What's The Use of Philosophy
What's The Use of Philosophy
What's The Use of Philosophy
Philip Kitcher
Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers
the University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education
by publishing worldwide. Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University
Press in the UK and certain other countries.
9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1
Printed by Sheridan Books, Inc., United States of America
To the wonderful graduate students
whom I have had the privilege of teaching
—
and for all the others
who once fell in love with philosophy
and who would like the relationship
to stay that way
CONTENTS
Preface ix
3. Pathology Report 57
Notes 183
References 185
vii
PREFACE
ix
x Preface
O nce upon a time, in a country not too far away, the most
prominent musicians decided to become serious about their
profession. They encouraged their promising students to devote
hours to special exercises designed to strengthen fingers, shape
lips, and extend breath control. Within a few years, conservato-
ries began to hold exciting competitions, at which the most rig-
orous études would be performed in public. For a while, these
contests went on side by side with concerts devoted to the tra-
ditional repertoire. Gradually, however, interest in the composi-
tions of the past—and virtually all those of the present—began
to wane. Serious pianists found the studies composed by Chopin,
Liszt, Debussy, and Ligeti insufficiently taxing and dismissed
the suites, concertos, and sonatas of Bach, Mozart, Beethoven,
Brahms, Bartok, and Prokofiev as worthy of performance only by
second-raters.
Popular interest in the festivals organized by the major con-
servatories quickly declined, although the contests continued to
be attended by a tiny group of self-described cognoscenti. A few
maverick musicians, including some who had once been counted
What’s the Use of Philosophy? Philip Kitcher, Oxford University Press. © Oxford University Press
2023. DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780197657249.003.0001
2 What’s the Use of Philosophy?
***
***
Whether or not this is a good diagnosis for his time or for ours
is something I’ll consider later. For the moment, however, I want
to see it as pointing to two axes along which philosophy has
10 What’s the Use of Philosophy?
The search for natural knowledge defines one axis along which
philosophy has been directed. As that search is undertaken, the
form of the question changes. Ancient thinkers wanted to know
the fundamental elements out of which the cosmos is built. Two
millennia later, it began to become clear that answers to questions
like that would require complicated interactions with the natural
world to address all sorts of preliminary issues, and that dawning
recognition gave rise to a division of labor. From the nineteenth
century on, philosophy’s role in the search for natural knowledge
has been that of an assistant—sometimes, as in recent work iden-
tifying causes (Spirtes et al. 2000), of an assistant who is promoted
to a full partner. There are places where difficulties arise through
conceptual confusion, or where options are limited because some
presupposition defines the apparent possibilities—and in these
places natural philosophy can still flourish. I’ll postpone for the
moment any further consideration of this role for philosophy, and
of how it can contribute to the enterprise of factual knowledge
(the following chapter will offer some examples).
The second axis marked out by Dewey’s diagnosis is directed
toward identifying value. For Paleolithic people, living together
in small bands, as for well-born members of a Greek polis and for
citizens of contemporary societies, there were and are issues about
what ways of life are worthwhile, what ends are worth pursuing,
what rules should govern their interactions, and what institutions
they should fashion or maintain. Questions like these arise from
the conditions in which people find themselves, and, as those con-
ditions change, we should not expect that the formulations that
are most salient or most apt should remain invariant. They are
questions that are urgent for all people—or at least for all people
12 What’s the Use of Philosophy?
who have any chance of directing the course of their lives. They
deserve answers that are not only pertinent to the situations in
which people find themselves but also are as well-informed as pos-
sible about the character of the world in which we live (including
what is known about ourselves). Hence Dewey emphasizes the
importance of integrating the contributions of various forms of
inquiry and of connecting them with our search for what is valu-
able. As he goes on to remark:
***
***
life for at least fifty thousand years, and for most of that time our
moral practices have been worked out in very small groups.
Here is a brief and blunt overview (a more extended account
is given in Kitcher 2011a). Our hominid ancestors, like our evo-
lutionary cousins, the chimpanzees, lived in groups mixed by age
and sex. They were able to achieve that social state because they had
acquired psychological dispositions to respond to their fellows.
Like contemporary chimp societies, those hominid groups were
constantly in danger of social dissolution because of the limits of
the responsiveness: evolution under natural selection has equipped
us with psychological dispositions to take the needs of others into
account—sometimes. Unfortunately, our adaptive equipment
allows for many occasions in which we ignore what those around
us are attempting to achieve, and our neglect typically provokes
social trouble. Unlike our evolutionary relatives, who continue
to solve their social problems through time-consuming forms of
reconciliation, human beings gained an ability to control some
socially disruptive inclinations through self-command. The moral
project began when our ancestors deliberated with one another,
on terms of (rough) equality among the adult members, all of
whom were needed for the survival of the band, and arrived at an
agreement on rules that would govern their lives together. They
initiated a series of experiments of living—to use Mill’s phrase—
and we, who come late in that series, have inherited the experi-
mental ideas that were most culturally successful.
We cannot tell whether either natural or cultural selection has
any tendency to generate elements of ethical practice that might
merit the title of “truth” or “rightness.” Yet it is still possible to find
a kind of objectivity in our moral codes. The patterns of conduct
P hilosophy I nside O ut 19
we praise and the rules we endorse are objective to the extent that
they help in overcoming not merely the surface symptoms but the
deep cause—the restricted character of our evolved responsive-
ness to others. Objectivity in that sense enables us to talk of moral
progress, not as increasing proximity to independently fixed moral
truths, but in terms of problem-solving. The keys we sometimes
devise fit some of the locks we need to open. As with other forms
of technology, we can understand progress in morality as accumu-
lating solutions to problems. Moral progress has been partial, and
vulnerable to reversal, and it occurs significantly less frequently
than would be desirable—but it exists. Dewey’s hope—which
I share—is that an understanding of the character of the moral
project (and its offspring, the ethical project) can help us make
progressive transitions more frequently, more completely, more
reliably, and with more enduring results (Kitcher 2021a).
If anything like this picture is correct, then it bears on the way
philosophy should proceed along the value axis. Contemporary
meta-ethics, as practiced in the English-speaking world, is full of
questions about “reasons” and “knowledge” that an account of eth-
ics as social technology bypasses. Those who use these idioms rarely
deploy them to offer methodological advice for ethical inquiry.
Their discussions of reasons candidly concede that little can be said
about what reasons are. Indeed, we might wonder whether enti-
ties appropriately dubbed “reasons” exist. To be sure, people make
up their minds by thinking things through, engaging in forms of
reasoning good or bad. Does that entail the existence of reasons?
