledge. This is to be
contrasted with the opposing fallibilist view that mathematical truth is corrigible, and
can never be regarded as being above revision and correction.
Much is made of the absolutist-fallibilist distinction because, as is shown
subsequently, the choice of which of these two philosophical perspectives is adopted
is perhaps the most important epistemological factor underlying the teaching of
mathematics.
3
The Philosophy of Mathematics Education
Assumption
This assumption is the basis of foundationism, the doctrine that the function of the
philosophy of mathematics is to provide certain foundations for mathematical
knowledge. Foundationism is bound up with the absolutist view of mathematical
knowledge, for it regards the task of justifying this view to be central to the
philosophy of mathematics.
4
A Critique of Absolutist Philosophies
the foundation of mathematical knowledge, that is the grounds for asserting the truth
of mathematical propositions, consists of deductive proof.
The proof of a mathematical proposition is a finite sequence of statements ending
in the proposition, which satisfies the following property. Each statement is an axiom
drawn from a previously stipulated set of axioms, or is derived by a rule of inference
from one or more statements occurring earlier in the sequence. The term ‘set of
axioms’ is conceived broadly, to include whatever statements are admitted into a
proof without demonstration, including axioms, postulates and definitions.
An example is provided by the following proof of the statement ‘1+1=2’ in the
axiomatic system of Peano Arithmetic. For this proof we need the definitions and
axioms s0=1, s1=2, x+0=x, x+sy=s(x+y) from Peano Arithmetic, and the logical
rules of inference P(r), r=t ⇒P(t); P(v)⇒P(c) (where r, t; v; c; and P(t) range over
terms; variables; constants; and propositions in the term t, respectively, and ‘⇒’
signifies logical implication).2 The following is a proof of 1+1=2: x+sy=s(x+y),
1+sy=s(1+y), 1+s0=s(1+0), x+0=x, 1+0=1, 1+s0=s1, s0=1, 1+1=s1, s1=2, 1+1=2.
An explanation of this proof is as follows. s0=1[D1] and s1=2[D2] are
definitions of the constants 1 and 2, respectively, in Peano Arithmetic, x+0=x[A1]
and x+sy=s(x+y)[A2] are axioms of Peano Arithmetic. P(r), r=t⇒P(t)[R1] and
P(v) ⇒P(c)[R2], with the symbols as explained above, are logical rules of inference.
The justification of the proof, statement by statement as shown in Table 1.1.
This proof establishes ‘1+1= 2’ as an item of mathematical knowledge or truth,
according to the previous analysis, since the deductive proof provides a legitimate
warrant for asserting the statement. Furthermore it is a priori knowledge, since it is
asserted on the basis of reason alone.
However, what has not been made clear are the grounds for the assumptions
made in the proof. The assumptions made are of two types: mathematical and logical
assumptions. The mathematical assumptions used are the definitions (D1 and D2) and
the axioms (A1 and A2). The logical assumptions are the rules of inference used (R1
and R2), which are part of the underlying proof theory, and the underlying syntax of
the formal language.
5
The Philosophy of Mathematics Education
6
A Critique of Absolutist Philosophies
the Parallel Postulate, merely leads to other bodies of geometric knowledge (non-
euclidean geometry).
Beyond Euclid, modern mathematical knowledge includes many branches
which depend on the assumption of sets of axioms which cannot be claimed to be
basic universal truths, for example, the axioms of group theory, or of set theory
(Maddy, 1984).
The deductive method provides the warrant for the assertion of mathematical
knowledge. The grounds for claiming that mathematics (and logic) provide absolutely
certain knowledge, that is truth, are therefore as follows. First of all, the basic statements
used in proofs are taken to be true. Mathematical axioms are assumed to be true, for
the purposes of developing that system under consideration, mathematical definitions
are true by fiat, and logical axioms are accepted as true. Secondly, the logical rules of
7
The Philosophy of Mathematics Education
inference preserve truth, that is they allow nothing but truths to be deduced from
truths. On the basis of these two facts, every statement in a deductive proof, including
its conclusion, is true. Thus, since mathematical theorems are all established by means of
deductive proofs, they are all certain truths. This constitutes the basis of the claim of
many philosophers that mathematical truths are certain truths.
This absolutist view of mathematical knowledge is based on two types of
assumptions: those of mathematics, concerning the assumption of axioms and
definitions, and those of logic concerning the assumption of axioms, rules of
inference and the formal language and its syntax. These are local or micro-
assumptions. There is also the possibility of global or macro-assumptions, such as
whether logical deduction suffices to establish all mathematical truths. I shall
subsequently argue that each of these assumptions weakens the claim of certainty for
mathematical knowledge.
The absolutist view of mathematical knowledge encountered problems at the
beginning of the twentieth century when a number of antinomies and
contradictions were derived in mathematics (Kline, 1980; Kneebone, 1963; Wilder,
1965). In a series of publications Gottlob Frege (1879, 1893) established by far the
most rigorous formulation of mathematical logic known to that time, as a foundation
for mathematical knowledge. Russell (1902), however, was able to show that Frege’s
system was inconsistent. The problem lay in Frege’s Fifth Basic Law, which allows a
set to be created from the extension of any concept, and for concepts or properties
to be applied to this set (Furth, 1964). Russell produced his well-known paradox by
defining the property of ‘not being an element of itself. Frege’s law allows the
extension of this property to be regarded as a set. But then this set is an element of
itself if, and only if, it is not; a contradiction. Frege’s Law could not be dropped
without seriously weakening his system, and yet it could not be retained.
Other contradictions also emerged in the theory of sets and the theory of
functions. Such findings have, of course, grave implications for the absolutist view of
mathematical knowledge. For if mathematics is certain, and all its theorems are
certain, how can contradictions (i.e., falsehoods) be among its theorems? Since there
was no mistake about the appearance of these contradictions, something must be
wrong in the foundations of mathematics. The outcome of this crisis was the
development of a number of schools in the philosophy of mathematics whose aims
were to account for the nature of mathematical knowledge and to re-establish its
certainty. The three major schools are known as logicism, formalism and
constructivism (incorporating intuitionism). The tenets of these schools of thought
were not fully developed until the twentieth century, but Korner (1960) shows that
their philosophical roots can be traced back at least as far as Leibniz and Kant.
A. Logicism
Logicism is the school of thought that regards pure mathematics as a part of logic. The
major proponents of this view are G.Leibniz, G.Frege (1893), B.Russell (1919),
8
A Critique of Absolutist Philosophies
A.N.Whitehead and R.Carnap (1931). At the hands of Bertrand Russell the claims of
logicism received the clearest and most explicit formulation. There are two claims:
1 All the concepts of mathematics can ultimately be reduced to logical
concepts, provided that these are taken to include the concepts of set theory
or some system of similar power, such as Russell’s Theory of Types.
2 All mathematical truths can be proved from the axioms and rules of inference
of logic alone.
The purpose of these claims is clear. If all of mathematics can be expressed in purely
logical terms and proved from logical principles alone, then the certainty of
mathematical knowledge can be reduced to that of logic. Logic was considered to
provide a certain foundation for truth, apart from over-ambitious attempts to extend
logic, such as Frege’s Fifth Law. Thus if carried through, the logicist programme
would provide certain logical foundations for mathematical knowledge,
reestablishing absolute certainty in mathematics.
Whitehead and Russell (1910–13) were able to establish the first of the two claims
by means of chains of definitions. However logicism foundered on the second claim.
Mathematics requires non-logical axioms such as the Axiom of Infinity (the set of all
natural numbers is infinite) and the Axiom of Choice (the Cartesian product of a
family of non-empty sets is itself non-empty). Russell expressed it himself as follows.
But although all logical (or mathematical) propositions can be expressed
wholly in terms of logical constants together with variables, it is not the
case that, conversely, all propositions that can be expressed in this way are
logical. We have found so far a necessary but not a sufficient criterion of
mathematical propositions. We have sufficiently defined the character of the
primitive ideas in terms of which all the ideas of mathematics can be defined,
but not of the primitive propositions from which all the propositions of
mathematics can be deduced. This is a more difficult matter, as to which it is
not yet known what the full answer is.
We may take the axiom of infinity as an example of a proposition which,
though it can be enunciated in logical terms, cannot be asserted by logic to
be true.
(Russell, 1919, pages 202–3, original emphasis)
Thus not all mathematical theorems and hence not all the truths of mathematics can be
derived from the axioms of logic alone. This means that the axioms of mathematics are
not eliminable in favour of those of logic. Mathematical theorems depend on an
irreducible set of mathematical assumptions. Indeed, a number of important mathematical
axioms are independent, and either they or their negation can be adopted, without
inconsistency (Cohen, 1966). Thus the second claim of logicism is refuted
To overcome this problem Russell retreated to a weaker version of logicism called
‘if-thenism’, which claims that pure mathematics consists of implication statements of
the form ‘A T’. According to this view, as before, mathematical truths are
established as theorems by logical proofs. Each of these theorems (T) becomes the
9
The Philosophy of Mathematics Education
B. Formalism
Kurt Godel’s Incompleteness Theorems (Godel, 1931) showed that the programme
could not be fulfilled. His first theorem showed that not even all the truths of
arithmetic can be derived from Peano’s Axioms (or any larger recursive axiom set).
10
A Critique of Absolutist Philosophies
This proof-theoretic result has since been exemplified in mathematics by Paris and
Harrington, whose version of Ramsey’s Theorem is true but not provable in Peano
Arithmetic (Barwise, 1977). The second Incompleteness Theorem showed that in the
desired cases consistency proofs require a meta-mathematics more powerful than the
system to be safeguarded, which is thus no safeguard at all. For example, to prove the
consistency of Peano Arithmetic requires all the axioms of that system and further
assumptions, such as the principle of transfinite induction over countable ordinals
(Gentzen, 1936).
The formalist programme, had it been successful, would have provided support
for an absolutist view of mathematical truth. For formal proof, based in consistent
formal mathematical systems, would have provided a touchstone for mathematical
truth. However, it can be seen that both the claims of formalism have been refuted.
Not all the truths of mathematics can be represented as theorems in formal systems,
and furthermore, the systems themselves cannot be guaranteed safe.
C. Constructivism
11
The Philosophy of Mathematics Education
constructive processes performed with pencil and paper, the stricter view of the
intuitionists, led by Brouwer, is that mathematics takes place primarily in the mind,
and that written mathematics is secondary. One consequence of that is that Brouwer
regards all axiomatizations of intuitionistic logic to be incomplete. Reflection can
always uncover further intuitively true axioms of intuitionistic logic, and so it can
never be regarded as being in final form.
Intuitionism represents the most fully formulated constructivist philosophy of
mathematics. Two separable claims of intuitionism can be distinguished, which
Dummett terms the positive and the negative theses.
The positive one is to the effect that the intuitionistic way of construing
mathematical notions and logical operations is a coherent and legitimate
one, that intuitionistic mathematics forms an intelligible body of theory.
The negative thesis is to the effect that the classical way of construing
mathematical notions and logical operations is incoherent and illegitimate,
that classical mathematics, while containing, in distorted form, much of
value, is, nevertheless, as it stands unintelligible.
(Dummett, 1977, page 360).
In restricted areas where there are both classical and constructivist proofs of a result,
the latter is often preferable as more informative. Whereas a classical existence proof
may merely demonstrate the logical necessity of existence, a constructive existence
proof shows how to construct the mathematical object whose existence is asserted.
This lends strength to the positive thesis, from a mathematical point of view.
However, the negative thesis is much more problematic, since it not only fails to
account for the substantial body of non-constructive classical mathematics, but also
denies its validity. The constructivists have not demonstrated that there are
inescapable problems facing classical mathematics nor that it is incoherent and
invalid. Indeed both pure and applied classical mathematics have gone from strength
to strength since the constructivist programme was proposed. Therefore, the negative
thesis of intuitionism is rejected.
Another problem for the constructivist view, is that some of its results are
inconsistent with classical mathematics. Thus, for example, the real number
continuum, as defined by the intuitionists, is countable. This contradicts the classical
result not because there is an inherent contradiction, but because the definition of
real numbers is different. Constructivist notions often have a different meaning from
the corresponding classical notions.
From an epistemological perspective, both the positive and negative theses of
intuitionism are flawed. The intuitionists claim to provide a certain foundation for their
version of mathematical truth by deriving it (mentally) from intuitively certain axioms,
using intuitively safe methods of proof. This view bases mathematical knowledge
exclusively on subjective belief. But absolute truth (which the intuitionists claim to
provide) cannot be based on subjective belief alone. Nor is there any guarantee that
different intuitionists’ intuitions of basic truth will coincide, as indeed they do not.
12
A Critique of Absolutist Philosophies
Thus the positive thesis of intuitionism does not provide a certain foundation for
even a subset of mathematical knowledge. This criticism extends to other forms of
constructivism which also claim to base constructive mathematical truth on a
foundation of self-evident constructivist assumptions.
The negative thesis of intuitionism (and of constructivism, when it is embraced),
leads to the unwarranted rejection of accepted mathematical knowledge, on the
grounds that it is unintelligible. But classical mathematics is intelligible. It differs from
constructivist mathematics largely in the assumptions on which it is based.4 Thus
constructivism is guilty of what is analogous to a Type I Error in statistics, namely the
rejection of valid knowledge.
13
Introduction
mathematics also have a powerful impact on the way mathematics is taught (Davis,
1967; Cooney, 1988; Ernest, 1988b, 1989c). One influential study concluded:
3. This book
The first part of the book treats the philosophy of mathematics. It contains both a
critique of existing approaches, and a new philosophy of mathematics. For although
the traditional paradigm is under attack, the novel and promising ideas in the Zeitgeist
have not yet been synthesized. Social constructivism is offered to fill this vacuum.
The second part explores the philosophy of mathematics education. It shows that
many aspects of mathematics education rest on underlying philosophical assumptions.
By uncovering some of them, the aim is to put a critical tool into the hands of
teachers and researchers.
Notes
1 A systematic ambiguity should be signalled. The philosophy of mathematics is the overall field of
philosophical inquiry into the nature of mathematics. In contrast, a philosophy of mathematics is a
particular account or view of the nature of mathematics. In general, these meanings are signalled by
the use of the definite or indefinite article (or the plural form), respectively.
2 It should be mentioned that a more negative attitude to mathematics was associated with view (B)
of the SMP students.
xiv
A Critique of Absolutist Philosophies
The above criticism is decisive for the absolutist view of mathematics. However, it is
possible to accept the criticism without adopting a fallibilist philosophy of
mathematics. For it is possible to accept a form of hypothetico-deductivism which
denies the corrigibility and the possibility of deep-seated error in mathematics. Such
a position views axioms simply as hypotheses from which the theorems of
mathematics are logically deduced, and relative to which the theorems are certain. In
other words, although the axioms of mathematics are tentative, logic and the use of
logic to derive theorems from the axioms guarantee a secure development of
mathematics, albeit from an assumed basis. This weakened form of the absolutist
position resembles Russell’s ‘if thenism’ in its strategy of adopting axioms without
either proof or cost to the system’s security. However this weakened absolutist
position is based on assumptions which leave it open to a fallibilist critique.
The central argument against the absolutist view of mathematical knowledge can be
circumvented by a hypothetico-deductive approach. However, beyond the problem
of the assumed truth of the axioms, the absolutist view suffers from further major
weaknesses.
The first of these concerns the underlying logic on which mathematical proof
rests. The establishment of mathematical truths, that is the deduction of theorems
from a set of axioms, requires further assumptions, namely the axioms and rules of
inference of logic itself. These are non-trivial and non-eliminable assumptions, and
15
The Philosophy of Mathematics Education
Assumption A
The proofs that mathematicians publish as warrants for asserting theorems can, in
principle, be translated into fully rigorous formal proofs.
The informal proofs that mathematicians publish are commonly flawed, and are by
no means wholly reliable (Davis, 1972). Translating them into fully rigorous formal
16
A Critique of Absolutist Philosophies
proofs is a major, non-mechanical task. It requires human ingenuity to bridge gaps and
to remedy errors. Since the total formalization of mathematics is unlikely to be carried
out, what is the value of the claim that informal proofs can be translated into formal
proofs ‘in principle’? It is an unfulfilled promise, rather than grounds for certainty. Total
rigor is an unattained ideal and not a practical reality. Therefore certainty cannot be
claimed for mathematical proofs, even if the preceding criticisms are discounted.
Assumption B
Assumption C
Mathematical theories can be validly translated into formal axiom sets.
The formalization of intuitive mathematical theories in the past hundred years
(e.g., mathematical logic, number theory, set theory, analysis) has led to unanticipated
deep problems, as the concepts and proofs come under ever more piercing scrutiny,
during attempts to explicate and reconstruct them. The satisfactory formalization of
the rest of mathematics cannot be assumed to be unproblematic. Until this
formalization is carried out it is not possible to assert with certainty that it can be
carried out validly. But until mathematics is formalized, its rigour, which is a
necessary condition for certainty, falls far short of the ideal.
Assumption D
17
The Philosophy of Mathematics Education
the assumed truth of the basis of mathematical knowledge (i.e., the basic
assumptions). Rather these are problems in trying to transmit the assumed truth of
these assumptions to the rest of mathematical knowledge by means of deductive
proof, and in establishing the reliability of the method.
The absolutist view of mathematical knowledge has been subject to a severe, and in my
view, irrefutable criticism.6 Its rejection leads to the acceptance of the opposing fallibilist
view of mathematical knowledge. This is the view that mathematical truth is fallible and
corrigible, and can never be regarded as beyond revision and correction. The fallibilist
thesis thus has two equivalent forms, one positive and one negative. The negative form
concerns the rejection of absolutism: mathematical knowledge is not absolute truth, and
does not have absolute validity. The positive form is that mathematical knowledge is
corrigible and perpetually open to revision. In this section I wish to demonstrate that
support for the fallibilist viewpoint, in one form or the other, is much broader than might
have been supposed. The following is a selection from the range of logicians,
mathematicians and philosophers who support this viewpoint:
In his paper ‘A renaissance of empiricism in the philosophy of mathematics’,
Lakatos quotes from the later works of Russell, Fraenkel, Carnap, Weyl, von
Neumann, Bernays, Church, Godel, Quine, Rosser, Curry, Mostowski and Kalmar (a
list that includes many of the key logicians of the twentieth century) to demonstrate
their common view concerning ‘the impossibility of complete certainty’ in
mathematics, and in many cases, their agreement that mathematical knowledge has
an empirical basis, entailing the rejection of absolutism. (Lakatos, 1978, page 25,
quotation from R.Carnap)
18
A Critique of Absolutist Philosophies
Or: logic as the foundation of mathematics does not work, and to show
this it is enough that the cogency of logical proof stands and falls with its
geometrical cogency….
The logical certainty of proofs—I want to say—does not extend beyond
their geometrical certainty.
