Yew-Kwang NG - Efficiency, Equality and Public Policy - With A Case For Higher Public Spending - Palgrave Macmillan (2000)
Yew-Kwang NG - Efficiency, Equality and Public Policy - With A Case For Higher Public Spending - Palgrave Macmillan (2000)
Yew-Kwang NG - Efficiency, Equality and Public Policy - With A Case For Higher Public Spending - Palgrave Macmillan (2000)
Public Policy
With a Case for Higher Public Spending
Yew-Kwang Ng
Efficiency, Equality and Public Policy
Also by Yew-Kwang Ng
Yew-Kwang Ng
Professor of Economics
Monash University
Victoria
Australia
First published in Great Britain 2000 by
MACMILLAN PRESS LTD
Houndmills, Basingstoke, Hampshire RG21 6XS and London
Companies and representatives throughout the world
A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library.
ISBN 0–333–67165–1
No paragraph of this publication may be reproduced, copied or transmitted save with written
permission or in accordance with the provisions of the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act
1988, or under the terms of any licence permitting limited copying issued by the Copyright
Licensing Agency, 90 Tottenham Court Road, London W1P 0LP.
Any person who does any unauthorised act in relation to this publication may be liable to
criminal prosecution and civil claims for damages.
The author has asserted his right to be identified as the author of this work in accordance with
the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988.
This book is printed on paper suitable for recycling and made from fully managed and sustained
forest sources.
10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1
09 08 07 06 05 04 03 02 01 00
Preface x
1 Introduction 1
1.1 A dollar is a dollar: a simple solution to the big
efficiency–equality tradeoff 1
1.2 A partial resurrection of the old ‘new welfare
economics’? 1
1.3 Introductory summary 2
1.4 A case for higher public spending 4
1.5 The misguided consensus 5
1.6 Three basic problems of social choice/public policy 7
1.7 Some specific points made 9
1.8 A methodological note 9
1.9 What this book is not about 10
3 Welfarism 24
3.1 The Sen–Ng debate on welfarism: an appraisal 24
3.2 Another argument for welfarism 30
3.3 Rational individualism implies welfarism 32
5 Utilitarianism 57
5.1 Compelling arguments for utilitarianism 57
vii
viii Contents
Notes 165
References 169
x
1
Introduction
1
2 Efficiency, Equality and Public Policy
tion tests or welfare criteria in the 1940s and 1950s ended with the
ambivalent attitude towards the Little (1949, 1957) criterion. Though
I strongly defended (in Ng, 1979/1983, Chapter 3) the acceptability of
Little’s criterion (compensation test plus a distributional proviso), it
gives no answers to many cases and its distributional part requires inter-
personal comparison of cardinal utility. Thus, in its attempt to get rid
of cardinal utility and interpersonal comparison, the new welfare econ-
omics failed.
In this book, I argue that interpersonal comparison of cardinal utility
is necessary for making social choice. However, my proposal for
tackling the efficiency–equality tradeoff by treating a dollar as a dollar
whomsoever it goes to at every specific issue, leaving the pursuit of
equality to the general tax/transfer system means that cardinal utility
and interpersonal comparison are not needed except in determining
the optimal tradeoff between efficiency and equality in the general
tax/transfer system. Thus, in this sense, the objective of new welfare
economics in doing away with cardinal utility and interpersonal
comparison may be said to be largely (but not completely) met in our
proposal.
taken. Chapter 3 argues that the social objective or social welfare should
depend ultimately only on individual utilities (welfarism). Chapter 4
argues that, where individual utility (representing her preference) and
individual welfare (representing her happiness) differ, happiness should
be the ultimate concern. (Where I continue to use ‘utility’, it is partly
due to its more popular usage, partly to the presumption of no diver-
gence, and partly to distinguish it from ‘social welfare’ more clearly.)
Chapter 5 argues that social welfare should be an unweighted sum of
individual cardinal utilities/welfares (utilitarianism). Rational individu-
alistic egalitarianism alone is sufficient to yield utilitarianism. Harsanyi’s
(1953, 1955) arguments for utilitarianism are defended against their
recent critics and utilitarianism is defended against the criticism that it
ignores process fairness.
While interpersonal comparison of cardinal utilities is necessary for
social choice, it is in practice very difficult to obtain these utility indices
and to compare them interpersonally. A simple method to largely solve
this dilemma is proposed in Chapter 6. Basically, the willingness to pay
is used to reveal individual intensities of preference and the unweighted
sum of these figures (‘a dollar is a dollar’) is used as the criterion in order
to achieve efficiency, leaving the objective of equality to be tackled
in the general tax/transfer system where interpersonal comparison of
cardinal utility is still needed to achieve a rough trade-off (between
efficiency and equality). This achieves a tremendous simplification in
the formulation of public economic policy in general and in
cost–benefit analysis in particular. This principle of ‘a dollar is a dollar’
is consistent with the utilitarian objective but utilitarianism is not
necessary for the principle. This principle can be based just on the
normal Pareto principle. If my argument is correct, anyone accepting
the Pareto principle must accept the principle of ‘a dollar is a dollar’.
This rules out specific purely equality-oriented policies such as the use
of distributional weights in cost–benefit analysis, subsidies/taxes on
goods consumed mainly by the poor/rich, the first-come-first-served
method for car parking spaces to provide ‘equal access’ in city-centre
parking, etc. However, it does not rule out measures based on efficiency
considerations such as external effects, second-best factors, etc. For
example, subsidies on education and health care may be justified on the
grounds of external benefits but not on the ground of equality. It is not
in favour of more or less equality. Rather, for any degree of equality
aimed at, it is more efficient (in the Pareto sense) to achieve it by adopt-
ing the principle of ‘a dollar is a dollar’ and using the appropriate degree
of progressivity in the tax/transfer system.
4 Efficiency, Equality and Public Policy
The second property is of course the (strong) Pareto principle. The first
property is further factorised by Sen into the following three distinct
parts:
(1) Welfarism
Social welfare is a function of personal utility levels, so that any two
social states must be ranked entirely on the basis of personal utilities
in the respective states (irrespective of the non-utility features of the
states).
(2) Ordinalism
Only the ordinal properties of the individual utility functions are to
be used in social welfare judgements.
(3) Non-comparable Utilities
The social welfare ranking must be independent of the way the
utilities of different individuals compare with each other.
Sen, 1979, p.538
Some other specific points argued in this book include the following:
Generally speaking, this book is concerned with the more general issues
of public policy at the more fundamental level. Thus, it is concerned
with what public policy should ultimately aim at rather than with sec-
ondary principles and specific issues. It is concerned with the ultimate
ethical foundation of public policy rather than with issues at the
practical or political levels. While it discusses the problem of public
spending and names some specific areas (research and environmental
protection), it is still mainly concerned with the more general and fun-
damental issues than with specific items and complications of imple-
mentation and political feasibility. This does not mean that such issues
are regarded as unimportant; rather, they are beyond the scope of this
book and also largely beyond the expertise of the author. While issues
of feasibility and practical difficulties have to be faced at the stage of
actual policy decisions, the issue of basic objectives and fundamental
principles remains important and relevant even at the implementation
level.
This book avoids unnecessary formalism and technical analysis.
Virtually no mathematics is used except in some appendices. While by
no means against the use of rigorous mathematical techniques (as I have
Introduction 11
used them myself), I believe that their use has become excessive and is
unnecessary in many cases. Two examples related to the theme here
may be given. It is compelling, at the ultimate level, that the desir-
ability of a social state depends only on all its relevant variables or
characteristics (rather than that of another social state), due to the
exhaustive nature of ‘all relevant variables’ and the mutually exclusive
nature of social states. This makes the pure element of independence a
compelling condition. Then, analysis is sufficient by using the concept
of a social welfare function (with the social welfare of any social state
depending only on variables at that social state) instead of that of a
social welfare functional (with the social welfare of any social state
depending on the variables of all social states). Though it is formally
more general to conduct the analysis in terms of a social welfare func-
tional and then impose the compelling condition of independence, this
makes the analysis unnecessarily more complicated and less accessible
to people unfamiliar with the complicated technical framework. As
another example, when stripped of its technical facade, the essence of
the (valid) argument by Roemer (1986, 1996) that resource egalitarian-
ism implies welfare egalitarianism may be seen in a simple diagram (see
Appendix B). Thus presented, the rationale for the validity of the argu-
ment, the ethical unacceptability of both resource egalitarianism and
welfare egalitarianism are all clear. However, I am sympathetic towards
Roemer (and others) for their presentation of arguments in complicated
mathematics; it is increasingly difficult to publish academic papers not
using complicated mathematics. If Roemer’s argument were originally
presented in the transparent form of a simple diagram, it would almost
certainly have been rejected by the Quarterly Journal of Economics. When
formalism has progressed to such a level, a reconsideration is in order.
(For a critique of formalism in modern economics, see Blaug, 1998; for
a discussion, see Backhouse, 1998; Chick, 1998; Krugman, 1998 and
Weintraub, 1998.)
This page intentionally left blank
Part I
The Foundation of Public
Economic Policy
This page intentionally left blank
2
The Necessity of Interpersonal
Cardinal Utility
15
16 Efficiency, Equality and Public Policy
In most cases, conflicts arise in the sense that the choice of one alter-
native over the other makes some members better off but some other
members worse off. It is such cases of conflict that make the problem
of social choice of substance and interesting. For simplicity, assume that
you and your spouse are always indifferent over the relevant alterna-
tives and hence you choose purely in accordance to the preferences of
the children. There is another trivial case where interpersonal compari-
son of cardinal utility is not needed. If one of the children is your
favoured child such that you let him/her choose, ignoring the prefer-
ence of other children, then your family choice problem is solved by
the dictatorial choice of this favoured child. (This is ruled out by Arrow’s
condition of non-dictatorship.)
You might adopt the simple rule that, for divisible choices, always
divide equally between all the children and for indivisible choices,
always toss a coin to decide. This may ‘work’ and appears ‘fair’. However,
it violates the weak Pareto principle (which says that if all individuals
prefer x to y, the society or the family should prefer x to y). For sim-
plicity, take the case of only two children, Jan and Kelvin, and only one
divisible good, money, to be allocated. The principle involved is applic-
able to general cases.
Suppose Jan prefers hot weather if she has enough money ($75) to
enable her to go surfing but would rather have cold weather with
less money than enduring the heat without surfing. On the other
hand, Kelvin prefers cold weather if he has enough money ($75) to
go skiing, but would rather have hot weather with less money than
watching the snow without being able to ski. Now consider the
following four alternatives H1, H2, C1, C2, each pair corresponding to
two different distributions of the given $100 in two alternative weather
conditions:
UK
C1
H2
H1
C2
UJ
Figure 2.1
I studied Sen, 1970a and DeMeyer and Plott, 1971, I realised the necess-
ity of interpersonal comparison as well.) However, after the ordinalism
revolution in consumer theory, economists are very hostile to cardinal
utilities. A recent textbook example is Varian. (A non-textbook example
is Kolm, 1993.)
happiness
in utils
0 time
unhappiness
in utils
Figure 2.2
I want money but not for its own sake, only to obtain, ultimately,
happiness. Thus, I have diminishing marginal happiness of money.
For big variations, my willingness to pay twice as much does not indi-
cate twice as much happiness or utility. (The two are the same if we
abstract away ignorance, concern for others, and irrational preference.
This is so with my definition of irrational preference as preferring some-
thing that decreases one’s own happiness or welfare, neither due
to ignorance nor to a concern for the welfare of others. Utility here is
taken as representing preference which can be cardinal. See Chapter 4
for details.) However, as I want happiness for its own sake, if bundle
A (or anything else) gives me twice as much happiness as bundle B,
it is perfectly sensible, natural, and informative to say that I prefer
(reminding the abstraction of ignorance, etc.) bundle A twice as much
as bundle B.
Even if we re-introduce factors other than personal happiness in the
preference function, I have no difficulty (except for imperfect infor-
mation to be discussed presently) in comparing the intensities of my
preference for different pairs of alternatives. Thus, if I take into account
the income or welfare levels of others, there is no problem in allowing
for that. For the simple case where both my and the only other person’s
welfare are functions of the log of own income, my preference or utility
function could be the log of my income plus alpha times the log of the
other person’s income, where alpha is a positive number slightly larger
than zero. I could also allow for alpha itself to be a function of the
20 Efficiency, Equality and Public Policy
that you can easily compare, is her/his happiness over that period
higher/lower/about the same; 2. by 0%//1–10%/11–30%/31–100%/over
100%.
For all questions, respondents are also provided with boxes marked
‘cannot answer’ and ‘this question is meaningless’. I had expected far
more economists to regard Question A2 as either unanswerable or mean-
ingless than the general public. The difference is much smaller than I
expected. The sample size is 49 for the general public (from shopping
and entertainment centres) and 52 for economists, consisting of par-
ticipants of an econometrics conference (31) and a social choice con-
ference (21). For the general public, 16.3% (8 out of 49) answered either
‘cannot answer’ or ‘meaningless’ for Question A2. If we group all econ-
omists together, 32% (16 out of 50; 2 did not answer) ticked ‘cannot
answer’ or ‘meaningless’. While this is certainly a significant difference,
the difference is not as remarkable as I expected. I expected more than
half to tick so. On hindsight, it may be said that, the majority of
economists still retain the commonsense that happiness is cardinally
measurable, despite their professional training to the contrary. I also
expected the group from the social choice conference to be more sym-
pathetic to cardinal measurability than the group from the economet-
rics conference. But there is no significant difference (7 out of 21 and
9 out of 29 respectively).
For the general public, 14.3% (7 out of 49) and 18.75% (9 out of 48)
answered either ‘cannot answer’ or ‘meaningless’ to Question B1 and
B2 respectively. The corresponding figures for economists are 40.4% (21
out of 52) and 51.1% (23 out of 45; 7 did not answer) respectively.
Again, there are no significant differences between the two sup-groups
of economists. Less than 10% of any group answered ‘cannot answer’
or ‘meaningless’ to Question A1.
fare economics. For the latter, we need a SWF for a given set of indi-
vidual preferences. If the set of individual preferences changes, we
have another SWF. By not requiring any consistency or reasonable
conditions between the different SWF’s corresponding to different
sets of individual preferences, Arrow’s impossibility result does not
apply. Honestly, I am not persuaded by this line of reasoning. As indi-
vidual preferences change, the social ordering or social choice may
change. But why should the rule used to aggregate individual prefer-
ences into social choice change? Nevertheless, for my purpose here, I
would rather have readers agreeing with Little and Samuelson, as this
would increase the importance of the following result that I was
involved in proving.
Kemp and Ng (1976) and Parks (1976) show that, even operating
within the same set of individual preferences or holding individual pref-
erences unchanged (the so-called single-profile or intra-profile frame-
work), impossibility results may still be proved using compelling
conditions, if we have only individual ordinal preferences to base on.
This impossibility result was quickly generalised (Hammond, 1976;
Pollak, 1979 and Roberts, 1980), establishing the existence of a corre-
sponding (impossibility or possibility) proposition in the single-profile
framework for every proposition in the multi-profile or inter-profile (i.e.
the original Arrowian) framework. This should seal the fate of ordinal-
ism but Samuelson objected.
Samuelson (1977) argues that an axiom (Anonymity Plus Orderings
Only) used by Kemp and Ng is objectionable. Since no one objects to
anonymity, the real issue concerns ordinalism. For the general social
choice problem, I myself regard ordinalism as unreasonable. However,
since the point here is about whether ordinalism is a sufficient basis
for the single-profile social choice, the axiom is a natural condition to
impose. If Samuelson objects to this axiom, he should not continue to
insist on the sufficiency of ordinalism.
Some years after the Kemp–Ng–Samuelson debate, I discussed the
problem with Arrow. He said that, if Samuelson insisted on ordinalism,
he had to give up independence. I replied that independence is com-
pelling. Later, I realised that independence is really implied in the
Bergson–Samuelson tradition of writing social welfare at any social state
x as a function of individual utilities at x only. This tradition is all right
if we have interpersonally comparable cardinal utilities. However,
Samuelson insists that the individual utility indices are only ordinal.
This is the crux of the impossibility. (See Appendix E for more detailed
argument.)
The Necessity of Interpersonal Cardinal Utility 23
24
Welfarism 25
x y z
Person 1’s welfare 4 7 7
Person 2’s welfare 10 8 8
In a footnote, Sen adds: ‘It is assumed that there are no indirect conse-
quences of torture, e.g. in attitude formation. These indirect effects do
not change the nature of the difficulty, even though they can be prop-
erly accommodated only in a much more complex analysis.’
The above argument of Sen against welfarism appears very persuasive.
However, it seems to me whether one has to reject welfarism on the
grounds of such moral principles as no-torture depends on whether one
believes in these principles as his basic value judgements. ‘A value judge-
ment can be called “basic” to a person, if the judgement is supposed to
apply under all conceivable circumstances, and it is “non-basic” other-
wise’ (Sen, 1970, p.59).2 Those whose belief in no-torture is more basic
than welfarism must withdraw their commitment to welfarism in cir-
cumstances like z. But one, like myself, may also believe in no-torture
not as a basic value judgement but as derived from a welfarist SWF
because one may believe that in practically all circumstances, torture
leads, directly and indirectly, to more harm than good. However, most
people believe that it is wrong to inflict harm on others even if the
pleasure of doing so exceeds the direct and indirect sufferings caused.
Thus, it is very tempting to reject welfarism (and utilitarianism, a spe-
Welfarism 27
any serious theory of human or civil rights will bring in other [than
sentient] aspects of people which also differentiate them from stones.
The respect and concern that one person owes another can hardly
be seen as a function only of the latter’s capacity for pleasure. Indeed,
28 Efficiency, Equality and Public Policy
even after a person dies and obviously has no further capacity for
pleasure or pain, right-based considerations vis-à-vis him do not all
cease to apply, e.g. they are relevant in disposing of his body, or in
defending him against vilification.
Sen, 1981, p.534
ism in general (for example, see Smart and Williams, 1973). ‘Ng’s own
view of the matter should not be confused with a claim that a consen-
sus does exist on this question’ (Sen, 1981, p.532), though I may attempt
to persuade economists to stick to welfarism, and for the defectors to
re-embrace welfarism after a more ‘critical’ examination.
The third concession I wish to make is based on practical consider-
ations including the lack of complete information about individual wel-
fares mentioned above. Partly because of this lack of information and
partly because of the cost of making a detailed welfarist calculation for
each decision, it is sensible to adopt some principles, procedures, etc.
that are generally consistent with the ultimate welfarist objective. (The
relevance of arguments, e.g. Suzumura, 1999, on the importance of the
appropriate procedures should be seen in this light. They are relevant
and important and yet do not affect the validity of welfarism at the ulti-
mate level. See also Section 5.5 which argues that utilitarianism is con-
sistent with process fairness.) In time, these principles are valued for
their own sake and these secondary or derived values have to be reck-
oned with even by a pure welfarist (who may however try at the same
time to persuade people not to value non-basic principles over and
above their instrumental values so that we can avoid being the slaves
of certain ‘moral principles’ which are no longer conducive to social
welfare due to new circumstances). Therefore, while I continue to
adhere to a pure welfarist objective at the basic philosophical or ‘criti-
cal’ level, I am quite willing to concede that, at the practical day-to-day
(or even year-to-year, decade-to-decade) basis, characteristic of most
economic and social decisions, non-welfarist (from the short-term view-
point) principles have to be reckoned with. At least in this sense, then,
Sen’s objection to a purely welfarist calculation is important.3
After making these concessions to Sen, I am sure I will not jeopardise
my friendship with him by adding a caution against his following con-
clusion: ‘Arrow’s impossibility theorem can be seen as resulting largely
from combining ‘welfarism’ (ruling out the use of non-utility infor-
mation) with remarkably poor utility information (especially because of
the avoidance of interpersonal comparisons)’ (Sen, 1979, p.554). I agree
whole-heartedly that the poor utility information (non-cardinalism
and non-comparability) is of paramount importance in producing the
impossibility result (see Chapter 2). I also agree that the introduction
of non-welfarist principles may help social choice in particular in-
stances. However, without richer utility information, the rejection of
welfarism itself does not provide a satisfactory solution to the paradox
of social choice, as shown in Chapter 2 above. (For more rigorous
30 Efficiency, Equality and Public Policy
lie are regarded as rather dull. Lying in W2 is like telling a joke in W0.