Although deliberators often describe themselves as doing things
for reasons, that hardly clinches the matter. After all, people do
things for the sake of those they care about. I suspect very few of
20 What’s the Use of Philosophy?
***
Why does that image matter? What is the point of the metaphi-
losophical question? I gave one part of the answer already: the
common Anglophone conception of philosophy shapes the ways
in which practitioners relate to other areas of inquiry and to the
problems of everyday human life. A faulty image will mislead
the profession of philosophy, and the consequence will be a fail-
ure to fulfill the functions with which philosophers are properly
charged. My reintroduction of the theme of education suggests
the second part of the answer. Graduate programs in philosophy
currently train highly intelligent and imaginative young people,
whose lives will be dominated for decades by the problems their
mentors and colleagues take to be central to the field. We train
them well by giving them studies that improve their facility for
thinking precisely and rigorously. If, however, the prevailing
image of philosophy fails to distinguish the preliminary studies
from the genuine work, if it treats what is most important as mere
periphery, as a place in which the second-raters slum it, then their
education will have failed them. Whether they eventually recog-
nize it or not, they may spend their entire lives knocking a second
off the performance of Multi-Scale 937 or adding an extra trill to
Quadruple Tremolo 41.
2 “ SO . . . W H O IS YO U R
AU D I E N C E? ”
What’s the Use of Philosophy? Philip Kitcher, Oxford University Press. © Oxford University Press
2023. DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780197657249.003.0002
“ S O . . . W H O I S YO U R A U D I E N C E ? ” 27
***
***
***
For all of its attractions, I am not happy with this answer. Let
me explain.
***
them. Almost forty years ago, Clark Glymour and Judaea Pearl
independently began to explore the possibilities of using directed
graphs to frame causal hypotheses from statistical data (Spirtes,
Glymour, and Scheines 2000; Pearl 2000). Today, the method-
ological proposals advanced by Pearl, and, perhaps, even more
those articulated by Glymour and the brilliant team he has assem-
bled at Carnegie-Mellon University, are being used across a swath
of special sciences. Valuable exercises in methodology have them-
selves been revived with the resurrection of causality (Woodward
2021). Nevertheless, Fine is partly vindicated. Significant further
work in methodology required a different focus (on the problem
of finding causal hypotheses), one that was compatible with the
disunities found in scientific practice. And, perhaps most impor-
tantly, it required a vast amount of dedicated effort on the part of
highly talented people.
My second example addresses an even larger lacuna in the logi-
cal empiricist approach, one shared with the great tradition out
of which it grew. With the conspicuous exception of Peirce, pre-
twentieth-century methodologists sought canons of individual
methodology. They considered how a single investigator should
properly adjust belief in light of interactions with nature. Peirce
not only recognized that inquiry is a communal affair. He also
started to consider the ways in which the efforts of individual
researchers might best be distributed if the community is to
make epistemic progress—he talked of the “economy of research.”
Twentieth- century methodology ignored the hint, remaining
relentlessly individualistic, until— interestingly—Kuhn’s cele-
brated monograph highlighted the scientific community and rec-
ognized the possibility of reasonable cognitive variation within it.
48 What’s the Use of Philosophy?
***
And I also want to make a case for the third possible audience.
Indeed, at this particular moment in human history, the need to
present scientific issues clearly to people who are not scientists
seems to me the most crucial task of all. The rest of this chapter
will be devoted to explaining and defending that view, idiosyn-
cratic as it may initially appear.
We live at a time when many decisions profoundly affecting
human lives turn on the details of the sciences, sometimes with
respect to matters on which a community of scientists agree,
sometimes on topics about which there is lively debate. When
citizens of affluent democracies have misguided views about what
policies (and which candidates) will advance their goals, their
choices at the ballot box can run directly contrary to their inter-
ests. Ironically, the act through which democracy is often taken to
express its commitment to individual freedom then undermines
that freedom. Where misinformation is rife, democracy starts to
collapse.
Hence, advancing the knowledge of citizens is an important
task. If philosophers writing for the general public were able to
make their readers more likely to understand and accept the
50 What’s the Use of Philosophy?
***
***
work beside the various areas of inquiry and culture and practice.
Instead, it works between and among them. As Dewey puts the
point, it tries to offer the meanings of what human beings have
come to know. In that consists the successor discipline we need to
replace the metaphysics of the past.
In a highly complex world, the project of offering an illuminat-
ing synthesis of every significant aspect may be too ambitious for
any individual thinker. Philosophers are often disinclined to col-
laborate, but perhaps it is worth considering a more cooperative
future. An obvious alternative would be to focus on a particular
facet of the world as we find it. Philosophy of science would con-
tribute a general picture of the sciences and of science as an impor-
tant institution in human societies.
For all their faults, logical positivism and logical empiricism
undertook part of that task. So, too, did Popper and Kuhn. Their
greater influence may stem from their willingness to connect,
from time to time, with social and political issues. Today, perhaps
because we recognize the heterogeneity of scientific practices, the
philosophy of science has not yet offered any convincing substitute.
Ironically, though, the best versions we have emerge in the writ-
ings of prominent “disunity theorists”—Longino, Cartwright,
Dupré, Ian Hacking, Hasok Chang, and Michela Massimi.
So I offer a threefold answer to my original question. The audi-
ence for philosophy of science should include philosophers, scien-
tists, and thoughtful members of the public (the supposed, possibly
mythical, “educated general reader”). If, as a matter of fact, any of
these groups—especially the last—is playing truant, it’s part of our
responsibility to try to bring them back. Occasionally, a philoso-
pher can speak to all three audiences at once—as Daniel Dennett
56 What’s the Use of Philosophy?
What’s the Use of Philosophy? Philip Kitcher, Oxford University Press. © Oxford University Press
2023. DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780197657249.003.0003
58 What’s the Use of Philosophy?
***
***
reminder that “in the long run we are all dead,” convergence theo-
rems might guide an inquiry to finding evidence that would accel-
erate consensus.
Nevertheless, all too many important scientific decisions, past
and present, could not and cannot be made in the way formal
theorists envisage. Consider the prediction that, by 2070, over a
billion people will be forced to leave their homes because increases
in local temperatures will make those places uninhabitable.
Despite a vast amount of evidence about the changing climate,
nobody has a formal calculus for assigning a probability to that
hypothesis. The best those who deliberate about the issue—like
the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (IPCC)—can
do is to rely on the informal judgments of a very wide population
of experts (who make their own best guesses). Fetishistic formal-
ization aims to drive out judgment. Often, however, the judgment
of the experienced is the best we have. Reasonableness outruns the
kind of rationality that demands algorithms and is never satisfied
without calculations.