(Wittgenstein, 1978, pages 174–5)
A Euclidean theory may be claimed to be true; a quasi-empirical theory—
at best—to be well-corroborated, but always conjectural. Also, in a
Euclidean theory the true basic statements at the ‘top’ of the deductive
system (usually called ‘axioms’) prove, as it were, the rest of the system; in a
quasi-empirical theory the (true) basic statements are explained by the rest
of the system…Mathematics is quasi-empirical
(Lakatos, 1978, pages 28–29 & 30)
Tautologies are necessarily true, but mathematics is not. We cannot tell
whether the axioms of arithmetic are consistent; and if they are not, any
particular theorem of arithmetic may be false. Therefore these theorems are
not tautologies. They are and must always remain tentative, while a
tautology is an incontrovertible truism…
[T]he mathematician feels compelled to accept mathematics as true, even
though he is today deprived of the belief in its logical necessity and
doomed to admit forever the conceivable possibility that its whole fabric
may suddenly collapse by revealing a decisive self-contradiction.
(Polanyi, 1958, pages 187 and 189)
The doctrine that mathematical knowledge is a priori mathematical apriorism
has been articulated many different ways during the course of reflection
about mathematics…I shall offer a picture of mathematical knowledge
which rejects mathematical apriorism…the alternative to mathematical
apriorism—mathematical empiricism—has never been given a detailed
articulation. I shall try to give the missing account.
(Kitcher, 1984, pages 3–4)
[Mathematical knowledge resembles empirical knowledge—that is, the criterion
of truth in mathematics just as much as in physics is success of our ideas in
practice, and that mathematical knowledge is corrigible and not absolute.
(Putnam, 1975, page 51)
It is reasonable to propose a new task for mathematical philosophy: not to
seek indubitable truth but to give an account of mathematical knowledge as
it really is—fallible, corrigible, tentative and evolving, as is every other kind
of human knowledge.
(Hersh, 1979, page 43)
Why not honestly admit mathematical fallibility, and try to defend the
dignity of fallible knowledge from cynical scepticism, rather than delude
19
The Philosophy of Mathematics Education
ourselves that we shall be able to mend invisibly the latest tear in the fabric
of our ‘ultimate’ intuitions.
(Lakatos, 1962, page 184)
8. Conclusion
Notes
1 In this chapter, for simplicity, the definition of truth in mathematics is assumed to be unproblematic
and unambiguous. Whilst justified as a simplifying assumption, since none of the arguments of the
chapter hinge on the ambiguity of this notion, the meaning of the concept of truth in mathematics
has changed over time. We can distinguish between three truth-related concepts used in
mathematics:
(a) There is the traditional view of mathematical truth, namely that a mathematical truth is a
general statement which not only correctly describes all its instances in the world (as does a
true empirical generalisation), but is necessarily true of its instances. Implicit in this view is the
assumption that mathematical theories have an intended interpretation, namely some
idealization of the world.
(b) There is the modern view of the truth of a mathematical statement relative to a background
mathematical theory: the statement is satisfied by some interpretation or model of the theory.
According to this (and the following) view, mathematics is open to multiple interpretations,
i.e., possible worlds. Truth consists merely in being true (i.e., satisfied, following Tarski, 1936) in
one of these possible worlds.
(c) There is the modern view of the logical truth or validity of a mathematical statement relative
to a background theory: the statement is satisfied by all interpretations or models of the theory.
Thus the statement is true in all of these possible worlds.
Truth in sense (c) can be established by deduction from the background theory as an axiom set. For
a given theory, truths in a sense (c) are a subset (usually a proper subset) of truths in sense (b).
20
A Critique of Absolutist Philosophies
Incompleteness arises (as Godel, 1931, proved) in most mathematical theories as there are sentences
true in sense (b) (i.e., satisfiable) which are not true in sense (c).
Thus not only does the concept of truth have multiple meanings, but crucial mathematical
issues hinge upon this ambiguity. Beyond this, the modern mathematical view of truth differs
from the traditional mathematical view of truth (a), and the everyday sense of the term, which
resembles it. For in a naive sense truths are statements which accurately describe a state of
affairs—a relationship—in some realm of discourse. In this view, the terms which express the
truth name objects in the realm of discourse, and the statement as a whole describes a true state
of affairs, the relationship that holds between the denotations of the terms. This shows that the
concept of truth employed in mathematics no longer has the same meaning as either the
everyday, naive notion of truth, or its equivalent (a) as was used in mathematics, in the past
(Richards, 1980, 1989).
The consequence of this is that the traditional problem of establishing the indubitable
foundations of mathematical truth has changed, as the definition of truth employed has changed. In
particular to claim that a statement is true in sense (b) is much weaker than senses (a) or (c). ‘1+1=1’
is true in sense (b)(it is satisfied in Boolean algebra, but not in sense (a) which assumes the standard
Peano interpretation).
2 For the proof to be rigorous, a formal language L for Peano Arithmetic should be specified in full.
L is a first-order predicate calculus in universally quantified free variable form. The syntax of L will
specify as usual the terms and formulas of L, the formula ‘P(r)’ in the term ‘r’, and the result ‘P(t)’
of substituting the term ‘t’ for the occurrences of Y in ‘P(r)’ (sometimes written P(r)[r/t]). It should
also be mentioned that a modernised form of the Peano Axioms is adopted above (see, for example,
Bell and Machover, 1977), which is not literally that of Peano (Heijenoort, 1967).
3 Scholars believe that Euclid’s fifth postulate was not considered to be as self-evident as the others. It
is less terse, and more like a proposition (a theorem) than a postulate (it is the converse of
proposition I 17). Euclid does not use it until proposition I 29. For this reason, over the ages, many
attempts to prove the posulate were made including Sacchieri’s attempt to prove it by reductio ad
absurdam based on its denial (Eves, 1953).
4 It is worth remarking that the classical predicate calculus is translatable into intuitionist logic in a
constructive way that preserves deducibility (see Bell and Machover, 1977). This means that all the
theorems of classical mathematics expressible in the predicate calculus can be represented as
intuitionistic theorems. Thus classical mathematics cannot easily be claimed to be intuitionistically
unintelligible. (Note that the reverse translation procedure is intuitionistically unacceptable, since it
replaces ‘-P’ by ‘P’, and ‘-(x)-P’ by ‘(Ex)P’, reading-, (x), and (Ex) as ’not’, ‘for all x’ and ‘there exists
x’, respectively).
5 Some readers may feel that assertion requires justification. What valid warrant can there be for
mathematical knowledge other than demonstration or proof? Clearly it is necessary to find other
grounds for asserting that mathematical statements are true. The principal accounts of truth are the
correspondence theory of truth, the coherence theory of truth (Woozley, 1949), the pragmatic
theory of truth (Dewey, 1938) and truth as convention (Quine, 1936; Quinton, 1963). We can first
dismiss the coherence and pragmatic theories of truth as irrelevant here, since these do not claim
that truth can be warranted absolutely. The correspondence theory can be interpreted either
empirically or non-empirically, to say that basic mathematical truths describe true states of affairs
either in the world or in some abstract realm. But then the truths of mathematics are justified
empirically or intuitively, respectively, and neither grounds serve as warrants for certain
knowledge.
The conventional theory of truth asserts that basic mathematical statements are true by virtue of
the meanings of the terms therein. But the fact that the axioms express what we want or believe
terms to mean does not absolve us from having to assume them, even if we simply stipulate them
by fiat. Rather it is an admission that we simply have to assume certain basic propositions. Beyond
this, to say that complex axioms such as those of Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory are true by virtue of
the meanings of the constituent terms is not supportable. (Maddy, 1984, gives an account of set-
theoretic axioms in current use which by no stretch of the imagination are considered true). We
must regard these axioms as implicit definitions of their constituent terms, and it is evident we must
assume the axioms to proceed with set theory.
21
The Philosophy of Mathematics Education
6 The critique of absolutism can be used to criticize this chapter, as follows. If no knowledge,
including mathematics is certain how can the modestly founded assertions of this chapter be true?
Is not the assertion that there is no truth self-defeating?
The answer is that the assertions and arguments of this chapter do not pretend to be the truth,
but a plausible account. The grounds for accepting the truths of mathematics, imperfect as they are,
are far firmer than the arguments of the chapter. (The argument can be defended analogously to the
way Ayer, 1946, defends the Principle of Verification.)
22
2
23
The Philosophy of Mathematics Education
According to these views, the role of the philosophy of mathematics is to reflect on,
and give an account of the nature of mathematics. The key issue concerns how ‘giving
an account of’ mathematics is conceived. Absolutist philosophies of mathematics such
as logicism, formalism and intuitionism attempt to provide prescriptive accounts of the
nature of mathematics. Such accounts, as we have seen, are programmatic, legislating
how mathematics should be understood, rather than providing accurately descriptive
accounts of the nature of mathematics.Thus they are failing to account for mathematics
as it is, in the hope of fulfilling their vision of how it should be. But ‘to confuse
description and programme—to confuse ‘is’ with ‘ought to be’ or ‘should be’—is just
as harmful in the philosophy of mathematics as elsewhere.’
(Korner, 1960, page 12)
The inquiry can begin with the traditional questions of epistemology and ontology.
What is the nature and basis of mathematical knowledge? What is the nature of, and
how do we account for, the existence of mathematical objects (numbers, functions,
sets, etc.)?
However, the answers to these questions will not provide a descriptive account of
the nature of mathematics. For the narrow focus of these ‘internal’ questions
concerning the philosophy of mathematics fails to locate mathematics within the
broader context of human thought and history. Without such a context, according to
Lakatos, the philosophy of mathematics loses its content.
Under the present dominance of formalism (i.e., foundationism), one is
tempted to paraphrase Kant: the history of mathematics, lacking the
guidance of philosophy has become blind, while the philosophy of
24
The Philosophy of Mathematics Reconceptualized
Thus much more should fall within the scope of the philosophy of mathematics than
merely the justification of mathematical knowledge, provided through its
reconstruction by a foundationist programme. Mathematics is multi-faceted, and as
well as a body of prepositional knowledge, it can be described in terms of its
concepts, characteristics, history and practices. The philosophy of mathematics must
account for this complexity, and we also need to ask the following questions. What is
the purpose of mathematics? What is the role of human beings in mathematics? How
does the subjective knowledge of individuals become the objective knowledge of
mathematics? How has mathematical knowledge evolved? How does its history
illuminate the philosophy of mathematics? What is the relationship between
mathematics and the other areas of human knowledge and experience? Why have
the theories of pure mathematics proved to be so powerful and useful in their
applications to science and to practical problems?
These questions represent a broadening of the scope of the philosophy of
mathematics from the internal concerns of absolutism. Three issues may be selected
as being of particular importance, philosophically and educationally. Each of these
issues is expressed in terms of a dichotomy, and the absolutist and fallibilist
perspectives on the issue are contrasted. The three issues are as follows.
First of all, there is the contrast between knowledge as a finished product, largely
expressed as a body of propositions, and the activity of knowing or knowledge
getting. This latter is concerned with the genesis of knowledge, and with the
contribution of humans to its creation. As we have seen, absolutist views focus on the
former, that is finished or published knowledge, and its foundations and justification.
Absolutist views not only focus on knowledge as an objective product, they often
deny the philosophical legitimacy of considering the genesis of knowledge at all, and
consign this to psychology and the social sciences. One partial exception to this is
constructivism, which admits the knowing agent in a stylized form.
In contrast, fallibilist views of the nature of mathematics, by acknowledging the
role of error in mathematics cannot escape from considering theory replacement and
the growth of knowledge. Beyond this, such views must be concerned with the
human contexts of knowledge creation and the historical genesis of mathematics, if
they are to account adequately for mathematics, in all its fullness.
Because of the importance of the issue, it is worth adding a further and more
general argument for the necessity for considering the genesis of knowledge. This
argument is based on the reality of knowledge growth. As history illustrates,
knowledge is perpetually in a state of change in every discipline, including
mathematics. Epistemology is not accounting adequately for knowledge if it
concentrates only on a single static formulation, and ignores the dynamics of
knowledge growth. It is like reviewing a film on the basis of a detailed scrutiny of a
single key frame! Thus epistemology must concern itself with the basis of knowing,
25
The Philosophy of Mathematics Education
which underpins the dynamics of knowledge growth, as well as with the specific
body of knowledge accepted at any one time. Traditional philosophers such as Locke
and Kant admit the legitimacy and indeed the necessity of genetic considerations in
epistemology. So do an increasing number of modern philosophers, such as Dewey
(1950), Wittgenstein (1953), Ryle (1949), Lakatos (1970), Toulmin (1972), Polanyi
(1958), Kuhn (1970) and Hamlyn (1978).
Secondly, there is the distinction between mathematics as an isolated and discrete
discipline, which is strictly demarcated and separated from other realms of
knowledge, as opposed to a view of mathematics which is connected with, and
indissolubly a part of the whole fabric of human knowledge. Absolutist views of
mathematics accord it a unique status, it being (with logic) the only certain realm of
knowledge, which uniquely rests on rigorous proof. These conditions, together with
the associated internalist denial of the relevance of history or genetic or human
contexts, serve to demarcate mathematics as an isolated and discrete discipline.
Fallibilists include much more within the ambit of the philosophy of mathematics.
Since mathematics is seen as fallible, it cannot be categorically divorced from the
empirical (and hence fallible) knowledge of the physical and other sciences. Since
fallibilism attends to the genesis of mathematical knowledge as well as its product,
mathematics is seen as embedded in history and in human practice. Therefore
mathematics cannot be divorced from the humanities and the social sciences, or from
a consideration of human culture in general. Thus from a fallibilist perspective
mathematics is seen as connected with, and indissolubly a part of the whole fabric of
human knowledge.
The third distinction can be seen as a specialisation and further development of
the second. It distinguishes between views of mathematics as objective and value free,
being concerned only with its own inner logic, in contrast with mathematics seen as
an integral part of human culture, and thus as fully imbued with human values as
other realms of knowledge and endeavour. Absolutist views, with their internal
concerns, see mathematics as objective and absolutely free of moral and human
values. The fallibilist view, on the other hand, connects mathematics with the rest of
human knowledge through its historical and social origins. Hence it sees
mathematics as value-laden, imbued with moral and social values which play a
significant role in the development and applications of mathematics.
What has been proposed is that the proper concern of the philosophy of
mathematics should include external questions as to the historical origins and social
context of mathematics, in addition to the internal questions concerning knowledge,
existence, and their justification. For some years there has been a parallel debate over
an internalist-externalist dichotomy in the philosophy of science (Losee, 1987). As in
the philosophy of mathematics there has been a split between philosophers promoting
an internalist view in the philosophy of science (such as the logical empiricists and
Popper) and those espousing an externalist view. The latter include many of the most
influential recent philosophers of science, such as Feyerabend, Hanson, Kuhn, Lakatos,
Laudan and Toulmin. The contributions of these authors to the philosophy of science
is a powerful testimony to the necessity of considering ‘external’ questions in the
26
The Philosophy of Mathematics Reconceptualized
It has been argued that the role of the philosophy of mathematics is to account for
the nature of mathematics, where this task is conceived broadly to include ‘external’
issues such as the history, genesis and practice of mathematics, as well as ‘internal’
epistemological and ontological issues, such as the justification of mathematical
knowledge. These criteria can be stated more explicitly: a proposed philosophy of
mathematics should account for:
(i) Mathematical knowledge: its nature, justification and genesis,
(ii) The objects of mathematics: their nature and origins,
(iii) The applications of mathematics: its effectiveness in science, technology and
other realms.
(iv) Mathematical practice: the activities of mathematicians, both in the present
and the past.
It is proposed, therefore, to adopt these as adequacy criteria for any proposed
philosophy of mathematics. These criteria represent a reconceptualization of the role
of the philosophy of mathematics. However, this role, it is argued, represents the
proper task of the philosophy of mathematics, which was obscured by the mistaken
identification of the philosophy of mathematics with the study of the logical
foundations of mathematical knowledge.
The new criteria provide a means to assess the adequacy of schools of thought in the
philosophy of mathematics.
In the previous chapter we saw that the logicist, formalist and intuitionist schools are
absolutist. We have given an account of the failure of the programmes of these
schools, and indeed refuted in general the possibility of absolutism in the philosophy
of mathematics. On the basis of the above criteria we can further criticize these
schools for their inadequacy as philosophies of mathematics. Their task should have
included accounting for the nature of mathematics, including external social and
historical factors, such as the utility of mathematics, and its genesis. Because of their
narrow, exclusively internal preoccupations, these schools have made no contribution
27
The Philosophy of Mathematics Education
B. Progressive Absolutism
Although the various forms of absolutism are grouped and criticized together,
different forms of absolutism in mathematics can be distinguished. Drawing a parallel
with the philosophy of science, Confrey (1981) separates formal absolutist and
progressive absolutist philosophies of mathematics.1 The formal absolutist view of
mathematics is
28
The Philosophy of Mathematics Reconceptualized
Intuitionism (and constructivism, more generally) fit this description. For intuitionism
is foundationist and absolutist, seeking secure foundations for mathematical
knowledge through intuitionistic proofs and ‘ur-intuition’ (Kalmar, 1967). However,
intuitionism (1) acknowledges human mathematical activity as fundamental in the
construction of proofs or mathematical objects, the creation of new knowledge, and
(2) acknowledges that the axioms of intuitionistic mathematical theory (and logic) are
fundamentally incomplete, and need to be added to as more mathematical truth is
revealed informally or by intuition (Brouwer, 1927; Dummett, 1977).
In consequence, intuitionism, and progressive absolutist philosophies in general,
satisfy more of the adequacy criteria than formal absolutist philosophies, whilst
nevertheless remaining refuted overall. For they give some place, although restricted,
to the activities of mathematicians (criterion 4). They acknowledge human agency,
albeit in stylized form, in the domain of informal mathematics. This partial fulfilment
of the criteria deserves acknowledgment, for it means that not all absolutist
philosophies are on a par. It also turns out to be significant for education.
C. Platonism
Platonism is the view that the objects of mathematics have a real, objective existence
in some ideal realm. It originates with Plato, and can be discerned in the writings of
the logicists Frege and Russell, and includes Cantor, Bernays (1934), Hardy (1967)
and Godel (1964) among its distinguished supporters. Platonists maintain that the
objects and structures of mathematics have a real existence independent of humanity,
and that doing mathematics is the process of discovering their pre-existing
relationships. According to platonism mathematical knowledge consists of
descriptions of these objects and the relationships and structures connecting them.
Platonism evidently provides a solution to the problem of the objectivity of
mathematics. It accounts both for its truths and the existence of its objects, as well as
for the apparent autonomy of mathematics, which obeys its own inner laws and logic.
The problem of platonism, unlike that of the absolutist foundational school, is not
entirely one of failure, for it offers no foundationist programme to reconstruct and
safeguard mathematics. What is of more interest is to account for the fact that such an
implausible philosophy provides aid and comfort to successful mathematicians of the
stature of Cantor and Godel.
