The History of Law in Europe
The History of Law in Europe
The History of Law in Europe
Bart Wauters
Professor of Law, IE University, Spain
Marco de Benito
Professor of Law, IE University, Spain
� Edward Elgar
P-UBLISHING
Published by
Edward Elgar Publishing LimitedThe
Lypiatts
15 Lansdown Road
Cheltenham
Glos GL50 2JA
UK
Edward Elgar Publishing, Inc.
William Pratt House
9 Dewey Court
Northampton
Massachusetts 01060
USA
DOI 10.4337/9781786430762
Introduction
1. ROMAN
LAWI
Justinian
A. The codification project
B. The historical background of the Digest
C. The importance of the Corpus iuris
II The history of Rome
A. The Archaic Period
B. The Republic
C. The Principate
D. The Dominate
Ill The evolution of Roman law
A. Archaic law
B. The ius civile
C. Classical Roman jurisprudence
D. Post-classical law
5. THE BOURGEOIS
AGEI Historical
evolution
A. Economy
B. Politics
C. Church and religion
II. Law and jurisprudence during the Enlightenment
A. The Enlightenment
B. Law and society according to the Enlightenment
philosophers
C. Codification projects in Central Europe
Ill Napoleonic codification
A. The dream of legal unification in France
B. Revolutionary projects
C. The Code civil
D. The other Napoleonic codes
E. The expansion of the French codes
F. An assessment of the Code civil
IV. Jurisprudence
A. The Exegetic School
B. The Historical School
C. Pandectism
V. Pandectist codification
A. The Bilrgerliches Gesetzbuch (8GB)
B. Characteristics and intellectual context
C. The second pandectist code: Switzerland
D. The expansion of the pandectist codes
6. COMMON LAW
I The origins of English common law
A. The Anglo-Saxon period
B. The Norman conquest
C. The introduction of royal justice
II The central courts of common law
A. The development of the central courts
B. Uniformity and the abolition of common law courts
Ill Writs
A. Remedies precede rights
B. Writs until 1258
C.Writs after 1258IV
The rise of equity
A. The rigidity of common law
B. Chancery
V Other courts
VI. Peculiar features of common law
A. Lawmaking
B. Jurisprudence
VII. The expansion of the English common law
A. Europe
B. The United States of America and the British Empire
C. Scots law
VIII. Common law and ius commune
Epilogue
Further reading
Index
Introduction
I. JUSTINIAN
The Digest stands out from among the books of the Corpus iuris
as an illustration of Rome's legal genius and its unparalleled
originality. Formally Roman law did not recognize jurisprudence
(iuris prudentia or iuris scientia, knowledge of the law) as a
legitimate source of law. The advice and opinions (responsa) of
jurisconsults (iuris prudentes, "those who know the law," here
referred to interchangeably as "jurists") lacked normative force,
although in practice they enjoyed great influence. Recognizing this
social reality, the first emperors granted the most eminent jurists
the privilege to reply on their behalf to legal questions posed to
them, the so-called ius respondendi. While the opinion of such
eminent jurists officially lacked normative force, the reality is that
judges to whom these opinions were presented rarely deviated
from them. This is just one more example of the characteristic
distinction and balance maintained in Rome in all areas between
potestas (formally valid and binding power) and auctoritas
(socially recognized prestige or authority). For centuries it was the
jurists who, with their peculiar auctoritas, contributed to the
thorough refinement and development of Roman law.
This unofficial status, however, was also a source of problems.
Firstly, not all jurists' writings were easily accessible in an empire
as vast as that of Rome. In addition, after centuries of
accumulation and refinement of legal knowledge, the sheer
number of writings and opinions proved excessive, significantly
undermining their effective application. Finally, not all the writings
and jurists agreed, clashing on many issues. In an effort to solve
these problems, Emperor Theodosius II considered the possibility
of carrying out a selection of those texts and writings retaining
contemporary value, but the plan could not be carried out.
Theodosius then enacted the Lex citandi (426), the Law of
Citations, which stated that only the writings of five classic jurists
-Papinian, Paulus, Gaius, Ulpian and Modestinus - could be
invoked before the courts, and established the procedure to be
adopted should the opinions of these five jurists conflict: the
majority opinion was to be respected; in the event of a tie that of
Papinian was to prevail; and where Papinian had issued no
decision on the issue, it was up to the judge to choose between
the other opinions.
In the end the Law of Citations proved to be no solution. Some
writings were difficult to find, or their authenticity was questioned.