Once this point is appreciated, it is possible to see how a valu-
able philosophical program can degenerate into insignificance,
pressing for formalization when playing with the existing tools
will only yield tiny returns, if any at all. Although the philosophy
of science is a relatively healthy subdiscipline, its zest for formal-
ization über alles sometimes needs to be restrained.
Formalistic fetishism is more evident in other parts of philoso-
phy. Sometimes, to be sure, using some existing formal language
enables an author to avoid ambiguity in the presentation of some
putative principle. All too often, however, the introduction of the
notation seems to be designed to add extra importance to some
68 What’s the Use of Philosophy?
***
70 What’s the Use of Philosophy?
Philosopher Deciding
Derek is a philosopher, trying to decide whether a particu-
lar ethical principle is correct. He considers a wide variety of
cases to which the principle might be applied. Finding that,
in some of them, his intuition is that it holds, while, in a few
of them, his intuition tells him that it does not, he modi-
fies the principle. The new version is—intuitively—satisfied
in all the cases. But, pressing further, he invents new cases
in which his revised principle breaks down (as he discovers
through consulting his intuition). Accordingly, he revises the
principle again and repeats the procedure. After a number of
iterations, he is content. The principle at which he has now
arrived is—intuitively—completely successful. He judges it
to be correct. Is Derek’s final judgment justified?
Drowning Child
You are well-dressed for a social event. On your way to it, you
pass a pond, and observe a child in the water. The child is
obviously struggling, and although the pond is not very deep,
will drown unless someone intervenes. You are the only per-
son in the vicinity. To wade into the water would make your
clothes wet and muddy, so that you would be inappropriately
clad for the occasion to which you are headed. What should
you do?
Like Singer, like every other philosopher I know, like all the
undergraduates to whom I have ever told some version of this
story, I take the answer to be obvious. You should plunge in and
rescue the child. Simply walking on and arriving unsullied at the
72 What’s the Use of Philosophy?
Lots of people think it’s obvious. You should throw the switch and
save the five. It’s impossible to rescue all these luckless people, and
it’s better that five should survive, rather than only one.
Anyone who believes that the numbers always count will
arrive at that verdict. So, provided you are already committed to a
Pathology R eport 73
into the case. But still, if you ask me how I would act, if I were
beside the track, I’d search for some way of stopping the trolley.
I wouldn’t know that it’s impossible, and I’d keep trying. At the last
moment, in desperation, I might throw the switch, but I wouldn’t
see that as the right thing, only as the lesser of two bad options. I’d
regard myself as having failed. I hadn’t been sufficiently resource-
ful in finding a way out.”
That response— and I’ve heard something like it several
times—identifies a crucial difficulty with this kind of case. To
make the case work, all kinds of constraints have to be imposed.
Moreover, it’s not enough for these conditions to apply in the
envisaged situation—they also have to be matters about which
the agent is completely sure. So a world is constructed, a “small
world,” one totally alien to the students’ experience. Imaginative
identification is blocked because they can’t think themselves into
a world with those properties, can’t imagine being certain about
all the things that force the alleged options for them. This world is
just too small—it constricts them. They rightly resist the attempt
to compel judgment when their capacities for judging find no pur-
chase. So they lack the “intuitions” philosophers think they are
supposed to have.
But it gets worse. Trackside View is only the beginning of wis-
dom in Trolleyology. My students are even more perplexed by a
well-known follow-up case.
***
Pathology R eport 81
Let’s briefly take stock. I’ve reviewed three pathologies: the fetish
for complete clarity, the fetish for formalization, and the intro-
duction of hypothetical cases, so far removed from reality as to
defy imaginative identification. Before proceeding to my second
trio, it’s worth noting how these three are easily found in combi-
nation with one another.
Someone who seeks an analysis of a concept that will cover all
possible cases, or the formulation of a principle that would hold
in any possible situation, will be driven to test proposed analyses
or available versions against any scenario an inventive mind can
dream up. The enterprise of revising current proposals may start
close enough to home to elicit confident responses about whether,
under the circumstances considered, the test has been passed. Yet,
given the goal of universality, the enterprise must leave the sphere
within which imaginative identification can be achieved. The test
cases introduced will come to include some ingenious fantasies
with respect to which unbiased “intuition” yields no answer. At
this point, aspiring authors committed to a particular analysis
or principle often declare the test to have been passed, while oth-
ers, with different affiliations, will see failure. Both sides are then
inspired to generate more scenarios, ever more intricate and fan-
ciful, in their endeavors to demonstrate the correctness of their
response to the cases that provoke division. For any philosopher
who has followed the career of a significant number of debates
during the past several decades, the dynamic is surely familiar.
Cases are multiplied. The analyses and principles become laden
with qualifying clauses in attempts to accommodate the cornuco-
pia of “intuitive evidence.” Until, ultimately, the enterprise runs
82 What’s the Use of Philosophy?
***
authoritative testimony, and the like. Let’s say, then, that a claim is
weakly a priori just in case it satisfies only Kant’s first condition—
the thought process generating it is always available, and if, given
the experience the believer has, it is actually justified and actually
true. I suspect that most of the authors who decorate the premises
they introduce (without further support) as “a priori” have some-
thing like this in mind. If they do not, they owe the world some
account of why they are using the term, since they appear to be
rejecting all the conditions that their illustrious philosophical pre-
decessors have placed upon it.
If, however, they declare their favored necessary premise to
be weakly a priori, they have lapsed into a fourth pathology—I’ll
call it sprinkling fairy dust. For the effect of labeling Necessary
Premise in this way (probably the intended effect) is to trans-
form an unfamiliar and often ugly statement—a philosophical
frog—into a gleaming philosophical prince. Wearing “a priori”
Necessary Premise stands before the readers in full glory. No fur-
ther questions need to be asked about its (his) credentials. Just
look inward and reflect. The thought process should run its course
in you, bringing the indisputable charm of Necessary Premise to
your consciousness. If it does not . . . ? The defect is in you.
Claiming apriority is currently less popular than appeal-
ing to intuition about cases—but the two strategies are in the
same line of work, and sometimes even fused together.1 In both
instances, they preempt objections to a thesis the author needs,
if he is to elaborate his argument. I have already suggested a more
accurate and more modest reformulation of “My intuition about
this case is . . . .” The appeal to the a priori should also be recast.
Instead of saying “Necessary Premise is a priori,” it would be more
88 What’s the Use of Philosophy?
***
***
***
T he sentence that supplies the title for this chapter is the third and
last of a short paragraph in William James’s seminal Pragmatism.