This interest notwithstanding, platonism suffers from two major weaknesses. First
of all, it is not able to offer an adequate account of how mathematicians gain access
to knowledge of the platonic realm. We can grant that platonism accounts for
29
The Philosophy of Mathematics Education
mathematical knowledge in the way that naive inductivist science accounted for its
knowledge. That is as being based on observations of the real world (an ideal world,
in the case of platonism), subsequently generalized. But if mathematics is the natural
history of the crystalline platonic universe, how is it that mathematicians gain
knowledge of it? It must surely be through intuition, or some such special mental
faculty, and no account of this is given. If access is through intuition, then a
reconciliation is needed between the facts that (i) different mathematicians’
intuitions vary, in keeping with the subjectivity of intuition, and (ii) platonist
intuition must be objective, and lead to agreement. Thus the platonist view is
inadequate without an account of human access to the realm of platonic objects
which overcomes these difficulties.
If, on the other hand, the platonist’s access to the world of mathematical objects
is not through intuition but through reason and logic, then further problems arise.
How does the platonist know that his or her reasoning is correct? Either another
form of intuition is needed, which allows the platonist to see which proofs correctly
describe mathematical reality, or the platonist is in the same boat as everybody else
with regard to proof. But in this second case, what is platonism but empty faith, since
it provides no insight into truth or existence?
The second flaw in the platonist account is that it is not able to offer an adequate
account of mathematics, neither internally nor externally. Internally, an important
part of mathematics is its constructive, computational side. This depends vitally on
the representation of dynamic mathematical processes, such as iteration, recursive
functions, proof theory, and so on. Platonism accounts only for the static set-theoretic
and structural aspects of mathematics. Thus it omits a central area of mathematics
from its account. Externally, platonism fails to account adequately for the utility of
mathematics, its relations with science, human activity or culture, and the genesis of
knowledge. For platonists to say that mathematics advances as it is progressively
uncovered, just as geography advanced with the voyages of the explorers, is not
enough. Nor does it suffice to say its utility stems from the fact that mathematics
describes the necessary structure of observable reality. For these explanations beg the
very questions they are meant to settle.
Since it fails on all the above counts, platonism is rejected as a philosophy of
mathematics.
D. Conventionalism
30
The Philosophy of Mathematics Reconceptualized
31
The Philosophy of Mathematics Education
I have not yet made the role of miscalculating clear. The role of the
proposition: ‘I must have miscalculated’. It is really the key to an
understanding of the ‘foundations’ of mathematics.
(Wittgenstein, 1978, p. 221)
What Wittgenstein is saying here is that if our results contradict the underlying rules
of use, then we reject the results, we do not question the underlying rules.
In summary, Wittgenstein proposes that the logical necessity of mathematical (and
logical) knowledge rests on linguistic conventions, embedded in our socio-linguistic
practices.2
Conventionalism might appear, on the basis of the account given, to be absolutist,
for it claims that mathematical axioms, for example, are absolutely true on the basis
of linguistic conventions. But locating the foundations of mathematical knowledge in
the rules governing natural language usage allows for the development of
mathematical knowledge, and indeed for changes in the nature of mathematical truth
and meaning, as its basis evolves. For language and its patterns of use develop all the
while organically, and its sets of conventions and rules change. This is especially true
of informal mathematical language, in which the rules governing the use of such
terms as ‘set’, ‘infinity’, ‘infinitesimal’ and ‘proof have changed dramatically in the
last hundred years, as a mathematical practice has developed. Likewise new
conventions have warranted new truths (such as Hamilton’s ‘ij =-ji’ and, in logic
‘1=2 implies 1=1’). Thus conventionalism is not absolutist, for it allows for the
dethronement and replacement of basic mathematical truths (such as ‘xy=yx’). This
form of conventionalism is therefore consistent with fallibilism.
The conventionalist philosophy of mathematics has been criticized by previous
authors on two grounds. First of all, it is claimed to be uninformative: ‘apart from
pointing out the essentially social nature of mathematics, conventionalism tells us
remarkably little’. (Machover, 1983, page 6). The force of this criticism is that to be
an adequate philosophy of mathematics, a much more elaborated version of
conventionalism is needed.
The second objection is due to Quine.
Briefly the point is that the logical truths, being infinite in number, must be
given by general conventions rather than singly; and logic is needed then to
32
The Philosophy of Mathematics Reconceptualized
Thus according to Quine, our linguistic conventions must either include the infinite
number of truths of the form ‘(Sentence 1) and (Sentence 2) implies (Sentence 2)’,
or this single, general convention, in which case we need logic in the metalanguage
to derive all its instances.
But notice that the same objection applies to the possibility of grammatical
conventions in language. We either need to know of the infinite number of
grammatical instances of the form ‘(Subject) is a (Predicate)’, or we would need
metalinguistic rules of substitution to derive its instances from the general
grammatical convention. But we evidently do not need such additional rules to
speak, because the very scheme is a ‘production rule’. The sole function of such a
rule in a natural language is to generate instances. Likewise, logical schemes are rules
which guide the production of logical truths. Thus it is not the case that we need to
presuppose logic in a meta-language to derive instances from our logical scheme. It
is inappropriate to seek all the forms and distinctions of formal languages in natural
languages, which, for example, already differ in being their own meta-languages.
In fact, truths of the form ‘A&B implies B’ are not likely to depend on the above
sentential scheme, but on the rules governing the use of the word ‘and’. These rules
are likely to be semantic rules linking ‘and’ with ‘combine’, ‘join’, and ‘put together’,
that is with the conjunctive meaning of ‘and’. These semantic rules imply that the
consequences of ‘A&B’ are the consequnces of ‘A’ combined with those of ‘B’.
Quine’s objection is therefore dismissed in that it does not apply to natural
languages, and imposes an overly restrictive role on general conventions. On the
other hand he is right to say that we will not find all the truths of mathematics and
logic represented literally as linguistic rules and conventions.
Although Quine is critical of conventionalism in logic, he regards its potential as
a philosophy of mathematics quite differently.
For set theory the linguistic doctrine has seemed less empty; in set theory,
moreover, convention in quite the ordinary sense seems to be pretty much
what goes on. Conventionalism has a serious claim to attention in the
philosophy of mathematics, if only because of set theory.
(Quine, 1966, page 108)
33
The Philosophy of Mathematics Education
E. Empiricism
3. Quasi-empiricism
34
The Philosophy of Mathematics Reconceptualized
and have done, with all the imperfections inherent in any human activity or creation.
Quasi-empiricism represents a ‘new direction in the philosophy of mathematics’
(Tymoczko, 1986), because of the primacy it accords to mathematical practice.
Supporters of this view include Davis (1972), Hallett (1979), Hersh (1979),
Tymoczko (1979) and at least in part, Putnam (1975). A preliminary sketch of the
quasi-empiricist view of mathematics is as follows.
Mathematics is a dialogue between people tackling mathematical problems.
Mathematicians are fallible and their products, including concepts and proofs, can
never be considered final or perfect, but may require renegotiation as standards of
rigour change, or as new challenges or meanings emerge. As a human activity,
mathematics cannot be viewed in isolation from its history and its applications in the
sciences and elsewhere. Quasi-empiricism represents ‘a renaissance of empiricism in
the recent philosophy of mathematics’ (Lakatos, 1967).
2. Mathematics is hypothetico-deductive
Mathematics is acknowledged to be a hypothetico-deductive system, like the widely
accepted conception of empirical science due to Popper (1959). As in science, the
emphasis in such a system is not on the transmission of truth from true premises to
conclusions (the absolutist view), but on the re-transmission of falsity from falsified
conclusions (‘falsifiers’) to hypothetical premises. Since axiomatic theories are
formalizations of previously existing informal mathematical theories, their potential
falsifiers are the informal theorems of the pre-existing theory, (in addition to formal
contradictions). The existence of such a (informal theorem) falsifier shows that the
axiomatization has not validly expressed the informal theory, i.e. its source (Lakatos, 1978).
3. History is central
The epistemological task of the philosophy of mathematics is not simply to answer
the question ‘how is (any) mathematical knowledge possible?’, but to account for the
actual mathematical knowledge that exists. Thus, the philosophy of mathematics is
35
The Philosophy of Mathematics Education
indissolubly linked with the history of mathematics, since the latter is the history of
the evolution of mathematical knowledge.
36
The Philosophy of Mathematics Reconceptualized
37
The Philosophy of Mathematics Education
38
The Philosophy of Mathematics Reconceptualized
39
The Philosophy of Mathematics Education
thesis are logically independent, in that the rejection of one has no logical
implications for the other. Lakatos seems to be unaware of this distinction.
Sixth, Lakatos’ quasi-empiricist philosophy of mathematics provides grounds that
are necessary hut not sufficient for establishing mathematical knowledge. Examples
can be found of mathematical knowledge that after development and reformulation,
following the general pattern of Lakatos’ heuristic, is still not incorporated into the
body of accepted mathematical knowledge. Consider, as a fictional counterexample,
the idiosyncratic mathematics that may be developed by a group of mystics, sharing
a set of conventions and norms, including the basis of their critical methodology,
which is peculiar to themselves. The fact that this group’s mathematical creations
survive their process of proofs and refutations does not give them general acceptance.
To rule out such examples, quasi-empiricism requires the assumption of a shared
basis for its critical methodology, if there is to be universal agreement on its
outcomes. In effect, this is the assumption of the use of a standard logic, and of its
validity.
Lastly, there is no systematic exposition of quasi-empiricism, putting forward its
theses in detail, and anticipating and rebutting objections to it. Lakatos’ publications
on the philosophy of mathematics comprise reconstructed historical case studies and
polemical writings.
Overall, it can be seen that the major defects of quasi-empiricism are sins of
omission, rather than of commission. The above critique, admittedly from a
sympathetic viewpoint, discloses no fundamental flaw or defect. Rather it indicates a
needed research programme, namely to develop quasi-empiricism systematically and
fill the gaps.
40
The Philosophy of Mathematics Reconceptualized
Notes
1 ‘Formal absolutism’ is my term, in place of Confrey’s ‘absolutism’, to avoid ambiguity. Confrey also
has a third category of ‘conceptual change’ theories, corresponding to fallibilism and drawing heavily
on Lakatos (1976).
2 Wittgenstein’s conventionalism is more radical than the account given in the chapter, although the
selective account presented there can be considered independently of some of his other views.
Dummett (1959) terms it a ‘full blooded conventionalism’, because all of the ‘truths’ of mathematics
and logic, not just the axioms, are direct expressions of linguistic conventions. Consequently,
Wittgenstein denies that mathematics has any logical foundations, it rests instead on the rules of
actual practice, both linguistic and mathematical. He claims that every time we accept a new
theorem, we accept a new rule of language. He also holds a very strict constructivist view of
mathematics known as ‘strict finitism’, and thus rejects even more of classical mathematics than the
intuitionists. Dummett (1959) criticizes some of these views.
3 Considered as an empirical hypothesis about the development of mathematics, Lakatos’ thesis has its
limitations. It is based on a single case study from nineteenth century mathematics, the Euler
conjecture (perhaps two, counting uniform continuity). In other domains, such as number theory,
conjectures concerning well defined concepts (not needing redefinition, ‘monster barring’, etc) may
be proposed in final form, simply needing proofs (for example, Ramanujan’s conjectures proved by
Hardy and Littlewood). In yet further domains, such as axiomatic set theory, it may not be possible
to distinguish sharply between substance (concepts) and form (proofs), as Lakatos does in his case
studies. See my review of Lakatos (1976) in Mathematical Reviews for further elaboration of this point.
41
3
1. Social Constructivism1
42
Social Constructivism
2. Publication is necessary (but not sufficient) for subjective knowledge to become objective
mathematical knowledge
When an individual’s subjective mathematical knowledge production enters the
public domain through publication, it is eligible to become objective knowledge.
This will depend on its acceptance, but first it must be physically represented (in
print, electronically, in writing, or as the spoken word). (Here knowledge is
understood to include not only statements, but also their justification, typically in the
form of informal proofs).
43
The Philosophy of Mathematics Education
5. The objective criteria for criticizing published mathematical knowledge are based on
objective knowledge of language, as well as mathematics
The criteria depend to a large extent on shared mathematical knowledge, but
ultimately they rest on common knowledge of language, that is, on linguistic
conventions (the conventionalist view of the basis of knowledge). These too are
socially accepted, and hence objective. Thus both published mathematical knowledge
and the lingusitic conventions on which its justification rests are objective knowledge.
44
Social Constructivism
Additions can be new conjectures or proofs, which may include new concepts or
definitions. They can also be new applications of existing mathematics. Restructuring
contributions may be new concepts or theorems that generalize or otherwise link two
or more previously existing parts of mathematical knowledge. Contributions that
reproduce existing mathematics are typically textbooks or advanced expositions.
Two immediate problem areas arise from this brief account. First of all, there is the
identification of objectivity with the social or socially accepted. To identify the
immutable and enduring objectivity of the objects and truths of mathematics with
something as mutable and arbitrary as socially accepted knowledge does, initially,
seem problematic. However we have already established that all mathematical
knowledge is fallible and mutable. Thus many of the traditional attributes of
objectivity, such as its enduring and immutable nature, are already dismissed. With
them go many of the traditional arguments for objectivity as a super-human ideal.
Following Bloor (1984) we shall adopt a necessary condition for objectivity, social
acceptance, to be its sufficient condition as well. It remains to show that this
identification preserves the properties that we expect of objectivity.
Secondly, there is the problem of the proximity of social constructivism to
sociological or other empirical accounts of mathematics. Since it is quasi-empirical,
and has the task of accounting for the nature of mathematics including mathematical
practice, in a fully descriptive fashion, the boundary between mathematics and other
disciplines is weakened. By removing traditional philosophical barriers these
consequences bring the philosophy of mathematics closer to the history and sociology
of mathematics (and psychology too, concerning subjective knowledge). Thus there is
the danger of social constructivism straying into the provinces of history, sociology or
psychology.We saw that Lakatos (1976) conflates his theory of the historical evolution
of mathematical knowledge with his philosophical account of the genesis of
mathematical knowledge. Thus there is a real danger of conflating empirical with
philosophical accounts of mathematics, which social constructivism must avoid.
45
The Philosophy of Mathematics Education
We can call the physical world ‘world 1’, the world of our conscious
experiences ‘world 2’, and the world of the logical contents of books,
libraries, computer memories, and suchlike ‘world 3’.
(Popper, 1979, p. 74)
Here is the theory: it is that objectivity is social. What I mean by saying that
objectivity is social is that the impersonal and stable character that attaches
to some of our beliefs, and the sense of reality that attaches to their
reference, derives from these beliefs being social institutions.
I am taking it that a belief that is objective is one that does not belong
to any individual. It does not fluctuate like a subjective state or a personal
preference. It is not mine or yours, but can be shared. It has an external
thing-like aspect to it.
(Bloor, 1984, page 229).
Bloor argues that Popper’s world 3 can defensibly and fruitfully be identified with
the social world. He also argues that not only is the three-fold structure of Popper’s
theory preserved under this transformation, but so are the connections between the
three worlds. Naturally, the social interpretation does not preserve the meaning that
Popper attaches to objectivity, who regards the logical character of theories, proofs
and arguments sufficient to guarantee objectivity in an idealistic sense. Despite this,
the social view is able to account for most, if not all, features of objectivity: the
autonomy of objective knowledge, its external thing-like character (presumably the
original meaning of ‘object’-ivity), and its independence from any knowing subject’s
subjective knowledge. For the social view sees objective knowledge, like culture,
developing autonomously in keeping with tacitly accepted rules, and not subject to
the arbitrary dictates of individuals. Since objective knowledge and rules exist
outside individuals (in the community), they seem to have an object-like and
independent existence.
46
Social Constructivism
Thus it can be seen that the social view accounts for many of the necessary
characteristics of objectivity. Beyond this, it is worth remarking that Bloor’s social view
of objectivity explains and accounts for objectivity. In contrast traditional views
(including Popper’s) elaborate on, or at best define objectivity (intensively or extensively),
but never account for or explain objectivity. For the autonomous, independent existence
of objective knowledge is traditionally shown to be necessary, without any explanation
of what objectivity is, or how objective knowledge can emerge from subjective human
knowledge. In contrast, the social view of objectivity is able to offer an account of the
basis and nature of objectivity and objective knowledge.
One immediate problem the social view must face is that of accounting for the
necessity of logical and mathematical truth. The answer given by Bloor (1983,1984),
and adopted here, is that this necessity (understood in a fallibilist sense) rests on
linguistic conventions and rules, as Wittgenstein proposes. This is the full
conventionalist account of the basis of logic and mathematical knowledge.
Given the centrality of the role of objective knowledge, I wish to argue that the role of
subjective mathematical knowledge must also be acknowledged, or else the overall
account of mathematics will be incomplete. For subjective knowledge is needed to
account for the origins of new mathematical knowledge, as well as, according to the
theory proposed, the re-creation and sustainment of existing knowledge. Since objective
knowledge is social, and not a self-subsistent entity existing in some ideal realm, then
like all aspects of culture this knowledge must be reproduced and transmitted from
47
The Philosophy of Mathematics Education
generation to generation (admittedly with the aid of artefacts, such as text books).
According to the social constructivist account, subjective knowledge is what sustains
and renews objective knowledge, whether it be of mathematics, logic or language.Thus
subjective knowledge plays a central part in the proposed philosophy of mathematics.
Having said this, it must be acknowledged that the treatment of subjective as well
as objective knowledge, in the proposed theory, is at odds with much modern
thought in philosophy, and in the philosophy of mathematics, as we have seen
(barring intuitionism, which we have rejected). For example, Popper (1959) has
distinguished very carefully between the ‘Context of discovery’ and the ‘context of
justification’ in science. He regards the latter context as being subject to logical
analysis, and thus being the proper concern of philosophy. The former context,
however, concerns empirical matters, and therefore is the proper concern of
psychology, and not of logic or philosophy.
Anti-psychologism, the view that subjective knowledge—or at least its
psychological aspects—is unfitted for philosophical treatment, rests on the following
argument. Philosophy consists of logical analysis, including methodological problems
such as the general conditions for the possibility of knowledge. Such inquiry is a
priori, and is wholly independent of any particular empirical knowledge. Subjective
issues are of necessity psychological issues, since they of necessity refer to the
contents of individual minds. But such matters, and psychology in general, are
empirical. Therefore, because of this category difference (the a priori versus the
empirical realm) subjective knowledge cannot be the concern of philosophy.4
This argument is rejected here on two grounds. First of all, a powerful critique of
absolutism, and hence of the possibility of certain a priori knowledge has been mounted
(Chapter 1). On this basis all so-called a priori knowledge, including logic and
mathematics, depends for its justification on quasi-empirical grounds. But this
effectively destroys the unique categorical distinction between a priori knowledge and
empirical knowledge. Thus this distinction cannot be used to deny the applicability of
the a priori philosophical methods of objective knowledge to subjective knowledge, on
the grounds that the latter is empirically tainted. For now we see that all knowledge,
including objective knowledge, is empirically (or rather quasi-empirically) tainted.
The second argument, which is independent of the first, is as follows. In
discussing subjective knowledge it is not proposed to discuss the specific contents of
individuals’ minds, nor specific empirical psychological theories of the mind under
the guise of philosophy. Rather the intention is to discuss the possibility of subjective
knowledge in general, and what can be concluded about its possible nature on the
basis of logical reasoning alone (given a number of theoretical assumptions). This is a
legitimate philosophical activity, just as the philosophy of science can legitimately
reflect on an empirical realm, namely science, without therefore being an empirical
realm itself. Thus subjective knowledge is a proper matter for philosophical inquiry.