Everyone in W2 regards lying as morally good. Now, let us transform
W2 into W3 by making all sentients into non-sentient conscious beings
and eliminate all their memories of affairs in W2. Moreover, make some
minor changes if necessary such as to make W3 exactly the same as W1
in every aspect. If we ask the counterpart of Arthur in W2 (call him
Arthur2) what he thinks or would think of the moral standing of lying
in W3, he will probably say that lying is still morally good even in W3.
But by construction W3 is identical to W1. How could the same thing
(lying) in the same world (W1 or W3) be both morally bad and good at
the same time? Such absurdity can be avoided by accepting A2.
The acceptance of A2 seems to compel the acceptance of A3.
A3. In a world with sentients, what is of moral consequence is ultimately
due to the effects on the feelings of happiness or unhappiness of the sen-
tients in that world.
If what is of moral consequence is not ultimately due to the effects on
the feelings of happiness or unhappiness of sentients (or sentient feel-
ings for short), then something may be of moral consequence even
without in any way, directly or indirectly, affecting sentient feelings. If
this is true, something should also be of possible moral consequence in
a world with non-sentient conscious beings since there is no morally
relevant difference between the two. But this violates A2. Hence we
must also accept A3. Using utility to represent sentient feelings, A3 is
welfarism. Ultimately, what is morally good or bad depends only on the
effects on individual utilities:
w = w (u1 , u2 , . . . , un )
restricted, e.g. if there is only one alternative or if everyone has the same
preference/welfare levels, then our substantive axioms below will have
no scope to ‘bite’ and one may argue that all (or all Paretian) social
welfare functions satisfy our substantive axioms in a trivial sense. This
is, of course, not substantive. Those who want completeness may take
it that we are assuming:
Axiom 0. A social welfare function exists and the domain of social alter-
natives and individual welfare levels are not restricted.
In fact, we do not need the full force of this axiom. As it is purely
a non-substantive issue, we will not include this axiom in the follow-
ing discussion. It may also be noted that, in the absence of either car-
dinal utilities/welfares or their interpersonal comparison, no reasonable
SWF is possible, even if we operate with a fixed set of individual
preferences/welfares. (Kemp and Ng, 1976 and Parks, 1976 establish
the impossibility without cardinality; Sen, 1970a establishes the imposs-
ibility without interpersonal comparison.) Thus, for the question on the
appropriate form of SWF, we have to operate with the existence of inter-
personal comparable cardinal utility/welfare. (See Chapter 2.) We now
turn to the substantive axioms.
Axiom 1. Rational individualism: Where no other sentients outside
a given society are affected, what the society should ultimately maximise
should depend positively on what individuals in the society rationally and
knowledgeably want for themselves ultimately.
This axiom may be broken into the following four components.
1a. Individualism: The society consists of individuals and does not
exist independently of individuals. Thus, what the society wants should
depend on what individuals in the society want; what the society should
pursue ultimately should depend on what individuals in the society ultimately
want.
1b. Positive dependence (the Pareto principle): The dependence
of social choice on individual values should be positive other than negative.
1c. Proviso on others: Just as my pursuit of my welfare is subject to
certain constraints to avoid causing great harm to you, on my neighbours, on
animals, etc. a society’s maximisation is subject to a similar proviso.
However, since the appropriate constraints and/or tradeoff is beyond
the scope here, this proviso is just noted without discussing its detailed
implications, by confining to choices where no other sentients are
affected. Due to this confinement, any disagreement on this proviso has
no effect on our arguments. For example, suppose someone disagrees
that animal welfare should enter this proviso. This does not affect our
arguments which are concerned only with choices where animal welfare
34 Efficiency, Equality and Public Policy
is not affected. Another might believe that we should not have this
whole proviso at all. This only means that our conclusions would then
apply without subjecting to ‘no effects on others’.
1d. Rationalism: The individual preferences that should be used in
determining the social preferences should be those that are free from cor-
rectable ignorance, irrationality, and non-affective altruism or malice.
This consists of three components.
1d1. Informed preferences: To a certain extent, individual
preferences may be distorted by ignorance, imperfect foresight, or
misinformation. Many of these are not correctable as the society is
similarly ignorant. Others are correctable. The fluoridation of water
is partly justified on this ground. Harsanyi (1997) has convincingly
argued for the use of informed preferences over actual preferences.
(See Chapter 4.)
1d2. Exclusion of non-affective altruism: Non-affective altruism
is the pure concern (or malice if the concern is negative) for the welfare of
others (which need not be confined to human only) independent of or over
and above the effect on one’s own welfare.
I may donate money to the poor because I feel happier seeing them
in a less deprived condition (affective altruism) or because my donation
will increase my status in the community (not real altruism). However,
if my welfare loss in the money donated is larger than my welfare gain
through the above and all other effects and yet I prefer the donation,
non-affective altruism is involved. Non-affective altruistic preferences
should be excluded from social choice because the welfare of each
person (including that of the poor) should already be fully concerned
with on its own right in the relevant social welfare function. Including
non-affective altruistic preferences will lead to multiple counting. This,
together with a more detailed distinction of affective versus non-
affective altruism, the existence of the latter, and the unacceptability
of the Pareto principle in terms of preferences in the presence of non-
affective altruism are contained in Section 4.1 and Appendix D.
1d3. Rationality: Social choice should be based on individual prefer-
ences that are not distorted by irrationality.
The preference of an individual is defined to be irrational if they
prefer A to B while their welfare will be higher at B than at A and if their
preference is due neither to ignorance nor non-affective altruism.5 This
definition makes ignorance, non-affective altruism, and irrationality
three exhaustive reasons for the divergence between the preference and
the welfare of an individual. Section 4.2 in the next chapter explains
causes of irrational preferences and argues why they should be excluded.
Welfarism 35
W = W ( w 1, w 2 , . . . , w I )
36
Utility, Informed Preference, or Happiness 37
Table 4.1
x 2 7 2 8 9 10
y 6 2 6 5 8 11
z 8 5 8 9 13 17
u i = u i ( w 1, w 2 , . . . , w I )
w i = w i (a, b , c , . . . , w 1 , w 2 , . . . , w i -1 , w i +1 , . . . , w I )
children increases, but if this is not sufficient to offset their welfare loss
due to other factors (such as a lower level of consumption, less leisure,
worse health), the concerning effect is involved over and above the
minding effect.
As the minding effect actually affects the welfare level, it is already
taken fully into account in the social decision in accordance to Swi, as
it should be. For the concerning effect, the welfare of the concerning
person is not affected, but her preference is affected by her concern for
the welfare of others. However, in using, say, the unweighted sum of
individual values, the welfare of others is already taken fully into
account, i.e. is already fully ‘concerned’ with. Hence, there is no further
need to take the concern of this person for the welfare of others into
account.
The existence of non-affective altruism (the concerning effect) may
be doubted (especially by economists, as mentioned to me on several
occasions). This attitude has some advantages as many instances of
apparent altruism are consistent with self interest due to the influence
of social pressure, obligations, fame-seeking, future rewards, and the
like. (For a collection of papers on the economics of altruism, see
Zamagni, 1995. See also Bagwell and Bernheim, 1996 and Harbaugh,
1998 on the status or prestige motive for making charitable contribu-
tions; Clark, 1998; Eshel et al., 1998; Laitner and Juster, 1996 and Rose-
Ackerman, 1996 for evidence and economic theories regarding altruism;
Lunati, 1997 on some ethical aspects; and Mulligan, 1997 on parental
altruism towards children. Altonji et al., 1997 show that a dollar increase
in parental income plus a dollar decrease in the child’s income only lead
to a $0.13 increase in transfer, contrary to the altruistic model. However,
this is so only for a specific altruistic model, not necessarily so for some
more general one.)
It may be argued that, if Ms 2 is willing to choose z over x in con-
sideration of the welfare of Mr 1, she must be happier with z than with
x. So, ui and wi must always go together such that the situation depicted
in Table 4.1 where u2 and w2 conflict each other with respect to the pair
(x, z) cannot logically arise. In other words, only ‘minding’ is possible;
‘concerning’ is not possible. This argument is incorrect. As conceded
above, the two effects usually intertwine with each other, and ‘minding’
is more prevalent than ‘concerning’. Many apparently ‘concerning’
effects may actually be ‘minding’ effects upon closer examination.
However, some truly pure ‘concerning’ effects are possible. To see this,
consider the following purely hypothetical construction which never-
theless illustrates the point most dramatically:
42 Efficiency, Equality and Public Policy
small net loss to our own welfare, will not at least some of us be willing
to do that?
If we have a true concern (over and above the ‘minding’ effect) for
the welfare of our children, can we not have a similar (though lesser in
degree) concern for our siblings, our relatives, our friends, our fellow
countrymen/women, the whole humankind, and eventually all sen-
tients? (For some evidence for true altruism, see Hoffman, 1981 and
Monroe, 1996.)
To further support the distinction between preference and happiness,
it may be noted that neuro- and behavioural scientists (e.g. Berridge,
1996) found that wanting (related to preference) and liking (related to
happiness) arise from two different neural systems, and therefore pref-
erence may not be synonymous with happiness.
Moreover, our behaviour and preferences are affected by our biologi-
cally determined inclinations. Natural selection results in the maxi-
misation of inclusive fitness (Hamilton, 1964; Wilson, 1975). Fitness
here is the ability of an organism to survive and transmit its genes to
the next generation. Inclusive fitness consists of the individual’s own
fitness plus her effects on the fitness of genetically related neighbours.
Thus, an individual may be expected to be altruistic towards her close
relatives, especially her own children. In addition, Trivers’ (1971) model
of reciprocal altruism shows that natural selection had to favour some
degree of altruism even between non-related individuals provided that
there is a significant chance of role reversal, as may be expected for
social species, including homo sapiens.
We care about our children/relatives because they carry/share our
genes. Sometimes one (or one’s spouse) may wonder why one is so
willing to help one’s siblings (or other relatives) whom one does not
really love much, not knowing that perhaps the genetically determined
subconscious inclination may play a role. Thus, the existence of some
non-self-centring effects is a biological necessity. However, whether the
biologically determined non-self-centring effects manifest mainly/only
in the ‘minding’ or the ‘concerning’ effects remains to be explored. Of
course, we are much more influenced by nurture than other animals
and also have a higher, if not exclusive, sense of morality. It may be
conjectured that, the more important is the influence of nurture and
the more important is the sense of morality, the more likely is it for the
true concerning effect to be present and significant.
From the above discussion, it may be concluded that true concern
(i.e. on top of or over and above the ‘minding’ effect) for the welfare
44 Efficiency, Equality and Public Policy
goods and opportunities to others) and yet the person concerned (who
has the external preferences) genuinely suffers a lot subjectively. Such
external preferences should not be ignored. (However, we may have to
disregard many external preferences even when they genuinely affect
people’s welfare, on grounds of practical difficulties and undesirable side
effects; but this problem has been abstracted away in this chapter.)
The recognition that affective/non-affective altruistic preferences
should be included/excluded in social choice has practical implications.
For example, this is related to the issue on the extent to which gifts
should be taxed or subsidised. (There are of course other considerations
related to the tax/subsidy of gifts; see Kaplow, 1998. On the possible
unacceptability of the Pareto principle due to the presence of non-
affective altruism, see Appendix D.)
Some people pretend to have, and may in the end even convince
themselves that they have, some preferences they think to be fash-
ionable and sophisticated – even though their real preferences may
46 Efficiency, Equality and Public Policy
be quite different, or even though after a point they may not really
know themselves what their real preferences are. Devotees of various
esoteric art forms of questionable aesthetic value often form coteries
that seem to display this kind of behaviour.
Harsanyi, 1997, p.135.
I do not know much about these esoteric art forms but it could be debat-
able to call the preferences of their devotees self-deception.
Harsanyi believes that informed preferences, by definition, will always
be based on all the relevant information, so that they will always be in
agreement with our real interests. However, it is debatable that people’s
preferences must always coincide with their interests if they are fully
informed. The meaning of ‘interests’ here is vague. If it means whatever
people prefer under full information, then it coincides with informed
preference tautologically but the terminology of ‘interest’ is misleading.
If it means welfare, happiness, or something similar, then it is not
true that people’s preferences when fully informed always coincide
with their interest, for at least two reasons. First, there is non-affective
altruism (and possibly also malice), as discussed in the last section.
Secondly, biological and psychological motivational factors may affect
preference or behaviour in ways not fully consistent with welfare, as
argued below.
There are a number of causes that may make preferences differ from
happiness other than ignorance and a concern for the welfare of others,
hence irrational according to my definition. There are at least three
sources of irrational preferences:
The first source is not difficult to see. We are a biological species that
has evolved through many generations to survive natural selection.
(Otherwise I/you wouldn’t be here to write/read this book.) Natural
selection works through the preservation of those attributes (created
by random mutation) that are beneficial to the survival of the organ-
ism and the reproduction of offspring. In most lower species, their
behavioural patterns are completely determined by genetic programmes
and their interaction with specific environmental conditions. However,
Utility, Informed Preference, or Happiness 47
when the environment became more complex (largely due to the evol-
ution of more species and more complex species), the fitness enhanc-
ing responses became more difficult to programme in advance. When
consciousness evolved to make choices, an important advantage is
gained by delegating some responses to be decided at the specific
moment. Individuals of species of such capability decides on ‘fight or
flight’ by sizing up the specific situation instead of relying on a fixed
response triggered by a given stimulus. However, when consciousness
has evolved to guide choices, such conscious choices have to be gener-
ally consistent with fitness for consciousness to survive natural selec-
tion (Ng, 1995). God (or natural selection) solved this problem by
endowing the conscious species with a reward/penalty centre (or
centres). Thus, activities consistent with fitness, such as eating nu-
tritious food when hungry or mating with fertile members of the op-
posite sex, are rewarded with pleasure and those harmful to fitness, such
as injuries to the body, are penalised with pain. (This makes the flexi-
ble species also ‘rational’ as defined in Ng, 1996b which shows that
complex niches favour rational species which make the environment
more complex, leading to a virtuous cycle that accelerated the rate of
evolution, partly explaining the dramatic speed of evolution based
mainly on random mutation and natural selection, a speed doubted by
creationists. Note that a more ‘rational’ species refers to a species with
less fixed behavioural patterns; hence that ‘rationality’ differs from the
concept of ‘rationality’ used in this chapter.) Due to this, there is a high
degree of consistency between fitness and welfare. However, the con-
sistency is not perfect.
On top of the ex-post rewards and penalties, we are also endowed with
inner drives to satisfy the fitness-enhancing functions like mating. On
the whole, these powerful temptations and drives work in the right
direction, making us do things that both enhance our biological fitness
and psychological welfare. However, since evolution is largely fitness-
maximisation and the welfare-enhancing aspect is only indirectly to
enhance fitness, some divergence between our behaviour and our
welfare is unavoidable, as our behaviour is not completely determined
by rational calculation but also partly by the programmed inclination,
including drives. For example, traits that incline individuals to produce
a number of offspring larger than that dictated by welfare maxi-
misation may be selected (Ng, 1995). Thus, we are not only born with
reproductive capabilities that we may rationally use to increase our
welfare and fitness together but we also possess biological drives that
incline us to behave or prefer activities not fully consistent with our
welfare, at least in many occasions.
48 Efficiency, Equality and Public Policy
save then. I was careful enough to find out that this healthy-looking
young man was not expecting early death from a terminal disease or
the like.
Related to both the above causes of irrational preference but border-
ing on ignorance is the tendency of people (and animals) to choose
mainly in accordance to current utilities, ignoring the effects on the
utilities of future choices, and to underestimate the effects of current
pleasures/pains in decreasing/increasing future enjoyment through the
adaptation effects. For example, most people believe that winning a big
sum of money will bring them great happiness and are thus willing
to spend a lot of money buying lottery tickets at unfavourable odds.
However, psychologists find out that lottery winners are typically
not happier than non-winner controls. (See Brickman et al., 1978;
Herrnstein and Prelec, 1992.)
Most people regard our own species as the only one that has moral-
ity. I am agnostic on this. (I cannot rule out some rudimentary sense of
morality in, say, the chimp.) However, I accept that the sense of moral-
ity evolved very late in the phylogenetic scale. The inborn feelings for
morality probably helped our survival by enhancing cooperation in our
species which relies less on hard-wired fixed response patterns. Our
sense of morality is not only inborn, we are brought up and educated,
and we also learn and teach others, to behave morally, to value justice,
etc. This is extremely important in the smooth functioning of the
society and in improving human relationships. Morality is not only
important for the welfare of the individual but also for others. If any-
thing, I believe that modern education is deficient in the moral aspect.
However, the inborn and learned strong sense of morality also, at least
occasionally, make us do and prefer things consistent with our moral
principles but contrary to our welfare. If an individual acts against his
own welfare in order to observe certain moral principles, this need not
be irrational. First, his sacrifice may benefit others. Secondly, he may
feel bad in violating principles he values. Thirdly, violating moral prin-
ciples may have long-term undesirable effects both for him and for
others, including weakening the degree of morality. Fourthly, his choice
may be due to ignorance. However, if an individual knowingly sacrifices
so much welfare not made up by all of the above considerations put
together, he is irrational according to my definition.
An example of welfare-reducing moral principle that had been
observed for a long time with disastrous consequences is the scruple (in
ancient China in particular) that a woman has to stick to a single
husband even after the early death of the husband. Statues were erected
Utility, Informed Preference, or Happiness 51
to extol the virtue of not marrying again, observing the widowhood for
decades from youth to death. Enormous family and social pressures were
put on widows, with or without children, not to marry again, simply
because it is not virtuous to marry again. Most people agree now that
such blind insistence on moral virtue is irrational and indeed morally
wrong. Shouldn’t those who insist on whatever moral principles now
irrespective of or independent of their welfare implications take some
lessons from this example? (It may be thought that draconian anti-
welfare moral principles, such as the no-remarriage commandment, no
longer exist today, especially in the West. However, consider the prin-
ciple ‘life is sacrosanct’ and the related strict anti-euthanasia legislation
and the artificial prolonging of hopeless lives in pain by modern
machines. The amount of unnecessary suffering is still enormous.)
The above causes of irrational preference show that, due either to
imperfection in our endowed faculty, the biological bias in favour of
reproductive fitness, or certain side-effects of morality, we may do things
not quite consistent with our welfare. The issue here is that, for nor-
mative purposes, should we use welfare or actual preferences/behaviour.
It seems clear that, where individual irrational preferences are due to
the bias of biological drives or to imperfect telescopic faculty, social
choices should try to exclude such irrational preferences and be based
on individual welfares instead. An old Chinese dictum says, ‘Out of
the three unfilial acts, not having offspring is the greatest.’ However, for
the human species as a whole, we are certainly not getting smaller in
population size. Moreover, a long-run social welfare function account-
ing for the welfare of future generations should account for that. If we
go for biological fitness, we will prefer unlimited procreation even if that
means that we will all be suffering to a smaller population with a higher
aggregate welfare. We are the feeling selves that care ultimately about
our welfare (positive minus negative affective feelings). We are not them,
the unfeeling genes that, through random mutation and natural selec-
tion, programmed us to maximise fitness. Unlike other species who are
almost completely controlled by their genes and the environment, we
have learned to change our fate by using such measures as birth control.
For normative issues, it is our welfare, rather than the selected random
dictates of the unfeeling genes, that should count.