It is far less often quoted than its predecessor, which presents a theme
many scholars have seen as central to the pragmatist movement: the
idea of there being no difference that doesn’t make a difference to
“somebody, somehow, somewhere and somewhen.” The three sen-
tences of that paragraph were important to James. They all occur in
a much longer passage in the lecture in which he initially announced
“the pragmatic method,” a lecture delivered almost a decade earlier
(at what was then known as “the University of California”) and first
published six years after it was given (James 1904/1978).
Even more explicitly in that earlier lecture, James’s goal was
to point out how philosophical disputes can easily collapse into
What’s the Use of Philosophy? Philip Kitcher, Oxford University Press. © Oxford University Press
2023. DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780197657249.003.0004
T he W hole F unction of P hilosophy 109
James was far from the first to feel a need to scrutinize the
worth of philosophical projects. At the end of the Enquiry
Concerning Human Understanding, David Hume proposes a pro-
gram of philosophy book burning. Writings dealing with “rela-
tions of ideas”—treatises in logic and mathematics—should be
preserved. So, too, for works offering factual information about
the natural or social world. All the rest should be committed “to
the flames” because they “can contain nothing but sophistry and
illusion.” Hume’s peroration would be echoed, a decade or so after
James’s death, in the logical positivists’ campaign for the elimi-
nation of metaphysics. The difference between James’s diagnosis
and that shared by Hume and the positivists turns on alternative
readings of an ambiguous word: “significant.” For Hume and
company (including, allegedly, the properly domesticated James)
much of philosophy is insignificant in the sense of being literally
meaningless. For the real James, and even more explicitly for John
Dewey, philosophy, as often practiced, lacks significance because
it is unimportant, and the unimportance shows up in the lack of
any impact on people’s lives.
As previous chapters have noted, Dewey’s writings contain
many elaborations of James’s diagnosis. Democracy and Education
charges that philosophy may not only suffer from being “merely
verbal” but also become “a sentimental indulgence for a few”
(Dewey 1916/ 1975, 338). Five years later Reconstruction in
Philosophy amplifies the charge. Dewey reflects on academic life,
noting how it represents a “social division of labor.” The division,
he thinks, only proves healthy when those who pursue “theory and
knowledge” are “in unobstructed cooperation with other social
occupations, sensitive to others’ problems and transmitting results
T he W hole F unction of P hilosophy 111
***
did. But, they insist, that kind of work is not everything. It leaves
out important kinds of studies philosophers pursue. A world in
which philosophy is reduced to the ventures that make immediate
social impact would have lost something important.
I agree wholeheartedly. On this point, my critics are entirely
correct. My earlier account was incomplete. But I don’t think the
“enduringly significant core” of philosophy is what they think it
is. James saw more, and saw more clearly, than those who protest
my philistinism.
***
***
***
120 What’s the Use of Philosophy?
***
***
The world we inhabit often seems far more complicated than the
ones in which the great philosophers of the past made their wide-
ranging proposals. Should that excuse contemporary philosophers
from pursuing synthetic philosophy? Aristotle could do it. Kant,
perhaps, could do it. Sadly, though, we can’t do it.
To be sure, nobody today can hope to write as intelligently on
so many topics as Aristotle did. Yet it’s worth asking: did Aristotle
write about everything that mattered to his contemporaries?
Certainly not. He ignored a fair number of areas of potential con-
cern to various groups of people—most evidently, the slaves and
the women of his age. Even if we restrict attention to the well-born
male members of the polis, did he provide them with a complete
account of how everything hangs together? His works are a seri-
ous candidate for “most impressive synthesis of current knowledge
ever given.” But they are silent, or scanty in what they say, on any
number of issues: questions about religion, economic life, educa-
tion, and the treatment of animals, for example. Is the synthesis
only incomplete because the pertinent texts—like the examina-
tion of comedy—have gone missing?
Kant is the only subsequent philosopher whose synthetic
scope might rival Aristotle’s. Scholars routinely praise the depth
T he W hole F unction of P hilosophy 127
***
***
***
of the state decide on a selection. There is, then, a shift from think-
ing of what would be good for the individual pupil to considering
what the state most needs. In the modern world this is keyed to
the interest in economic and technological success. Reflections on
how to shape good citizens, or to prepare people to live fulfilling
lives, take second place—if they come in at all. As talented histori-
ans have shown (Graham 2005), American education (and educa-
tion in other affluent democracies) has tended to lurch from one
set of central purposes to another, driven by the perceived needs of
a society at various times. The emphasis on the imperative to out-
produce and outcompete rival nations is simply the latest chapter
in this disjointed story.
Parents all over the world hope the schools their children
attend will help them develop, to be the best they can be. How
those parents think about what is best is inevitably shaped by a
large variety of factors, some drawn from the dominant culture
(“Our daughter needs to learn how to support herself ”), some
from their own relation to other institutions (“It’s important
that she keeps her faith and forms a firm moral compass”), some
from their sense of what has been important (or lost) in their own
lives (“I would hate her to lose her freedom and spontaneity”),
some from their social and political commitments (“She needs to
understand the importance of community and serving the com-
munity”). They, too, are overloaded, wanting many things for
their kids, and not seeing clearly how to come to a manageable
selection.
These, then, were some of my phenomena. Chaotic and con-
fused. My task was to bring them to order. Not just for myself.
I was convinced that perplexities about what counts as good
142 What’s the Use of Philosophy?
the whole. Bringing some order to the chaos under my own hat
and offering the result to others.
One feature of this example may suggest good places in which
to look for the starting points from which synthetic philosophy
can grow. Our lives are wholes, but we live them in and across
many domains: we work and we play, we teach and are educated,
we earn money and we spend it, we play sports and we pursue
other hobbies, we participate in political life and we worship (or
turn our backs on religion), we form friendships and (sometimes)
provoke enmity, we fall in love. The domains are inhabited by
conventions, norms, rules, roles, and institutions. Each individual
domain may make what is, by its own lights, progress: the church
may be renewed, the economic system may become more efficient,
love may be deepened and enriched, or the recognition of loving
relations may be broadened.
Yet it is possible, it seems, that progress in some domains may
inhibit the progressive development of others. There can be insti-
tutional friction. That occurs when a change occurring in one set
of institutions counts, according to the standards reigning in that
domain as an advance, but also imposes checks on the progress
of another domain. The apparently progressive domain constrains
its neighbor, preventing advances or, worse, even causing regress.