Indeed, in discussing belief or the knowing subject, this is precisely what
epistemologists such as Sheffler (1965), Woozley (1949), Chisholm (1966) and indeed
Popper (1979), are considering. Further back, epistemology has traditionally
considered subjective knowledge, at least from the time of Descartes (and probably
48
Social Constructivism
further back to Plato), through the British empiricists Locke, Berkeley and Hume,
via Kant to the present day. Thus subjective knowledge is a legitimate area of
philosophical enquiry, based on a substantial philosophical tradition.
Although the claim that the consideration of subjective knowledge is
psychologistic is thus refuted, it is acknowledged that there are real dangers and
legitimate concerns arising from the philosophical treatment of subjective
knowledge. For it makes it easier to commit the error of using psychologistic
reasoning in philosophy, that is reasoning based on psychological belief of necessity as
opposed to logical argument. Furthermore, the distinction between subjective and
objective knowledge is a vital one to maintain, both for social constructivism, and for
philosophy in general. These are two genuinely distinct domains of knowledge.
For these reasons, in the explication of the social constructivist philosophy of
mathematics, the domains of objective and subjective knowledge will be treated
separately. The objective aspect of this philosophy is independent of the subjective
aspect in terms of its justification. So the reader wary of psychologism can follow the
objective aspect of social constructivism without qualms (concerning this issue, at least).
A. Objectivity in Mathematics
49
The Philosophy of Mathematics Education
mathematics, that is the basis for the autonomous existence of the objects of
mathematics. We consider first the substratum which provides the foundation for
objectivity in mathematics, namely language.
50
Social Constructivism
We cannot question the fact that ‘A and B’ entails ‘A’ or that 1+1=2 without
withdrawing some of the possibility of communication. We can only get around this
temporarily, by circumscribing a small domain of language use, and exposing and
questioning some of the rules governing its use.We may ‘freeze’ and thus suspend some
of these rules to dissect them. But in our other language games, including our meta-
language, these rules remain in force. And when our inquiry moves on, the rules
become reanimated, and reassume their living certitude. Like a boat in mid voyage, we
may tentatively remove a plank from the hull and question its role. But unless we
reinstate it before we continue our inspection, the whole enterprise may founder.
This is the general argument for the necessity of the rules associated with language
use. These rules codify the shared linguistic behaviour which allows the possibility of
communication. In detail, these rules depend on the particular terms and rules of
mathematics and logic embedded in our language. We consider these next.
Our natural language contains informal mathematics as a subset, including such
terms as ‘square’, ‘circle’, ‘shape’, ‘zero’, ‘one’, ‘two’, ‘number’, ‘add’, ‘less’, ‘greater’,
‘equals’, ‘set’, ‘element’, ‘infinite’ and so on. Some of these terms are directly
applicable to the shared world of our experience, and natural language includes rules
and conventions on how to apply these terms. In this sense, these terms resemble
those of science, for their basic terms are learned together. Such terms allow us to
describe events and objects in the world by classification and quantification. The
intended interpretations of informal mathematics, such as these, are implicit in the
semantics of natural language (which often provides multiple meanings for these
terms). In addition, the inter-relations between terms are established by linguistic
conventions and rules. Thus, for example, ‘one is less than two’ and ‘an infinite set
has more than two elements’ are both warranted on the basis of the semantic rules of
language. As was stated, the elementary applications of mathematics are also built into
the rules of linguistic use. The presence of these two types of rule, those concerning
the interconnections of terms and their intended applications in the world, account
for much of the implicit mathematical knowledge we unconsciously acquire with
linguistic competence.
This account is grossly oversimplified in one sense. For it appears to assume a
single external world. In fact, there are many overlapping domains of linguistic
discourse, many language games, each with their own shared worlds of reference.
Some relate to what is socially accepted by the majority as objective reality, others
less so, and some are wholly fictional or mythological. Each contains an informal
theory, a set of relationships between the entities that inhabit them. What they all
share is social agreement on the rules relating to discourse about them.
Many of our linguistic utterances, whatever ‘language game’ we are engaged in, are
laden with mathematical concepts, or highly ‘mathematized’ (Davis and Hersh, 1986).
For an example of the embeddedness of mathematics in every day language use,
consider the Zen koan ‘What is the sound of one hand clapping?’.This is based on the
linguistic knowledge that it takes two hands to clap, one is half of two, but half the
number of hands does not give half the amount of sound (I focus here on
mathematical content, and not on the purpose of the koan which is through cognitive
51
The Philosophy of Mathematics Education
challenge to induce satori). Overall, I wish to claim that natural language such as
English (and Japanese, apparently), and even more so informal mathematical language,
is rich with implicit mathematical rules, meanings and conventions. These rules, such
as ‘two is the successor of one’, necessitate the acceptance of truths, such as ‘1+1=2’.
52
Social Constructivism
natural language usage. This is the change that led Russell to claim that Boole
originated pure mathematics. Does this mean that the unique meanings of
mathematics have been lost? On the contrary, it means that we have added new,
more abstract language games, to those associated with the mathematical part of
natural language.
This notion of a range of language games encompassing the mathematical part of
natural language allows a possible objection to be addressed. This concerns the claim
that since the basis of mathematical and logical knowledge is inherent in natural
language usage, then all of mathematical knowledge must be inherent in natural
language. But this is patently false, the only legitimate conclusion from these
premises about the sum of all mathematical knowledge is that its basis, and not the
whole itself, is inherent in language usage. Given this basis, more and more new
language games embodying mathematical meaning and knowledge can be (and are)
developed, without necessitating the corresponding enlargement of the linguistic
basis. For specialist formal and informal mathematical discourses may be enlarged,
resting on the same natural language basis.
The mathematical knowledge embedded in language usage provides a basis for
informal (and ultimately formal) mathematical knowledge. The meanings and rules
embodied in this knowledge can be described in terms of a series of language games.
These games provide the basis of further, more refined language games, which abstract,
refine, extend and develop their rules and meanings. Thus a loose hierarchy can be
posited, with the mathematical knowledge embedded in natural language making up
the base. On this is built a series of language games embodying informal and ultimately
formal mathematical knowledge. In the upper reaches of the hierarchy informal
mathematical systems become formalized into axiomatized theories. At this level the
rules of the games or systems become almost completely explicit. In this way the
knowledge of mathematics implicit in language provides a basis for all mathematical
knowledge.Truths embodied in and vouchsafed by linguistic usage are reflected up the
hierarchy to justify elementary assumptions adopted in mathematics. The same is true
for the assumptions and rules of logic. In the next section we will explore the role of
such assumptions, in the justification of mathematical knowledge.
In this section we have seen that linguistic convention and usage provides
mathematical knowledge with its secure foundations. Similarly, it provides grounds
for change in mathematics, as linguistic conventions and usage develop over time.
Mathematics, like every other realm of knowledge depends essentially on tacit
linguistic assumptions. Fallibilism forces us to admit their presence, as well as their
changing nature, over the passage of time.
53
The Philosophy of Mathematics Education
54
Social Constructivism
logical axioms and rules of inference. These were justified, in the previous section,
as linguistic conventions, which are a part of the rules of meaning and use inherent
in our grasp of language. Thus, it is argued, the whole body of mathematical
knowledge is warranted by proofs, whose basis and security rests on linguistic
knowledge and rules.6
Objective mathematical definitions and truths specify the rules and properties
determining the objects of mathematics. This confers on them as much of an
objective existence as that of any social concepts. Just as universal linguistic terms,
such as ‘noun’, ‘sentence’, or ‘translation’ have a social existence, so too the terms
and objects of mathematics have the properties of autonomous, self-subsistent
objects. The objects of mathematics inherit a fixity (i.e., a stability of definition) from
the objectivity of mathematical knowledge, entailing in turn their own permanency
and objective existence. Their objectivity is the ontological commitment that
inevitably accompanies the acceptance of certain forms of discourse.
55
The Philosophy of Mathematics Education
Of course, this is not the end of the matter, for discourses commit us to all
manner of entities, from chairs, tables and cars, to ghosts, angels and souls. It cannot
be claimed that these are all on a par. But likewise, the objects of mathematics vary
from the relatively concrete, embedded in the natural language descriptions of the
sensible world, to the abstract theoretical entities of mathematics e.g., the least
inaccessible cardinal (Jech, 1971), many steps removed from this basis. However, most
of the objects of mathematics have more reality than the objects in some discourses,
such as the fantasy creatures of Tolkien’s (1954) Middle Earth. For they are the result
of social negotiation, not just the product of a single individual’s imagination.
Many of the elementary terms and concepts of mathematics have concrete
applications and examples in the world. For they are part of a language developed to
describe the physical (and social) world. Thus such terms as ‘one’, ‘two’, ‘ten’, ‘line’,
‘angle’, ‘square’, ‘triangle’, and so on, describe properties of objects or sets of objects,
in the world. Other terms such as ‘add’, ‘subtract’, ‘divide’, ‘measure’, ‘rotate’, and so
on, describe actions that can be performed on concrete objects. The denotations of
these terms, gain ‘objecthood’ by their concrete applications in objective reality.7 Yet
more terms, such as ‘equation’, ‘identity’, and ‘inequality’ refer to linguistic entities.
Each of these sets of terms describes aspects of objective reality, whether external or
linguistic, and thus provides a concrete basis for a ‘mathematical reality’. On this basis
further mathematical ter ms, such as ‘number’, ‘operation’, ‘shape’, and
‘transformation’, are defined, one level removed from concrete reference. At higher
and higher levels, further mathematical terms, increasingly abstract, apply to those
below them. Thus through such an hierarchy virtually all mathematical terms have
definitions and denote objects at lower levels. These denotations behave exactly like
objectively existing, autonomous objects. Thus the objects of mathematics are
objective in the same way as the knowledge of mathematics. They are public
linguistic objects, some concrete but most abstract.
An example is provided by algorithms. These denote precisely specified sequences
of actions, procedures which are as concrete as the terms they operate on. They
establish connections between the objects they operate on, and their products. They
are a part of the rich structure that interconnects, and thus helps to implicitly define,
the terms, and hence the objects of mathematics.
This account may seem to fall short of providing all that is required for objective
existence. However, the analogy between the above conceptual hierarchy of mathematics
and an empirical scientific theory should be noted. For although defined analogously,
the theoretical entities of theoretical science are understood to have an autonomous
existence. Hempel (1952) likens a scientific theory to a net. Knots represent terms, and
threads represent sentences of the theory (definitions, theoretical statements, or
interpretative links) which both bind together the net and anchor it to the bedrock of
observation. The theoretical terms of science, such as ‘neutrino’, ‘gravitational field’,
‘quark’, ‘strangeness’ and ‘big bang’ correspond to the abstract entities of mathematics,
in the analogy. The difference being that only concrete mathematical terms have an
empirical reference, whereas the theoretical terms of science are taken to denote the
physical entities whose empirical existence is posited by the current theory.
56
Social Constructivism
57
The Philosophy of Mathematics Education
58
Social Constructivism
For adequacy, social constructivism must account for the ‘unreasonable effectiveness
of mathematics in science’ (Wigner, 1960). It is able to account for the applicability
of mathematics on two grounds: (1) mathematics is founded on our empirical natural
language; and (2) the quasi-empiricism of mathematics means that it is not so very
different from empirical science anyway.
First of all, we have already argued that mathematical knowledge rests on the rules
and conventions of natural language. We have seen that there is a rich mathematical
vocabulary directly applicable to the world of our experience, and natural language
includes rules and conventions on how to apply these terms. Many of these belong
both to mathematics and to science, and allow us to use classification and
quantification in describing events and objects in the world (via conjectured
explanations). Everyday and scientific uses of natural language are a key feature of its
role, and in such uses the embedded mathematical concepts play an essential part.
Thus the linguistic basis for mathematics, as well as the other functions language
performs for mathematics, provides interpretative links with real world phenomena.
In this way its linguistic roots provide mathematics with applications.
Secondly, we have accepted Lakatos’ argument that mathematics is a quasi-
empirical hypothetico-deductive system. In acknowledging this, we are admitting a
much closer link between mathematics and empirical science than the traditional
absolutist philosphies allow. This is reflected in the close resemblance between
mathematical theories and scientific theories, which we have observed. Both types of
theory contain relatively concrete exemplifiable or observational terms, and
theoretical terms, interconnected by a ‘net’ of links and relationships. Quine (1960)
even sees them both as interwoven in a single, connected fabric. In view of this
striking structural analogy, it is not surprising that some of the general structures and
methods of mathematics are imported into physical theories. Indeed, much of
empirical theory is wholly expressed in the language of mathematics. Likewise, it is
not surprising that many scientific problems, formulated in the language of
mathematics, become the stimulus for mathematical creation. The need for ever
better models of the world, as science advances, provides mathematics growth points
for development. The consequent cross-fertilization and interpenetration of science
and mathematics is a fact that the absolutist philosophical separation between a priori
and empirical knowledge has masked and mystified. In its origins and throughout its
development, mathematics has maintained contact with the physical world by
modelling it, often in conjunction with empirical science. In addition, the forces that
lead to generalization and integration in mathematical knowledge, described above,
ensure that the contact and influence of the empirical world on mathematics are not
merely marginal. The applicable theories within mathematics are subsumed into
more general theories, as mathematics is restructured and remade. By these means,
the applicability of mathematics extends to the central abstract theories of
mathematics, and not merely those on its periphery.
Overall, the applicability of mathematical knowledge is sustained by the close
59
The Philosophy of Mathematics Education
First of all, there is the problem of the relativism of mathematical knowledge and
truth. If, as is claimed, mathematical truth rests on social conventions, then it is both
arbitrary and relative. It is arbitrary since it rests on arbitrary beliefs, practices and
conventions. It is relative since it rests on the beliefs of one group of humans.
Consequently there is no need for other groups of humans, let alone other intelligent
creatures in the universe, to accept the necessity of mathematical knowledge, which
only holds relative to a particular culture at a particular period.
To answer this, I wish to question two presuppositions. These are first, the notion
that linguistic and mathematical conventions are arbitrary and mutable; and second,
the misconception that mathematical and logical knowledge are necessary and
immutable (although this was largely refuted in Chapter 1).
Arbitrariness
The arbitrariness of mathematics, in the account given, arises from the fact that
mathematical knowledge is founded on linguistic conventions and rules. There is no
necessity behind these rules, and they could have developed differently. This is
undeniable. But the fact remains that language operates within the tight constraints
imposed by physical reality and interpersonal communication. The conventions of
language can be formulated differently, but the purpose of language in providing a
functioning social description of the world remains constant. The shared rules and
conventions of language are a part of a naive empirical theory of the physical world
and social life. Thus, although every symbol in natural language is arbitrary, as the
choice of any sign must be, the relationship between reality and the overall model of
it, provided by language is not.
60
Social Constructivism
Although such modelling may not be the whole function of language, it provides
crucial external anchors for language that keep it functioning viably. To maintain this
viability, some of the logical rules of language appear to be necessary. For example,
White (1982) argues that the principle of contradiction is necessary for any assertion
to be made by means of language. For without the principle in operation there would
be simultaneous assertion and denial. But assertions are ruled out by denial. Now in
some language uses the principle might be relaxed for certain purposes, such as
describing a deity. However it is difficult to argue that a language could function
viably without some such rules. Thus although much of the formulation of language
rules and conventions may be arbitrary in detail, the need for viability reduces much
of the scope of the arbitrariness of language to inessential details. For example, the
differences between natural languages indicate areas of arbitrariness in their formulation.
Relativism
The definition of objectivity adopted opens social constructivism to the charge of
relativism. That is, it is just the knowledge of a particular group at a particular time.
This is true, but there are two mitigating circumstances which remove much of the
force of this criticism. As we have seen, mathematics through language must provide
a viable description of aspects of empirical and social reality. Thus the relativism of
mathematics is reduced by its anchoring via these applications. In other words, both
mathematics and language are highly constrained by the need to describe, quantify
and predict events in the physical and human worlds effectively. In addition,
mathematics is constrained by its growth and development through the inner logic
of conjectures, proofs and refutations, described above. Thus mathematics not only
has its feet rooted in reality, but its upper parts have to survive the rigorous public
procedures of justification and criticism, based on the thorough-going application of
a small number of principles. Thus mathematical knowledge is relativistic knowledge
in that its objectivity is based in social agreement. But its relativism does not make it
equal or interchangeable with other social belief systems, unless they satisfy these
same two criteria.
Critics of the possibility of relativism in mathematics claim that alternative
mathematics or logic is inconceivable, which confirms the necessity and unique
status of mathematics and logic. This raises the question: what would an alternative
mathematics (or logic) look like? Bloor (1976) asks this question, and illustrates his
answer with alternative notions of number, calculus, and so on from the history of
mathematics. A critic’s reply to this might be that although our conceptions have
evolved and changed throughout history, they were just steps on the path to the
necessary modern notions. If the questionable teleological aspect of this claim is
ignored, then it is necessary to exhibit simultaneous competing alternatives for
mathematics, to answer the criticism. However, a further question needs to be asked:
how different does an alternative mathematics need to be to count as alternative (and
hence to refute the uniqueness claim)?
61
The Philosophy of Mathematics Education
The answer I propose is that an alternative mathematics (or logic) should be based
on concepts defined differently, with different means of establishing truths, and
which results in a very different body of truths. Furthermore, if the alternative is to
be taken seriously, there should be a respectable body of mathematicians who adhere
to the alternative, and who reject standard mathematics. This, in my view, is an
adequately strong characterization of an alternative form of academic (as opposed to
culturally embedded) mathematics. Strong as it is, it is not difficult to satisfy this
requirement. Intuitionist mathematics fits the requirement perfectly. Intuitionist
concepts, from the logical connectives ‘not’, ‘there exists’, to the concepts of ‘set’,
‘spread’ and the ‘continuum’ are quite different in meaning and in logical and
mathematical outcomes, from the corresponding classical concepts, where they exist.
Intuitionist axioms and principles of proof are also different, with the rejection of the
classical Law of the Excluded Middle, ‘-P↔P’, and ‘-(x)-A ↔(Ex)A’. Intuitionist
mathematics has its own body of truths including the countability of the continuum,
the Fan Theorem and the Bar Theorem, which do not appear in classical
mathematics, as well as rejecting the bulk of classical mathematics. Finally, since the
time of Brouwer, intuitionism has always had a cadre of respected adherent
mathematicians, committed to intuitionism (or constructivism) and who reject
classical mathematics (e.g. A.Heyting, H.Weyl, E.Bishop, A.Troelstra). Thus there is an
alternative mathematics, which includes an alternative logic.
This century there has been an explosion of other alternative or ‘deviant’ logics,
including many-valued logics, Boolean-valued logic, modal logic, deontic logic and
quantum logic. These show that further alternatives to logic are not only possible, but
exist. (However these deviant logics may not satisfy the last criterion given above, i.e.
the adherence of a group of mathematicians, who reject classical logic).