For irrational preferences due to rigid adherence to out-dated moral
principles, it may be more controversial. In fact, some people may be
against calling such preferences irrational. However, before the evol-
ution or development of morality and the like, we (perhaps still in the
form of apes) had no moral or other principles, no concept of commit-
52 Efficiency, Equality and Public Policy
ments and justice, etc. Self-interest dominated totally, though this does
not exclude genetically endowed ‘altruism’ for the maximisation of
inclusive fitness. As we evolved and relied more and more on our high
intelligence and social interaction for survival, the instinct for moral
feelings also evolved which helped our survival by enhancing cooper-
ation. This was enhanced by learning the importance of such moral
practices as honesty in improving our struggle against nature (includ-
ing wild animals) and against competing human groups. No one
can deny that the initial evolution/development of morality must be
purely instrumental (in enhancing either our welfare or our surviving
and propagation fitness) as there existed no morality to begin with.
We then learned and taught our children and students to value moral
principles, etc. first as a way to increase the degree of adherence to these
principles and hence our welfare. Eventually, some, if not most, people
came to value these principles in themselves by learning and probably
also by instinct. (The evolution of such commitment enhancing devices
as blushing can be fitness-enhancing; see Frank, 1987.) Failing to see
the ultimate values is a kind of illusion fostered by learning (I dare not
say indoctrination) and perhaps genetics. However, I personally have
great moral respect for people with such illusions. They most probably
make better citizens, friends and colleagues. But illusions they are
nevertheless, at least at the ultimate analytical or critical level. While
on the whole positive (in maintaining the moral standards), such
illusions do have some costs in delaying the rejection of certain out-
dated moral principles and in contributing to the wide disagreement in
normative discussion.
For those who agree with Harsanyi in rejecting spurious preferences
for normative purposes, it seems likely that irrational preferences due
to biological drives and imperfections and psychological conditioning
should similarly be rejected. However, there is a class of preferences
(‘autonomous desire not based on hedonistic considerations’) that may
be classified as irrational using my definition but insisted by Harsanyi
to be respectable, as discussed in the next section.
I quite agree that some of our desires are not based on hedonistic con-
siderations. However, I believe that the satisfaction of desires or prefer-
ences as such has no intrinsic normative value; it is the effects on
happiness that is ultimately valuable. Otherwise, why are spurious pref-
erences not normatively important?
We do have a natural desire to satisfy our curiosity. We are probably
both born and brought up to be so. As our species manages successfully
to survive mainly based on its superior intelligence and knowledge,
curiosity has a fitness-enhancing effect. Hence, we are also rewarded in
satisfying our curiosity by feeling very good. And the increased knowl-
edge contributes to future success. Thus, the satisfaction of this desire
is generally consistent with our welfare. However, there are cases where
the satisfaction of our curiosity actually makes us worse off. If a person
sees a box in her office, she will naturally open it to have a look. If a
colleague prevents her from doing so by seizing the box away from her,
she will be made a little unhappy. However, if the box contains a
poisonous snake, she will be very grateful to her colleague. It may be
said that, in this case, it is only the uninformed preference that is vio-
lated, not the informed one. But suppose the box contains a photograph
of her mother being raped by a soldier. Then, even after being informed
of that, she may still be unable to overcome her curiosity and will open
it to have a look. If this disturbs her a lot, she will be made much worse
off than by the seizing away of the box from her. Suppose that there are
no benefits, directly or indirectly, of so looking at the photograph, to
her or to others and that there are no side-effects of seizing the box away
from her. Most people will agree that, in this case, seizing away the box
from her is the right thing to do. If I were her, I would be most grateful
for that. The satisfaction of my (even if informed) preferences as such
has no normative significance for me; it is important only because, in
most cases, it makes me (and/or others) happier, directly or indirectly.
Now consider the desire for accomplishment. This may also have
some genetic basis and may be related to the accumulation instinct
possessed by many animal species. However, it is clear that this desire
is also affected by social and educational influences. We are not only
born and taught, but we also learn, to want to do useful things. Parents
teach and influence their children to be so for the good of themselves,
their children, and perhaps also of others. Having a desire to achieve is
generally good for the welfare of ourselves and of others. However, good
qualities may also be detrimental occasionally. Wise people try to avoid
this but not all people are perfectly wise. An extreme example of the
lack of wisdom is the saying ‘If I cannot be famous for my good deeds,
54 Efficiency, Equality and Public Policy
I will still try to be notorious for my bad ones.’ Once a person has a
strong desire to achieve, the satisfaction of the desire will make him
happy. However, he may be willing to undertake so much hardship
that far exceeds the happy feeling of achievement. This may still not be
irrational if his accomplishments greatly increase the welfare of others.
However, most of us have on some occasions been trying to fulfil our
desire for accomplishment (or for revenge) in such a way and to an
extent that decreases our own welfare without increasing that of others.
If this is not just due to ignorance, it is irrational according to my
definition. Though this definition may be debatable, we may achieve
some agreement by noting that there are different degrees of ir-
rationality. In any case, I do not find that there is any intrinsic norma-
tive significance in having the desire for accomplishment fulfilled,
except for the welfare effects of such fulfilment, including the indirect
ones through the accomplished deeds. Other autonomous desires (such
as preferring a less happy ‘real-world’ life to one of being attached to a
pleasure machine) may be similarly analysed.
Now, consider a concrete real example. As reported in Ming Pao Daily
(a reliable leading daily in Hong Kong) on 23 March 1997 (p.A11), a
man in Tienjin was sent to a hospital after fainting while cycling.
Further investigations revealed that he decided to buy a cellular mobile
phone costing more than $9,000, despite having a monthly salary of
only about $600 and a life saving of only $5,000 (all in Chinese dollars).
He thus cut down on all his expenses including food. After more than
four months of semi-fasting, he managed to buy the cellular mobile
phone with a loan of another $2,000 from relatives. The phone was not
for any business or other essential use. Rather, he used it to show off to
his friends, cycling from one house to another, ending up in the hos-
pital. Maybe he was ignorant of the possibility of fainting. However,
even if he did not faint, I do not think that the happiness he would
obtain from showing off his phone would be more than his welfare loss
from spending more than $9,000, including making himself rather
unhealthy from semi-fasting. His desire to have the phone, whether
autonomous or not, is likely to be irrational.
1. Separability
That the (social) weight attached to any individual utility is inde-
57
58 Efficiency, Equality and Public Policy
As Mueller observes:
The reason why WMP leads us to the utilitarian SWF is not difficult
to see. It requires that individual utility differences sufficient to give rise
to preferences of half of the population must be regarded as socially
more significant than differences not sufficient to give rise to prefer-
ences (or dispreferences) of another half. Since any group of individuals
comprising 50 per cent of the population is an acceptable half, this
effectively makes a just perceivable increment of utility of any individ-
ual equivalent to that of any other individual.
Ng (forthcoming, a) has a different argument for full utilitarianism.
Starting from separability as compellingly established by either Fleming
(1952) or Sugden and Weale (1979) (see Section 5.1 above), the follow-
ing condition is added:
Local Cardinal Individualism: For any four social alternatives, if all
individuals apart from any single individual j are strictly indifferent between
all the four alternatives, then the social welfare difference between a pair of
these alternatives is higher than that between another pair if individual j’s
utility difference between the first pair is higher than that between the second
pair. In symbols, for all a, b, c, d in the set of social alternatives, for any
individual j, if a I i b I i c I i d for all i π j (where Ii stands for strict indif-
ference by individual i), then:
62 Efficiency, Equality and Public Policy
x y
x¢ x y¢
y
x¢
y¢
Figure 5.1
64 Efficiency, Equality and Public Policy
of $100 when the income level is only one thousand dollars. However,
here the excesses are already in terms of welfare. If there is diminishing
marginal welfare of income, the same welfare excess when income is
high must already mean larger income excess. The society may also
not want to place the same weight on the two excesses or differences if
other individuals are differently affected. However, here individual B is
affected by exactly the same amount and all other individuals are not
affected at all. Thus, there is no individualism-consistent reason not
to give the welfare excess w A(x) - w A(y) the same social weight as the
welfare excess w A(x¢) - w A(y¢). These are valued to be exactly the same
in welfare to individual A. Strong Individualism requires the society to
value these two welfare differences also equally. Then, if the society
views the welfare difference w A(x) - w A(y) as big enough to outweigh the
negative welfare difference w B(x) - w B(y) to decide W(x) > W(y), it must
also regard the welfare difference w A(x¢) - w A(y¢) as big enough to out-
weigh the negative welfare difference w B(x¢) - w B(y¢), as x and x¢ gives
exactly the same welfare level to B and so do y and y¢, and all other indi-
vidual welfare levels are exactly the same. Thus, although labelled
‘strong’ to distinguish it from Axiom 1a, Strong Individualism is really
compelling.
It might be thought that, despite the fact that w A(x) - w A(y) = w A(x¢) -
w (y¢), the same welfare difference w A(x¢) - w A(y¢) may be regarded as
A
socially more important than that of w A(x) - w A(y) for the following con-
sideration. Suppose that person A is poor (in income) at y¢ and below
average at x¢, rich at y and very rich at x, with other things being the
same. While A may regard the increase in income from rich to very rich
as of similar welfare significance to her as the increase from poor to below
average, others in the society may regard the latter increase as more
important. In fact, they may not like A getting very rich as much as they
do not like seeing A in poverty. If this is true, as is likely to be the case,
it is socially more important to increase A’s income from poverty to
below average than to increase her income from rich to very rich.
However, this does not violate Strong Rational Individualism which
holds the welfare levels of all individuals except A and B (which is used
for comparison with A) unchanged. In the above consideration, other
individuals will have lower welfare levels in y¢ than x¢ and lower welfare
levels in x than in y.4 If other individuals all have the same welfare levels,
there is no individualism-consistent reason to give the same weight to
welfare differences of the same value for the same person.
What if the person herself gives different weights to welfare differ-
ences of the same value? Certainty it will then be individualism-
Utilitarianism 65
W = Â f i (w i )
From Strong Individualism, each and every f i must be linear in wi. This
is so because if any f i is not linear in wi, the social welfare significance
(effect on W) of some equal welfare differences will be different. Strong
Individualism must thus be violated. We must thus have W separable
and linear in individual welfares:
W = Â ai w i
W = Â wi
abstracted away (on which see Section 5.4 below). Axiom A then implies
that a maximal indifference (continuous with a marginal preference,
or Edgeworth’s minimum sensibile, or just perceptible increment of
pleasure) must be represented by a same positive constant. The VNM
utility indices satisfying Axiom A then must be the same as the Edge-
worthian cardinal utility indices. It is true that the zero point is left
undefined in this. However, for utilitarianism, the zero points do not
matter, only utility differences count for making social choice.
Even without using the above rigorous axiomatic justification of the
equivalence of the VNM utility and the subjective cardinal utility of the
classical utilitarians and neoclassical economists, a commonsense argu-
ment may also establish this equivalence. We only need to note that
the VNM utility indices do not come from thin air only to represent
individual choices over lotteries. Rather, each individual already has her
subjective cardinal utility function to begin with. When I face choices
involving risks, I compare the probabilities and the associated subjective
cardinal utility gains and losses involved before making a choice. More-
over, I choose to maximise, as far as possible, subject to mistakes (which,
together with things like regrets, excitement, give rise to various para-
doxes and intransitivities; see, e.g. Munier, 1988), my expected subjec-
tive cardinal utility. Thus, these subjective cardinal utility functions
exist before the VNM construction is used. The latter is used to discover
the pre-existing individual subjective cardinal utility functions by ob-
serving their choices involving risks. The degree of the pre-existent
diminishing/increasing marginal (subjective and cardinal) utility (of
income or some other objective indices) determines the degree of risk
aversion/preference, not the other way round.
What the ‘pure representation’ economists do is to say that the VNM
utility is purely a representation of individual choices involving risks
and has nothing to do with the subjective cardinal utility of the same
individual. This would be true if individuals did not consult their sub-
jective utility in making choices involving risks. (But then on what basis
do they make rational choices involving risks is rather mythical.) There
is a sense in which these pure representation economists are right. First,
the well-known axioms of the VNM hypothesis does not ensure that
individuals do consult their subjective utilities and try to maximise
expected subjective utility in making choices involving risks. However,
this may be taken as a commonsense requirement for rational choice
or, if one wants to be rigorous, Axiom A above may be assumed to ensure
this. This then makes Harsanyi’s result a full utilitarian one. Secondly,
Roemer (1996, p.142) is correct in claiming that the knowledge of all
Utilitarianism 69
Mongin has:
I wish to argue that one can have either type of ethical preference
and still be a utilitarian, if secondary effects are taken into account.
On the other hand, if secondary effects are abstracted away, as ap-
parently intended by Mongin (note his ‘once-and-for-all’ distribu-
tion and the dependence of utility on own endowments only), there
is no individualism-consistent grounds for either type of ethical
preference.
Mongin’s example is the adaptation of a famous Allais paradox
to the context of social choice. However, the intended paradox is
really there only if there is a confusion of fundamental values with
non-ultimate considerations by the ethical observer. Thus, I, a self-
proclaimed utilitarian at the fundamental level, prefer society A to B
and also prefer D to C, if the secondary effects of social cohesion in
A dominates the higher endowment of B (valuing the various effects
ultimately on individual utilities) and if the higher endowment in D
dominates the slightly more equality of C. However, if the 10 better
endowed persons in B are able to pursue worthwhile activities con-
tributory to future advance in welfare, I prefer B to A; if the extreme
inequality in D results in a polarised society with undesirable secondary
effects, I prefer C to D. Thus, if we take secondary effects into account,
none of the ethical preferences mentioned by Mongin need be contrary
to utilitarianism, nor is any of them inconsistent. On the other hand,
if these secondary effects have been abstracted away (as they should
be, otherwise they should be included in the description of the above
societies), there is no individualism-consistent grounds for having either
of the inconsistent types of ethical preferences mentioned by Mongin.
For example, since the utility of each and every individual depends only
on her own endowment, none of them finds complete equality dis-
tasteful. Then, how could the ethical observer choose ‘on the grounds
that complete equality is distasteful’? Surely, the hypothetical ethical
observer is supposed to choose on behalf of the 100 individuals, not on
behalf of herself! She is just a theoretical construct that does not really
exist.
72 Efficiency, Equality and Public Policy
If we accept the above objection, it just means that even this best avail-
able method is not ideal. With finite sensibility (which is an indis-
putable fact) and without some form of interpersonal comparison, we
cannot make a reasonable social choice except in the unlikely cases
where every individual strictly prefers x to y. Even the indifference of
one individual is sufficient to cloud the issue unless we are prepared
to make the interpersonal comparison that any utility difference associ-
ated with his indifference is not strong enough to overshadow the pref-
erences of others. Thirdly, even if it is true that a just perceivable
increment of utility differs across individuals either due to different
‘perceptive’ powers or due to different ‘jumps’ in utility, how are we to
know whose just perceivable increment is larger and whose smaller? In
the absence of specific knowledge regarding this, it seems best to regard
them as equal (cf. Lerner, 1944, pp.29ff; Sen, 1973b). If we adopt the
convention of designing an average just perceivable increment of utility
as one, then the just perceivable increment of any particular individual,
in the absence of any specific knowledge, may be expected to have a
probability distribution such as depicted in Figure 5.2, that is, the indi-
vidual is just as likely (if at all) to have a lower as a higher than average
value. We can thus minimise our mistake by taking this increment to
be one, the average value (Ng, 1980).
50% 50%
–41 –21 1 2 4
Figure 5.2
76 Efficiency, Equality and Public Policy
Table 5.1
x y z
a b a b a b
1 1 1 1 0 0 0
2 0 0 0 1 1 1
Even if the feeling for the process of choice, the welfare of future gen-
erations, etc. has been taken into account or has been abstracted away,
some people may still regard y as preferable to x because y gives indi-
vidual 2 a ‘fair shake’ while x does not. To be socially indifferent between
x and y is thus regarded as being unfair against 2. But I fail
to see why it is unfair if the society is also indifferent between y and
z (see Table 5.1 above), as utilitarianism axioms dictate. Is it unfair
against both individuals (!) to be socially indifferent between x, y and z,
despite the fact that both individuals are indifferent between y and
a 50–50 chance of x and z? It is probably difficult to convince those who
still regard y as preferable to both x and z, but I hope that the following
argument will persuade at least some of them to have a second thought.
Let us accept the reasonable assumption that social welfare is con-
tinuous in individual utilities (an infinitesimal change in individual
utilities does not cause a big jump in social welfare). To prefer y over x
and z then implies that if we change the utility indices of y sufficiently
slightly, then this new alternative y≤ is still preferred to x. To see this
more intuitively, note that we have to change the utility indices by a
finite amount (due to continuity), say to y¢ (see Table 5.2; the precise
figure is immaterial) to make it indifferent to x. We can then increase
the utility indices back a little to y≤ which will then be preferable to x
and z. I wish to show that the adoption of a SWF dictating this prefer-
ence is detrimental to the utility of both individuals and hence ir-
rational at least from the viewpoint of individualism, when individual
preferences satisfy the Marschak (VNM) axioms.
We do not adopt a SWF to guide our social choice for one particular
known instance only. Rather, once a SWF is adopted, it is used for all
instances until, for some reason, it has been discarded in favour of
another. Moreover, even if we consider a once-and-for-all choice only,
we do not know which particular alternatives that choice will involve
at the ‘constitutional stage’ or the ‘original position’. Thus, on the
Table 5.2
x y z y¢ y≤
a b a b a b a b a b
1 1 1 1 0 0 0 0.89 0 0.9 0
2 0 0 0 1 1 1 0 0.89 0 0.9
Utilitarianism 79
82
A Dollar is a Dollar 83
suming goods and services purchased from the income. They are trading
off the utility of leisure with the utility from work (which consists of
the utility from consuming the higher income and the positive or
negative utility of work itself). Moreover, the utility of consuming the
higher income is affected by whatever specific redistributive or prefer-
ential measures are in place. Thus, the preferential treatment against the
rich in government expenditure and other areas will add on to the pro-
gressive tax/transfer system to determine the total disincentive effects.
Hence, even if only a marginal amount of specific equality-oriented
measures are used, the disincentive effects involved are not just
marginal. Thus, for the same degree of equality in real income (utility)
achieved, the same degree of disincentive effects is incurred whether we
use only the tax/transfer system or a combination of it and some
specific purely equality-oriented system. But the latter alternative has
the additional efficiency costs of distorting choice, and is thus inferior.
In Ng (1984b), the following proposition is proved.
Proposition A (A dollar is a dollar): For any alternative (desig-
nated A) using a system (designated a) of purely equality-oriented pref-
erential treatment between the rich and the poor, there exists another
alternative, B, which does not use preferential treatment, that makes no
one worse off, achieves the same degree of equality (of real income, or
utility) and raises more government revenue, which could be used to
make everyone better off.
Under alternative B, a more (than alternative A) progressive tax/
transfer system (designated b) may have to be used. By definition,
progressivity in the tax/transfer system is not classified as ‘preferential
treatment’ here. Section 6.3 below argues that complications such as
administrative costs, political constraints, ignorance of benefits dis-
tribution, etc. either strengthen the proposition or do not affect the
main thrust significantly.
In fact, proposition A can be generalised to any efficiency-
inconsistent alternative A, not just an equality-oriented preferential
treatment. The proof of the proposition is exactly unaltered if the pref-
erential treatment is not equality-oriented but inequality-oriented.
Instead of counting a dollar to the poor as worth less than a dollar to
the rich in cost–benefit analysis, it is better to tax the rich less and tax
the poor more (or subsidise them less). Similarly, an alternative based
on random treatment, one based on tradition, etc. can all be shown to
be inferior to some alternative B defined to compensate for the gains
and losses in dismantling the efficiency-inconsistent methods used.
Then, ignoring issues of practical difficulties, individual ignorance, ir-
A Dollar is a Dollar 87
rationality, and procedural preferences (on the last item, see Ng, 1988),
alternative B must be Pareto superior.