That occurs in the example I have given. Economic life constrains
practices of education. The priority given to the goal of self-
maintenance (“getting a good job”) crowds out other educational
values—finding a satisfying identity, preparation for a fulfilling
life, becoming a good citizen—because the apparent streamlining
of economic arrangements demands more time for the develop-
ment of work-related skills, at cost to less “practical” studies.
144 What’s the Use of Philosophy?
***
what is not, worth pursuing should not be forced upon them from
an external standpoint. Each of us ought to look at our lives from
a number of angles, comparing what we conceive of doing with
the “experiments of living” pursued by others, and considering
whether the pattern of similarities and differences corresponds to
our own sense of spending our existence wisely. In a world where
it is all too easy for highly talented people to adopt the conven-
tions of a profession with obvious attractions, what is crucial is to
undermine complacency, to suggest angles from which everyday
practices look less obviously important, and to initiate a process
of self-interrogation. I hope I have said enough to start that—
philosophical—trial and to provide some resources for conducting
it appropriately. The eventual verdict, however, must be your own.
***
times, her studies are directed toward the ways in which particular
pieces of science are used in developing policies with social impact.
That part of her work falls under the so-called peripheral ventures
I praised in the first chapter. Some of the time, then, she is doing
synthetic philosophy, and at other times she is using (“applying”?)
philosophy to make a direct contribution to specific (and urgent)
social problems.
Which of these genres is more important? I find the question
impossible to answer. What criterion would we appeal to in rat-
ing one kind as more important—more “central to philosophy”
than the other? Nor do I believe in a sharp distinction between
them. For, if the synthesis is relatively small-scale and the social
problem relatively broad, either label may be appropriate. The
boundary between “two genres” becomes indecipherable. An
exploration of the potential ethical losses faced by people who
aspire to a very different kind of life than the ones common in the
communities into which they are born (the “strivers” as Jennifer
Morton calls them in an insightful recent book) can be viewed
either as addressed to a single social problem or as presenting
a synthetic perspective on a class of issues highly significant to
anyone whose chosen plan of life involves a disruption of com-
munity. The label attached to studies like this is unimportant. If
they are pursued with the care and sensitivity of Morton (2020),
their value is evident.
So, although I have used a ladder to climb, I now want to kick
it away. My articulation of James’s conception of “the whole func-
tion of philosophy” was an attempt to embrace an insight of critics
of my earlier efforts to offer a pragmatist account of philosophy.
T he W hole F unction of P hilosophy 147
***
But what exactly does it give to the intellectual and social worlds?
I want to close by trying for a little further clarity and precision.
We can make some progress on this issue by reflecting on a recent
debate, centered on the question of philosophy’s progress.
This is, I believe, typically couched in the wrong terms.
Philosophy is taken to strive for theories, and the theories are
intended to be true. But philosophers always disagree, and the dis-
agreements persist—indeed, they are so long-lasting, and so much
ingenuity is displayed in conducting them, that it would be folly
to hail any philosophical theory as true. Hence pessimism: there
is no progress in philosophy.
For some people, including powerful outsiders (perhaps a
Provost or Dean, keen on translational research and impatient
with the interminable debates endemic to supposedly important
disciplines), there’s a corollary. In hard budgetary times, you can
cut, or even abolish, the philosophy department. Why invest in
researchers who never offer any new knowledge? My answer is
straightforward: because, working in the interstices of the fields
of first-order inquiry, philosophy helps all those fields and helps
humanity to take full advantage of their epistemic achievements.
It does so by offering cognitive resources—not theories of every-
thing (or, indeed, anything) but concepts, questions, suggestive
arguments, and analogies. Those are useful in individual delibera-
tions as people try to come to terms with the particular muddles
T he W hole F unction of P hilosophy 149
***
What’s the Use of Philosophy? Philip Kitcher, Oxford University Press. © Oxford University Press
2023. DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780197657249.003.0005
156 What’s the Use of Philosophy?
lives. You do not wish to spend your own careers in this way. You
would like to contribute to a broader philosophical project, one
akin to what the past philosophers you admire most have pursued.
You would like your work to have an impact on people’s lives,
beyond the philosophy profession and beyond the academy. Like
me, you regret the dominant mood of judging such aspirations to
be somehow second-rate, inferior to the supposedly important
work that wins acceptance from “the top journals.”
But you are young. Your careers are just beginning. You have
no job security. Even if you are in a tenure-track position, you
know that your chances of obtaining permanent employment will
depend on assessments of your published work, perhaps of your
work-in-progress, and that, at some stage of the process, your con-
tributions will be assessed by people who adopt the dominant pro-
fessional attitude. Although your colleagues may be sympathetic
to the kind of philosophy you would like to write, it is highly
likely that some of the external letters they solicit will be more
dismissive. And, of course, your current post may be temporary, a
postdoctoral fellowship, or a one-year “replacement” position. You
may be scurrying from institution to institution as an underpaid
adjunct. You may be struggling with a heavy teaching load, one
those whose work enjoys high prestige would find intolerable. You
may not even have a job at all.
So, you ask, what are you to do? You judge that, if you do not
play by the rules, your prospects of continuing in philosophy are
far from bright. Hence, however appealing you may find my call
for reform, you see it as an invitation to gamble at unfavorable
odds, where the loss would involve forfeiting the opportunities
for which you have spent years of hard work preparing. It would
L etter to S ome Young P hilosophers 157
who completed a PhD, one who did not, decided on this as the
best choice for them. Both were dedicated to philosophy—and
equally dedicated to teaching precollege students. Finding them-
selves in a professional environment hostile to their own visions of
what philosophy should do, they resolved not to force themselves
into the molds expected of them but to teach under a regime in
which their future writing would not be a factor in advancing,
retarding, or ending their careers. They have retained the part of
philosophical practice they love; they teach and enlighten young
people, some of whom will go on to colleges and universities. In
their spare time, these two devoted teachers can write the kinds of
philosophy they value.
Would that satisfy you? Perhaps not. For you may reasonably
fear that, without continued interactions with colleagues and
with more advanced students, your own teaching would become
more mechanical and less effective. Contrary to a popular stereo-
type, teaching and research are by no means incompatible. To be
sure, there are only so many hours in a working day, and, when the
preparation for teaching is more demanding and the time in the
classroom increases, the period set aside for research is squeezed.
Moreover, many of you are at a stage in your lives when you expe-
rience not only the career challenges—writing articles that will
establish you as a researcher, learning how best to communicate
with your students—but also the demands and responsibilities
(and joys!) of raising children. Although creative thinking about
philosophical issues usually refreshes and enlivens teaching, just as
teaching often opens up new questions for philosophical research,
your days may be too loaded with other activities to allow very
much of either form of synergy.