The example of intuitionism shows that classical mathematics is neither necessary
nor unique, for an alternative is not only possible, but it exists. It also shows that
there are alternatives to classical logic. The example also demonstrates the relativism
of mathematics, subject to the constraints discussed above, since there are two
mathematical communities (classical and intuitionist) with their own, opposing
notions and standards of mathematical truth and proof. In previous chapters the
absolutist view of mathematics as a body of immutable and necessary truth was
refuted, and a fallibilist view argued in its place. This weakened the claim of necessity
for mathematics. This has now been supplemented with an example of a genuine
alternative, dispelling any possible claims of uniqueness or necessity for mathematics.
62
Social Constructivism
there is conflict in this community? Does this mean that a new piece of mathematics
can hover on the boundary between subjective and objective knowledge?
To answer the main point first: it would be inappropriate in a philosophical account
to specify any social groups or social dynamics, even as they impinge upon the
acceptance of objective knowledge. For this is the business of history and sociology,
and in particular, the history of mathematics and the sociology of its knowledge. The
claim that there is a social mechanism involved in objectivity and in the acceptance
of mathematical knowledge, and a conceptual analysis and elaboration of it remains
within the province of philosophy. The importation of concepts from history and
sociology to develop this theory, valuable as this might be, takes the discussion
outside the philosophy of mathematics. Thus this is not a valid criticism.
The secondary criticisms do hold some problems for social constructivism. If
there is simultaneous social acceptance of different sets of mathematical knowledge,
as was explored in section A above, then they both constitute objective mathematical
knowledge.
The transition of mathematical knowledge from subjective to objective
knowledge may benefit from further clarification. It needs to be made clear that
there is an intermediate state, which is neither. Subjective mathematical knowledge
resides in the mind of an individual, possibly supported by external representation.
For individuals developing subjective knowledge often do so with the aid of visual,
oral or other representations. Already such representations mean that there is a public
aspect supporting the individual’s subjective knowledge. When fully represented in
the public domain, it is no longer subjective knowledge as such, although the
originating individual may have corresponding subjective knowledge. Public
representations of knowledge are just that. They are not subjective knowledge, and
need not be (or represent, to be precise) objective knowledge either. However, they
have the potential to lead to the latter, when they are socially accepted.
Strictly speaking, public representations of knowledge are not knowledge at all,
for they consist only of symbols, and meanings and assertions have to be projected
into them by understanding subjects. Whereas knowledge is meaningful. This is
consistent with the view adopted in communications theory, that signals have to be
coded, transmitted and then decoded. During the transmission phase, that is when
coded, signals have no meaning. This has to be constructed during decoding.
It is convenient to adopt the current (but strictly speaking false) usage of
identifying public representations of objective knowledge (coded signals) with the
knowledge itself, and speaking as if the representation embodied information and
meaning. Such an attribution of meaning only works if it is assumed that the
appropriate community share the decoding knowledge. In the case of mathematical
knowledge this consists of knowledge of natural language and additional knowledge
of mathematics.
These then are some to the essential presuppositions about the social groups on
which social constructivism depends.
63
The Philosophy of Mathematics Education
64
Social Constructivism
does not literally contain all the basic truths and rules of mathematics and logic.
Rather it embodies the basic meanings, rules and conventions, which in refined and
elaborated form, provide the elementary truths and rules of mathematics and logic.
The account offered is superior in scope to that of traditional philosophies of
mathematics, because it provides an objective basis, warranting these elementary
assumptions. At best, other philosophies offer intuition (intuitionism, formalism,
platonism) or induction (empiricism), for these assumptions, if they offer any basis
at all.
3. Social constructivism conflates the contexts of discovery and justification, and commits the
error of psychologism.
By challenging the widespread assumption that the business of philosophy is only
with the context of justification, and not that of discovery, social constructivism may
seem to lay itself open to this charge. The account given acknowledges the
importance of these concepts, and distinguishes carefully between the two contexts,
as well as between the different proper concerns of philosophy, history, psychology
and sociology. However it is argued that on adequacy grounds the philosophy of
mathematics must account for the development and genesis of mathematical
knowledge, albeit from a philosophical perspective, as is accepted analogously in the
philosophy of science. It is also argued that subjective knowledge is a legitimate area
of philosophical enquiry, and need not lead to psychologism. Subjective thought and
knowledge must be included in a social constructivist account because it is the fount
of new mathematical knowledge. Naturally it must be treated philosophically, and
not psychologically, to avoid psychologism.
Notes
1 Other authors refer to mathematics as a social construct, notably Sal Restive (1985, 1988), in
developing a sociology of mathematical knowledge. Although approaching mathematics from
another perspective, he offers a range of insights compatible with the philosophy proposed here. This
is considered further in chapter 5.
2 Ideas from constructivist epistemology and learning theory, due to Glasersfeld, Piaget and others,
have also contributed to social constructivism.
3 Knowledge reproducing cycles occur also in sociology and education, but are concerned with the
genesis and reproduction of knowledge, not its justification (see Chapters 11 and 12). Such a cycle
is relatively novel in philosophical studies of mathematics, because it treats the genesis and social
origins of knowledge, as well as its justification. The approach adopted may be seen as part of a new
naturalistic approach to the philosophy of mathematics, typified by Kitcher (1984), and other
authors.
4 ‘Twentieth-century epistemology has been characterized by an attitude of explicit distaste for
theories of knowledge which describe the psychological capacities and activities of the subject. This
attitude has fostered an apsychologistic approach to knowledge…present in the writings of Russell,
Moore, Ayer, C.I.Lewis, R.Chisholm, R.Firth, W.Sellars and K.Lehrer, and is presupposed by the
discussions of science offered by Carnap, Hempel and Nagel.’ (Kitcher, 1984, page 14)
5 Notice the analogy with the ‘replicability’ criterion for experimentation in science, which demands
65
The Philosophy of Mathematics Education
that results, for acceptance, should not be peculiar to a unique scientist, but should be replicable.
Likewise a mathematical proof not only has to be surveyable to others, but this survey must result
each time in acceptance.
6 One possible objection to this account is that there seems to be a gap between the implicit ‘truths’
embedded in natural language, and the more abstract and sophisticated logical and mathematical
assumptions required to warrant mathematical knowledge. The answer to this is that linguistic
competence is not defined by a static level of performance and knowledge. Linguistic competence
presupposes competence in performing certain functions in certain social situations. The mastery of
these different linguistic functions, which representing the mastery of different ‘language games’ in
different social contexts, represents different types of linguistic competence. This range of contexts
brings with it a range of ever sharper linguistic conventions and rules, and those interested in
mathematical knowledge will of necessity have mastered a range of sophisticated mathematical and
logical language games.
In addition, the relatively elementary notions of rationality (implication, and contradiction)
underpin the more refined notions of logic. This ensures coherence and means that the more
refined notions are extrapolations of, and not discontinuous with, the simpler notions. Thus I
am claiming that the ‘gap’ is self closing. Those with knowledge enough to participate in the
language games of warranting mathematical knowledge will have extended their linguistic rules
and truths to the required point. Should they fall short, they will have their usage, and rules,
extended.
7 By objective reality I am referring to the socially agreed features of the external world. I
acknowledge the basic ontological assumption implicit in using this phrase, that is the assumption
of the existence of a physical world (Popper’ s world 1). I also acknowledge the existence of
human beings, as the basis for a social view of objective knowledge. However, I do not concede
that this commits me to ontological assumptions about the particular, conventionally labelled
objects in the world, beyond the fact that there is social agreement on their existence and
objectivity.
8 In case it seems a weakness of the social constructivist view that it denies the absolute existence of
mathematical objects, it is worth noting some of consequences of the mathematical notion of
existence. The criterion for existence in mathematics is consistency. If a mathematical theory is
consistent, then there is a set of objects (a model) providing denotations for all its terms and
satisfying all the conditions of the theory. That is, these objects have mathematical existence. Thus, for
example, provided the theories of Peano Arithmetic, the Real Numbers and Zermelo-Fraenkel (ZF)
Set Theory are consistent (which is accepted), there are models satisfying them. Thus the Natural
Numbers, Real Numbers and the universe of sets can be said to exist, which already allows for an
unbelievable richness of entities. But worse is to come. The Generalized Lowenheim-Skolem
Theorem (Bell and Slomson, 1971) establishes that these theories have models of every infinite
cardinality. Thus countable models of both Real Number Theory and ZF set theory exist, as do
models of the natural numbers of every (infinite) size. These all exist in world 3. Social
constructivism denies the existence this unpredictable and undreamed of multitude of mathematical
entities. In contrast, the outcome of the platonist view of existence in mathematics would be to
populate the universe far more densely than merely putting infinitely many angels to dance on the
head of every pin. The question is, what does it mean to say that the objects in the platonist
ontology actually exist? Surely this is using the term ‘exist’ in a novel way. The social constructivist
response to these ontological problems is basically to adopt the traditional conceptualist solution, but
in a new social guise (Quine, 1948).
9 Russell’s (1902) criticism of Frege’s system was rational, i.e. logical, being based on logical features
of the system (namely its inconsistency). Kronecker’s criticism of Cantor’s set theory evidently was
not purely rational or logical, since it had strongly moral and religious undertones.
The Kuhn-Popper debate in the philosophy of science hinged on the issue of rational
versus irrational criticism of scientific theories, which is analogous to the point made here
concerning mathematics. Popper’s position is prescriptive, he posits falsification as a rational
criterion for the rejection of a scientific theory. Kuhn, on the other hand, proposes a more
descriptive philosophy of science, which while treating the growth of objective knowledge
acknowledges that rational features are neither necessary nor sufficient to account for theory
acceptance or rejection.
66
Social Constructivism
10 Alan Bishop has presented evidence that in some of the 350 languages to be found in Papua
and New Guinea the conceptual structure is markedly different from that presupposed by
elementary mathematics. For example in one language the same word is used to denote ‘up’,
‘top’, ‘surface’ and ‘area’, indicating a conceptual structure very different from English and
comparable languages.
67
4
1. Prologue
This chapter faces a difficult task: that of showing the relationship between subjective
and objective knowledge of mathematics in social constructivism. The task is difficult
for a number of reasons. It skirts the edge of psychologism, and it needs to conjoin
two different languages, theories and modes of thought that apply to two different
realms, the subjective and the objective. Beyond this, the epistemology underpinning
social constructivism is quite slippery to grasp, since it is claimed that there is no
realm where a determinate entity ‘knowledge’ basks in tranquillity. Knowledge,
perhaps analogous to consciousness, is seen as an immensely complex and ultimately
irreducible process of humankind dependent on the contributions of a myriad of
centres of activity, but also transcending them. Science fiction authors (Stapledon,
1937) and mystical philosophers (Chardin, 1966) have groped for a vision of how the
consciousnesses of individual human beings can meld into a greater whole. But these
provide too simplistic a vision to account for knowledge and culture as dynamic,
cooperative dances uniting millions of thinking and acting but separate human
beings. The seduction of idealism is great: to say that knowledge exists somewhere in
an ultimate form, possibly growing and changing, but that all our representations of
knowledge are but imperfect reflections. The pull to view human knowledge
attempts as parts of a convergent sequence that tends to a limit in another realm, is
almost irresistible.
Once these simplifying myths are rejected, as they are by social constructivism,
there is the complex task of accounting for knowledge. It is social, but where is the
social? Is it a moving dance, a cloud of pirouetting butterflies, which when caught is
no more? Books do not contain knowledge, according to this account. They may
contain sequences of symbols, carefully and intentionally arranged, but they do not
contain meaning. This has to be created by the reader, although books may guide the
reader to create new meanings. This is subjective knowledge, the unique creation of
each individual. Yet by some miracle of interaction, the way human beings use this
knowlege in their transactions fits together.
The concept of the individual, the knowing subject, in Western thought is
68
Social Constructivism and Subjective Knowledge
another problem. Since Locke, or earlier, the subject is a tabula rasa, and gradually
knowledge is inscribed on its blank page by experience and education. But the form
and content of mind cannot be separated like this, and there is no universal form of
knowledge that can be written in our minds. The view that follows is that
knowledge has to be created anew in the mind of every human being, and solely in
response to their active efforts to know. Consequently, objective knowledge is all the
while being born anew. Thus knowledge is more like a human body, with its every
cell being replaced cyclically, or like the river: never the same twice! This is why I
called the epistemology involved slippery!
These are some of the problems that the present chapter raises and tries to tackle.
How does the individual acquire knowledge of the external world? Human beings
have incoming sense impressions of the world, as well as being able to act physically
on the world, and thus in some measure are able to control aspects of the
environment. Clearly subjective knowledge is acquired on the basis of interaction
with the external world, both through incoming sense data and through direct
actions. What is also clear is that these interactions are necessary but not sufficient for
the acquisition of knowlege of the external world. For the sense data are particulars.
Whereas our knowledge is evidently general, since it includes general concepts
(universals), and it allows for anticipation and the prediction of regularities in our
experience. Therefore some further mechanism is required to account for the
generation of general knowledge of the world of our experience, on the basis of
particular items of information or experiences.
This is precisely the problem that the philosophy of science faces, but expressed at
the subjective level. Namely, how can we account for (and justify) theoretical
scientific knowledge on the basis of observations and experiment alone? The
solution proposed is the same. The development of subjective knowledge, like that of
science, is hypothetico-deductive. The answer proposed is that the minds of
individuals are active, conjecturing and predicting patterns in the flow of experience,
69
The Philosophy of Mathematics Education
and thus building theories of the nature of the world, although these may be
unconsciously made theories. These conjectures or theories serve as guides for action,
and when they prove inadequate, as inevitably they do, they are elaborated or
replaced by new theories that overcome the inadequacy or failing of the previous
theory. Thus our subjective knowledge of the external world consists of conjectures,
which are continually used, tested and replaced when falsified.
Thus the account of the formation of subjective knowledge is a recursive one.
Our knowledge of the world of our experience consists of private conjectures or
theories, which order the world of our experience. These theories are based on two
factors. First, our immediate experiences of the world, including interactions with it,
as perceived and filtered through our theories. Second, our previously existing
theories. Thus the formation of our subjective theories is recursive in that it depends
essentially on these theories, albeit in an earlier state.
This account mirrors that of Popper (1959), but at the level of subjective as
opposed to objective knowledge.2 However, it is clear that Popper intends his account
of science to apply only to objective knowledge, and furthermore, he has nothing to
say on the genesis of scientific theories. As a purely subjective view of knowledge, this
view is elaborated by Glasersfeld (1983, 1984, 1989) as ‘radical constructivism’.
‘The world we live in’ can be understood also as the world of our
experience, the world as we see, hear and feel it. This world does not consist
of ‘objective facts’ or ‘things-in-themselves’ but of such invariants and
constancies as we are able to compute on the basis of our individual
experience. To adopt this reading, however, is tantamount to adopting a
radically different scenario for the activity of knowing. From an explorer
who is condemned to seek ‘structural properties’ of an inaccessible reality,
the experiencing organism now turns into a builder of cognitive structures
intended to solve such problems as the organism perceives or conceives.
Fifty years ago, Piaget characterised this scenario as one could wish:
‘Intelligence organises the world by organising itself’ (Piaget, 1937). What
determines the value of the conceptual structures is their experimental
adequacy, their goodness of fit with experience, their viability as means for
the solving of problems, among which is, of course, the never-ending
problem of consistent organisation that we call understanding.
The world we live in, from the vantage point of this new perspective, is
always and necessarily the world as we conceptualize it. ‘Facts’, as Vico saw
long ago, are made by us and our way of experiencing, rather than given by
an independently existing objective world. But that does not mean that we
can make them as we like. They are viable facts as long as they do not clash
with experience, as long as they remain tenable in the sense that they
continue to do what we expect them to do.
(Glasersfeld, 1983, p. 50–51)
Constructivism is a theory of knowledge with roots in philosophy,
psychology and cybernetics. It asserts two main principles…(a) knowledge
70
Social Constructivism and Subjective Knowledge
is not passively received but actively built up by the cognizing subject; (b)
the function of cognition is adaptive and serves the organization of the
experiential world, not the discovery of ontological reality.
(Glasersfeld, 1989, page 162)
This view accounts for the development of subjective knowledge of the external
world. It explains how an individual constructs subjective knowledge, notably a
theoretical model of a portion of the external world which fits that portion, and how
this knowledge or model develops, improving the fit. It does this without
presupposing that we construct true knowledge matching3 the given portion of the
world, which would contradict much modern thought, especially in the philosophy
of science. Thus the theory provides an account of how external reality serves as a
constraint in the construction of subjective knowledge, a constraint that ensures the
continued viability of the knowledge. What the theory does not yet do, is to account
for the possibility of communication and agreement between individuals. For the
sole constraint of fitting the external world does not of itself prevent individuals from
having wholly different, incompatible even, subjective models of the world.
Such differences would seem inescapable. However, this is not the case. Suitably
elaborated, the social constructivist view also provides an account of the development
of knowledge of the world of people and social interaction, and the acquisition of
language. The very mechanism which improves the fit of subjective knowledge with
the world also accounts for the fit with the social world, including patterns of
linguistic use and behaviour. Indeed, the experiential world of the cognizing subject
which Glasersfeld refers to, does not differentiate between physical or social reality.
Thus the generation and adaptation of personal theories on the basis of sense data and
interactions equally applies to the social world, as the following account shows.
Individuals, from the moment of birth, receive sense impressions from, and
interact with, the external and social worlds. They also formulate subjective theories
to account for, and hence guide, their interactions with these realms. These theories
are continually tested through interaction with the environment, animate and
inanimate. Part of this mental activity relates to other persons and speech. Heard
speech leads to theories concerning word (and sentence) meaning and use. As these
theories are conjectured, they are tested out through actions and utterances. The
patterns of responses of other individuals (chiefly the mother or guardian, initially)
lead to the correction of usage. This leads to the generation of an ever growing set of
personal rules of language use. These rules are part of a subjective theory, (or family
of theories) of language use. But the growth of this theory is not monotonic. The
correction of use leads to the abandonment of aspects of it, the adaptation of the
theory and hence the refinement of use. This subjective knowledge of language is
likely to be more procedural than prepositional knowledge. That is, it will be more
a matter of ‘knowing how’ than ‘knowing that’ (Ryle, 1949).
The acquisition of language involves the exchange of utterances with other
individuals in shared social and physical contexts. Such interaction provides
encounters with rule governed linguistic behaviour. In other words, it represents the
71
The Philosophy of Mathematics Education
72
Social Constructivism and Subjective Knowledge
The theory has a number of implications for communication, for the representation
of information, and for the basis and location of objective knowledge. With regard to
communication, the theor y imposes severe limits on the possibility of
communicating meanings by linguistic or other means. Since the subjective
meanings of individuals are uniquely constructed (with certain constraints
accommodated in view of their genesis), it is clear that communication cannot be
correctly described as the transfer of meanings. Signals can be transmitted and
received, but it is impossible to match the meanings that the sender and recipient of
the signals attach to them, or even talk of such a match. However, the ways in which
linguistic competence is acquired, mean that a fit between sender and receiver
meanings can be achieved and sustained, as evidenced by satisfactory participation in
shared language games. This view of communication is fully consistent with the
Communication Theory of Shannon (cited in Glasersfeld, 1989).