However, the existence of alternative B does not necessarily mean that
it can be identified and implemented. If system a is designed to take
account of second-best considerations, then system b can also be so
designed. But system a may only be consistent with second-best con-
siderations by chance rather than by design. In addition, the infor-
mational costs of designing a system consistent with the second-best
considerations may be prohibitive.3 Then we may not be able to iden-
tify system b. Thus, while alternative B may exist, it may not be feas-
ible to implement. Thus, if we wish to strengthen Proposition A to be
one about the existence of a feasible superior alternative B, it would
apply only in a probabilistic sense. That it (the strengthened prop-
osition) still applies in a probabilistic sense is due to the theory of third
best. Just as it may be consistent with second-best considerations,
system a may also be opposite to the requirement of second best. The
theory of third best (see Ng, 1977) can then be used to show that the
expected gain is negative. Hence, as far as the second-best consideration
is concerned, the use of system a involves negative expected gains.
Essentially, random divergence from first-best rules is as likely to be
inconsistent as to be consistent with the requirement of second best.
Due to the expected concavity in the relevant objective function, the
gain when it is consistent is less than the loss when it is inconsistent.
So the expected gain is negative. (See Ng, 1979/1983, Chapter 9 and Ng,
1984b for a more detailed demonstration of this.)
The half-a-century old argument of Little (1951) may be briefly dis-
cussed at this juncture. Basically, Little argues that one cannot say
that a direct tax (on income) is better than an indirect tax (on some
goods) on the ground that the former taxes all goods at the same rate.
The reason is that there is another good, leisure, which is also untaxed
under direct taxation. Taking the simple case of just two non-leisure
goods (see the top half of Figure 6.1), an indirect tax on one of the
goods creates a wedge (between relative costs and benefits) between
that good (good 1) and the other good (good 2) as well as between that
good and leisure. A direct tax causes a wedge between good 1 and leisure
and between good 2 and leisure. Hence, no conclusion can be made on
the desirability of direct versus indirect taxes without specific infor-
mation on the interrelationships between the various goods and leisure.
While this argument is formally correct in a certain sense, it is mis-
leading in its conclusion. Thus, it is certainly true that an indirect
tax on half of the (non-leisure) goods may be less distorting than a direct
88 Efficiency, Equality and Public Policy
Little’s Argument
G1 G2 G1 ≠ G2
≠ ≠ ≠
L L
(The ≠ sign signifies a wedge between MRS and MRT, i.e. relative benefits and costs)
Our Argument
G1 G2 G1 ≠ G2
≠ ≠ ≠
L L
Figure 6.1
sidised (or at least taxed less). Hence, due to the higher income tax rates
on the rich, the second-best consideration also suggests giving more sub-
sidies to the rich than others for the same leisure-substitutary goods,
and giving higher subsidies on leisure-substitutary goods that are dis-
proportionately consumed by the rich. Thus, luxuries as such do not
justify higher taxes. (The proposal to impose high taxes on ‘diamond
goods’ which are valued for their value is a separate matter of pure effi-
ciency; see Ng, 1987a and Part II of this book which argues for more
public spending partly based on this point.)
In practice, it is also informationally, politically, and administratively
impossible to design and implement specific taxes/subsidies and other
specific economic measures in accordance to the requirement of second
best. This requires full information of the interrelationships of all rele-
vant sectors in the economy. It may be informationally feasible to take
account of the more important interrelationships, but political consid-
90 Efficiency, Equality and Public Policy
ity and efficiency. However, equality and efficiency are important con-
siderations and the fact that preferential treatment is an inefficient tool
to achieve equality and efficiency has to be pointed out.
clusion can hardly be expected, it does not seem probable that costs
involved in the latter (i.e. preferential treatment) will be much lower
than costs involved in the former (i.e. a more progressive tax system).
On the other hand, the costs of administering a pure taxation system
are almost certainly significantly lower than those of administering
a system of taxation combined with preferential treatment in govern-
ment expenditure. Hence, consideration of transaction costs seems to
strengthen, not weaken, our central conclusion.
There may be specific cases whereby the use of an apparently ‘pref-
erential’ policy may be superior to making the income tax system more
progressive because of the significantly lower transaction (evasion, lob-
bying, and administrative) costs of the former. But such a policy is jus-
tified on its efficiency consideration of lower transaction costs (relative
to income taxation) and cannot be justified purely on the equality con-
sideration advanced by egalitarian lobbyists.
jects: project M will increase the incomes (after allowing for cost share)
of one million individuals by $10 thousand each, and project N will
increase the income of one single random individual by $10 billion.
Ruling out costless lump sum transfers (that would make us indifferent
between the two projects), it is clear that project M will be preferred to
project N by all social welfare functions egalitarian in incomes. This
preference is not based on valuing a marginal dollar to the rich as lower
than a marginal dollar to the poor. Rather, it is based on treating the
first dollar as more valuable than the 10 billionth dollar, to whomever
they go. (Due to diminishing marginal utility, the same person typically
regards the loss of $10,000 as more significant in utility terms than the
gain of $10,000.) Hence, the equality-incentive argument used above
does not apply here. However, the equality-incentive argument can be
used to dispel the possible belief that, since a project that itself creates
inequality is inferior to one with the same aggregate net benefits but
which does not create inequality, a project that creates equality must
be preferable to one with the same aggregate net benefits but distri-
butionally neutral. Consider a third project O that will yield the same
aggregate net benefits of $10 billion but be distributed across the
economy in such a way that the poor will have much higher benefits
and the rich have negative benefits. While this may seem to be a good
thing in itself, the incentive argument will show that project O is in
fact inferior to project M. If project O were to happen as a natural event,
it would be preferable. But if it is chosen instead of project M, it will
produce disincentive effects.
From the above, it may be said that, for projects whose redistributive
effects are marginal, one can simply choose in terms of aggregate net
benefits; for projects whose redistributive effects are significant, we
should prefer the one with less redistributive effects, given the same
aggregate net benefits. This seems to lend support to the concept
of a conservative social welfare function discussed by Corden (1974,
p.107).
stead of receiving some kind of dole money. This can largely be taken
care of by putting an appropriate shadow price on employment. For a
single person without dependents, his income from a low-paid job
is likely to be sufficient to preclude him from receiving a subsidy. All
that is needed is a low or zero income tax, so he will not have to suffer
the feeling of being on the dole. For families with dependents, the
subsidy can be effected in the form of, say, substantial child-endowment
payments differentiated according to income levels. A fixed child-
endowment is used in Australia with no one feeling ashamed of receiv-
ing it and the introduction of differentiation is unlikely to change this
substantially.
99
100 Efficiency, Equality and Public Policy
random restriction of the range of market operation makes both the rich
and the poor worse off.
In fact, the point can be seen without the mathematical example. To
see it more clearly, abstract from the effects of changes in relative prices
(which could go either way) by considering a case of fixed earning abili-
ties and fixed prices (as could be facilitated by constant returns, small
country, etc.). Starting from a situation where some of the goods
(private, no external effects) are not subject to market allocation but are
supplied in fixed amounts by the government to everyone (possibly
equally), dismantle the government provision and allow these goods to
be allocated in the market. The savings of the government from not
having to provide these goods are then used to pay each individual,
with each individual getting the worth of the previously allocated
amounts of these goods in money and free to buy whatever quantities
desired. Then obviously no individual will be worse off as she can buy
the previously allocated quantities if so desired. (It is assumed that
the transaction costs of market allocation are not higher than that of
government allocation.) Those choosing to buy different combinations
(including buying more or less of some or all goods) of these goods are
made better off.
The market economy can be shown to function perfectly efficiently
in the sense of Pareto optimality mainly under the assumptions of
perfect competition, adequate information by the market participants,
and the absence of external effects. Thus, possible reasons for govern-
ment intervention or even replacing the market include objectives
beyond Pareto efficiency on the one hand and certain serious violations
of the above assumptions (called ‘market failures’ below) on the other.
In my view, a valid objective beyond Pareto efficiency is distributional
equality. (See Ng, 1988, 1990a for arguments on the unacceptability of
many other proposed objectives.) However, as argued above, the objec-
tive of equality may justify a progressive tax/transfer system but does
not justify specific efficiency-inconsistent measures. It is true that this
argument assumes the feasibility of the appropriate tax/transfer system.
Where such a system is politically or administratively infeasible or
subject to very important uncertainty in its effects (Kelsey, 1988), it may
be efficient to supplement the tax/transfer system with other specific
equality-oriented measures, including commodity taxes (Cremer and
Gahvari, 1995). While such a possibility cannot be completely ruled out,
problems of administrative costs and political difficulties are likely to
be more serious for the specific equality-oriented measures, as argued in
Economics versus Politics 101
Section 6.4 above. Thus, we have to look to market failures for valid
reasons for replacing the market.
Different degrees of market failures prevail all over the place, most
requiring no or only limited intervention instead of supplanting the
market altogether. Thus, the existence of some market failures is not
enough; we have to look for very substantial, even overwhelming,
extent of market failures. I do not think we can find this with respect
to market power and ignorance. The wealthiest person may be able to
wield many times more influence than an average person if willingness
to pay is taken into account, but in most countries, no single person
earns a substantial fraction of the GNP. While substantial ignorance is
involved in political voting, it is not substantially alleviated by going
for the one-person-one-vote solution. This leaves external effects as the
possible source of substantial market failure.
Three distinct types of external effects may be associated with politi-
cal decisions. First, political decisions taken may externally affect people
beyond the jurisdiction and people in the future. This external effect
has little to do with the issue here, since the choice of either one-person-
one-vote or willingness-to-pay has negligible effects on these external
effects. Secondly, political decisions, being concerned with public issues,
involve the public-good external effect. Both the choice (usually in elec-
tions) of public officials and the decisions of the public officials on
public issues (including law and order, other regulations, provision of
public goods) are related to the public-good problems, including that of
free riding. Thus, if voters are allowed to actually pay money to express
their willingness to pay, most of them may pay nothing, preferring
to free-ride. However, this problem only makes the willingness-to-pay
principle difficult to put into effect, it does not make the principle
undesirable. If we have more sophisticated method of inducing self-
interested voters to express their true willingness to pay, such as the use
of the Vickrey–Clarke–Groves incentive-compatible mechanism on a
carefully selected sample of voters (Ng, 1979/1983, Section 8.3), the free-
riding problem could be overcome. Thus, I see the next external effect
as the most important stumbling block to the use of the efficiency prin-
ciple in political decisions.
The third type of external effects associated with political decisions is
less similar to the normal external effects familiar in economics; it may
even be controversial to describe it as an external effect. The function-
ing of a modern society, including its economy, requires political
stability, the maintenance of law and order, and preferably also a high
102 Efficiency, Equality and Public Policy
degree of social cohesion. These elements may also be desirable for the
psychological well-being of individuals in the society. These desirable
elements are fostered by a political system using the one-person-one-
vote principle in its political process instead of the willingness-to-pay
principle, except for a society where the majority of its citizens are as
good economists as you (i.e. the likely readers of this book), and this is
well nigh impossible, at least in the foreseeable future. The use of the
efficiency principle in political process is likely (if not certainly) to gen-
erate feelings of apathy, antagonism, and the like against the govern-
ment, the wealthy, and law and order among the poorer classes and
those in the political fringe. This will increase the difficulties or costs of
maintaining law and order and will likely reduce stability and cohesion.
Thus, the exercising of the preference intensities through the willing-
ness to pay in traditionally political sphere, especially by the rich, may
be said to entail important external costs. In most cases, this consid-
eration makes the use of one-person-one-vote principle optimal in the
political process despite the existence of the normal inefficiency as-
sociated with supplanting the market. This is the most important factor,
as far as I can see, in explaining the separation of political and economic
spheres. However, since this factor depends on the attitude of the
people, as this attitude changes with time and with the understanding
of economics, the optimal sphere of economics will gradually expand.
Nevertheless, knowing the difficulty of teaching basic economic prin-
ciples even to university students, I am not at all optimistic about the
speed of this expansion and about the ultimate conquest.
PART II
How Much Should the
Government Spend?
It is not the intention here to discuss all issues relevant to this central
question of public finance. Important questions like the relative ef-
ficiency of government versus private supply, the feasibility of the
private production of public goods, informational asymmetry, etc. are
not addressed except in passing. Instead, some neglected and perhaps
more important issues are focused. After reviewing the basic theory on
the appropriate size of government spending on public goods and some
empirical considerations, Chapter 8 argues for higher public spending
based on the importance of diamond goods, relative-income effects, and
environmental disruption effects, the unimportance of absolute income
for welfare at the social level at least for developed economies, and the
high welfare potential of public spending especially in research (the
example of a possible quantum leap in welfare through brain stimu-
lation is discussed in Appendix A). With reasonable assumptions, it is
shown that the optimal relative (to the GDP) size of public spending
increases with per capita income (Appendix C). Chapter 9 addresses the
question: Should the benefit–cost ratios for public projects exceed one
by a sufficient margin to account for the distortionary costs of raising
government revenue?
103
This page intentionally left blank
8
A Case for Higher Public Spending
Co-author: Siang Ng
105
106 Efficiency, Equality and Public Policy
ing may also be regarded as the cost of providing public goods. In many
countries, governments spend a lot on transfer payments such as old-
age pensions and unemployment benefits. These are regarded as redis-
tributive spending rather than spending on public goods. While these
items certainly have redistributive effects, they also have some public-
goods aspect. Thus, keeping the unemployed paid reduces crimes and a
more equal distribution of income increases social cohesion and enters
positively into many people’s utility function. Hence, while the aspect
of public goods provision does not exhaust the function of government
spending, it is the major one for most countries. For simplicity, only
this major aspect is focused here.
A public good is non-rivalrous in consumption. My tuning to a radio
or TV broadcast in no way affects your reception of it. Thus, in contrast
to the equation of the marginal benefit of each and every consumer to
the marginal cost for a private good, the optimal supply of a public good
is based on equating the aggregate marginal benefit (vertical sum of indi-
vidual marginal benefit curves) to the marginal cost of provision, as is
(should I just say ‘should be’) now well known to all undergraduates in
economics. A simple theory on the appropriate size of public spending
may then be stated thus. Sum the aggregate marginal benefit curves of
all relevant public goods horizontally to give the aggregate marginal
benefit curve of public spending in general. The intersection of this
curve with the marginal cost curve of public spending then determines
the optimal size of public spending.
Due to the heterogeneity of different public goods, a convenient way
of measuring public spending is by the dollar amount spent. Then, a
change in the efficiency in supplying public goods will be reflected in
different physical quantities for the same spending. This will be reflected
in a shift in the aggregate marginal benefit curve rather than in the cost
curve. However, despite the dollar definition of public spending, the
marginal cost of a unit of public spending need not be one dollar. Taking
account of the excess burden (also called deadweight loss or distor-
tionary cost) of taxation and other excess costs of raising government
revenue (administrative, compliance, and policing cost), the marginal
cost of a dollar of public spending is typically regarded as exceeding one
dollar by a considerable margin. Feldstein (1997) gave an estimate as
high as $2.65. (On the marginal cost of public funds, see also Fortin and
Lacroix, 1994 and references therein.) With a higher marginal cost of
public spending, the optimal size of public spending is smaller, given
the marginal benefit curve. However, contrary to this traditional view,
A Case for Higher Public Spending 107
Kaplow (1996) argues that the benefit–cost ratio for public project only
needs to exceed one. Chapter 9 addresses this issue. (If we ask the wider
question whether a higher public sector increases unemployment
and/or reduces the rate of economic growth, it seems that the evidence
is inconclusive; see, e.g. Dowrick, 1993; Karras, 1996; Phelps and Zoega,
1998, pp.788–9.)
marginal unit is halved. The marginal benefit curve must thus shift
downward in its initial range to become MB¢. The value of (the new) MB
(i.e. the height of the MB’ curve) at any given level of public spending
g is only half of the original value of MB at half that level of public
spending g/2; e.g. the height of A¢ is only half that of A. This is so
because, by halving provision efficiency as assumed, the g amount of
public spending provides only g/2 amount of public goods previously
provided, and a marginal increase in g also results in half of the previ-
ous increment. This results in a downward shift in the marginal benefit
curve for the range where the curve is elastic in the sense of a demand
curve (i.e. if a more than 1% increase in g is associated with a 1 per cent
reduction in the marginal benefit, which must be true starting at g = 0;
note that the MB curve being elastic in the sense of a demand curve
really means that the fall in MB is proportionately small with respect to
an increase in g). However, for the range where the marginal benefit
curve is inelastic, a decrease in provision efficiency shifts the MB curve
upward. Thus, if the MC curve intersects the MB curve at the inelastic
range as shown in Figure 8.1, inefficiency in public provision may in
fact increase the optimal level of public spending. (This is subject to the
condition that the decrease in provision efficiency is not so large as to
make non-provision optimal or to make a shift to private provision
optimal.) We thus have (see Appendix F for a formal demonstration):
MC
A¢
MB MB¢
0 g
g* g*¢
Figure 8.1
110 Efficiency, Equality and Public Policy
It should be emphasised that our case for higher taxes on goods with
significant diamond effects is purely efficiency based, not equality
based. In fact, as argued in Chapter 6, the objective of equality is more
efficiently achieved through the general tax/transfer system rather than
through specific measures.
world perspective, though each individual and even each nation may
find growth important, as argued in more details in Ng and Wang
(1993). Appendix C goes further to show that welfare-reducing growth
may prevail even if the government chooses the optimal level of public
spending and the optimal amount of spending on environment-
disruption abatement.
the same, both significantly higher than that of Japan. (See Cummins,
1998.)
While there are notable cases like Japan and France that are far off
the regression line, statistically significant positive relationship between
happiness and income exists cross-nationally globally. However, this is
due mainly to the inter-group difference between the high-income and
high-happiness advanced and free countries and the others. The analy-
sis by Schyns (1998) shows that there is no positive relationship
between income and happiness within either of these two groups.
Kenny (1999, p.12) reports a similar lack of relationship within each
group by splitting all countries into two groups of below and above
$8,000 in per-capita income.
The relationship between happiness and income level inter-
temporally within the same country (at least for the advanced countries
which have such data) is even less encouraging in terms of giving a posi-
tive relationship. For example, from the 1940s to 1994, the real income
per capita of the US nearly trebled. However, the percentage of people
who regard themselves as very happy fluctuated around 30 per cent,
without showing an upward trend; another measure of average happi-
ness fluctuated around 72 per cent. Over the period 1958–88, the per
capita real income level in Japan increased by more than five times
(Summers and Heston, 1991). However, its average happiness measure
fluctuated around 59 per cent, also without an upward trend. (See Veen-
hoven, 1993; Myers, 1996, p.445; Diener and Suh, 1997; Oswald, 1997;
Frank, 1999.) In fact, ‘if there is any causal relationship in rich
countries, it appears to run from happiness to growth, not vice-versa’
(Kenny, 1999, p.19). Also, recent research suggests that individuals who
strongly value extrinsic goals (e.g. fame, wealth, image) relative to
intrinsic goals (e.g. personal development, relatedness, community)
have less happiness (Ryan et al., forthcoming).
Kenny (1999, pp.4–5) also puts the point of fast diminishing marginal
utility of income in more objective terms thus:
On the other hand, there are factors that affect or at least correlate
with happiness much more significantly than income, including
being married or single (Myers, 1996, p.510), being employed or not
(Winkelmann and Winkelmann, 1998), and having a religious belief
and church attendance.
For those who do not trust the more subjective measure of happiness
and opt to use more objective indicators of the quality of life, the picture
is not much different. Analysing a panel dataset of 95 quality-of-life
indicators (covering education, health, transport, inequality, pollution,
democracy, political stability) covering 1960–90, Easterly (1997) reaches
some remarkable results:
The surprising results are not due to the worsening income distri-
bution (there is some evidence that the share of the poor gets better
with growth). Rather, the quality of life of any country depends less on
its own economic growth or income level but more on the scientific,
technological, and other breakthroughs at the world level. These
depend more on public spending than private consumption.
If higher income does not really increase happiness, why do people
put so much emphasis in making money? Apart from the importance
of relative-income effects and the public bad aspect of environmental
disruption, individual ignorance and/or irrationality may also have a
role to play. Apart from the discussion in Chapter 4 (Section 4.2 in par-
ticular), some further remarks may be added here.