L etter to S ome Young P hilosophers 163
That is a serious loss. For, if you are lucky enough to have time
for exploration, your teaching can even open up a new field, one
to which you may devote years. I had that good fortune. Almost
at the beginning of my teaching career, a student at the University
of Vermont changed the direction of my writing. Somewhat dif-
fidently, he came to see me in office hours, to tell me that the
students in my philosophy of science class were, like him, mostly
premeds, and that they would appreciate some examples from
biology. I was too ashamed to confess that I was utterly ignorant
about this area of science, but his plea did prod me to visit the
library, where I discovered David Hull’s recently published intro-
ductory volume (Hull 1974—probably the most important text
in inspiring the development of philosophy of biology). I started
reading and was hooked. It led me to a program of wide reading
in biology, to many long sessions with biologist colleagues, to a
sabbatical at Harvard’s Museum of Comparative Zoology, and to
writing a number of books and articles in this area of philosophy.
A very few people spend a lifetime as wonderful teachers
of philosophy, without writing very much at all. Another small
minority are prolific authors, although they never teach. For most,
however, there is a useful interaction between the two parts of a
philosophical career. You may well conclude that, without tak-
ing on both roles, you would not succeed in the one to which you
devoted all your time.
Option two attempts to respond to that concern. Instead of
abandoning research, you live a divided professional life. You rec-
ognize that, to teach philosophy at the level that satisfies you, in
the way that you take to be most helpful to your students (and,
possibly, to other audiences), you need an academic license. To
164 What’s the Use of Philosophy?
buy and renew that license, you have to pay in the currency the
profession demands. So, periodically, you will have to publish an
article or two, to show you are still a card-carrying member of the
professional philosophers’ club. You don’t like the genre, but you
know how to play the game. You resolve to do that throughout
your academic life.
You wonder, of course, if you can keep it up. Will the times
at which you find paying your dues frustrating, unpleasant, even
sickening, come to be frequent enough to provoke you to chuck
it all in? Even if you are confident about your strength of will,
you are still likely to feel unsatisfied. You probably want to con-
tribute not only to the lives of those whom you teach but also to
the advance of philosophy. Realistically, none of us can expect to
do very much in this way—the changes most philosophical writ-
ing can inspire are small—but you want to try to leave your own
mark. You care about philosophy. You would like to show how to
think philosophically about a live social issue or to craft some par-
tial synthesis. The hoops you must jump through to maintain your
credentials detract from your ability to do the kind of research you
passionately want to pursue. They take considerable time. And
they sap your energy. Perhaps you also regard your professional
writings as a kind of pretense, and your hours spent on them as
exercises in mauvaise foi.
The research pressures of the world you inhabit are consider-
ably more intense than those I experienced when I was starting
out. During the course of your graduate training, you may have
been advised by well-meaning mentors to send off a paper to a jour-
nal. If you heeded the advice, you have probably already felt the
keen sting of disappointment that comes from rejection, whether
L etter to S ome Young P hilosophers 165
few talks about the deep flaws in Creationism. The third accident
occurred when, over lunch with Harry and Betty Stanton (the
founders of Bradford Books), I casually mentioned what I had
been doing. They immediately insisted that I must write a short
book on the subject. Abusing Science (Kitcher 1982) was the out-
come of that conversation, written in the following months, and
published very quickly thereafter.
Few philosophers feel contempt for those who take up the
cudgels on this kind of issue. Or for those who write about the
overreach of human sociobiology, or about the ethical and social
implications of the Human Genome Project, or about “intelligent
design,” or about the dangers of scientism, or about debates over
what to do about climate change. I have had it very easy. As do
many philosophers of science. There are plenty of places at which
pieces of scientific research have an impact on public policies and
thus on human lives. Philosophers who write on these topics will
not be dismissed as having abandoned the discipline. They are
seen as using their philosophical training in valuable ways, even
though it isn’t “core philosophy.” And, of course, if they some-
times publish articles in “mainstream journals,” that adds to the
aura of respectability.
No cunning plan, laid out in advance. Lots of luck, with, at
the end, an emerging perspective on what philosophy is and what
it should be. The hybrid option will work—if your interests lie in
particular directions, and if you enjoy sufficiently large doses of
good fortune.
My fourth option attempts to generalize from the hybrid
approach. It looks for philosophical fields in which questions
arise that have an impact on people’s lives and also are likely to be
L etter to S ome Young P hilosophers 171
far stronger claim to the title of deserter. Isn’t the narrowness and
insularity of their productions a clear sign of having abandoned
the great philosophical tradition?
I do not think what I have said so far touches the deepest
source of your concerns. For it leaves in place many features of the
status quo. As I hear you, you do not simply want to carve out a
life in which you can do the work you want, having a satisfactory
career within a philosophical world run according to a particular
conception, and imposing particular standards. Or to leave it, and
work elsewhere, on terms of peaceful coexistence with the profes-
sional orthodoxy. You want to change the conception and replace
the standards. Even if “core philosophers” come to recognize the
value of what you do, you don’t want the prevailing notion of what
“core philosophy” is to remain in place. Perhaps (like the author
who wrote the original version of Chapter 1) you would like to
turn philosophy inside out. Or maybe (as I hope) you share the
present author’s wish that the pathologies will be cured, the dis-
tinction between core and periphery abolished, and the philo-
sophical venture regain its power to have an intellectual impact,
through its direct contributions to resolving particular live issues
and through its partial syntheses. In the end, it’s not just about
your life. It’s about the future of the discipline you love.
As I said in my reply to that first questioner, and have said on
several occasions since, it’s the responsibility of senior members of
the profession who have arrived (sometimes, as I have, in chancy
and muddled ways) at the views I have outlined here, to do what
they can to amend the norms and conventions of the profession,
the constraints that bind, under which you chafe. To “play the
game” or to “go under cover” or even to follow my fourth option
L etter to S ome Young P hilosophers 177
would not count as a full solution. The point is not just to under-
stand the state of the Anglophone philosophy profession. It is to
change it.
How can that be done? Hastening to the barricades to dem-
onstrate against the philosophical establishment is not likely to
succeed. Defenders of the current professionalization will use
the skills they deploy in their professional work to eviscerate the
demonstrators—or to carry out what they, and those who are like-
minded, can claim to be evisceration. We do better, I think, to
build on some of the developments of the past decade to create—
together—an academic environment in which the kind of work
you hope to do can be supported, in which its worth—and its
attractions—will become ever more visible.