However, there is something I want to call objective, which enters into
communication. This is not the informational content of messages, but the pre-
existing norms, rules and conventions of linguistic behaviour that every speaker meets
(in some form) when entering into a linguistic community. These, in Wittgenstein’s
(1953) term, are a ‘form of life’, the enacted rules of linguistic behaviour shared (at
least in approximation) by speakers. These rules, represent the constraints of the world
of interpersonal communication, which permit the possibility of a fit between
senders’ and receivers’ meanings. Such a fit will depend on the extent to which the
actors are drawn from communities which share the same norms of linguistic
competence, as well as on the success of the individuals in reconstructing these norms
for themselves.These norms or rules are objective, in the sense that they are social, and
transcend individuals. However, at any one time, they are located in the regularities of
the linguistic behaviour of the group, sustained by the subjective representations of
them, in the minds of the individual group members.
A further consequence of the view of subjective knowledge growth concerns the
extent to which meanings are inherent in symbolic representations of information,
such as a book or a mathematical proof. According to the view proposed, such
meanings are the constructions of the reader. (This view is in essence, Derrida’s
deconstructive approach to textual meanings; Anderson et al., 1986). The linguistic
rules, conventions and norms reconstructed by a reader during their acquisition of
language constrain the reader to a possible interpretation whose consequences fit
with those of other readers. In other words, there is no meaning per se in books and
proofs. The meanings have to be created by readers, or rather, constructed on the
basis of their existing subjective meanings. Within a given linguistic community, the
readers’ private meaning structures are constructed to fit the constraints of publicly
73
The Philosophy of Mathematics Education
manifested linguistic rules. Thus it is the fit between the readers’ subjective theories
of language, brought about by a common context of acquisition, including shared
constraints, rather than an inherent property of text that brings about a fit between
interpretations. However, the social agreement within a community as to how a
symbolism is to be decoded constrains individuals’ meaning constuctions, giving the
sense that there is informational content in the text itself.
This is consistent with the account given of objective knowledge in the previous
chapter. For it was stated that public representations of subjective knowledge are just
that. Knowledge, truth and meaning cannot be attributed to sets of marks or symbols.
Only the assignment of meanings to a set of marks, or a symbol system, which
ultimately has to be done by an individual, results in the knowledge or meaning of
a published document. As in communications theory, decoding is essential if meaning
is to be attributed to a set of broadcast codes.
The social constructivist account of subjective knowledge is also consistent with
the conventionalist account of the basis of mathematical, logical and linguistic
knowledge given in previous chapters. For according to the constructivist view, the
growth of the subjective knowledge of an individual is shaped by interactions with
others (and the world). This shaping takes place throughout a linguistic community,
so that the constraints accommodated by all of its individuals allow shared
participation in language games and activities. These constraints are the objective,
publicly manifested rules and conventions of language. On the basis of these
constraints individuals construct their own subjective rules and conventions of
language. It can be said that these ‘fit’ (but do not necessarily match) since they allow
for shared purposes and interchange which satisfy the participants to any degree of
refinement desired.
One problem that arises from the account of the constructivist epistemology that
has been given is that it seems to necessitate cumbersome circumlocutions.
Knowledge is no longer ‘acquired’, ‘learned’, or ‘transmitted’, but ‘constructed’ or
‘reconstructed’ as the creative subjective response of an individual to certain stimuli,
based on the individual’s pre-existing knowledge which has been shaped to
accommodate rules and constraints inferred (or rather induced) from interactions
with others. Whilst the latter account is the accurate one from the constructivist
viewpoint, it is convenient to retain the former usage on the understanding that it is
merely a façon de parler, and an abbreviation for the latter.
An analogy for such usage is provided by the language of analysis in mathematics.
To say that a function f(x) (defined on the reals) approaches infinity is acceptable,
provided this is understood to have the following more refined meaning (provided in
the nineteenth century). Namely, that for every real number r there is another s such
if x>s, then f(x)>r. This reformulation no longer says that the function literally
approaches infinity, but that for every finite value, there is some point such that
thereafter all values of the function exceed it. The two meanings expressed are quite
different, but the convention is adopted that the first denotes the second. The
rationale for this is that an abbreviated and historically prior mode of speech is
retained, which in all contexts can be replaced by a more precise definition.
74
Social Constructivism and Subjective Knowledge
It has been argued that linguistic knowledge provides the foundation (genetic and
justificatory) for objective mathematical knowledge, both in defending the
conventionalist thesis, and subsequently as part of the social constructivist philosophy
of mathematics. What is proposed here is the parallel but distinct claim that linguistic
knowledge also provides the foundation, both genetic and justificatory, for the
subjective knowledge of mathematics. In a previous section we saw how social (i.e.
objective) rules of language, logic, etc., circumscribe the acceptance of published
mathematical creations, allowing them to become part of the body of objective
mathematical knowledge. Thus we were concerned with the subjective origins of
objective knowledge. In this section the focus is on the genesis of subjective
mathematical knowledge, and it will be argued that the origins of this knowledge lie
firmly rooted in linguistic knowledge and competence.
Mathematical knowledge begins, it can be said, with the acquisition of linguistic
knowledge. Natural language includes the basis of mathematics through its register of
elementary mathematical terms, through everyday knowledge of the uses and inter-
connections of these terms, and through the rules and conventions which provide
the foundation for logic and logical truth. Thus the foundation of mathematical
knowledge, both genetic and justificatory, is acquired with language. For both the
genetic basis of mathematical concepts and propositions, and the justificatory
foundation of prepositional mathematical knowledge, are found in this linguistic
knowledge. In addition, the structure of subjective mathematical knowledge,
particularly its conceptual structure, results from its acquisition through language.
One of the characteristics of mathematical knowledge is its stratified and
hierarchical nature, particularly among terms and concepts. This is a logical property
of mathematical knowledge, which is manifested both in public expositions of
objective mathematical knowledge and, as will be claimed here, in subjective
mathematical knowledge. We consider first the hierarchical nature of objective
mathematical knowledge.
75
The Philosophy of Mathematics Education
It is acknowledged that concepts and terms, both in science and mathematics, can
be divided into those that are defined and those taken as primitive and undefined, in
any theory (see, for example, Popper, 1979; Hempel, 1966; Barker, 1964). The defined
terms are defined using other terms. Ultimately, after a finite number of defining links,
chains of definition can be chased back to primitive terms, or else the definitions
would be based on, and lead to, an infinite regress4. On the basis of the division of terms
into primitive and defined, a simple inductive definition of the level of every term
within an hierarchical structure can be given. Assuming that each concept is named by
a term, this provides an hierarchy of both terms and concepts. Let the terms of level 1
be the primitive terms of the theory. Assuming that the terms of level n are defined, we
define the terms of level n+1 to be those whose definitions include terms of level n, but
none of any higher level (although terms of lower level may be included).This definition
unambiguously assigns each term of an objective mathematical theory to a level, and
hence determines an hierarchy of terms and concepts (relative to a given theory).5
In the domain of subjective knowledge, we can, at least theoretically, divide
concepts similarly, into primative observational concepts, and abstract concepts defined
in terms of other concepts. Given such a division, an hierarchical structure may be
imposed on the terms and concepts of a subjective mathematical theory precisely as
above. Indeed Skemp (1971) offers an analysis of this sort. He terms observational and
defined concepts primary and secondary concepts, respectively. He bases the notion of
conceptual hierarchy upon this distinction in much the same way as above, without
assigning numbers to levels. His proposals are based on a logical analysis of the nature
of concepts, and their relationships. Thus the notion of a conceptual hierarchy can be
utilized in a philosophical theory of subjective knowledge without introducing any
empirical conjecture concerning the nature of concepts.
To illustrate the hierarchical nature of subjective mathematical knowledge, consider
the following sample contents, which exemplify its linguistic origins. At the lowest
level of the hierarchy are basic terms with direct empirical applications, such as ‘line’,
‘triangle’, ‘cube’, ‘one’, and ‘nine’. At higher levels there are terms defined by means of
those at lower levels, such as ‘shape’, ‘number’, ‘addition’ and ‘collection’. At higher
levels still, there are yet more abstract concepts such as ‘function’, ‘set’, ‘number system’,
based on those at lower levels, and so on. In this way, the concepts of mathematics are
stratified into a hierarchy of many levels. Concepts on succeeding levels are defined
implicitly or explicitly in terms of those on lower levels. An implicit definition may
take the following form: numbers consist of ‘one’, ‘two’, ‘three’, and other objects with
the same properties as these. ‘Shape’ applies to circles, squares, triangles, and other
objects of similar type. Thus new concepts are defined in terms of the implicit
properties of a finite set of exemplars, whose membership implicitly includes
(explicitly includes, under the new concept) further exemplars of the properties.
It is not the intention to claim here that there is a uniquely defined hierarchy of
concepts in either objective or subjective mathematical knowledge. Nor is it claimed
than an individual will have but one conceptual hierarchy. Different individuals may
construct distinct hierarchies for themselves depending on their unique situations,
learning histories, and for particular learning contexts. We saw in the previous section
76
Social Constructivism and Subjective Knowledge
that different individuals’ use of the same terms in ways that conform to the social
rules of use does not mean that the terms denote identical concepts or meanings
(such an assertion would be unverifiable, except negatively). Similarly, such
conformity does not mean that individuals’ conceptual structures are isomorphic,
with corresponding connections. All that can be claimed is that the subjective
conceptual knowledge of mathematics of an individual is ordered hierarchically.
It is conjectured that the generation of a hierarchy of increasingly abstract concepts
reflects a particular tendency in the genesis of human mathematical knowledge.
Namely, to generalize and abstract the shared structural features of previously existing
knowledge in the formation of new concepts and knowledge. We conjecture the
existence of some such mechanism to account for the genesis of abstract concepts and
knowledge (as was noted above). At each succeeding level of the conceptual hierarchy
described, we see the results of this process. That is the appearance of new concepts
implicitly defined in terms of a finite set of lower level terms or concepts.
This abstractive, vertical process contrasts with a second mode of mathematical
knowledge generation: the refinement, elaboration or combination of existing
knowledge, without necessarily moving to a higher level of abstraction. Thus the
genesis of mathematical knowledge and ideas within individual minds is conjectured
to involve both vertical and horizontal processes, relative to an individual’s
conceptual hierarchy. These directions are analogous with those involved in inductive
and deductive processes, respectively. We discuss both these modes of knowledge
generation in turn, beginning with that described as vertical.
Before continuing with the exposition of the mechanisms underpinning the
genesis of mathematical knowledge, a methodological remark is called for. It should
be noted that the conjectures concerning the vertical and horizontal modes of
thought in the genesis of subjective mathematical knowledge are inessential for social
constructivism. It has been argued that some (mental) mechanism is needed to
account for the generation of abstract knowledge from particular and concrete
experience. This is central to social constructivism. But as a philosophy of
mathematics it is not necessary to analyse this mechanism further, or to conjecture its
properties. Thus the rejection of the following exploration of this mechanism need
not entail the rejection of the social constructivist philosophy of mathematics.
The vertical processes of subjective knowledge generation involve generalization,
abstraction and reification, and include concept formation.Typically, this process involves
the transformation of properties, constructions, or collections of constructions into
objects. Thus, for example, we can rationally reconstruct the creation of the number
concept, beginning with ordination, to illustrate this process.The ordinal number ‘5’ is
associated with the 5th member of a counting sequence, ranging over 5 objects. This
becomes abstracted from the particular order of counting, and a generalization ‘5’, is
applied as an adjective to the whole collection of 5 objects.The adjective ‘5’ (applicable
to a set), is reified into an object, ‘5’, which is a noun, the name of a thing-in-itself.
Later, the collection of such numbers is reified into the set ‘number’.Thus we see how
a path can be constructed from a concrete operation (using the ordinal number ‘5’),
through the processes of abstraction and reification, which ultimately leads (via the
77
The Philosophy of Mathematics Education
cardinal number ‘5’) to the abstract concept of ‘number’.This account is not offered as
a psychological hypothesis, but as a theoretical reconstruction of the genesis of subjective
mathematical knowledge by abstraction.
What is proposed is that by a vertical process of abstraction or concept formation,
a collection of objects or constructions at lower, pre-existing levels of a personal
concept hierarchy become ‘reified’ into an object-like concept, or noun-like term.
Skemp refers to this ‘detachability’, or ‘the ability to isolate concepts from any of the
examples which give rise to them’ (Skemp, 1971, page 28) as an essential part of the
process of abstraction in concept formation. Such a newly defined concept applies to
those lower level concepts whose properties it abstracts, but it has a generality that
goes beyond them. The term ‘reification’ is applied because such a newly formed’
concept acquires an integrity and the properties of a primitive mathematical object,
which means that it can be treated as a unity, and at a subsequent stage it too can be
abstracted from, in an iteration of the process.6
The increasing complexity of subjective mathematical knowledge can also be
attributed to horizontal processes of concept and property elaboration and clarification.
This horizontal process of object formation in mathematics is that described by Lakatos
(1976), in his reconstruction of the evolution of the Euler formula and its justification.
Namely, the reformulation (and ‘stretching’) of mathematical concepts or definitions
to achieve consistency and coherence in their relationships within a broader context.
This is essentially a process of elaboration and refinement, unlike the vertical process
which lies behind ‘objectification’ or ‘reification’.
Thus far, the account given has dwelt on the genesis and structure of the
conceptual and terminological part of subjective mathematics. There is also the
genesis of the propositions, relationships and conjectures of subjective mathematical
knowledge to be considered. But this can be accommodated analogously. We have
already discussed how the elementary truths of mathematics and logic are acquired
during the learning of mathematical language. As new concepts are developed by
individuals, following the hierarchical pattern described above, their definitions,
properties and relationships underpin new mathematical propositions, which must be
acquired with them, to permit their uses. New items of prepositional knowledge are
developed by the two modes of genesis described above, namely by informal
inductive and deductive processes. Intuition being the name given to the facility of
perceiving (i.e., conjecturing with belief) such propositions and relationships
between mathematical concepts on the basis of their meaning and properties, prior
to the production of warrants for justifying them. Overall, we see, therefore, that the
general features of the account of the genesis of mathematical concepts also holds for
prepositional mathematical knowledge. That is we posit analogous inductive and
deductive processes, albeit informal, to account for this genesis.
In summary, this section has dealt with the genesis of the concepts and
propositions of subjective mathematical knowledge. The account given of this genesis
involves four claims. First of all, the concepts and propositions of mathematics
originate and are rooted in those of natural language, and are acquired (constructed)
alongside linguistic competence. Secondly, that they can be divided into primitive
78
Social Constructivism and Subjective Knowledge
and derived concepts and propositions. The concepts can be divided into those based
on observation and direct sensory experience, and those defined linguistically by
means of other terms and concepts, or abstracted from them. Likewise, the
propositions consist of those acquired linguistically, and those derived from pre-
existing mathematical propositions, although this distinction is not claimed to be
clear cut. Thirdly, the division of concepts, coupled with the order of their definition,
results in a subjective (and personal) hierarchical structure of concepts (with which
the propositions are associated, according to their constituent concepts). Fourthly, the
genesis of the concepts and propositions of subjective mathematics utilizes both
vertical and horizontal processes of concept and proposition derivation, which take
the form of inductive and deductive reasoning.
These claims comprise the social constructivist account of the genesis of
subjective mathematical knowledge. However, in providing the accounts, examples
have been given, especially concerning the third and fourth of these claims, which
may have the status of empirical conjectures. The hierarchical nature of subjective
mathematical knowledge can be accepted, without relying on such empirical
conjectures. Likewise the existence of the horizontal process of subjective concept
refinement or prepositional deduction, by analogy with Lakatos’ logic of
mathematical discovery, can be accepted in principle. This leaves only the vertical
processes of abstraction, reification or induction to account for, without assuming
empirical grounds. But some such procedure is necessary, if subjective knowledge is
to be constructed by individuals on the basis of primitive concepts derived from
sense impressions and interactions, or elementary mathematical propositions
embedded in language use, as we have assumed. For it is clear that relatively abstract
knowledge must be constructed from relatively concrete knowledge, to account for
the increasing abstraction of the subjective knowledge of mathematics. Hence, as
with the horizontal process, the existence of this vertical process is needed in
principle, irrespective of the fact that some of the details included in the account
might be construed as empirical conjectures. For this reason, these details were
characterized as inessential to the central thesis of social constructivism.
79
The Philosophy of Mathematics Education
80
Social Constructivism and Subjective Knowledge
(ii) logical necessity, through their logical foundations and deductive structure. These
properties are what give rise to a belief in the objective existence of mathematics
and its objects.
Traditionally, knowledge has been divided into the real and the ideal. It is common
to accept the reality of the external world and our scientific knowledge of it (scientific
realism). It is also common to accept the ideal existence of (objective) mathematics
and mathematical objects (idealism or platonism). This dichotomy places physical and
scientific objects in one realm (Popper’s world 1) and mathematical objects in another
(subjective knowledge of them in world 2, objective knowledge in world 3). Thus it
places mathematical and physical objects in different categories. The social
constructivist thesis is that we have no direct access to world 1, and that physical and
scientific objects are only accessible when represented by constructs in world 3
(objective concepts) or in world 2 (subjective concepts). Thus our knowledge of
physical and mathematical objects has the same status, contrary to traditional views.
The difference resides only in the nature of the constraints physical reality imposes on
scientific concepts, through the means of verification adopted for the two types of
knowledge (scientific or mathematical). The similarity, including the social basis of the
objectivity of both types of knowledge, accounts for the subjective belief in the
existence of mathematical objects (almost) just as for theoretical physical objects.7
81
The Philosophy of Mathematics Education
includes creation not only at the edges of mathematical knowledge, but also
throughout the body of mathematical knowledge. This is the way that subjective
knowledge of mathematics explicitly contributes to the creation of objective
mathematical knowledge.8 However, there is also a more far-reaching but implicit way
in which subjective mathematical knowledge contributes to objective mathematical
knowledge.
The social constructivist view is that objective knowledge of mathematics is
social, and is not contained in texts or other recorded materials, nor in some ideal
realm. Objective knowledge of mathematics resides in the shared rules, conventions,
understandings and meanings of the individual members of society, and in their
interactions (and consequently, their social institutions). Thus objective knowledge of
mathematics is continually recreated and renewed by the growth of subjective
knowledge of mathematics, in the minds of countless individuals. This provides the
substratum which supports objective knowledge, for it is through subjective
representations that the social, the rules and conventions of language and human
interaction, is sustained. These mutually observed rules, in their turn, legitimate
certain formulations of mathematics as accepted objective mathematical knowledge.
Thus objective knowledge of mathematics survives through a social group enduring
and reproducing itself. Through passing on their subjective knowledge of
mathematics, including their knowledge of the meaning to be attributed to the
symbolism in published mathematical texts, objective knowledge of mathematics
passes from one generation to the next.