118 Efficiency, Equality and Public Policy
While noting that the rat race for material growth may be welfare reduc-
ing, I am not anti-growth. Instead of hoping for a slower growth or even
a depression, as some environmentalists do, a healthy growth with an
appropriate increase in environmental protection measures seems a
much superior option. Moreover, if economic growth is conducive to
a higher degree of civilisation by providing more resources to support
scientific and technological advances conducive to welfare, it may be
welfare-improving despite some negative environmental effects. For
example, the advance in science and its applications to medicine, engin-
eering, etc. have contributed much to a comfortable and enriched life,
the relief of pain, and the cure of many illnesses. The development of
the Westminster and other forms of democratic government and the
rule of law, the prevalence of modern communications and social inter-
action have also helped create a freer and more peaceful world. The
understanding of the working of the market mechanism has contributed
to the collapse of the communist totalitarian system and to the end of
the Cold War. Higher education is becoming more widespread. Looking
into the future, one can be reasonably confident that further advances
in these and related areas will be forthcoming. Moreover, there are likely
to be significant or even dramatic improvements in welfare from sources
most people do not dream of now. For example, the techniques of elec-
trical brain stimulation (discussed in Appendix A) and genetic engin-
120 Efficiency, Equality and Public Policy
• The very topic of the appropriate size of the public sector, regarded
by Feldstein (1997) as the central public finance question, is very
under-researched. For example, few, if any, researchers relate the
important issue of relative income to this central question. While I
have discussed this and other related issues above, a lot more quan-
titative studies are needed.
• While studies on the effects of specific drugs and ingredients have
been done, it seems that a general study tracing the different types
A Case for Higher Public Spending 123
124
The Appropriate Benefit–Cost Ratio 125
‘First, higher tax rates may reduce the supply of labor and, in the
longer run, the supply of capital. . . . Second, higher tax rates change
the forms in which individuals take their compensation. A higher
marginal tax rate on labor income induces a substitution of untaxed
fringe benefits and more pleasant working conditions for taxable
cash income . . . [Third,] higher marginal tax rates reduce taxable
income by inducing more spending on things that are tax deductible
(including . . . charitable gifts, and health care) . . . many economists
believe that an increase in tax rates would cause only a small dead-
weight loss . . . as a “small” triangle. . . . That line of reasoning is
wrong for four reasons. First, the deadweight loss caused by a change
in tax rates is not a small triangle but a much larger trapezoid because
126 Efficiency, Equality and Public Policy
While some recent literature has qualified the Pigou principle, a full-
scale onslaught is presented by Kaplow. He argues that public goods can
be financed without additional distortion by using an adjustment to the
income tax that offsets the benefits of the public good. The:
(in comparison to a lower degree of protection and lower tax) and pays
more by the same amount if she earns more, leaving the incentive struc-
ture unaffected.
If the benefit of a public good is a constant amount across all income
levels but it is financed by a proportional income tax, then a disincen-
tive effect may be involved. But then ‘it will be accompanied by a
countervailing change in redistributive benefits that has been ignored’
(Kaplow, 1996, p.525). To this observation, it may be added that, in the
reversed case, e.g. where a public good with benefit proportional to
income is financed by a lump-sum tax, a negative redistributive benefit
will be involved, but it will be accompanied by a negative disincentive
effect, reasonably assuming that a tax increasing in income is already
in existence for redistributive purposes. If the income-tax schedule has
been designed to approximately achieve an optimal balance between
the redistributive benefits and the distortive costs of taxation, the redis-
tributive benefits (positive or negative) of non-benefit-proportional
financing of a (non-huge) public good will be approximately offset by
its distortionary costs (positive or negative). For a huge public good or
the cumulative effects of a large number of public goods, either benefit-
proportional financing may be used or a change to the income-tax
schedule may be made to redress any significant divergence between
redistributive benefits and the distortionary costs of taxation.
For the case where the benefits of the public goods increase with the
income level, it may be interpreted as a case where there is significant
complementarity between the public good and the taxed goods. In this
case, some recent analysis allows for certain offsetting effect on the
extent of distortionary costs. (Intuitively, an increase in public goods
then increases the demand for the taxed goods, generating more tax
revenue and offsetting the under-consumption of these taxed goods.)
However, while this complementarity is unambiguous in reducing the
distortionary costs, it is ambiguous in affecting the optimal size of
public good provision due to the following counteracting effect. An
increase in public good provision necessitates higher taxes on the taxed
goods, leading to higher prices of these goods which reduces the
marginal valuation on and hence the optimal size of the public good
through complementarity. Substitutability has the reversed effects. (See
Batina, 1990 and Chang, 1997.) Since the Kaplow principle is concerned
with the size of the required benefit–cost ratio for public goods rather
than on the level of public spending directly, it is not affected by the
counteracting effect through complementarity on the marginal valu-
ation on public goods. Moreover, most of the recent contributions in
128 Efficiency, Equality and Public Policy
This would require a higher benefit–cost ratio for all public goods or a
distributional weighting system favouring the poor and against the rich
for all specific cases. (For the case of libraries, I believe that there are
counteracting benefits, including indirect external economies and merit
goods, justifying higher levels of provision. But this is a separate issue.
On indirect externalities, see Ng, 1975b.)
The second qualification refers to heterogeneity of preferences for
people on the same income. It is not feasible to design income tax
schedules and public spending programmes that differ between people
on the same income but of different preferences. Thus, the construction
of compensating tax/transfer changes in either Kaplow’s or my argu-
130 Efficiency, Equality and Public Policy
ment can only make people on each income as a group no worse off.
People who differ in preference significantly from the average (at that
income level) one way or the other may either gain or lose. However,
the gainers within each income level could compensate the losers fully
(with some overall gains left over). This is called a quasi-Pareto social
improvement in Ng (1984b). Objections to the compensation tests are
mainly based on the distributional consideration that a gain valued at
$2 million by the rich need not be more important than a loss valued
at $1 million by the poor if the compensation is not actually paid. For
a quasi-Pareto social improvement, full compensation is possible within
each group of the same income level. The rich-poor issue does not apply.
(The minor problem of possible inconsistency in the application of
compensation tests is also discussed in Ng, 1984b.) Thus, the problem
of heterogeneity of preferences does not cause a big problem. A more
important qualification to the Kaplow principle (but not to the ‘a dollar
is a dollar’ principle) is discussed below.
The positions of Kaplow and Feldstein (and that of most other econ-
omists, including myself before I read Kaplow) appear to be diametri-
cally opposite, with Kaplow arguing for the adequacy of the simple
benefit–cost principle and Feldstein emphasising the need to account
for the big deadweight loss of raising revenue for public spending.
However, I wish to argue in this section that we may adopt an inter-
pretation that makes both sides basically correct, subject to some impor-
tant qualifications.
Subject to an important comment mentioned below, Feldstein is basi-
cally correct that, given the various ways individuals adjust to the higher
tax rates, raising an additional dollar of public revenue (by, say, a mar-
ginal proportionate increase in tax rates across the board) on its own does
impose, in general, a significant (say, 100 per cent) distortionary cost
over and above the revenue collected. However, this does not mean that
the benefit–cost ratio for a public project has to exceed 2. There are off-
setting benefits at the spending side (on top of the direct benefits of the
public goods).3 If the valuation of the higher public spending is the same
as the extent of the higher taxes at each and every income level, then
the higher disincentive effects of the higher taxes will be exactly (subject
to the qualifications mentioned at the end of Section 9.2 above and
another qualification to be mentioned presently) offset to give no net
increase in disincentive effects, as shown by Kaplow. This is so because
The Appropriate Benefit–Cost Ratio 131
when people reckon in terms of the total package of the higher taxes
and spending, the gains offset the losses at each income group. Putting
it differently, the fact that people at higher income levels place higher
values on the public goods makes the spending side possess negative dis-
incentive effects or positive incentive effects, offsetting the disincentive
effects of the higher taxes, when the higher taxes do cause disincentive
effects.4 On the other hand, if the degree at which the valuation of the
higher public spending increases with income is less than the degree at
which higher taxes increases with income, such that there are higher
disincentive effects for the total package (of higher taxes and higher
spending), there exist offsetting distributional gains (since the poor gain
and the rich lose in net terms). In the opposite case where the poor lose
and the rich gain in net terms, there are distributional losses. But then
the combined disincentive effects of the total package are negative. In
any of these three cases, the Kaplow principle applies.
However, apart from the qualifications mentioned at the end of
Section 9.2, the Kaplow principle is subject to another important quali-
fication. (See Appendix C of Ng, forthcoming b, on another more com-
plicated consideration.) Kaplow’s analysis ignores the behavioural
responses to higher taxes except through the income (consumption)/
leisure choice. As Feldstein (1997) emphasises, there are other responses
including substitution into less tax-assessable spending like luxurious
offices. This encouragement of inefficient choices does increase the dis-
tortionary costs of higher taxes despite Kaplow’s argument. Higher taxes
encourage people at each and almost all income levels (especially those
facing high marginal tax rates) to use less-beneficial though more tax
(avoidance)-effective ways of spending money. This extra distortion is
not offset by any extra benefit of the higher public spending. This quali-
fication to the Kaplow principle applies also to illegal means of tax
evasion: higher tax rates encourage more evasion. Here, the loss in tax
revenue itself is not a distortionary cost as it is offset by the gain of the
taxpayers. The distortionary cost consists in the fact that the taxpayers
would prefer to have the higher incomes legally, without having to go
into the dubious, time-consuming, and likely less beneficial means that
are more tax-effective. In practice, this may be the most important
qualification to the Kaplow principle.
A query may arise: Why do the higher benefits of the higher
public spending, financed by the higher compensatory taxes, offset
the higher tax-rates to produce neutrality (no extra disincentive effect)
in income/leisure choice, but do not offset the higher tax-rates to
also produce neutrality in tax evasion and other similar choices? This
132 Efficiency, Equality and Public Policy
Discerning readers may have noticed that Part I of this book is some-
what ‘rightwing’ while Part II is ‘leftwing’. Thus, Part I argues strongly
for utilitarianism (Chapter 5) and against pure egalitarianism (Appen-
dix B), and for the principle of ‘a dollar is a dollar’ (Chapter 6). On the
other hand, Part II argues for higher public spending, especially on
research and environmental protection. However, though the two parts
may be opposite in their political philosophy, they are not inconsistent
with each other. For example, the fact that the principle of ‘a dollar is
a dollar’ is consistent with the argument for higher public spending may
be seen easily as the latter is based purely on the efficiency consider-
ations of relative-income effects, environmental disruption effects, the
negative disincentive effects of public spending (the Kaplow principle),
the global public-good nature of research, etc. I may be schizophrenic
in the sense that my heart is leftwing and my head is rightwing.
However, there is no inconsistency in my arguments. In fact, the op-
posite political inclinations of the two parts demonstrate that I follow
the dictates of my logical analysis wherever they take me, without stick-
ing to a political preconception.
While there is no inconsistency, there may be some tension between
different arguments. For example, my allowance for the difference
between preference and welfare due to non-affective altruism (or
malice), ignorance, and irrationality (Chapter 4) and the use of the will-
ingness to pay (Chapter 6) need some explanation. As should be clear
from Chapter 3 and Chapter 4, I view happiness or welfare as the appro-
priate ultimate objective. However, partly because it is more difficult to
obtain information on happiness than on willingness to pay, especially
on economic issues, and partly because of the possible negative effects
of overriding people’s preferences even for their own welfare, I have
135
136 Efficiency, Equality and Public Policy
Cutting government funding on research is starving the goose that lays the
golden eggs. In a developed economy like ours, it is research that contributes
most to social welfare and further economic growth. Without sufficient safe-
guard on protecting the environment and without increasing welfare-improving
measures like research, pure increases in income and consumption may well be
welfare-decreasing.
137
138 Appendix A
A3 Enormous benefits
Apart from relieving pain and inducing pleasure, EBS may also be used as a
‘primer’ in improving well-being. For example, Heath (1964, p.236) reported,
‘strong pleasure [from brain stimulation] was associated with sexual feel-
ings, and in most instances the patient experienced spontaneous orgasm. . . .
This patient, now married to her third husband, had never experienced orgasm
before she received . . . stimulation to the brain, but since then has consistently
achieved climax during sexual relations’. Once the right neurons have been
excited, they become excitable more easily. The right neural pathways have been
established.
Among the important social problems of our time are drug addiction, crimes
and (mental) depression. These social problems, and possibly others, seem to be
largely solvable with the widespread use of EBS. In comparison to EBS, the use
of addictive drugs like heroin is a very inefficient and dangerous method of
achieving a ‘high’. If one has easy access to pleasurable sensations by just turning
on the electricity, there seems little reason left to try dangerous alternatives like
heroin. Just as intractable pain may be relieved by EBS, mental depression should
also be largely removable by positive EBS. Since most depressions are caused by
failure to achieve happiness one way or other, the availability of happy sen-
sations by EBS should provide a definite relief. Among others, the amelioration
of stress (Patterson et al., 1994), reduction of stress ulcers (Yadin and Thomas,
1996), improved performance in a maze (Jiang et al., 1997), and the treatment
of alcoholics (Krupitskii et al., 1993) have been reported.
(Patterson and Kesner, 1981) of EBS over a sustained period for a long time (e.g.
a few hours daily over a number of years) has proved to be quite safe. Thus EBS
addiction is only a problem if it leads to the serious disregard of other duties
such as to threaten the welfare of (mainly) other people (especially the future
generations). While the pleasures induced by EBS can be intense, I doubt
that psychological addiction of such a magnitude would occur. Rats choose to
use EBS until exhaustion but humans only for ‘up to half an hour daily’ (Sem-
Jacobsen, reported in Delgado, 1976, p.484). Relative to other pleasures and
objectives, the pleasure of EBS does not seem to be compelling for humans
(Bishop et al., 1964; Valenstein, 1973, p.28). If one believes in creation, perhaps
God made us this way so that we could eventually provide happiness not only
for ourselves but also for animals. In the unlikely event of serious addiction, the
problem could be solved by using legal and/or technical devices restricting the
unlimited use of EBS.
While EBS addiction is unlikely to be so serious as to threaten the survival of
a civilised society, it may be feared that it would significantly reduce mutual
human relationships. If one could obtain pleasure by simply turning on the
electricity, there might be little motivation left for the cultivation of personal
relationships. This is unlikely to happen. Even if one could obtain a variety of
pleasurable sensations by EBS, there would still be the innate need for com-
panionship left. Secondly, the pleasure from EBS to humans does not seem to be
as fulfilling as, say, a full sexual relationship with its simultaneous stimulation
of a number of areas and close personal contact, nor as rewarding as spiritual
fulfilment of the highest order. Thirdly, the provision of pleasure which might
otherwise be unavailable in sufficient amount may in fact create many happy
and easy-to-go-with individuals. This may remove many personal conflicts and
promote better mutual relationships. Fourthly, even if personal relationships
were reduced, the benefits of EBS would still likely to more than compensate for
the loss. For example, the introduction of television probably has significantly
reduced conversation. But that does not necessarily make it a bad thing. Its ben-
efits have to be taken into account as well.
In this connection, the long-lasting nature of pleasure from EBS definitely gives
it a big advantage. Inventions like television usually appear to have enormous
potential benefits around the time of their initial introduction. After prolonged
usage, some of their disadvantages are discovered though some other beneficial
usages may also be found. More importantly, the novelty value has disappeared.
For example, while watching television is very enjoyable for those just getting
access to it, it may become a second best option after its novelty value has dis-
appeared. The benefits of television probably still outweigh its costs by a very
wide margin, but not by as much as it would be if the novelty value could be
maintained. With EBS, the situation would be different. Since EBS is the direct
stimulation of the brain, the pleasure during stimulation does not depend on
any novelty value. Moreover, the intensity of pleasure from EBS does not dimin-
ish with prolonged stimulation (either continuously or daily over a number of
years). Thus the enormous increase in happiness brought about by EBS could be
expected to be maintained largely unabated, and in fact could be greatly
increased through better techniques of stimulation.
EBS may be regarded as unnatural in the sense that it does not occur in the
course of our natural biological survival. But most civilized products, institutions,
medical treatments, etc. are unnatural in this sense. This does not make them
140 Appendix A
bad. To improve our welfare, we have invented many ‘unnatural’ things. EBS is
a recent invention that if properly made use of widely, possesses welfare signifi-
cance surpassing all previous inventions put together.
Many people from the West may find, upon first contact, the culture, tra-
dition, and ways of enjoying life in the East and in some primitive tribes degrad-
ing. The same is true for people from the East on some Western ways of life. But
we have learned from liberalism to be more tolerant towards different cultures
and ways of life as long as they are not harmful. Many liberals would go further
in tolerating individual freedom of action even for those actions which are
harmful to the actors themselves. EBS is about the least harmful way of induc-
ing intense pleasure and should never be regarded as degrading by anyone who
has the slightest adherence to liberalism.
Will God approve EBS? If one does not believe in God, the question does
not arise. If one believes in God, then the answer seems to be affirmative. For
example, the ten commandments do not include: Thou shall not engage in EBS.
Nor do they include: Thou shall not enjoy yourself. Moreover, if God does not
want us to use EBS, why did He create us in a way that EBS can induce intense
positive reward?
If higher funding for research could result in such spectacularly welfare-
improving discoveries and inventions as EBS, the present writer would be pre-
pared to halve his post-tax income to help pay for them.
Appendix B
Pure Egalitarianism: a Critique
Egalitarianism has made much headway. When utilitarianism was first proposed
by classical utilitarians in the 19th century, it was regarded as a radical philos-
ophy used to justify egalitarian policies through such arguments as diminishing
marginal utility. (For a modern statement of this, see Hare, 1997.) Now, most
people writing on related issues (e.g. Rawls, 1971; Dworkin, 1981; Nielsen, 1985;
Sen, 1992 and Roemer, 1996) seem to view utilitarianism as a conservative
philosophy; they prefer much more radical egalitarianism. In this appendix,
it is argued that this is based on questionable reasoning. On the other hand,
there are writers arguing for something much to the right of utilitarianism. For
example, Nozick (1974) argues for liberty and against equality; Posner (1981)
argues for wealth maximisation. Such extreme divergence of views is, at least
partly, based on the confusion of non-ultimate considerations with basic values,
rather than just on the difference in basic value judgements.
For example, as argued in Chapter 6, for whatever degree of equality-efficiency
tradeoff aimed at, it is more efficient to pursue efficiency or wealth maximisa-
tion (treating a dollar as a dollar whomsoever it goes to) on specific issues of
public policy, leaving the equality objective to be pursued through the general
tax/transfer system. However, as the ultimate social objective, wealth maxi-
misation is clearly unacceptable. (Another example of confusing non-ultimate
considerations with basic values is the concern, e.g. Kappel, 1997, for simulta-
neous inequality with life-time equality.)
At the non-ultimate (e.g. political, day-to-day) levels, liberty, efficiency, equal-
ity of incomes (or resources, primary goods, capabilities), etc. are all important
considerations. However, they typically may be in conflict and need be traded-
off with each others. At the ultimate level, the optimal tradeoff should be decided
by the maximisation of aggregate individual welfares, as argued in Section B1.
This is also a form of egalitarianism, equality in the weights attached to the
welfare of all individuals. This is the only appropriate equality to insist on at the
ultimate level (Section B2). At this ultimate level, the arguments of the libertar-
ians (Section B3), Rawls (Section B4), various forms of egalitarianism including
resource and welfare egalitarianism (Section B5) and capability egalitarianism
(Section B6) are shown to be unacceptable.
141
142 Appendix B
they possess a lot of money. We all want money, health, etc. in order to be happy.
But we do not want happiness for the purpose of obtaining anything else. Hap-
piness is good in itself.
We do not have to ask why is happiness valuable or good because we all enjoy
our happy feelings and suffer from unhappy feelings. We are like this because of
biological reasons. We are intelligent beings capable of making choices. (This is
also true for at least some animal species higher up in the phylogenetic scale.)
Due to this capability, God (or evolution) found it necessary to ensure that we
make the ‘right’ choices (from the viewpoint of survival and reproduction, i.e.
biological fitness). Thus we are genetically programmed to want to do the fitness-
enhancing things by being awarded with pleasures when eating fresh and nu-
tritious foods when hungry, when mating with fertile members of the opposite
sex, and penalised with pain when we injure ourselves.