In my opening fantasy, the breakaway pianists who desert the
étude Olympics to perform classics (and, perhaps, some newly
written pieces) for an appreciative audience only elicit even more
disdainful sniffs from the cognoscenti. That is not the inevi-
table end of the story, although it may well be a passing phase.
Continued acclaim for “popular concerts” could slowly begin an
exodus. Not only does the noncompeting audience for further
assaults on Multiple Tremolo 41 disappear entirely, but, each year,
the number of competitors diminishes. Eventually, disdain proves
hard to sustain. Only the diehards resist joining their fellows who
receive the adulation of the slums.
As the previous chapter noted, the past ten years have witnessed
a shift. More philosophers have begun to write for a broader public.
Their ranks include some established figures, people whose writ-
ings on “core topics” have been much admired. I gave a very short
list (the first few people who came to my mind) in the previous
178 What’s the Use of Philosophy?
chapter, but there are many more, people whose work you know
better than I do, and whose writings may have given you encourage-
ment. Inspired by this trend, those who would like to see philoso-
phy regain its place in the wider culture might band together, start
a movement to plead for institutional changes, at first on a modest
scale. The acknowledgment of “public philosophy” as an important
part of what philosophers do could be expressed in the funding
of centers to support scholars—especially younger scholars—so
they could have time to develop their contributions to this genre.
Fellowships for one year or for two years would be a start.
A campaign to enrich philosophical culture could begin there.
It should aspire, however, to go much further. Centers of this kind
might invest in longer-term support. The seven years of an All
Souls’ Prize Fellowship—under which Amia Srinivasan was given
time to think through her ideas—provide a model for nurturing
more ambitious ventures in synthetic philosophy. The status quo
does not have to be overthrown overnight. Its limitations may
become evident as alternatives to the current professional style
become ever more diverse and ever more visible.
If these limited ventures succeed, more ambitious reforms
may follow. Philosophy is currently an isolated discipline within
a larger cluster of academic fields, the always-besieged low-status
areas universities call “the Humanities.” As philosophers emerge
who can begin to engage with their colleagues from other parts of
this culture, philosophy contributes to a valuable general program
in the Humanities—philosophers participate in a curriculum
in which the synthetic enterprises of philosophy’s past are given
their due. Such programs enlighten those who teach, as well as
those whose official role is that of student. Rereading classic works
L etter to S ome Young P hilosophers 179
CHAPTER 1
1. My case is restricted to philosophy in the English- speaking world.
Some non-A nglophone traditions seem healthier. I think, for example,
of Frankfurt School critical theory, especially as developed by Jürgen
Habermas, Axel Honneth, and Rahel Jaeggi.
2. I follow other authors, especially Bernard Williams, in distinguishing
between morality and ethics. Morality is concerned with action: its central
question is “What should I do?” Ethics is broader, asking “What kind of
person should I be?” It is more inclusive than morality, since acting rightly
is necessary (but not sufficient) for being ethically good.
CHAPTER 2
1. As noted in the Preface, my references to particular authors, whom
I associate with positive developments, are intended merely to point to
instances of various general types. It would be foolish to claim that my
choices are the only exemplars, or even the best ones. Others would select
differently, and I would expect broad agreement on the value of a far
lengthier list.
CHAPTER 3
1. Perhaps the author would be inclined to imitate Shakespeare’s Cassius:
183
184 Notes
2. Perhaps evolutionary debunkers will contend that this is not the challenge
they intend to level. “We’re concerned,” they may say, “with the selective
advantage of a whole moral sense. What’s the use of that?” To which
the obvious reply is: “In which environment? If you are talking about a
world—like ours—in which people with defective capacities of this kind
are condemned and socially sanctioned, there are some pretty obvious
advantages of having the capacity moral realists ascribe. The real issue,
then, is how an environment of that type came to be, how a significantly
large majority of the human population came to be able to make and act on
correct moral judgments and to expect their fellows to conform to them.
Hence, your question is a historical one, focused on how an embryonic
power of detection caught on sufficiently widely to make that kind of
environment possible. So you are asking the same question as the higher
end versions of Creationism, while remaining lamentably vague about the
specifics. And offering the same cheap gibe.”
REFERENCES
Akerlof, George. 1984. “The Market for Lemons: Quality, Uncertainty, and
the Market Mechanism.” In An Economic Theorist’s Book of Tales, 7–22.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Albert, David. 1992. Quantum Mechanics and Experience. Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press.
Anderson, Elizabeth. 2010. The Imperative of Integration. Princeton,
NJ: Princeton University Press.
Anderson, Elizabeth. 2017. Private Government. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press.
Appiah, Kwame Anthony. 1992. In My Father’s House. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Appiah, Kwame Anthony. 2006. The Ethics of Identity. Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press.
Appiah, Kwame Anthony. 2018. The Lies That Bind. New York: Norton/
Liveright.
Barnes, Barry. 1977. Interests and the Growth of Knowledge. London: Routledge
and Kegan Paul.
Carnap, Rudolf. 1928. Scheinprobleme in der Philosophie. Berlin:
Weltkreis-Verlag.
Cartwright, Nancy. 1983. How the Laws of Physics Lie. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Cartwright, Nancy. 1999. The Dappled World. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Cartwright, Nancy. 2007. Hunting Causes and Using Them. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
185
186 References
Cavell, Stanley. 1969. Must We Mean What We Say? New York: Scribner’s.
Churchland, Patricia. 2019. Conscience. New York: W.W. Norton.
Collins, Harry. 1985. Changing Order. London: Sage.
Danto, Arthur. 1964. “The Artworld.” Journal of Philosophy 61: 571–584.
Danto, Arthur. 1981. The Transfiguration of the Commonplace. Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press.
Danto, Arthur. 1997. After the End of Art. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press.
Dewey, John. (1909) 1998. “The Influence of Darwin on Philosophy.” In
John Dewey, The Middle Works, Vol. 4, 3–14. Carbondale: University of
Southern Illinois.
Dewey, John. (1916) 1980. Democracy and Education. Carbondale: University
of Southern Illinois. 1980 reprinting of the 1916 original as John Dewey,
The Middle Works, vol. 9.
Dewey, John. (1920) 1982. Reconstruction in Philosophy. Carbondale: University
of Southern Illinois. 1982 reprinting of the 1920 original as John Dewey,
The Middle Works, vol. 12.
Dewey, John. (1925) 1981. Experience and Nature. Carbondale: University
of Southern Illinois Press. 1981 reprinting of the 1925 original as John
Dewey: The Later Works, vol. 1.