Moreover, the system of numerical majority was not devoid of
arbitrariness. As such, it starkly conflicted with the very essence of
Romans' conception of the law: legal problems were expected to
have rational, not arbitrary solutions, as was such dependence on
chance majorities. However, the Law of Citations would end up
having a lasting influence when Justinian set about resuming
Theodosius's project of selecting those legal texts with
contemporary value. It is no coincidence that the vast majority of
the fragments in the Digest came from the writings of the five
jurists recognized by the Law of Citations; the other 34 jurists cited
in the Digest account for only a small portion of the total.
In another example of sharp conflict with the spirit of classical
jurisprudence, Justinian prohibited the drafting of further
comments or additional interpretations of the Digest. If an excerpt
was found to be vague, the question was to be referred to the
emperor. The objective was thereby to prevent the excessive
proliferation of opinions and interpretations, so characteristic of
classical times, and which had inspired the Justinian compilation
in the first place. This prohibition exemplifies how the emperor
presented and established himself as the sole source of law,
expressing the monarch's ideological and political agenda. It also
illustrates how the Digest marked the end of an entire era, the
involuntary certification of the demise of Rome's great tradition of
jurisprudence.
B. The Republic
D. The Dominate
After the crisis of the third century, two forceful figures - Diocletian
(284-305) and Constantine (306-37) - managed to gain power
and hold it firmly for a long period, though the latter would be
forced to fight two civil wars to do so. Diocletian realized that he
needed to limit the power of the army in order to stabilize the
government. For this purpose he removed generals from key
executive positions and fomented the development of a body of
civil servants in each government branch. Such initiatives were
complemented by the glorification and even worship of his own
person; the emperor was no longer merely the princeps or "first
citizen," but "lord over all," or Dominus. Diocletian employed a
series of ceremonies to exalt his position, including substituting
the old salutation by the prostration before the imperial purple
robe, thereby illustrating the infinite distance between the emperor
and his subjects. His few public appearances were orchestrated
as epiphanies of an almost sacred nature. Thus ensued a period
of absolute monarchy, depending upon an anonymous but
effective bureaucracy, which came to be termed the Dominate.
During the Dominate the division between the Eastern Empire
and Western Empire became more pronounced, and there was
rarely optimal collaboration between the two. The center of power
shifted towards Constantinople. In the West, Rome even lost its
status as a political center when the seat of government was
moved first to Milan, and then to Ravenna. With the Empire
Christianized, only the Bishop of Rome remained an important
political figure in the Eternal City.
Diocletian and Constantine did manage to keep the territorial
integrity of the Empire essentially intact. The West, however, was
devastated when in the fifth century Germanic and Asian
barbarian tribes invaded in search of new territories. In 476 the
last Western emperor was toppled. The eastern part of the
Empire, however, managed to survive, and during the fifth century
enjoyed a period of peace and relative prosperity. In the sixth
century, under Justinian, it even undertook an attempt at
expansion, albeit a short-lived one.
Theodosius I (379-95) was one of the last great emperors. In
an attempt to shore up the crumbling unity of a politically, socially
and ethnically diverse Empire he declared Christianity - already
officially tolerated as of 313 and widely favored by Constantine -
to be the Empire's sole and official religion. The Christianization of
the Empire had consequences for private law, particularly with
regard to that governing people and families, which was softened
in comparison to the harsh family regime largely inherited from the
Archaic Period. The legal status of slaves and women, for
example, substantially improved. In other areas of law Christianity
intensified a moralistic tendency and a certain disregard for form,
which spread along with the classical ius. The growing importance
of the bureaucracy tended to undermine the role of the classical
jurists and their refined reasonings. Likewise, the bureaucratic
vocation of post-classical jurists made them venture into areas
beyond the old ius, such as administrative, tax, and criminal
issues; the distinction between private law and public law became
significant. Neither did jurisprudence escape the general crisis.
Only in some schools of law, such as those at Berytus and
Constantinople (modern-day Beirut and Istanbul) - both located,
not coincidentally, in the eastern part of the Empire - was
jurisprudence still cultivated.
A. Archaic Law
During the third century BC, the pontiffs saw their influence upon
the application and development of law reduced as the jurists and
praetors came to supplant them. At the beginning the study of law
formed part of a young patrician's general education, along with
military training and, somewhat later, rhetorical skills. Some of
these men pursued their studies in the law and managed to
acquire a deep level of understanding in this area. Increasingly
their fellow citizens would turn to these legal scholars for legal
advice. The jurists inherited function, method and style from the
priests, continuing to formulate responsa: concise answers to
particular cases with which they were presented. As a result,
except for the Law of the Twelve Tables, the ius civile remained
eminently casuistic.
In principle the ius civile applied only to the law of the Romans,
i.e. those who possessed Roman citizenship. As of the third
century BC the ius featured three layers or strata: the oldest and
most archaic was made up of moral and custom-based precepts
which, as a class, were referred to as mos maiorum; the Law of
the Twelve Tables constituted a second stratum; while the last
was formed by the responsa, issued by experts.