It may also be true that we have an instinct for justice or morality. At least we
have a sense of morality which may be partly inborn and partly learned. As long
as the sense of morality is formed by nature and/or by nurture, we also feel
happy/unhappy in doing/seeing/suffering something morally good/bad. Such
happiness/unhappiness should of course be included in the utilitarian calculus.
However, moral principles are ultimately valuable only because of their contri-
bution to welfare, as argued in Section 4.1.
Like other non-ultimate objectives like freedom, democracy, etc. equality is
a valuable objective if and only if it contributes, directly or indirectly, to the
ultimate objective of happiness or welfare. (Individual welfare is defined to
be the net happiness of the individual.) Generally, equality is a highly valuable
objective as it contributes to welfare in several important ways, including
through the undisputed fact of diminishing marginal utility, through fostering
better social cohesion, and through our sense of justice. Thus, I regard myself as
a utilitarian egalitarian. To the extent that the pursuit of equality does not harm
too much other valuable objectives like liberty and efficiency, it contributes to
welfare.
Consider the hypothetical situation where most people do not like equality in
the distribution of income (or primary goods, etc.). They find equality dull. Each
of them would rather be one of the poor in a society of income inequality than
be one in a society of equal income, even at a higher average income. Then, even
abstracting from disincentive effects, equality itself may make everyone worse
off. Clearly, in this case, equality is not good for the society even if efficiency,
liberty, and other valuable objectives are not diminished. Thus, it is clear that,
ultimately speaking, equality is only of instrumental value; it is not valuable in
itself.
While the above example is hypothetical, it is true in the real world that people
ultimately want happiness, not equality in itself. They do want equality but only
to foster their welfare and perhaps also the welfare of others. Some evidence may
be adduced to support this claim. First, surveys indicate that people view hap-
piness as their ultimate objectives (Veenhoven, 1984 and Ng, 1996a). Secondly,
people from very poor countries of less unequal distribution still eagerly seek to
migrate to countries of higher incomes even if more unequally distributed, and
even if they would become one of the poorest class if they are successful in
migrating. Thirdly, most readers can convince themselves by asking what they
themselves value ultimately. Be persistent and try to go to the truly ultimate. If
Appendix B 143
you think you value equality, ask, ‘Why?’ Answer: ‘equality is good’. Then ask:
‘why is equality good?’ or ‘is equality good if it makes everyone suffer enor-
mously?’, etc.
B3 The libertarians
No doubt, liberty is extremely important. At the political level, it makes sense
most of the times to insists on liberty as if it is sacrosanct. The sacrifice of liberty
on some grounds of expediency may increase welfare at the moment but is likely
to produce undesirable side effects and hence undesirable in the long run even
from the viewpoint of welfare maximisation. Thus, again, I regard myself as a
utilitarian libertarian. However, liberty is not our ultimate objective. If we have
included all the side effects, most people, like me, would rather be happy but
not free than be free but unhappy.
144 Appendix B
B4 Rawls
In contrast to the libertarians, Rawls (1971) does not accept the justice of unequal
endowments. But he goes to the other extreme in believing that primary goods
(i.e. income, wealth, opportunities, the social bases of self-respect, etc.) should
be distributed equally unless inequality makes everyone better off.
Rawls’ (1971, 1982) theory of justice may be summarised into two
principles:
1. Each person has an equal right to a fully adequate scheme of equal basic lib-
erties which is compatible with a similar scheme of liberties for all.
2. Social and economic inequalities are to satisfy two conditions. First, they must
be attached to offices and positions open to all under conditions of fair equal-
ity of opportunity; and secondly, they must be to the greatest benefit of the
least advantaged members of society.
I am prepared to accept the first principle on the following understanding:
• that it is adopted because it promotes the general welfare;
• in circumstances where it is disastrous to the general welfare, it may have to
be suspended;
• in deciding what is the ‘most extensive total system’ and what is ‘compat-
ible . . . for all’, the ultimate criterion is the general welfare.
Appendix B 145
A sex maniac may be in favour of freedom to rape and claim that this is com-
patible with everyone’s freedom to rape.1 It may also happen that the sex maniac
is the person of the lowest welfare level such that freedom to rape for all will
maximise the welfare of the worst off, hence consistent with the spirit of Rawls’
second principle to be discussed below. However, if freedom to rape results in
the reduction of the welfare of those raped and scared of being raped by more
than (in aggregate) the welfare gain of the rapists (even though the former still
have higher welfare levels than the latter group even with freedom to rape), then
freedom to rape should be regarded as not compatible with the freedom of not
being raped. The ‘most extensive total system of basic liberties’ should then not
include the freedom to rape. However, thus interpreted, the first principle is really
a device to promote the general welfare. It is not ultimate. The first part of Rawls’
second principle may be similarly accepted as the first principle.
Now, consider the second part of maximising the benefit of the least advan-
taged, with advantage being judged by the possession of primary goods. This
maximin principle is in direct contrast to the utilitarian principle of maximising
the unweighted sum of welfares. The latter gives equal weights to all while the
former gives an infinite weight to the welfare of the least advantaged. Being the
least advantaged, they probably have very high marginal welfare of income.
Giving equal weights to their welfares already implies valuing a dollar to them
as worth more than to the more advantaged groups. Giving an infinite weight
implies the willingness to sacrifice the welfare levels of all others enormously
(provided that none of them becomes more disadvantaged than the least advan-
taged) for a marginal increase in the welfare of the least advantaged. This is
morally unacceptable. In fact, if I were the least advantaged person, I do not
want any person/group in the society to sacrifice a big welfare loss just to increase
my own welfare a little. (For an interesting argument on the unacceptability of
the Rawlsian version of egalitarianism as it implies: ‘that redistribution ought to
aim to equalize the life expectancy of men and women by making men have
longer and women shorter lives . . . to employ fewer men and more women in
. . . undesirable jobs. Men . . . ought to have shorter working days and longer
vacations than women’, see Kekes, 1997, p.661.)
Ur
N
M
E
45°
0 Up
Figure B1
Appendix B 147
Uk
3
A F
1
F
2
F E
W2
W1
45°
0 C UJ
Figure B2
point that this apparently innocent axiom is objectionable and the point that it
(together with other reasonable axioms) leads to welfare egalitarianism may be
illustrated together in Figure B2.
First, suppose that, in situation 1 with a given amount of resources and the
utility functions of the two persons, we have the symmetrical utility feasibility
frontier (UFF) F1. (Points on and within the frontier are feasible to attain; points
above or beyond the frontier are not feasible.) The reasonable axiom of sym-
metry assumed by Roemer then dictates the choice of the equal welfare/utility
point E. The assumed concavity in the individual utility functions without inter-
dependence and the abstraction from production considerations may mean that
the UFF is concave (the feasibility set is convex). However, since no upper limit
is placed on the degree of concavity, we have as the limiting case, F2 as a possi-
bility. The point E still has to be chosen given F2 (from either symmetry or from
the Pareto principle). Now suppose that the amount of resources increases unam-
biguously but in a way that increases the utility possibility of person K only, such
that the new UFF F3 is the curve ABEC. Resource Monotonicity requires that, in
this new situation with F3, no individual utility can be lower in comparison to
the situation at F1 or F2. This means that E still has to be chosen from F3. There
is no upper limit as to how steep the section BE of F3 may be, except that it is
downward sloping. If BE is steep enough, any SWF allowing for some tradeoff
between utility levels of different persons, including those satisfying symmetry,
such as one represented by the welfare contours W1 and W2, will choose a point
B from F3 that is northwest of E. This shows that Resource Monotonity, by insist-
ing on E, is unreasonable.
Consider a concrete example. Suppose that the two persons concerned are my
brother and myself and that no other sentient will be affected. Suppose first that
we are endowed only with food which we enjoy equally with diminishing mar-
148 Appendix B
ginal utility. It makes sense to share the food equally. (The issues of desert and
incentives do not arise by assumption.) Now, suppose that we also have a ball
(assumed not exchangeable into food). I hate ball games while my brother loves
them. It makes sense to let him have the ball. However, he enjoys playing with
the ball only if he has enough to eat; the more he plays with the ball, the hun-
grier he becomes. Thus, his utility can only increase substantially if he has more
than half of the food. Ball games increase his marginal utility of food dramati-
cally. It makes sense for me to agree to let him eat more than I do. The increase
in endowment of a ball should in this case result in an optimal outcome involv-
ing my having less welfare. Is this unfair on me? I genuinely think not. If the
increase in endowment is in the form of a sword with which I like to play very
much and which my brother hates, then I should similarly have more to eat to
be able to enjoy the sword. Provided this will also be done, there is no unfair-
ness. My welfare and that of my brother has the same weight in the social welfare
function of our two-person society. By maximising the unweighted sum of util-
ities, the society maximises the expected utility of each individual under the veil
of ignorance. This is fair and moral.
person, I would not think it is morally right for the society to incur huge costs
to improve my capability marginally.
Sen (1992, p.84) argues that: ‘Capability represents freedom, whereas primary
goods tell us only about the means to freedom.’ I will similarly argue that ‘welfare
is the ultimate objective, whereas capability tells us only about the means to
welfare’.
Sen does not go for equality in welfare for two reasons. One is the issue of
responsibility also emphasised by others (e.g. Dworkin, 1981). The society should
compensate the disadvantaged for circumstances for which they are not respon-
sible, not for something for which they are responsible, including inequalities
from the exercise of personal preferences. The other one is Sen’s view that people
are not only concerned with welfare. Let us come to this second point later and
assume now that people are only concerned ultimately with welfare. Then, the
following argument is reasonable. A person is no less disadvantaged and no more
accountable if he is unlucky enough to be born with some handicaps in per-
forming valuable functions than if he is unlucky enough to have lower inborn
earning abilities and/or is less lucky in business. This may justify the movement
from equality in (objective) resources to equality in primary goods and in
capability. However, following this logic to its logical conclusion compels us to
welfare egalitarianism. If people want to maximise their own welfare and, with
equal capability,2 end up with different welfare levels, this must be due either to
different abilities in making appropriate choices (if this ability is included in the
definition of capability and is equalised, only the next reason applies) or to
differences in luck. Differences in ability to make appropriate choices are not
different morally from differences in ability to earn income and in capability
to perform functionings. Luck in obtaining higher welfare levels is no differ-
ent morally from luck in earning higher incomes. Thus, if we should move
from resource egalitarianism to capability egalitarianism, we should also move
from capability egalitarianism to welfare egalitarianism. (Cf. the arguments of
Arneson, 1989/1995.)
Sen will object to the argument of the above paragraph on the ground that
people do not just want to maximise welfare/happiness but have other objec-
tives as well, including opulence (wealth) and agency goals. Even for misers,
wealth or money is not wanted for its own sake. While most people want money
to buy goods now or in the future (for the purposes of consumption, security,
power, rivalry and indication of success), misers derive so much pleasure from
looking at the money that spending money is seriously curtailed. But no one
wants money for its own sake. Some people may enjoy the process or the fact of
making money. Still, it is the enjoyment, the prestige, etc. that counts. These all
increase the happiness for them to be valuable. Thus, opulence is not an ulti-
mate objective.
People also want to do certain things, to accomplish certain achievements, and
prefer to do so themselves. For example, I want the moral compellingness of utili-
tarianism at the fundamental level to be generally accepted. If I myself con-
tribute to this acceptance, all the better. This is what Sen means by agency goals.
This is important enough, but again not at the fundamental level. I like to con-
tribute to this enlightenment myself because it makes me feel good and also
increases the respect of others for me which again makes me feel good and more
likely to be successful in other activities which are in turn pursued for the purpose
150 Appendix B
B7 Concluding remark
This appendix has examined several views regarding egalitarianism, including
the libertarian, the Rawlsian, welfare egalitarianism, and capability egalitarian-
ism and has found them to be unacceptable as an ultimate social objective. That
such extremely different views are held by intelligent and reasonable authors
may be explained by the confusion of non-ultimate considerations with basic
values. For example, the reason why Nielsen (1985, p.45, p.53) is in favour of
having ‘the income and wealth . . . be so divided that each person will have a
right to an equal share’ is to avoid giving ‘one person power or control over
another’. Presumably, being subject to the power and control by others is bad
for welfare. Thus, when we reckon at the ultimate level, we may take into account
such negative effects of inequality of wealth and analyse using the ultimate
objective of welfare. Then, the society should not go for equal welfare but for
maximum aggregate welfare as individuals want more welfare for themselves,
not equal welfare with others.
Liberty, equality of resources, of capability, etc. may be desirable aspects usually
conducive to the general welfare when other things are held unchanged.
However, they are not the appropriate ultimate objective for the society. As
argued here and elsewhere in this book, the appropriate ultimate social objec-
tive should be individual happiness or welfare. The maximisation of the
unweighted (equivalent to equal weights for all individuals) sum of these indi-
vidual welfares (i.e. utilitarianism) is the appropriate form of egalitarianism.
In fact, Section 5.2 shows that Rational Individualistic Egalitarianism implies
utilitarianism.
Appendix C
Economic Growth Increases the
Optimal Share of the Public Sector
Joint Author: Siang Ng
There are two very important observations, one well known to all econ-
omists and uncontroversial and one not well known and may be contro-
versial. The first is that government spending as a share of GDP (or GNP)
increases historically and increases with per capita GDP both intertemporarily
and cross-nationally. (See Section 8.1.) The second is that, for rich countries, the
level of happiness does not increase with per capita income. (See Section
8.5.) The main purpose of this appendix is to provide a simple but reason-
able analytical model that simultaneously explains these two apparently
unrelated observations. The main results are summarised into two propositions
below.
Without intending to be exhaustive, some important factors affecting the
welfare of a person are included in the analysis proposed below. First, we accept
the traditional variables focused most closely by economists, personal con-
sumption c (in real terms, as also true for all variables discussed in this appen-
dix) and leisure x. Secondly, the amount of public goods provision g is included.
Obviously, apart from personal consumption, one benefits from the provision of
law and order and other public goods and facilities. This has also been well recog-
nised and analysed by economists. Thirdly, as discussed in Section 8.5 in the text,
we include relative consumption or relative income r. (For our purpose here, it
does not really matter which one is used.) Fourthly, environmental quality E is
included. Again, in the current era of heavy pollution, congestion, deforestation,
and other forms of environmental disruption, the importance of this factor needs
hardly any justification.
Of course, there are other factors affecting happiness; they are not analysed
here. Also, we ignore the possible existence of ignorance, imperfect foresight,
and other possible divergences (non-affective altruism and irrationality) between
preference (represented by a utility function) and happiness (represented by a
personal welfare function). Arguments on the existence and implications of these
divergences have been discussed in Chapter 4.
We thus take the utility or welfare function of an individual as
U = U (c , x, r , g , E ); Uc , Ux , Ur , Ug , UE > 0 (C1)
Where r ∫ y/Y, y is the income of the individual concerned and Y is the average
income of the relevant society, a subscript denotes partial differentiation, e.g. Uc
= dU/dc. An individual maximises (C1) subject to:
151
152 Appendix C
c = (1 - t )y (C2)
y = (1 - x )w (C3)
taking g, E, t, w as given; where t is the proportional (assumed for simplicity)
income tax, and w is the exogenously given earning ability, and the time con-
straint is normalised to be unity. Assuming an interior solution (compelling as
starvation and exhaustion are both unacceptable), the first-order solution is:
dU dc ˆ dx ˆ dr ˆ
= Uc Ê + Ux Ê + Ur Ê (C5)
dw Ë dw ¯ Ë dw ¯ Ë dw ¯
Substituting in dc/dw and dr/dw from the differentiation of (C2), (C3) and r ∫ y/Y,
taking Y as given, and substituting in (C4) (which makes the term associated
with dx/dw equals zero; intuitively, as the individual starts with an optimal pos-
ition with respect to the choice of leisure x, a marginal change in x has no first-
order effect on utility), we have after multiplying through by w/U to express in
proportionate or elasticity terms:
sUw = hUc + hUr (C6)
where s ∫ (dU/dw)w/U is the proportionate total response of U with respect to
Uw
Note that Ur does not appear in (C7) as y and Y change by the same proportion,
leaving r unchanged. We should now introduce the determination of govern-
ment spending on public goods g and environmental quality E. In our simple
model, these are:
g = N (1 - a )tY (C8)
E = E( A, Y ); E A > 0, EY < 0 (C9)
where N is the given number of individuals, a is the proportion of tax revenue
used for the abatement (A) of environmental disruption, leaving the proportion
(1 - a) for spending on public goods. That EY < 0 captures the environmental dis-
ruption effect of most production and consumption. We also have:
A = atYN (C10)
Substitute dc/dw, dg/dW, dE/dW from the differentiation of (C2), (C3), (C8), (C9),
taking N, t and a as given, we have, after simplification using (C4) (but we cannot
get rid of all the terms associated with dx/dw this time, as Equation C4 is not
in general optimal from the social viewpoint) and multiplication with W/U to
express in proportionate terms:
x ˆ XW Ur
sUW t,a = hUc + hUg + hUE ( h EA + h EY ) + Ê s [h - hUg - hUE ( h EA + h EY )]
Ë 1- x¯
(C11)
where s ∫ (da/db)b/a and h ∫ (da/db)b/a for any a, b as before, and |t, a| indi-
ab ab
cates that t and a are being held constant. The first three terms in the RHS of
(C11) are the direct effects of an economy-wide increase in earning or produc-
tivity, including an intrinsic consumption effect hUc as the higher productivity
allows higher per capita consumption, a public-good effect hUg as higher national
income allows more spending on public goods, and an environmental disrup-
tion effect hUE(hEA + hEY). For this last effect, the environmental quality effect hUE
has to be multiplied by both the abatement effect hEA and the disruption effect
hEY because an increase in production both increases the disruption and the
abatement (through the higher tax revenue a constant share of which is used for
abatement). The last complex term in (C11) is the indirect effect through sXW,
the (proportionate) effect of earning ability W on leisure X. As everything in
(C11) is put in proportionate terms, this has to be multiplied by x/(1 - x), the
ratio of leisure to working hours. The rest of this complex term, i.e. [hUr - hUg -
hUE(hEA + hEY)], captures the external effects of individual income/leisure choice.
An increased consumption of leisure reduces one’s own income and hence ben-
efits others through the relative-income effect hUr, but harms others through a
reduction in public goods provision (hence minus hUg), and may benefit or harm
others through the environmental effect hUE depending on whether (hEA + hEY) is
negative or positive. It is perhaps not unreasonable to assume that (hEA + hEY) is
negative. Even if a given proportion (provided not excessively large to begin
with) of tax revenue is used for abatement, an increase in production still causes
more disruption to the environment.
The RHS (right-hand side) of (C11), in contrast to that of (C6), is of ambigu-
ous sign. An individual may rationally engage in the rat race for making money.
For the society, an increase in productivity may not be an unmixed blessing even
154 Appendix C
if the higher production finances more public goods provision and more
abatement.
So far, we have assumed that the tax rate t and the proportion of tax revenue
used for abatement a are being held constant. However, as productivity W
increases, the government may wish to change these ratios. Allowing t and a to
change with W, we have, instead of (C11):
t ˆ tw Uc È tw Ê a ˆ aw ˘ Ug
s UW = s UW t , a - Ê s h + s - s h + (s tw + s aw )hUE h EA
Ë 1- t ¯ ÍÎ Ë 1- a ¯ ˚˙
(C12)
t ˆ Uc Ê x ˆ Xt Ur
sUt = hUg + hUE hEA - Ê h + s [ h - hUg - hUE ( hEA + hEY )]
Ë1-t ¯ Ë1-x¯
(C13)
where s and h to the double superscripts are as defined under (C11). Similar to
(C11), the first three terms in the RHS of (C13) are the direct effects and the last
term is the indirect effect. While the indirect effect is completely analogous to
that in (C11) and has the same interpretation, the direct effects (of an increase
in tax rate t) consist in a public goods provision effect hUg, an (environmental
disruption) abatement effect hUEhEA (as a higher tax revenue finances for both
public goods provision and abatement), and a (reduced) consumption effect
Ê t ˆ hUc . The last effect has the term [t/(1 - t)] because of the proportionate
Ë 1- t ¯
nature of all terms in (C13). For this particular effect, it is easier to see its rationale
in non-proportionate terms. If we multiply both sides by U/t to undo the propor-
tionality, we have, showing in the RHS the reduced consumption effect only:
dU ydU
= ... ... (C13¢)
dt dc
In this form, it is clear that an increase in t reduces utility at the rate y through
the consumption effect as an increase in t reduces c at the rate y.