Dewey, John. (1929) 1988. The Quest for Certainty. Carbondale: University
of Southern Illinois Press. 1988 reprinting of the 1929 original as John
Dewey: The Later Works, vol. 4.
Dewey, John. (1934) 1986. A Common Faith. Carbondale: University of
Southern Illinois Press. 1986 reprinting of the 1934 original as John
Dewey: The Later Works, vol. 9.
Douglas, Heather. 2009. Science, Policy, and the Value-Free Ideal. Pittsburgh:
University of Pittsburgh Press.
Dupré, John. 1993. The Disorder of Things. Cambridge MA: Harvard
University Press.
Dupré, John. 2001. Human Nature and the Limits of Science. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Elgin, Catherine. 2017. True Enough. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
References 187
Feyerabend, Paul. 1978. Science in a Free Society. London: New Left Books.
Feyerabend, Paul. 1987. Farewell to Reason. London: Verso/New Left Books.
Fine, Arthur. 1988. “Interpreting Science.” PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial
Meetings of the Philosophy of Science Association 1988, no. 2: 3–11.
Foot, Philippa. 1967. “The Problem of Abortion and the Doctrine of Double
Effect.” Oxford Review 5. Reprinted in Virtues and Vices. Berkeley: University
of California Press, 1978.
Frege, Gottlob. (1884) 1968. The Foundations of Arithmetic. Oxford: Blackwell.
Fricker, Miranda. 2007. Epistemic Injustice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Friedman, Michael. 1974. “Explanation and Scientific Understanding.”
Journal of Philosophy 71: 5–19.
Godfrey-Smith, Peter. 2016. Other Minds: The Octopus, the Sea, and the Deep
Origins of Consciousness. New York: Farrar, Straus, Giroux.
Godfrey- Smith, Peter. 2020. Metazoa: Animal Minds and the Birth of
Consciousness. New York: Farrar, Straus, Giroux.
Goehr, Lydia. 2007. The Imaginary Museum of Musical Works. New York:
Oxford University Press.
Goldman, Alvin. 1999. Knowledge in a Social World. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Graham, Patricia Albjerg. 2005. Schooling America. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Gross, Paul, and Norman Levitt. 1994. Higher Superstition. Baltimore: Johns
Hopkins University Press.
Hardy, G. H. 1967. A Mathematician’s Apology. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Hegselmann, Rainer, and Ulrich Krause. 2002. “Opinion Dynamics and
Bounded Confidence Models, Analysis, and Simulation.” Journal of
Artificial Societies and Social Simulation 5, no. 3. https://w ww.jasss.org/
5/3/2 .html.
Hempel, C. G. 1950. “Problems and Changes in the Empiricist Criterion of
Meaning.” Revue Internationale de Philosophie 41: 41–63.
Hempel, C. G. 1951. “The Concept of Cognitive Significance: A Reconsidera
tion.” Proceedings of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences 80: 61–77.
188 References
Kitcher, Philip. 2021a. Moral Progress. New York: Oxford University Press.
Kitcher, Philip. 2021b. The Main Enterprise of the World: Rethinking
Education. New York: Oxford University Press.
Kitcher, Philip, and Evelyn Fox Keller. 2017. The Seasons Alter. New York:
Norton/Liveright.
Kuhn, T. S. 1962. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago: University
of Chicago Press.
Lakatos, Imre. 1970. “Falsificationism and the Methodology of Scientific
Research Programmes.” In Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge,
edited by I. Lakatos and A. Musgrave, 91–196. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Lange, Marc. 2017. Because without Cause. New York: Oxford University
Press.
Latour, Bruno. 1987. Science in Action. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
Laudan, Larry. 1977. Progress and its Problems. Berkeley: University of
California Press.
Levi, Isaac. 1974. “On Indeterminate Probabilities.” Journal of Philosophy
71: 391–418.
Lewis, David. 1973. Counterfactuals. Oxford: Blackwell.
Lloyd, Elisabeth, and Eric Winsberg, eds. 2018. Climate Modeling: Philosophical
and Conceptual Issues. London: Palgrave Macmillan.
Longino, Helen. 1990. Science as Social Knowledge. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press.
Mill, John Stuart. (1859) 2008. On Liberty and Other Essays. Oxford: Oxford
University Press (World’s Classics).
Morton, Jennifer M. 2020. Moving Up Without Losing Your Way. Princeton,
NJ: Princeton University Press.
Munro, E., N. Cartwright, J. Hardie, and E. Montuschi. 2017. Improving
Child Safety: Deliberation, Judgement and Empirical Research. Durham,
UK: Centre for Humanities Engaging Science and Society.
Nehamas, Alexander. 1998. The Art of Living. Berkeley: University of
California Press.
190 References
Peirce, Charles Sanders. (1878) 1974. “How to Make Our Ideas Clear.”
In Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, edited by Charles
Hartshorne and Paul Weiss, vol. V, 248–271. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
Pippin, Robert. 2000. Henry James and Modern Moral Life. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Popper, K. R. 1934. Logik der Forschung. Wien: Julius Springer.
Rawls, John. 1993. Political Liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press.
Rawls, John. 1999. A Theory of Justice. Revised edition. Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press.
Salmon, Wesley. 1971. Statistical Explanation and Statistical Relevance.
Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.
Scheffler, Israel. 1967. Science and Subjectivity. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill.
Schelling, Thomas. 1978. “Sorting and Mixing: Race and Sex.” In his
Micromotives and Macrobehavior, 135–166. New York: Norton.
Sellars, Wilfrid. 1963. Science, Perception, and Reality. London: Routledge
and Kegan Paul.
Sen, Amartya. 1977. “Rational Fools.” Philosophy and Public Affairs 6:
317–3 44.
Singer, Peter. 1972. “Famine, Affluence, and Morality.” Philosophy and Public
Affairs 1: 229–243.
Skyrms, Brian. 1996. Evolution of the Social Contract. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Skyrms, Brian. 2004. The Stag Hunt. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Sokal, Alan. 1996. “Transgressing the Boundaries: Toward a Transformative
Hermeneutics of Quantum Gravity.” Social Text 46/47: 217–252.
Spirtes, Peter, Clark Glymour, and Richard Scheines. 2000. Causation,
Predication, and Search. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Srinivasan, Amia. 2021. The Right to Sex. New York: Farrar, Straus, Giroux.
Stalnaker, Robert. 1968. “A Theory of Conditionals.” In Studies in Logical
Theory, edited by Nicholas Rescher, 98–112. Oxford: Blackwell.
Stanley, Jason. 2015. How Propaganda Works. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press.
192 References