In general legislation was not decisive in this phase of private
Roman law, nor was it in the subsequent phase, the Classical
Era. The Roman Republic featured different types of legislation
depending upon the assembly that approved it. However, lex did
not have much influence on ius; with a few exceptions the Roman
leges had to do mainly with public law and criminal law. The
exceptions included the Law of the Twelve Tables and the Lex
Aquilia (c. 287BC), a law that addressed specific difficulties on tort
law without, however, regulating it systematically.
During the Republic the figure of the praetor, a magistrate who
exercised jurisdiction, that is, who administrated justice, became
central. Under the Republic the praetor was the second most
prestigious magistrate after the consul and, like the latter, wielded
imperium, or the highest executive power. As with the post of
consul, praetors were appointed to one-year terms. They did not,
however, operate as a body. Over time there were several
praetors, but without forming a council with a veto right. It was a
non-remunerated post, as were all the Republican magistracies.
Originally there was only one praetor, but as the population of
the city increased due to a massive influx of foreigners, in the
middle of the third century BC a second praetor was instituted.
One of them, the praetor urbanus, continued to handle the
administration of justice between Roman citizens, while the other,
the praetor peregrinus, was responsible for the administration of
justice between foreigners and between foreigners and Romans.
Over time the need arose for the establishment of additional
praetorships.
In order to fully comprehend the praetor's role as a central
element in the evolution of Roman law it is necessary to
understand the peculiar structure of Roman civil procedure. Civil
procedure consisted of two stages, its bipartition enduring as one
of its most noteworthy characteristics until well into the imperial
era. The first phase, called in iure, took place before the praetor.
The second phase, apud iudicem, "before the judge" or iudex. The
praetor was a magistrate of the Republic, while the judge was a
private citizen who did not occupy any honorary post and was
appointed as needed. During the first phase the praetor, in the
exercise of his jurisdictional authority, processed the suit in the
legally established manner: he took note of the claim and the
defenses (exceptiones), verified whether they fell under any of the
cases provided for, and granted or denied the action. If he denied
it the process ended. If he granted the action, the litigants passed
to the next phase, before the judge, who would hear the witnesses
and lawyers, learn about the facts in detail and, finally, without
departing from the strict limits determined by the praetor when
granting the action, issue his ruling. The praetor actively
participated, along with the parties, in the legal evaluation of the
case, while the judge was confined to passively hearing the
evidence and arguments before ruling in favor of one party or the
other. The first phase took place in public, in the northeastern
zone of the Forum, the central square of Rome and the heart of
political life, or in a basilica near it, such as the basilica Aemilia.
The praetor received the parties clad in his toga praetexta (an
ordinary white toga with a purple stripe on the border), on a
platform (tribunal) and sitting in a curule chair, a folding and
portable ivory stool, flanked by six lictors, a class of bodyguards
who on their shoulders carried the fasces, a bound bundle of rods
from which an axe blade protruded. Such were the symbols of
imperium (originally exclusive to the rex), which the praetor
wielded. The second phase, apud iudicem, was usually held in the
Forum or basilica itself at an agreed-upon place, but did not
feature any symbols of imperium, which the judge, a common
citizen, utterly lacked.
The praetors were not necessarily experts in law, but rather
experienced politicians eager to successfully ascend during their
year as praetors the penultimate step in the ranking of public
offices before they could become consuls. Nor was it common for
the citizen acting as the judge to have legal training. Therefore,
each of them was advised by a group of jurists.
The praetors inherited from the pontiffs a rigid and solemn civil
process, ritualized with certain gestures and words. Legal
complaints were to be processed according to a limited number of
remedies called legis actiones ("actions of the law"), which
constituted a mode of litigation peculiar to the Archaic period.
What could not be formulated within a legis actio lacked legal
protection, in which case the praetor was forced to deny access to
justice. Such was the praetor's main task: to determine whether
the claim was compatible with the legis actio according to which it
was to be heard.
The influx of foreigners, to whom ius civile was not applied,
augmented the discretionary capacity of the praetor peregrinus.
For foreigners Roman law provided for the development of a
different procedure: the procedure per formulas, or formulary
procedure, which allowed the praetor to bypass the legis actiones
and decide with greater autonomy whether to allow or reject an
action. In accordance with the new formulary procedure the
praetor, after analyzing the case with the parties, condensed and
noted down on a formula (literally, a "little form"), in what were
instructions binding upon the judge, the criteria according to which
he was to rule after having examined the evidence. This was still a
formal procedure, but one more flexible, versatile and responsive
to changing legal and economic conditions. Soon pressures grew
and opened up the new formulary procedure to suits between
Roman citizens as well. Gradually the archaic legis actiones fell
into disuse, and by the end of the Republic they were almost
forgotten. Formulary procedure characterized and left its peculiar
mark upon classical Roman law.