Similarly, differentiating U in (C1) with respect to a, we have:
a ˆ Ug
s Ua = hUE h EA - Ê h (C14)
Ë 1- a ¯
choice of t and a entails setting (C13) and (C14) to zero. Substitute the result-
ing equations into (C12), yielding:
t ˆ 1 ˆ tW Ug
sUW t *, a * = ÏÌ1 + Ê (1 - s tW )¸˝hUc + hUE h EY + ÊË s h
Ó Ë1-t¯ ˛ 1- a¯
x ˆ XW hUg ˘
+Ê (s - s xt )ÈÍhUr - hUE h EY - (C15)
Ë 1- x¯ Î 1 - a ˙˚
where |t*,a*| indicates that the tax rate and the proportion of revenue used for
abatement are being optimised. Thus, (C15) gives, in proportionate terms, the
effect of an exogenous increase in productivity on utility, while both the tax rate
and the abatement ratio are being optimised before and after the increase.
Despite this optimisation, the RHS of (C15) is of ambiguous sign. The first term
(consumption effect) is positive (but likely to be small for rich economies), the
second term (environmental disruption effect) is negative (and likely to be
absolutely sizeable for rich economies), the third term is positive/negative if the
optimal tax rate t increases/decreases with W, and the last term is of ambiguous
sign. With likely opposing income and substitution effects, both sXW and sxt are
È hUg ˘
of ambiguous sign. The term Í hUr - hUE h EY - is itself of ambiguous sign, con-
Î 1 - a ˙˚
sisting of the first two positive parts and a negative (and enlarged absolutely, as
1/(1 - a) is larger than one) third part.
If the negative environmental disruption effect is large absolutely and both the
consumption and public goods effects (first and third terms in the RHS of
Equation C15) are relatively small, the first three terms may sum to be negative.
If, in addition, leisure does not respond substantially (as has been the case empiri-
cally; see Pencavel, 1986), the last term fails to make a big difference, leaving the
RHS of (C15) possibly negative. From the contrast between the unambiguously
positive (and likely large for both poor and rich economies alike) RHS of (C6)
and the possibly negative RHS of (C15), we may conclude
Proposition 1: Reasonably assuming the existence of important
environmental disruption effect and relative-income effect, econ-
omic growth may decrease happiness even if the provision of public
goods and disruption abatement are being optimised, and even
though all individuals are rationally engaging in the rat race for
making more money.
Proposition 1 came to us as a surprise, at least with respect to the optimal
choice of the tax rate t. At one stage, we thought that proposition is true only if
t is held constant. If t can be increased at will to shrink the private sector and
expand the provision of disruption abatement and public goods, we thought that
this should ensure the sufficiency of the utility-enhancement effect of pro-
ductivity growth. After ensuring the correctness of our mathematics, we discov-
ered the intuitive reason for the insufficiency. This is related to the fact that we
allow production Y, rather than just private consumption C to enter (negatively)
into the environmental quality function E. This means that the production of
the public sector itself is environmentally disruptive. This is a reasonable assump-
tion. However, this means that, if a higher tax rate does not discourage work sig-
nificantly (sxt not large), the instrument of income tax is powerless in reducing
the higher environmental disruption of higher production (through higher pro-
156 Appendix C
t ˆ
s UW t *, a * = ÏÌ1 + Ê (1 - s tW )¸˝( hUc + hUE h EC )
Ó Ë 1- t ¯ ˛
Ê x ˆ tW
Ë 1 - x ¯(
+ s - s )[h - h - hUE ( h EA + h EC )]
xt Ur Ug
(C15¢)
Now, even if hUc + hUEhEC is negative (i.e. the environmental disruption effect
dominates the consumption effect) and the responses of leisure negligible, (C15¢)
may still be positive by having a large enough stW. If the provision of public
goods is not environmentally disruptive, a sufficient increase in tax rate must
be sufficient to check the higher disruption effect of higher productivity and
to provide more abatement and other public goods to ensure higher utility
with growth. Of course, different public goods may have different degrees of
environmental disruption effects. Then, it means that growth may be utility-
enhancing if it finances extra provision of public goods that provide more
benefits than disruption.
(C13) equal to zero (for optimal t) after substituting in sxt = 0 from Assumption
D. Totally differentiate the resulting equation, yielding:
This appendix argues that, there is a particular set of circumstances where the
Pareto principle in terms of preferences, even in its weak form (dictating a social
preference only when there is a unanimous strong preference by all individuals),
is clearly unacceptable, even in the absence of ignorance and undesirable effects
on the future or the like. The unacceptability of the Pareto principle in the
presence of altruism or the need to exclude ‘external’ preferences in social
choice have been remarked by a number of authors (e.g. Hammond, 1987/1995;
Harsanyi, 1995, p.325), but no distinction has been made between affective
versus non-affective altruism. While non-affective altruism should be excluded
in social choice, affective altruism should not.
158
Appendix D 159
that the set of people concerned is fixed. With these assumptions, it seems that
the Pareto principle is compelling. The discovery of a set of circumstances where
the Pareto principle is clearly unacceptable even under these assumptions is thus
remarkable.
It is possible for an individual to prefer x to y even if she will be happier at x
than at y, even without ignorance and irrationality, since the individual may
have a concern for the welfare of others, as argued in Section 4.1. In other words,
an individual may be altruistic in reason, on top of being altruistic in emotion
or affection. In emotional or affective altruism, one’s welfare (i.e. happiness)
is increased by an increase in the welfare levels of others. In ‘rational’ or non-
affective altruism, one’s utility is increased by an increase in the welfare levels
of others over and above the affective altruistic effect through one’s own welfare
level. In the presence of such non-affective altruism, it is possible that the society
should prefer y to x even if every individual prefers x to y, since social preference
should then take account of individual welfare rather than individual utility
levels to avoid multiple counting, as argued in the next section.
Table D1
x 6 12 18 6 16 22 36 44
y 18 5 12 18 17 24 35 59
160 Appendix D
wish to argue that the weak (and a fortiori the strong) Pareto principle is not
acceptable in such circumstances and that the society should prefer x to y.
We should also abstract away the complications of indirect or long-term effects
by assuming that the individual welfares and utilities figures for x and y in the
above figures capture all relevant outcomes and that there are no other effects.
If we focus attention on individual welfares only, it is clear that x is preferable
to y. Not only is the sum of individual welfares higher in x than in y, all social
welfare functions of individual welfares that is anonymous and increasing
in individual welfares must obviously rank x higher than y. However, should
the social welfare function be a function of individual welfares or of individual
utilities?
If the individual welfare figures in Table D1 already capture all relevant effects
as mentioned above and if the welfare levels of all other sentients are abstracted
away or assumed unchanged, Section 4.1 argues that social choice should be
based on individual welfares than on individual utilities. Here, a more com-
pelling and simple case can be made due to the fact that individual welfares and
utilities differ here because of only a specific reason by construction.
In the example of Table D1, misinformation, ignorance, and all other reasons
that may cause the utility (representing preference) of a person to differ from her
welfare have been abstracted away, except non-affective altruism. Person 1 is
assumed to be not altruistic non-affectively so that his utility does not differ from
his welfare. Persons 2 and 3 are both assumed to be strongly non-affectively altru-
istic towards person 1. (We do not need such a high degree of non-affective altru-
ism to establish the point if we have more individuals.) Each of them has a higher
welfare level at x than at y but prefers y to x because of a non-affective concern
for the welfare of person 1. However, for social choice, since the welfare of person
1 is already fully taken into account as w1 in any reasonable (including the prop-
erty of anonymity) social welfare function, it should not be taken into account
again as components of u2 and u3. Otherwise, multiple counting is involved. To
see this point more clearly, consider a simpler case of just two persons depicted
in Table D2.
For this case, it is obvious that, taking account of the welfare levels of the indi-
viduals, any anonymous social welfare function increasing in individual welfares
ranks x above y. However, if the utility figures are taken as relevant for social
choice instead, any anonymous and non-anti-egalitarian social welfare function
(such as W = Sui) prefers y to x, as y has a more equal utility profile with a bigger
sum than x. Nevertheless, the social preference of y to x is patently unfair to
person 2. The welfare of person 1 is only counted once while that of person 2 is
Table D2
w1 w2 u1 = w1 u2 = w2 + w1 Sw i Sui
x 2 7 2 9 9 11
y 7 1 7 8 8 15
Appendix D 161
counted twice, once as the component w1 in u1, and once as the component w1
in u2, because person 2 has a perfect concern for the welfare of person 1. If she
were to make the choice herself, she would choose in accordance to w2 + w1. If
person 1 had a similar perfect concern for the welfare of person 2, the use of Sui
would rank x above y. Due to the asymmetrical degrees of non-affective altru-
ism, the use of utility figures instead of welfare figures biases social choice in
favour of persons of lower degrees of non-affective altruism, effectively penalis-
ing persons with higher degrees of non-affective altruism. The example of Table
D2 shows clearly that, where the difference between utility and welfare levels is
due only to non-affective altruism, social choice should be based on individual
welfare rather than utility figures.
Coming back to Table D1, the agreement to the use of individual welfare figures
for social choice means that any anonymous and increasing SWF will rank x
above y, despite the fact that every individual prefers y to x. As the society should
prefer x to y even when every individual prefers y to x, the Pareto principle, even
in its weak and hence more compelling version, is not acceptable in this set of
circumstances.
Table D3
m1 m2 w1 w2 u1 u2
x 6 6 6 6 6 6
y 8 4 7 7 7 7
162 Appendix D
y) decreases the welfare of all individuals. It may be argued that unequal distri-
bution may have undesirable long-term consequences. If so, that should be
included into the welfare figures in Table D3. Then, we can judge according to
the figures inclusive of all effects.
163
Appendix F
Inefficiency in Provision May
Increase Optimal Public Spending
Ignoring the possible interaction between benefit and cost, we may choose g to
maximise net benefit N:
N = B[a( g )] - C( g ) (8.1)
where B = (total) benefit, a = actual or physical amount of public good provided,
g = monetary amount of public spending, C = (total) cost. The use of this general
cost function allows for possible excess burden in financing for g:
a( g ) = Ag (8.2)
where A is an index on the efficiency in the public provision of public goods.
Assuming the satisfaction of the usual conditions (differentiability of the func-
tions, B¢ and C¢ > 0, B≤ < 0 and C≤ > 0), the maximisation of (8.1) with respect
to g, using (8.2) gives:
B¢A = C¢ (8.3)
Totally differentiating (8.3) with respect to A, we have, after using the total
differentiation of (8.2):
dg * dA = ( B¢ + aB¢¢ ) (C ¢¢ - A 2 B¢¢ ) (8.4)
Since the denominator of the RHS is positive, the sign of dg*/dA is the same as
that of the numerator. As (B¢ + aB≤) is positive/negative if and only if B¢ >/< -aB≤
or 1>/< - (dB¢/da)a/B¢, we have Proposition 8.1 in the text. To show that the (pro-
portionate) responsiveness of marginal benefit is the same whether we use the
monetary level of public spending g or the physical level of public good a (given
that the provision efficiency A is independent of g), note that, from the B func-
tion in (8.1) and from (8.2) we have Bg ∫ dB/dg = B¢A from which we have, dBg/dg
= B≤A2, and hence (dBg/dg)g/Bg = (dB¢/da)a/B¢. Thus, the marginal benefit is equally
responsive proportionately either with respect to the monetary amount of public
spending g or to the physical amount of public good a.
164
Notes
Chapter 3
1. A different welfarist reason for including such apparently ‘non-welfarist’ indi-
cators into the short-run SWF is their effects on welfare in the long run. For
example, a less unequal distribution of income may promote social harmony.
2. See also Sen, 1967. I define basicness somewhat differently: ‘a value judge-
ment [is] basic to a person if it is not derived from some other value judge-
ment and he believes in it for its own ethical appeal’ (Ng, 1979/1983, p.19).
Whether this definition differs from Sen’s depends on the interpretation of
‘all conceivable circumstances’ in Sen’s definition.
3. As an example of the importance of this practical consideration, see Creedy
(1996) who argues that the maximisation of the utilitarian objective of the
unweighted sum of individual welfares in the long run may be close to, in
the short run, the pursuit of Rawlsian maximin or the use of target efficiency
in poverty reduction.
4. However, perception and affective feelings probably evolved simultaneously.
As I hope to argue elsewhere, perception without affective feelings also serves
no evolutionary purposes. Here, perception is defined as involving subjective
consciousness, not just in the wider sense ‘reception and interpretation of
signals from the environment’, regarded as evidenced in the bacterium E. coli,
see M. Delbrück, 1986.
5. This leaves a little vague as to whether non-affective malice is rational or ir-
rational. I prefer to regard non-affective malice as irrational. Since both ir-
rationality and non-affective altruism/malice are excluded by Axiom 1, this
vagueness does not affect the argument below.
Chapter 4
1. This chapter is largely based on Ng (1999).
2. In this simple formulation of the utility function, it may appear that some
subtle differences such as whether the higher welfare levels of others are
caused by one’s own actions or not (Sen’s ‘agency’ problem) are not distin-
guished’; however, certain relevant activities such as one’s own contribution
to charity may be allowed to enter one’s welfare function in the text below.
Chapter 5
1. Fleming only lists postulates ensuring the existence of a social ordering. With
continuity, this ensures the existence of a SWF as well. Continuity and the
existence of a SWF is implicitly assumed in Fleming’s derivation. The exis-
tence of a social ordering alone is not sufficient for Fleming’s purpose as a
lexicographic social ordering cannot be represented by a SWF at all.
165
166 Notes
2. Or, rather, if they had an equal chance of being ‘put in the place of’ any indi-
vidual member of the society, with regard not only to his objective social (and
economic) conditions, but also to their subjective attitudes and tastes. In
other words, they ought to judge the utility of another individual’s position
not in terms of his own attitudes and tastes but rather in terms of the atti-
tudes and tastes of the individual actually holding this position (Harsanyi’s
note).
3. This proviso is redundant if we accept Rational Individualism (Axiom 1)
which implies welfarism.
4. This has to be so as non-welfare variables are being held constant; also, non-
affective altruism/malice is to be excluded in social choice from Axiom 1d2.
5. From the continuity of preference, one should really use one to measure the
welfare difference of a just imperceptible indifference, and anything larger
than one will be perceptible preference (Ng, 1975a). However, since a just
imperceptible indifference is continuous with a just perceptible preference,
we will ignore this pedantic point.
6. The difference between individual preferences (used by Fleming) and indi-
vidual welfares is ignored. This does not affect our argument here since
Rational Individualism insists on the use of individual welfares where the two
diverge.
7. If WE and EW always yield the same result, we have WE = W(SjqjUj1, . . . ,
SjqjUjI ) = EW= SjqjW(Uj1, . . . , UjI ). Differentiation with respect to Uji gives
∂W/∂EUi = ∂W/∂Uji at any given situation. Such an equality cannot hold
through for every set of q’s unless W is a sum (unweighted or weighted with
uniform individual weights) of its arguments.
Chapter 6
1. In my 1979/83 treatment, I did not discuss the big differences between will-
ingness to pay and willingness to accept due to the unwillingness of many
people to actually pay for something they believe they are ‘entitled’ to or
other similar problems. (See, for example, Mitchell and Carson, 1989;
Milgrom, 1993.) For such cases, there are added practical difficulties to dis-
cover people’s real willingness to pay as a reflection of their preferences for
the items as such untainted by the objections or ill-feelings associated with
payment. This difficulty of the intertwining of two different types of prefer-
ences/dispreferences is similar to the intrusion of factors such as regret,
anxiety, excitement, etc. into the process or outcomes of choices involving
risk, making the application of the expected utility theory difficult in those
cases. However, in both cases, the principles involved are not invalidated.
2. As real tax liabilities depend on non-income characteristics such as age,
marital status, home-ownership, etc. the evaluation of effective income tax
progressivity may not be simple. However, see Hayes et al. (1995) for an algo-
rithm to evaluate effective income tax progression.
3. Second-best taxation-pricing rules are typically very complicated, even if only
the efficiency consideration is taken into account. For the literature on
optimal taxation, see Mirrlees (1976, 1981) and Sandmo (1976). Conditions
making second-best considerations ineffective are rather stringent, for
example, separability in the utility function (see Atkinson and Stiglitz, 1976;
compare Bergstrom and Cornes, 1983).
Notes 167
4. For example, consider the argument of William Baumol and Dietrich Fischer
(1979) that the use of discrimination in wage rate is much more efficient (less
output foregone) than non-discriminatory taxation in achieving equality.
This is based on the detailed knowledge of individual input supply functions
that they recognise to be unavailable. But they suggest that some rough dis-
crimination between broad groups of income earners such as doctors versus
ditch diggers may yet be feasible. But if a discrimination, such as supple-
menting ‘wage rates for the one and limit[ing] wages for the other’ (p.522),
is feasible, there is little reason to expect that it is not feasible to have higher
income tax rates for doctors and lower for ditch diggers.
5. Borghans and Groot (1998) attribute the discrepancy/inefficiency to some
form of monopolistic power. However, I regard the insignificant losses of the
replacement of the superstars by their runners up as more important, making
the discrepancy/inefficiency non-existent or insignificant for superstars in say
science and technology or the generation of real knowledge in general. Here,
in fact, the superstars earn far less than their marginal contributions due to
the global public-good and long-term nature of knowledge.
Chapter 9
1. Political-economy issues like rent-seeking and tax policy in accordance to
political instead of distortionary costs (on which see, e.g. Brennan, 1984;
Buchanan, 1993; Hettich and Winer, 1997; Holcombe, 1998 and Winer and
Hettich, 1998), while relevant, are not considered here.
2. Batina (1990) in fact allows for heterogeneous individuals and hence ident-
ifies a distributional term but does not relate it to the offsetting of the disin-
centive effects.
3. Combined with this consideration is the point that, while the existence and
size of excess burdens or distortions depend on the net substitution effects,
the marginal cost of fund depends on the gross substitution effect (disincen-
tive effect when related to the income/leisure choice). See Ng, forthcoming
b, (second half of its Appendix A in particular); cf. Browning and Liu (1998).
4. Gross of the income effect, a higher tax may not cause disincentive effects.
Appendix B
1. It is true that Rawls would argue that freedom to rape is not a basic liberty
while the right to non-violation of body is. However, how do we determine
what are basic liberties? Either it is based on the utilitarian (or at least wel-
farist) principle or it is open to the objection of possibly sanctioning a disas-
trous outcome. For the unacceptability of rights-based ethics, see Ng (1990a,
Sec. IIIB).
2. Including holding the degree of altruism/malice the same across individuals;
for differences in this, see the text below.
Appendix C
1. If hEA is large, then the optimality condition for the division between abate-
ment and other public goods (from the equating of the RHS of Equation C14
168 Notes
to zero) dictates a large hUg, making the third term of the RHS of (C15)
dominating.
2. It may also be noted that the term associated with sxt in (C13) contains an
expression (reflecting the indirect effects) of ambiguous sign whose parts are
likely to change in offsetting directions with W. Hence, even if sxt is not
assumed negligible, the qualification to our conclusion below is likely to be
small.
References
Ackerman, F., Kiron, D., Goodwin, N. R., Harris, J. M. and Gallagher, K. (1997),
Human Well-being and Economic Goals (Washington, DC: Island Press).
Adler, Matthew D. and Posner, Eric A. (1999), ‘Rethinking Cost–Benefit Analy-
sis’, Chicago Law & Economics Working Paper No. 72 (2D series).