This process of transmission does not merely account for the genesis of
mathematical knowledge. It is also the means by which both the justificatory canons
for mathematical knowledge, and the warrants justifying mathematical knowledge
itself are sustained. Kitcher (1984) likewise claims that the basis for the justification of
objective mathematical knowledge is passed on in this way, from one generation of
mathematicians to the next, starting with empirically warranted knowledge.
As a rational reconstruction of mathematical history to warrant mathematical
knowledge, Kitcher’s account has some plausibility. Like Kitcher, social
constructivism sees as primary the social community whose acceptance confers
objectivity on mathematical knowledge. However, unlike Kitcher, social
constructivism sees the social as sustaining the full rational justification for objective
mathematical knowledge, without the need for historical support for this
justification. According to social con¬ structivism, the social community which
sustains mathematics endures smoothly over history, with all its functions intact, just
as a biological organism smoothly survives the death and replacement of its cells.
These functions include all that is needed for warranting mathematical knowledge.
It should be made clear that the claim that objective mathematical knowledge is
sustained by the subjective knowledge of members and society does not imply the
reducibility of the objective to the subjective. Objective knowledge of mathematics
depends upon social institutions, including established ‘forms of life’ and patterns of
social interaction. These are sustained, admittedly, by subjective knowledge and
individual patterns of behaviour as is the social phenomenon of language. But this no
82
Social Constructivism and Subjective Knowledge
more implies the reducibility of the objective to the subjective, than materialism
implies that thought can be reduced to, and explained in terms of physics. The sum
of all subjective knowledge is not objective knowledge. Subjective knowledge is
essentially private, whereas objective knowledge is public and social. Thus although
objective knowledge of mathematics rests on the substratum of subjective
knowledge, which continually recreates it, it is not reducible to subjective
knowledge.
As a thought experiment, imagine that all social institutions and personal
interactions ceased to exist. Although this would leave subjective knowledge of
mathematics intact, it would destroy objective mathematics. Not necessarily
immediately, but certainly within one lifetime. For without social interaction there
could be no acquisition of natural language, on which mathematics rests. Without
interaction and the negotiation of meanings to ensure a continued fit, individual’s
subjective knowledge would begin to develop idiosyncratically, to grow apart,
unchecked. The objective knowledge of mathematics, and all the implicit knowledge
sustaining it, such as the justificatory canons, would cease to be passed on. Naturally
no new mathematics could be socially accepted either. Thus the death of the social
would spell the death of objective mathematics, irrespective of the survival of
subjective knowledge.
The converse also holds true. If, as another thought experiment we imagine that
all subjective knowledge of mathematics ceased to exist, then so too would objective
knowledge of mathematics cease to exist. For no individual could legitimately assent
to any symbolic representations as embodying acceptable mathematics, being
deprived of the basis for such assent. Therefore there could be no acceptance of
mathematics by any social group. This establishes the converse relationship, namely
that the existence of subjective knowledge is necessary for there to be objective
knowledge of mathematics.
Of course it is hard to follow through all the consequences of the second thought
experiment, because of the impossibility of separating out an individual’s subjective
knowledge of language and mathematics. Knowledge of language depends heavily
on the conceptual tools for classifying, categorising and quantifying our experience
and for framing logical utterances. But according to social constructivism these form
the basis for mathematical knowledge. If we delete these from subjective knowledge
in the thought experiment, then virtually all knowledge of language and its
conceptual hierarchy, would collapse. If we leave this informal knowledge and only
debate explicit knowledge of mathematics (that learned as mathematics and not as
language), then subjective knowledge of mathematics could be rebuilt, for we would
have left its foundations intact.9
In summary, the social constructivist thesis is that objective knowledge of
mathematics exists in and through the social world of human actions, interactions
and rules, supported by individuals’ subjective knowledge of mathematics (and
language and social life), which need constant re-creation. Thus subjective
knowledge re-creates objective knowledge, without the latter being reducible to the
83
The Philosophy of Mathematics Education
84
Social Constructivism and Subjective Knowledge
85
The Philosophy of Mathematics Education
Secondly, there are criticisms that can be directed at the novel synthesis that is
provided by social constructivism. Two criticisms in this category will be considered.
These concern the use of empirical assumptions in social constructivism, and the
tension between the subsumed theor ies of conventionalism and radical
constructivism.
Throughout the exposition, it has been argued that the genesis as well as the
justification of knowledge is the proper concern of the philosophy of mathematics.
Consequently both these contexts have been discussed, but an attempt has been
made to distinguish between them carefully, and to avoid or to demarcate carefully
any empirical assumptions, especially concerning the genesis of mathematical
knowledge. This was a criticism directed at Lakatos in Chapter 2, that in his account
of the conditions of the genesis of mathematical knowledge, he introduced an
historical (i.e. empirical) conjecture. It may be felt that the social constructivist
account errs similarly. However, I believe that this would indicate that a clearer
exposition of social constructivism is needed, rather than necessitating a rejection of
the entire philosophy.
A more substantial criticism arises from a possible tension, or even inconsistency,
between the subsumed theories of conventionalism and radical constructivism. For
the former gives primacy to the social, comprising accepted rules and conventions
underpinning the use of language and objective knowledge of mathematics. This
reflects a ‘form of life’, constituting accepted social and verbal behaviour patterns.
The latter, gives primacy to the knowing subject, an unreachable monad
constructing hypo-thetical world-pictures to represent exper iences of an
unknowable reality. To an adherent of one but not the other philosophy, their
conjunction in social constructivism may seem to be an unholy alliance, for neither
of the two foci is given precedence. Rather each is the centre of a separate realm.
The knowing subject is at the centre of the private realm of individuals and
subjective knowledge. This realm assumes a real but unknowable world, as well as the
knowing subject. But this realm is not enough to account for objective knowledge,
let alone for humanity. For humankind is a social animal, and depends essentially on
interchange and language. The social realm takes this as its basis, including social
institutions and social agreements (albeit tacit). This realm assumes the existence of
social groups of human beings. However, this perspective seems weak in terms of the
interior life and consciousness it ascribes to individuals.
Thus although the primacy of focus of each of conventionalism and radical
constructivism is sacrificed in social constructivism, their conjunction in it serves to
compensate for their individual weaknesses, yet this conjunction raises the question
as to their mutual consistency. In answer it can be said that they treat different
domains, and both involve social negotiation at their boundaries (as Figure 4.1
illustrates). Thus inconsistency seems unlikely, for it could only come about from
their straying over the interface of social interaction, into each other’s domains.
The separateness of the private and social realms, together with their separate
theoretical accounts, has another consequence. It means that the parts of the social
constructivist account could be modified (e.g., the account of subjective knowledge)
86
Social Constructivism and Subjective Knowledge
without changing the whole philosophy. This suggests that the philosophy lacks a
single overarching principle. However, there are unifying concepts (or metaphors)
which unite the private and social realms, namely construction and negotiation. For
both subjective and objective knowledge are deemed to be human constructions,
built up from pre-existing knowledge components. The second unifying concept is
that of social negotiation. This not only plays a central role in the shaping of
subjective and objective knowledge. It also plays a key role in the justification of
mathematical knowledge according to social constructivism, from the quasi-
empiricist component.
Notes
1 Reference is made to subjective knowledge. Philosophically this usage is problematic, because knowlege
has been defined as justified belief, where the justification is understood to be objective. Thus
knowledge is socially verifiable and socially accepted belief. But subjective belief which is not
publicly represented cannot be socially accepted, and hence cannot be knowledge. To follow this
strict usage, all references to subjective knowledge should be replaced by references to subjective
belief. However, there is a well known precedent for continuing with the current usage. Individuals
are frequently described as possessing procedural knowledge (Sheffler, 1965) or knowledge as ‘know
how’ (Ryle, 1949). Thus a precedent exists for not observing the strict usage described above. I shall
continue to refer to ‘subjective knowledge’, in full consciousness of the possible transgression
involved, but without assuming that subjective knowledge is objectively justified.
2 There is also a powerful analogy with Kuhn’s (1970) theory of the structure of scientific revolutions.
For in the proposed account we have an alternation between viable subjective theories used to guide
action, which parallels Kuhn’s periods of ‘normal science’, followed by conflicts between the
predictions of the subjective theories and observations, paralleling Kuhn’s periods of ‘revolutionary
science’ (as well as Popper’s falsification of theories), when the old subjective theories are rejected,
and new theories are built from them and accepted, completing the cycle (see Ernest, 1990).
3 I follow Glasersfeld’s (1984) use of the terms ‘fit’ and ‘match’ which make an important distinction.
They both refer to the relationship between a representation and what it represents. Thus a map
‘matches’ the geographical region it represents because there is a morphism, a structure preserving
relation, between them. In this way ‘matching’ resembles the correspondence theory of truth. In
contrast, a key ‘fits’ a lock when it works and turns the lock. Such a ‘fit’ does not represent the
structure of the lock, but merely a functional relationship between the two. When a theory, account
or representation ‘fits’ it means that it satisfies a basic set of constraints, but that beyond that it can
have any form. ‘Fitting’ resembles the pragmatic conception of truth. The crucial difference is that
theories that ‘fit’ a portion of the world do not tell us about the structure of the world, whereas any
that ‘match’ would do so.
4 If this assertion is considered to be controversial, we simply exclude from the discussion any terms
which do not fit the description. Subsequent discussion of hierarchies therefore only refer to those
terms included in them, and not any excluded circularly defined terms.
5 This hierarchy can also be used as a basis for imposing a hierarchical structure on the sentences and
formulas of the theory. We simply define the level of a sentence or formula to be the maximum level
of the terms occurring in it.
6 Such an account has previously been offered to explain the genesis of set-theoretic objects from
mathematical constructions, within an objective philosophy of mathematics, by Machover (1983).
The purpose being to found abstract, classical mathematics on the more intuitive (and presumably
safer) realm of constructive mathematics, analogous to the formalist strategy. However, by proposing
that the objects of mathematics are interpreted as ‘reified constructions’, Machover is opening the
door for a genetic epistemology in mathematics, as is proposed by Piaget (1972) and Kitcher (1984),
among others, albeit from a different viewpoint.
It is also worth mentioning that the vertical process of object formation or reification is part of
set theory, both formal and informal, in the standard objective mathematical theory. Typically, such a
87
The Philosophy of Mathematics Education
process is permitted by a comprehension axiom, which allows the collection of objects satisfying a
defined mathematical property to become a new mathematical object, a set:
For all P, there exists p, such that p={x/P(x)}) (Where ‘P(x)’ is a first-order defined property
with free variable ‘x’, and ‘p’ is the set comprising the extension of ‘P(x)’).
Of course such an unrestricted comprehension principle leads to contradictions (Russell, 1902).
Indeed many of the innovations in logic and set theory in the early part of this century (Russell’s
theory of types, Zermelo-Fraenkel and Godel-Bernays-von Neumann set theories) were expressly
motivated to permit the safe use of some form of the comprehension principle.
Thus the process of reification, i.e., the elevation of (the extension of) a property to objecthood,
is an established principle in objective mathematics. Since, according to social constructivism,
objective mathematics is a socially accepted reflection of subjective mathematics, this adds plausibility
to the assumption of the vertical reifying process in the genesis of subjective mathematical
knowledge.
7 There is a further explanation for the subjective belief in the objects of mathematics based on the
propensity to objectify and reify the concepts of mathematics into objects, discussed above. Once
objectified, such mentally constructed mathematical objects can be (nearly) as potent as physical
objects. Indeed a platonist view of mathematical existence is often held by practising mathematicians
(such as Frege, Hardy, Godel, Thom) whose extensive mathematical activities by constantly using
their mathematical concepts and objects reinforce their subjective ‘solidity’ or ‘object’-like qualities.
Thus the reification of mathematical objects, coupled with other features, such as a propensity for
belief in socially accepted constructs, gives them an apparent existence, accounting for some
mathematicians’ platonism.
8 Subjective knowledge of mathematics (syntactical knowledge of mathematics, Schwab, 1975) also
plays a part in the process of acceptance of new mathematical knowledge, via the process of criticism.
9 Popper (1979, pages 107–108) uses this second interpretation of the thought experiment as a basis
for an argument that books contain objective knowledge. For with our capacity to learn from books
intact, Popper argues that we can re-acquire objective knowledge from libraries. However, the social
constructivist view is that only the explicit, more advanced part of subjective (and objective)
knowledge is eradicated in this interpretation of the thought experiment. The reconstruction of
these forms of knowledge with the aid of libraries shows that the foundations of this knowledge has
survived. (However, this conclusion does not contradict Popper’s, since his sense of ‘objectivity’ does
not include implicit, socially accepted linguistic knowledge).
88
5
1. Introduction
2. Philosophical Parallels
A. Sceptical Philosophy
89
The Philosophy of Mathematics Education
One challenge for the social constructivist account of subjective knowledge is the
‘private language’ problem. If an individual’s concepts are personal constructions,
how are they able to communicate using a shared language? Why should different
mathematicians understand the same thing by a concept or proposition, when their
meanings are personally unique? May not each have a private language, to refer to
his or her own private meanings?
Social constructivism overcomes this problem through the interpersonal
negotiation of meanings to achieve a ‘fit’. Support for this position, if not the precise
form of argument, is widespread. Wittgenstein (1953) first answered the problem,
arguing that private languages cannot exist. A number of philosophers commenting
on his work, such as Kenny (1973) and Bloor (1983), support the rejection of private
languages, as do others including Ayer (1956) and Quine (1960). With regard to
mathematics, the private language problem is also considered soluble, for example by
Tymoczko (1985) and Lerman (1989), both arguing from a position close to social
constructivism.
The solution of the private language problem by social constructivism reflects a
substantial body of philosophical opinion. Generally, it is argued that the shared rules
and ‘objective pull’ of inter-personal language use makes it public, consistent with
social constructivism.
90
The Parallels of Social Constructivism
Other authors have looked to an evolutionary model to account for the growth
and development of knowledge. This includes the genetic epistemology of Piaget
(1972, 1977), and the evolutionary epistemologies of Popper (1979), Toulmin (1972)
and Lorenz (1977).
The majority of modern philosophers of science view it as a growing and
developing body of knowledge either detached from history (Popper, 1979) or
embedded in human history (Kuhn, Feyerabend, Lakatos, Toulmin and Laudan).
Educational thinkers have also stressed the processes and means of knowledge
acquisition, as a basis for the curriculum, including, most notably, Schwab (1975) and
Bruner (1960).
The process of coming to know relates to practical knowledge and the
applications of knowledge. Ryle (1949) established that practical knowledge
(‘knowing how’) belongs to epistemology as well as declarative knowledge
(‘knowing that’). Sneed (1971) proposes a model of scientific knowledge which
incorporates the range of intended applications (models) as well as the core theory.
This model has been extended to mathematics by Jahnke (Steiner, 1987). Such
approaches admitting practical knowledge or its applications into the traditional
domain of knowledge thus parallel aspects of the social constructivist proposals.
The social constructivist account of the nature and genesis of subjective
knowledge of mathematics is to a large extent based on the radical constructivism of
Glasersfeld (1984, 1989). This has parallels in the thought of Kant, and even more so,
Vico, as well as with the American pragmatists and modern philosophers of science
cited above.
Thus there is a growing current of thought in modern philosophy which gives a
central place in epistemology to considerations of the human activity of knowing
and the evolution of knowledge, as in social constructivism.
91
The Philosophy of Mathematics Education
he argues, the different disciplines have changed. Their objects, concepts, accepted
rules of thought and aims have evolved and changed, even amounting, in extreme
cases, to discontinuities. Knowledge, in his view, is but one component of ‘discursive
practice’, which includes language, social context and social relations. In evidence, he
documents how certain socially privileged groups, such as doctors and lawyers, have
established discourses creating new objects of thought, grouping together hitherto
unconnected phenomena defined as delinquent behaviour or crime. Elsewhere,
Foucault (1981) shows how a new area of knowledge, the discourse of human
sexuality, was defined by church and state, to serve their own interests.
Lyotard (1984) considers all human knowledge to consist of narratives, whether
literary or scientific. Each disciplined narrative has its own legitimation criteria,
which are internal, and which develop to overcome or engulf contradictions. He
describes how mathematics overcame crises in its axiomatic foundations due to
Godel’s Theorem by incorporating meta-mathematics into an enlarged research
paradigm. He also claims that continuous differentiable functions are losing their pre-
eminence as paradigms of knowledge and prediction, as mathematics incorporates
undecidability, incompleteness, Catastrophe theory and chaos. Thus a static system of
logic and rationality does not underpin mathematics, or any discipline. Rather they
rest on narratives and language games, which shift with organic changes of culture.
These thinkers exemplify a move to view the traditional objective criteria of
knowledge and truth within the disciplines as internal myths, which attempt to deny
the social basis of all knowing. This new intellectual tradition affirms that all human
knowledge is interconnected through a shared cultural substratum, as social
constructivism asserts.
Another post-structuralist is Derrida, who as well as supporting this view, argues
for the ‘deconstructive’ reading of texts:
In writing, the text is set free from the writer. It is released to the public
who find meaning in it as they read it. These readings are the product of
circumstance. The same holds true even for philosophy. There can be no
way of fixing readings…
Anderson et al. (1986, page 124)
This offers a parallel to the social constructivist thesis that mathematical texts are
empty of meaning. Meanings must be constructed for them by individuals or groups
on the basis of their knowledge (and context).
Various modern philosophers of mathematics have views consistent with some if not
all of the theses of social constructivism. Here we draw together some of the points
of contact between them and social constructivism.
Some philosophers emphasize the significance of the history and empirical
aspects of mathematics for philosophy. Kitcher (1984) erects a system basing the
92
The Parallels of Social Constructivism
93
The Philosophy of Mathematics Education
this fits here, because it represents an historical parallel with aspects of quasi-empiricism
and social constructivism, at the micro social level. Szabo (1967) argues that the
deductive logic of Euclid derives from pre-socratic dialectics, with conversation serving
as the model. Again, this fits with the social constructivist account.
Studies of the macro social context offer theories of the structural patterns, social
relationships or ‘laws’ in the development of mathematical knowledge in history and
culture. Many of these are social constructionist accounts, consistent with
conventionalism, and hence social constructivism, albeit in a different realm. In this
bracket can be included a new breed of histories of mathematics acknowledging its
fallibility (Kline, 1980) and its multi-cultural social construction (Joseph, 1990).
Historical and cultural studies of mathematics with a bearing on the philosophy
of mathematics draw strength and inspiration from the comparable ‘externalist’
approaches to the philosophy of science, such as those of Kuhn (1970) and Toulmin
(1972). Such historical approaches, as well as the philosophy of science, provide
parallels and support for social constructivism. Likewise, when the social constructi¬
vist account is supplemented with empirical hypotheses, a theory of the history of
mathematics results, as in the quasi-empiricism of Lakatos (1976).
94
The Parallels of Social Constructivism
95
The Philosophy of Mathematics Education
He argues that the form of products becomes reified and fetishized into an abstract
thing: money, value or commodity (Lefebvre, 1972). Subsequent theorists in this
tradition of thought, such as Lukacs, have extended the range of operation of
reification to a much broader range of concepts.