Aghion, Philippe and Williamson, Jeffrey (1999), Growth, Inequality and Global-
ization: Theory, History and Policy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).
Aiken, William and La Follette, Hugh (eds) (1977), World Hunger and Moral
Obligation (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall).
Ake, Christopher (1975), ‘Justice as equality’, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 1,
69–89.
Altonji, J. G., Hayashi, F. and Kotlikoff, L. J. (1997), ‘Parental altruism and inter
vivos transfers: theory and evidence’, Journal of Political Economy, 105, 1121–66.
Arneson, Richard J. (1989/1995), ‘Equality and equal opportunity for welfare’,
Philosophical Studies, 56, 77–93; reprinted with a postscript (1995) in Pojman
and Westmoreland (eds), (1999). pp.229–42.
Arrow, Kenneth J. (1951/1963), Social Choice and Individual Values (New York:
John Wiley).
Arrow, Kenneth J. and Intriligator, Michael D. (1986), Handbook of Mathematical
Economics, Vol. III (Amsterdam: North-Holland).
Arrow, Kenneth J. and Scitovsky, Tibor (eds) (1969), Readings in Welfare Econ-
omics (London: Allen & Unwin).
Ashenfelter, Orley C. and Layard, Richard (eds) (1986), Handbook of Labor Econ-
omics, Vol. 1 (Amsterdam: North-Holland).
Atkinson, Anthony B. and Stiglitz, Joseph E. (1976), ‘The design of tax structure:
direct versus indirect taxation’, Journal of Public Economics, 6, 55–75.
Atkinson, Anthony B. and Stiglitz, Joseph E. (1980), Lectures on Public Economics,
(New York: McGraw-Hill).
Auten, Gerald and Carroll, Robert (1994), ‘Taxpayer behavior and the 1986 Tax
Reform Act’, Office of Tax Analysis Working Paper (Washington, DC, US
Department of the Treasury).
Backhouse, Roger E. (1998), ‘If mathematics is informal, then perhaps we should
accept that economics must be informal too’, Economic Journal, 108, 1848–
58.
Bagwell, L. S. and Bernheim, B. D. (1996), ‘Veblen effects in a theory of con-
spicuous consumption’, American Economic Review, 86, 349–73.
Baland, Jean-Marie and Platteau, Jean-Philippe (1997), ‘Wealth inequality and
efficiency in the commons’, Part I, Oxford Economic Papers, 49, 451–82.
Ballard, Charles L. and Medema, Steven G. (1993), ‘The marginal efficiency effect
of taxes and subsidies in the presence of externalities: a computational general
equilibrium approach’, Journal of Public Economics, 52, 199–216.
Ballard, Charles, Shoven, John and Whalley, John (1985), ‘General equilibrium
computations of the marginal welfare cost of taxes in the United States’,
American Economic Review, 75 (1), 128–38.
169
170 References
Brennan, Geoffrey (1984), ‘Elements of a fiscal politics: public choice and public
finance’, Australian Economic Review, 3rd quarter, 67, 62–72.
Brickman, Phillip, Coates, Dan and Janoff-Bulman, Ronnie (1978), ‘Lottery
winners and accident victims: is happiness relative?’, Journal of Personality and
Social Psychology, 36, 917–27.
Broome, John (1991), Weighing Goods: Equality, Uncertainty and Time (Oxford:
Blackwell).
Brown, Donald and Heal, Geoffrey (1979), ‘Equity, efficiency and increasing
returns’, Review of Economic Studies, 571–86.
Browning, Edgar K. (1987), ‘On the marginal welfare cost of taxation’, American
Economic Review, 77 (1), 11–23.
Browning, Edgar K. and Liu, Ligun (1998), ‘The optimal supply of public goods
and the distortionary cost of taxation: Comment’, National Tax Journal, 51 (1),
103–16.
Buchanan, James A. (1993), ‘The political efficiency of general taxation’, National
Tax Journal, 46 (4), 401–10.
Chang, Ming Chung (1997), ‘Optimal public good provision – cases with
complementarities between the public good and the taxed commodities’,
Typescript.
Chick, Victoria (1998), ‘On knowing one’s place: the role of formalism in econ-
omics’, Economic Journal, 108, 1859–69.
Christiansen, Vidar (1981), ‘Evaluation of public projects under optimal
taxation’, Review of Economic Studies, XLVIII, 447–57.
Clark, J. (1998), ‘Fairness preferences and optimization skills: are they substitutes?
An experimental investigation’, Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization,
34 (4), 541–57.
Cohen, G. A. (1989), ‘On the currency of egalitarian justice’, Ethics, 99, 906–44.
Cole, Harold L., Mailath, George J. and Postlewaite, Andrew (1992), ‘Social
norms, savings behavior, and growth’, Journal of Political Economy, 100 (6),
1092–125.
Congleton, R. D. (1997), ‘Political efficiency and equal protection of the law’,
Kyklos, 50, 485–505.
Corden, W. M. (1974), Trade Policy and Economic Welfare (London: Oxford
University Press).
Creedy, John (1996), ‘Comparing tax and transfer systems: poverty, inequality
and target efficiency’, Economica, 63, S163–S174.
Creedy, John and McDonald, Ian M. (1990), ‘A tax package to reduce the mar-
ginal rate of income tax and wage demands of trade unions’, Economic Review,
66, 195–202.
Cremer, Helmuth and Gahvari, Firouz (1995), ‘Uncertainty, optimal taxation
and the direct versus indirect tax controversy’, Economic Journal, 105, 1165–
79.
Cummins, Robert A. (1998), ‘The second approximation to an international
standard for life satisfaction’, Social Indicators Research, 43, 307–44.
D’Aspremont, Claude and Gevers, Louis (1977), ‘Equity and the informational
basis of collective choice’, Review of Economic Studies, 44, 199–209.
David, P. A. and Reder, M. W. (eds) (1974), Nations and Households in Economic
Growth: Essays in Honour of Moses Abramowitz (New York: Academic Press).
de Bartolome, Charles A. M. (1995), ‘Which tax rate do people use: average or
marginal?’, Journal of Public Economics, 56, 79–96.
172 References
panel study of the 1986 Tax Reform Act’, Journal of Political Economy, 103 (3),
551–72.
Feldstein, Martin (1995b), ‘Tax avoidance and the deadweight loss of the income
tax’, NBER Working Paper No.5055 (Cambridge, MA: National Bureau of Econ-
omic Research).
Feldstein, Martin (1997), ‘How big should government be?’, National Tax Journal,
50 (2), 197–213.
Feldstein, Martin and Feenberg, Daniel (1996), ‘The effect of increased tax rates
on taxable income and economic efficiency: a preliminary analysis of the 1993
tax rate increases’, in Tax Policy and the Economy, Vol. 10, pp.89–117.
Ferris, Stephen J. and West, Edwin G. (1996), ‘Testing theories of real govern-
ment size: U.S. experience, 1959–89’, Southern Economic Journal, 62 (3), 537–53.
Fleming, Marcus (1952), ‘A cardinal concept of welfare’, Quarterly Journal of
Economics, 66, 366–84.
Fortin, Bernard and Lacroix, Guy (1994), ‘Labour supply, tax evasion and the
marginal cost of public funds: an empirical investigation’, Journal of Public
Economics, 55, 407–31.
Frank, Robert H. (1985), Choosing the Right Pond: Human Behaviour and the Quest
for Status (New York: Oxford University Press).
Frank, Robert H. (1987), ‘If homo economicus could choose his own utility func-
tion, would he want one with a conscience?’, American Economic Review, 77,
593–604.
Frank, Robert H. (1999), Luxury Fever: Why Money Fails to Satisfy in an Era of
Excess (New York, NY: Free Press).
Gemmell, Norman (1993), The Growth of the Public Sector: Theories and Inter-
national Evidence (Aldershot, England: Edward Elgar).
Goodin, Robert E. (1995), Utilitarianism as a Public Philosophy (Cambridge, New
York: Cambridge University Press).
Grossman, Herschel (1994), ‘Production, appropriation and land reform’, Amer-
ican Economic Review, 84 (3), 705–12.
Hamilton, W. D. (1964), ‘The genetical evolution of social behaviour. I and II’,
Journal of Theoretical Biology, 7, 1–52.
Hammond, Peter J. (1976), ‘Why ethical measures of inequality need interper-
sonal comparisons’, Theory and Decision, 7, 262–274.
Hammond, Peter J. (1987/1995), ‘Altruism’, in Eatwell et al., Vol. 1, pp.85–7,
reprinted in Stefano Zamagni (1995), pp.165–7.
Hammond, Peter J. (1991), ‘Interpersonal comparisons of utility: why and how
they are and should be made’, in Elster and Roemer, (eds), pp.200–54.
Hammond, Peter J. (1996), ‘Consequentialist decision theory and utilitarian
ethics’, in Farina, Hahn and Vannucci (eds).
Harbaugh, W. T. (1998), ‘What do donations buy? a model of philanthropy based
on prestige and warm glow’, Journal of Public Economics, 67 (2), 269–84.
Hardy, J. D., Wolff, Harold G. and Goodell, Helen (1952), Pain Sensations and
Reactions (Baltimore: The Williams and Wilkins Co.).
Hare, R. M. (1976), ‘Ethical theory and utilitarianism’, in Lewis (ed.), pp.113–31.
Hare, R. M. (1997), ‘Justice and equality’, in Pojman and Westmoreland’s
pp.218–28.
Harris, Richard and Olewiler, Nancy (1979), ‘The welfare economics of ex post
optimality’, Economica, 46, 137–47.
174 References
Le Grand, Julian (1997), ‘Knights, knaves or pawns?: human behaviour and social
policy’, Journal of Social Policy, 26, 149–69.
Lee, Woojin and Roemer, John E. (1999), ‘Income distribution, redistributive pol-
itics, and economic growth’, Journal of Economic Growth, 3, 217–40.
Leontief, W. (1966), Essays in Economics: Theories and Theorizing (New York:
Oxford University Press).
Lerner, Abba P. (1944), The Economics of Control (New York: Macmillan).
Levitt, M. S. and Joyce, M. A. S. (1987), The Growth and Efficiency of Public Spend-
ing (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).
Lewis, H. D. (ed.) (1976), Contemporary British Philosophy (London: Allen and
Unwin).
Linbeck, Assar, Nyberg, Stern and Weibull, Jörgen W. (1999), ‘Social norma and
economic incentives in the welfare state’, Quarterly Journal of Economics, 116,
1–36.
Little, Ian M. D. (1949), ‘The foundations of welfare economics’, Oxford Economic
Papers, 1, 227–46.
Little, Ian M. D. (1951), ‘Direct versus indirect taxes’, Economic Journal, 61,
577–84.
Little, Ian M. D. (1952), ‘Social Choice and Individual Values’, Journal of Political
Economy, 60, 422–32.
Little, Ian M. D. (1957), A Critique of Welfare Economics, 2nd edn (London: Oxford
University Press).
Little, Ian M. D. and Mirrlees, James A. (1974), Profit Appraisal and Planning for
Developing Countries (London: Heinemann).
Livingston, Arthur (ed.) (1935), Mind and Society, Vol. 4 (London: Jonathan
Cape).
Lockwood, Ben and Manning, Alan (1993), ‘Wage setting and the tax system:
theory and evidence for the united kingdom values’, Journal of Public Econ-
omics, 52, 1–29.
Loewenstein, George and Elster, Jon (eds) (1992), Choice Over Time (New York:
Sage).
Lunati, M. Teresa (1997), Ethical Issues in Economics: From Altruism to Cooperation
to Equity (New York: St. Martin’s Press; London: Macmillan Press).
Lybeck, J. A. and Henrekson, M. (1988), Explaining the Growth of Government
(Amsterdam: North-Holland).
Marmola, Elisabetta (1999), ‘A constitutional theory of public goods’, Journal of
Economic Behaviour and Organization, 38, 27–42.
Marr, W. and Raj, B. (eds) (1983), How Economists Explain – A Reader in Method-
ology (Washington: University Press of America).
Marschak, J. (1950), ‘Rational behaviour, uncertain prospects and measurable
utility’, Econometrica, 18, 111–141; also ‘Errata’, 312.
Maskin, Eric (1978), ‘A theorem on utilitarianism’, Review of Economic Studies, 45,
93–6.
Meltzer, A. H. and Richard, Scott F. (1981), ‘A rational theory of the size of gov-
ernment’, Journal of Political Economy, 89, 914–27.
Michael, Mark A. (1997), ‘Redistributive taxation, self-ownership and the fruit of
labour’, Journal of Applied Philosophy, 14, 137–46.
Milgrom, Paul (1993), ‘Is sympathy an economic value?: philosophy, econom-
ics, and the contingent valuation method’, in Hausman, pp.417–35.
References 177
Mirrlees, James A. (1971), ‘An exploration in the theory of optimal income tax-
ation’, Review of Economic Studies, 38, 174–208.
Mirrlees, James A. (1976), ‘Optimal tax theory: a synthesis’, Journal of Public Econ-
omics, 6, 327–58.
Mirrlees, James A. (1981), ‘The theory of optimal taxation’, in Arrow and Intrili-
gator (1986), pp.1197–1249.
Mirrlees, James A. (1982), ‘The economic uses of utilitarianism’, in Sen and
Williams, pp.63–84.
Mitchell, Robert C, and Carson, Richard T. (1989), ‘Using surveys to value public
goods: the contingent valuation method’, Washington, DC: Resources for the
Future (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press).
Mongin, Philippe (1988), ‘A comment on J. Harsanyi’s “Assessing other people’s
utilities” ’, in Munier, (ed.), 139–44.
Mongin, Philippe (1994), ‘Harsanyi’s aggregation theorem: multi-profile version
and unsettled questions’, Social Choice and Welfare, 11, 331–54.
Monroe, Kristen R. (1996), The Heart of Altruism (Princeton University Press).
Mueller, Dennis (1989), Public Choice II (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).
Mueller, Dennis (ed.) (1997), Perspectives on Public Choice: a Handbook (Cam-
bridge: Cambridge University Press).
Munier, Bertrand R. (ed.) (1988), Risk, Decision and Rationality (Dordrecht: Reidel).
Mulligan, Casey B. (1997), Parental Priorities and Economic Inequality (Chicago and
London: University of Chicago Press).
Murphy, K., Shleifer, A. and Vishny, R. (1989), ‘Income distribution, market size,
and industrialization’, Quarterly Journal of Economics, 537–64.
Myers, David (1996), Social Psychology (New York: Macmillan).
Nagel, Stuart S. (ed.) (1998), Applications of Super-Optimizing Policy Analysis,
Research in Public Policy Analysis and Management, Vol. 8 (Greenwich, Conn.
and London: JAI Press).
Nath, S. K. (1969), A Reappraisal of Welfare Economics (London: Routledge & Kegan
Paul).
Ng, Yew-Kwang (1971), ‘The possibility of a Paretian liberal: impossibility the-
orems and cardinal utility’, Journal of Political Economy, 79 (6), 1397–402.
Ng, Yew-Kwang (1972), ‘Value judgements and economists’ role in policy rec-
ommendation’, Economic Journal, Sept., 1014–18; reprinted in Marr and Raj,
(1983).
Ng, Yew-Kwang (1975a), ‘Bentham or Bergson?: finite sensibility, utility functions
and social welfare functions’, Review of Economic Studies, 42, 545–70.
Ng, Yew-Kwang (1975b), ‘Non-economic activities, indirect externalities and
third-best policies’, Kyklos, 28, 507–25; reprinted in Ng (1990b).
Ng, Yew-Kwang (1977), ‘Towards a theory of third-best’, Public Finance, 1–15.
Ng, Yew-Kwang (1979/1983), Welfare Economics: Introduction and Development of
Basic Concepts (London: Macmillan).
Ng, Yew-Kwang (1980), ‘Toward eudaimonology: notes on a quantitative frame-
work for the study of happiness’, Mathematical Social Sciences, 1, 51–68.
Ng, Yew-Kwang (1981a), ‘Welfarism: a defence against Sen’s attack’, Economic
Journal, 91, June, 527–30.
Ng, Yew-Kwang (1981b), ‘Bentham or Nash?: on the acceptable form of
social welfare functions’, Economic Record, 57 Sept., 238–50; reprinted in Ng
(1990b).
178 References
Ng, Yew-Kwang (forthcoming b), ‘The optimal size of public spending and the
distortionary cost of taxation’, revision under consideration by National Tax
Journal.
Ng, Yew-Kwang and Wang, Jianguo (1993), ‘Relative income, aspiration, en-
vironmental quality, individual and political myopia: why may the rat-race for
material growth be welfare-reducing?’, Mathematical Social Sciences, 26, 3–23.
Nielsen, Kai (1985), Equality and Liberty: a Defence of Radical Egalitarianism
(Totowa, NJ: Rowman & Allanheld).
Nozick, Robert (1974), Anarchy, State, and Utopia (New York: Basic Books).
Okun, Arthur M. (1975), Equality and Efficiency: The Big Tradeoff (Washington:
Brookings Institution).
Olds, J. and Milner, P. (1954), ‘Positive reinforcement produced by electrical stim-
ulation of septal area and other regions of the rat brain’, Journal of Compara-
tive Physiological Psychology, 47, 419–27.
Osborne, D. K. (1976), ‘Irrelevant alternatives and social welfare’, Econometrica,
44, 1001–15.
Oswald, Andrew J. (1997), ‘Happiness and economic performance’, Economic
Journal, 107, 1815–31.
Pareto, V. (1935), The Mind and Society, trans. Livingston (London: Cape).
Parks, Robert P. (1976), ‘An Impossibility theorem for fixed preferences: a dicta-
torial Bergson–Samuelson welfare function’, Review of Economic Studies, 43,
447–50.
Pattanaik, Prasanta K. (1971), Voting and Collective Choice (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press).
Pattanaik, Prasanta K. and Salles, Maurice (eds) (1983), Social Choice and Welfare
(Amsterdam: North-Holland).
Patterson, M. M. and Kesner, R. P. (1981), Electrical Stimulation Research Techniques
(New York: Academic Press).
Patterson, M., Krupitsky, E., Flood, N. and Baker, D. (1994), ‘Amelioration of
stress in chemical dependency detoxification by transcranial electrostimu-
lation’, Stress Medicine, Apr., 10 (2), 115–26.
Payne, J. E. and Ewing, B. T. (1996), ‘International evidence on Wagner’s hypoth-
esis: a cointegration analysis’, Public Finance, 51 (2), 258–74.
Peltzman, S. (1980), ‘The growth of government’, Journal of Law and Economics,
23, 209–87.
Pencavel, John (1986), ‘Labor supply of man: a survey’, in Ashenfelter and Layard
pp.3–102.
Perotti, Roberto (1996), ‘Growth, income distribution, and democracy: what the
data say’, Journal of Economics Growth, 1, 149–87.
Persson, Torsten and Tabellini, Guido (1994), ‘Is inequality harmful for growth?’,
American Economic Review, 84, 600–21.
Phelps, Edmund S. and Zoega, Gylfi (1998), ‘Natural-rate theory and OECD
unemployment’, Economic Journal, 108, May, 782–801.
Pigou, Arthur C. (1912/1929/1932), Wealth and Welfare. Later editions (1920, 1924,
1929, 1932) assume the title The Economics of Welfare (London: Macmillan).
Pigou, Arthur C. (1928), Public Finance (London: Macmillan).
Pojman, Louis P. and Westmoreland, Robert, (eds) (1997), Equality: Selected Read-
ings (Oxford: Oxford University Press).
180 References
Winkelmann, Liliana and Winkelmann, Rainer (1998), ‘Why are the unemployed
so unhappy?’, Economica, 65, 1–15.
Yadin, E. and Thomas, E. (1996), ‘Stimulation of the lateral septum attenuates
immobilisation-induced stress ulcers’, Physiology and Behavior, 59, 883–6.
Zamagni, Stefano (ed.) (1995), The Economics of Altruism (Aldershot, Brookfield,
Vt, USA: Edward Elgar).
Name Index
184
Name Index 185
188
Subject Index 189