Evidently the social constructivist thesis concerning the reification of newly
defined concepts has a strong parallel in Marxist sociology. This parallel has been
extended to mathematics by Davis (1974) and others such as Sohn-Rethel, as
Restivo (1985) reports.
96
The Parallels of Social Constructivism
97
The Philosophy of Mathematics Education
(i) Mathematicians. At any one time, the nature of mathematics is determined primarily
by a fuzzy set of persons: mathematicians. The set is partially ordered by the relations
of power and status. The set and the relations on it are continually changing, and thus
mathematics is continuously evolving. The set of mathematicians has different
strengths of membership (which could in theory be quantified from 0 to 1). This
includes ‘strong’ members (institutionally powerful or active research mathematicians)
and ‘weak’ members (teachers of mathematics). The ‘weakest’ members could simply
be numerate citizens. The notion of a fuzzy set usefully models the varying strengths
of individuals’ contribution to the institution of mathematics. Mathematical
knowledge is legitimated through acceptance by the ‘strongest’ members of the set. In
practice the set of mathematicians is made up of many sub-sets pursuing research in
sub-fields, each with a similar sub-structure, but loosely interconnected through
various social institutions (journals, conferences, universities, funding agencies).
(ii) Joining the set. Membership of the set of mathematicians results from an extended
period of training (to acquire the necessary knowledge and skills) followed by
participation in the institutions of mathematics, and presumably the adoption of (at
least some) of the values of the mathematics community (Davis and Hersh, 1980;
Tymoczko, 1985). The training requires interaction with other mathematicians, and
with information technology artefacts (books, papers, software, etc.). Over a period
of time this results in personal knowledge of mathematics. To the extent that it exists,
the shared knowledge of mathematics results from this period of training in which
students are indoctrinated with a ‘standard’ body of mathematical knowledge. This is
achieved through common learning experiences and the use of key texts, which have
included Euclid, Van der Waerden, Bourbaki, Birkhoff and MacLane, and Rudin, in
the past. Many, probably most students fall away during this process. Those that
remain have successfully learned part of the official body of mathematical knowledge
and have been ‘socialized’ into mathematics. This is a necessary, but not sufficient
condition for entry into the set of mathematicians (with a membership value
significantly greater than 0). The ‘standard’ body of knowledge will have a shared
basis, but will vary according to which subfields the mathematician contributes.
98
The Parallels of Social Constructivism
and the nexus of human rules, purposes and decisions concerning language use,
respectively. In constructing this system, Morris added to the formal logical levels of
syntax and semantics a further level of pragmatics, inspired by pragmatism.
There is also a parallel with the three interlocking systems of language
distinguished by Halliday (1978), consisting the forms, meanings and functions of
language. In the sociology of mathematics, Restivo (1985) distinguishes the syntactical
and semantic properties of an object (following Hofstadter), paralleling the syntax-
semantics distinction. Hersh (1988) makes an analogous distinction between the
‘front’ and ‘back’ of mathematics. Restivo (1988) also distinguishes between ‘social’
and ‘technical’ talk of mathematics, paralleling the distinction between the third level
of pragmatic considerations and the first two levels taken as one, respectively. Thus
precursors of these three levels, in various forms, are to be found in the literature.
The three levels of mathematical discourse proposed are as follows. First of all,
there is the level of syntax or formal mathematics. This consists of rigorous
formulations of mathematics, consisting of the formal statement and proof of results,
comprising such things as axioms, definitions, lemmas, theorems and proofs, in pure
mathematics, and problems, boundary conditions and values, theorems, methods,
derivations, models, predictions and results in applied mathematics. This level includes
the mathematics in articles and papers accepted for conferences and journal
publication, and constitutes what is accepted as official mathematics. It is considered
to be objective and impersonal, the so-called ‘real’ mathematics. This is the level of
high status knowledge in mathematics, what Hersh (1988) terms ‘the front’ of
mathematics. This level is not that of total rigour, which would require exclusive use
of one of the logical calculi, but of what passes in the profession for acceptable rigour.
Secondly, there is the level of informal or semantic mathematics. This includes
heuristic formulations of problems, informal or unverified conjectures, proof
attempts, historical and informal discussion. This is the level of unofficial
mathematics, concerned with meanings, relationships and heuristics. Mathematicians
refer to remarks on this level as ‘motivation’ or ‘background’. It consists of subjective
and personal mathematics. It is considered to be low status knowledge in
mathematics, what Hersh (1988) terms ‘the back’ of mathematics.
Third, there is the level of pragmatic or professional knowledge of mathematics
and the professional mathematical community. It concerns the institutions of
mathematics, including the conferences, places of work, journals, libraries, prizes,
grants, and so on. It also concerns the professional lives of mathematicians, their
specialisms, publications, position, status and power in the community, their work
places and so on. This is not considered to be mathematical knowledge at all. The
knowledge has no official status in mathematics, since it does not concern the
cognitive content of mathematics, although aspects of it are reflected in journal
announcements. This is the level of ‘social talk’ of mathematics (Restivo, 1988).
These three levels are the different domains of practice within which
mathematicians operate. As languages and domains of discourse they form a
hierarchy, from the more narrow, specialized and precise (the level of syntax), to the
more inclusive, expressive and vague (the level of pragmatics). The more expressive
99
The Philosophy of Mathematics Education
systems can refer to the contents of the less expressive systems, but the relation is
asymmetric.
The hierarchy also embodies some of the values of mathematicians. Namely, the
more formal, abstract and impersonal that the mathematical knowledge is, the more
highly it is valued.The more heuristic, concrete and personal mathematical knowledge
is, the less it is prized. Restivo (1985) argues that the development of abstract mathematics
follows from the economic and social separation of the ‘hand’ and ‘brain’. For abstract
mathematics is far removed from practical concerns. Since the ‘brain’ is associated with
wealth and power in society, this division may be said to lead to the above values.
The values described above lead to the identification of mathematics with its
formal representations (on the syntactical level). This is an identification which is
made both by mathematicians, and philosophers of mathematics (at least those
endorsing the absolutist philosophies). The valuing of abstraction in mathematics may
also partly explain why mathematics is objectified. For the values emphasize the pure
forms and rules of mathematics, facilitating their objectification and reification, as
Davis (1974) suggests.4 This valuation allows the objectified concepts and rules of
mathematics to be depersonalized and reformulated with little concerns of ownership,
unlike literary creations. Such changes are subject to strict and general mathematical
rules and values, which are a part of the mathematical culture. This has the result of
offsetting some of the effects of sectional interests exercised by those with power in
the community of mathematicians. However, this in no way threatens the status of the
most powerful mathematicians. For the objective rules of acceptable knowledge serve
to legitimate the position of the elite in the mathematical community.
Restivo (1988) distinguishes between ‘technical’ and ‘social’ talk of mathematics,
as we saw, and argues that unless the latter is included, mathematics as a social
construction cannot be understood. Technical talk is identified here with the first and
second levels (the levels of syntax and semantics), and social talk is identified with the
third level (that of pragmatics and professional concerns).
Denied access to this last level, no sociology of mathematics is possible, including
a social constructionist sociology of mathematics. However, social constructivism as a
philosophy of mathematics does not need access to this level, although it requires the
existence of the social and language, in general. An innovation of social
constructivism is the acceptance of the second level (semantics) as central to the
philosophy of mathematics, following Lakatos. For traditional philosophies of
mathematics focus on the first level alone.
Sociologically, the three levels may be regarded as distinct but inter-related
discursive practices, after Foucault. For each has its own symbol systems, knowledge
base, social context and associated power relationships, although they may be hidden.
For example, at the level of syntax, there are rigorous rules concerning acceptable
forms, which are strictly maintained by the mathematics establishment (although
they change over time). This can be seen as the exercise of power by a social group.
In contrast, the absolutist mathematician’s view is that nothing but logical reasoning
and rational decision-making is relevant to this level. Thus a full sociological
understanding of mathematics requires an understanding of each of these discursive
100
The Parallels of Social Constructivism
The above suggests that social constructivism may offer a potentially fruitful parallel
sociological account of mathematics. Such a parallel, highly compatible with social
constructivism is already partly developed by Restivo (1984, 1985, 1988) and others.
Although sociological parallels do not add weight to social constructivism in purely
philosophical terms, they offer the prospect of an interdisciplinary social constructivist
theory, offering a broader account of mathematics than a philosophy alone. Mathematics
is a single phenomenon, and a single account applicable to each of the perspectives of
philosophy, history, sociology and psychology is desirable, since it reflects the unity of
mathematics. If successful, such an account would have the characteristics of unity,
simplicity and generality, which are good grounds for theory choice.5
4. Psychological Parallels
A. Constructivism in Psychology
101
The Philosophy of Mathematics Education
102
The Parallels of Social Constructivism
constructivism here, although in the next sections we consider briefly some of the
key components of such a theory.
Following Piaget, schema theorists such as Rumelhart and Norman (1978), Skemp
(1979) and others, have accepted the model of knowledge growth utilizing the twin
processes of assimilation and accommodation. These offer parallels to the social
constructivist accounts of subjective and objective knowledge growth. For knowledge,
according to this account, is hypothetico-deductive. Theoretical models or systems are
conjectured, and then have their consequences inferred.This can include the applications
of known procedures or methods, as well as the elaboration, application, working out
of consequences, or interpretation of new facts within a mathematical theory or
framework. In subjective terms, this amounts to elaborating and enriching existing
theories and structures. In terms of objective knowledge, it consists of reformulating
existing knowledge or developing the consequences of accepted axiom systems or
other mathematical theories. Overall, this corresponds to the psychological process of
assimilation, in which experiences are interpreted in terms of, and incorporated into
an existing schema. It also corresponds to Kuhn’s (1970) concept of normal science, in
which new knowledge is elaborated within an existing paradigm, which, in the case of
mathematics, includes applying known (paradigmatic) procedures or proof methods to
new problems, or working out new consequences of an established theory.
The comparison between assimilation, on the psychological plane, and Kuhn’s
notion of normal science, in philosophy, depends on the analogy between mental
schemas and scientfic theories. Both schemas (Skemp, 1971; Resnick and Ford, 1981)
and theories (Hempel, 1952; Quine 1960) can be described as interconnected
structures of concepts and propositions, linked by their relationships. This analogy has
been pointed out explicitly by Gregory (in Miller, 1983), Salner (1986), Skemp
(1979) and Ernest (1990), who analyzes the parallel further.
The comparison may be extended to schema accommodation and revolutionary
change in theories. In mathematics, novel developments may exceed the limits of
‘normal’ mathematical theory development, described above. Dramatic new methods
can be constructed and applied, new axiom systems or mathematical theories
developed, and old theories can be restructured or unified by novel concepts or
approaches. Such periods of change can occur at both the subjective and objective
knowledge levels. It corresponds directly to the psychological process of
accommodation, in which schemas are restructured. It also corresponds to Kuhn’s
concept of revolutionary science, when existing theories and paradigms are
challenged and replaced.
Piaget introduced the concept of cognitive conflict or cognitive dissonance (which
will not be distinguished here). In the social constructivist account of mathematics, this
has a parallel with the emergence of a formal inconsistency, or a conflict between a
formal axiom system and the informal mathematical system that is its source (Lakatos,
103
The Philosophy of Mathematics Education
1978a). This is analogous to cognitive conflict, which occurs when there is conflict
between two schemas, due to inconsistency or conflicting outcomes. In psychology, this
is resolved through the accommodation of one or both of the schemas. Likewise in
mathematics, or in science, this stimulates revolutionary developments of new theories.
Overall, there is a striking analogy between theory growth and conflict in the social
constructivist philosophy of mathematics and schema theory in psychology, and
underlying it, between theories and schemas. Unlike the situation in the philosophy of
mathematics, schema theory, as sketched above, represents the received view in
psychology, lending support to a psychological parallel for social constructivism.
104
The Parallels of Social Constructivism
A central thesis of social constructivism is that the unique subjective meanings and
theories constructed by individuals are developed to ‘fit’ the social and physical
worlds. The main agency for this is interaction, and in the acquisition of language,
social inter-action. This results in the negotiation of meanings, that is the correction
of verbal behaviour and the changing of underlying meanings to improve ‘fit’.
Briefly put, this is the conjectured process by means of which the partial inner
representation of public knowledge is achieved.
This thesis is close to the social theory of mind of Vygotsky (1962) and his
followers. Vygotsky’s theory entails that for the individual, thought and language
105
The Philosophy of Mathematics Education
Vygotsky’s point is not that there are hidden cognitive structures awaiting
release through social interaction. His point is the radical one that they are
formed through social interaction. Development is not the process of the
hidden becoming public, but on the contrary, of the public and inter-
subjective becoming private.
(Williams, 1989, page 113)
Thus Vygotsky’s social theory of mind offers a strong parallel with social
constructivism, one that can also be found elsewhere in psychology, such as Mead’s
(1934) symbolic interactionism. A further development in this direction is the
Activity Theory of Leont’ev (1978), with perceives psychological motives and
functioning as inseparable from the socio-political context. Possibly less radical is the
move to see knowing as bound up with its context in ‘Situated cognition’ (Lave,
1988; Brown et al., 1989), although Walkerdine (1988, 1989) proposes a fully social
constructionist psychology of mathematics. Social constructionism as a movement in
psychology is gaining in force, as Harre (1989) reports, and is replacing the
traditional developmental or behaviourist paradigms of psychology with that of social
negotiation. Harre goes so far as to propose that inner concepts such as self-identity
are linguistic-related social constructions.
F. Psychological Parallels
106
The Parallels of Social Constructivism
Due to the multidisciplinary nature of the issues raised, there is also the prospect
of a unified social constructivist account of mathematics. The aim of this section is to
propose an overall social constructivist theory of mathematics, incorporating its
philosophy, history, sociology and psychology. These are distinct disciplines, with
different questions, methodologies and data. What is proposed is an overarching
social constructivist meta-theory of mathematics, to provide schematic explanations
treating the issues and processes in each of these fields, to be developed to suit the
characteristics and constraints of that field. This would result in parallel social
constructivist accounts of:
1 the history of mathematics: its development at different times and in different
cultures;
2 the sociology of mathematics; mathematics as a living social construction,
with its own values, institutions, and relationship with society in the large;
3 the psychology of mathematics: how individuals learn, use and create
mathematics.
The goal of providing such a meta-theory of mathematics is ambitious, but legitimate.
Theoretical physics is currently seeking to unify its various theories into a grand theory.
In the past century other great strides have been made to unify and link sciences.There
have been ambitious schemes to document a shared methodology and foundations,
such as the International Encyclopedia of Unified Science.The history of mathematics
likewise provides many examples of theoretical unification.What is claimed here is that
this is also a desirable goal for the philosophy of mathematics.
There are a number of reasons why such a project is worthwhile. First of all, as
mathematics is a single discipline and social institution, it is appropriate to coordinate
different perspectives of it, for the unity of mathematics should transcend the divisions
between disciplines. A meta-theory which reflects this unity gains in plausibility, and
reflects the characteristics of a good theory, namely agreement with the data,
conceptual integration and unity, simplicity, generality and, it is to be hoped, fertility.
Secondly, beyond this general argument is the fact of the strong parallels between
the social constructivist philosophy and the history, sociology and psychology of
mathematics demonstrated above.These are not coincidental, but arise from genuinely
interdisciplinary issues inherent in the nature of mathematics as a social institution.
Thirdly, in exploring these parallels one factor has recurred, the greater
acceptability of the parallel theses in general philosophy, sociology, psychology and
the history of mathematics, than in the philosophy of mathematics. In these fields,
many of these theses are close to the received view or a major school of thought. In
particular, social constructionist views in sociology and psychology have a great deal
of support. This contrasts strongly with the position in the philosophy of
mathematics, where absolutist philosophies have dominated until very recently. Thus
the call for a social constructivist meta-theory of mathematics is stronger from the
surrounding fields than from the traditional philosophy of mathematics.
Fourthly, one of the theses of social constructivism is that there is no absolute
dichotomy between mathematical and empirical knowledge. This suggests the
107
The Philosophy of Mathematics Education
Notes
1 There is an interesting analogy between deductive proof and Kitcher’s (1984) justification of
mathematical knowledge, which might be its source. Just substitute axioms for his basis and inference
as the means of deriving each stage from the next.
2 An example of this ‘standard’ view is that of Scheffler: ‘science is a systematic public enterprise,
controlled by logic and empirical fact whose purpose is to formulate the truth about the empirical
world’. (Brown et al., 1981, page 253)
3 A leading exponent of social constructionism as a sociology of mathematics is Sal Restivo (1984,
1985, 1988). (In addition Restivo, 1984, offers valuable insights into social constructivism as a
philosophy of mathematics). David Bloor (1976, 1983) has made major contributions to both the
sociology and philosophy of mathematics as a social construction.
4 Restivo (1985, page 192) also suggests, following Struik, that the separation of form from content in
the objectification of mathematical knowledge is a product of the prevailing social conditions. The
argument is that idealism results from, and provides a solution to problems in social outlook, during
periods of social decline, such as the disintegration of the western Roman empire, and the
enfeeblement of empire. Similarly Koestler (1964, page 57) suggests that Plato’s idealism was a
response to the decline of Greece. An interesting analogy might be drawn with the development of
the rigid philosophy of logical positivism in post-Great war Austria and Germany.
5 The strength of the sociological parallels might be used to direct a charge of sociologism against
social constructivism, claiming that it is a sociological theory of mathematical knowledge, which
although avoiding overtly empirical matters, remains essentially sociological. My response is that the
primary focus is on the general conditions and justification of mathematical knowledge, which is the
proper concern of the philosophy of mathematics.
6 ‘Constuctivism’ has many meanings. Below two senses of ‘constructivism’ are distinguished in
psychology. In the philosophy of mathematics, ‘constructivism’ encompasses intuitionism and similar
schools of thought. The psychological and philosophical senses are quite distinct (Lerman, 1989).
‘Social constructivism’ introduces another sense into the philosophy of mathematics. Social
constructivism is also applied in the sociology of mathematics, by Restivo. ‘Constructivism’ also
denotes a movement in the history of modern art, with proponents such as Gabo, Pevsner and Tatlin.
The account of judicial reasoning of Ronald Dworkin (in his 1977 book ‘Taking Rights Seriously’)
is termed ‘constructivist’, according to the Fontana Dictionary of Modern Thought.
Doubtless further ‘constructivist’ schools of thought exist in other disciplines. What they seem to
share is the metaphor of construction: the product involved is built up by a synthetic process from
previously constructed components.
7 An outcome of the social constructivist meta-theory of mathematics might be to demystify the
philosophy of mathematics. For if the meta-theory is possible, then the strict demarcation of the
disciplines may be seen as the reification, mystification and even the fetishization of philosophy and
mathematics. The force with which the inviolability of the boundaries has been asserted (e.g. by
logical positivists and empiricists) resembles a social taboo. It is surely in the interests of knowledge
to offer a rational challenge to such a taboo, even if it is against the interests of the professionals who
have created the mystique.
108