The formula was a kind of guide or script for the subsequent
trial phase before the judge, which it authorized at the same time
as it concluded the phase before the praetor. In essence it
consisted of a description of a hypothesis whose ultimate
substantiation was to determine the defendant's conviction or
acquittal. This logical core could be supplemented by other
elements or clauses, but these did not alter the general structure
of the formula. More specifically, they usually contained, among
other clauses, the designation of the judge, a concise description
of the essential legal elements of the claim, the defendant's
possible defense, and, in short, the instructions for the judge,
always expressed in contingent format: if the aforestated turns out
to be, convict (always pending the payment of a sum); if not,
acquit. Let us look at a simple example, cited by Gaius (Gai. IV,
41-43): "Titius, act as judge. If it be proven that the defendant
owes 10,000 sesterces to the claimant, sentence him to pay that
amount; if not, acquit him." Logically, the statement of the factual
hypothesis could become very complicated through the addition of
clauses containing other elements relevant to the case, but the
structure remained invariable.
Once the wording of the formula was determined, usually with
the agreement of the parties, it was recorded on tablets in an act
called the litis contestatio (something akin to a "public certification,
before witnesses, of the suit"). Following the litis contestatio the
object of the dispute could not be changed and it was no longer
possible to initiate another process based on the same claim.
During the second phase of the trial the role of the private judge
was limited to verifying facts and giving his opinion (sententia) with
regards to the question set down in the formula. Indeed, if after
the presentation of the evidence - witnesses, documents - the
judge believed that the facts described in the formula were true,
he was obligated to convict the defendant. If he did not consider
the facts proven, or if he considered the facts presented in the
defense to have been proven, he was compelled to acquit him. He
was also obliged to respect the legal qualification of the facts
made by the praetor and the parties in the formula: if it said
therein that the amount requested was pursuant to a deposit
agreement, the judge could not investigate whether the contract
was instead a lease. For all these reasons, the exact wording of
the formula was crucial.
During the Republican period there was no possibility of
appealing the judge's verdict, because, after all, a common citizen
designated for the occasion did not form part of any hierarchical
organization in which a superior could correct the errors of his
subordinate. The possibility of appealing civil judgments would
only appear with the Empire and, in particular, the development of
its hierarchically structured judicial bureaucracy.
The execution of the judgment was primarily the responsibility
of the parties, as there was no effective enforcement by the
Roman authorities. Since, theoretically, a debtor responded with
his limbs when he failed to comply with the decision, the creditor
could physically apprehend him and take him before the praetor.
He would be released from his creditor's hands only by complying
with the judgment. The spread of personal guarantees and
Rome's peculiar social structure meant that if the defendant had
no assets his patron or friends would usually take care of
payment.
The success of formulary litigation was related to the praetors'
growing exercise of their power to issue edicts of obligatory
compliance, which the praetor possessed, along with other
magistrates, aedi/es, consuls and censors. Thus, every year, upon
taking possession of his office, the praetor published an edict in
which he announced the remedies or classes of claims he would
be entertaining, something like the legal manifesto for his term in
office, which he would place on the walls of the Forum, on a set of
whitewashed wooden tablets. As a program this edict was valid
only for the period during which the individual praetor occupied his
position: one year. In theory every praetor was free to completely
rewrite these edicts, but in practice they repeated the majority of
the content established by predecessors, with amendments or
innovations suggested by the jurists, based on their having found
them necessary during the latest annual terms of the praetor's
office. Thanks to the conscious adoption of preceding praetors'
promulgations, by the end of the Republic a core of praetorian
actions had been developed which remained, nevertheless,
subject to adjustments by future praetors. In this wise balance
between tradition and innovation, along with the versatility of
formulary procedure, lies the secret of the extraordinary
development of the law by praetors during the central centuries of
Roman history.
The set of precepts contained in the edicts of the praetors was
termed ius praetorium ("the law of the praetors") or, more
generally, ius honorarium (as the magistracies were known as
honores, and to include the aediles, lower magistrates who also
issued edicts governing commerce). /us honorarium, or honorary
law, would ultimately make up a complete legal system. It did not,
however, replace the old ius civile, but rather overlapped or was
juxtaposed to it to supplement it. The praetors, indeed, did not
alter the basic nucleus of archaic law. A profound respect for the
ius civile, passed down from generation to generation, from time
immemorial, a manifestation of Roman society's general
conservatism, prevented the praetors from transforming this
nucleus. Still, they could supplement and adapt it to the changing
circumstances. The old Lex Aquilia, for example, did not contain,
strictly speaking, a general precept establishing civil responsibility.
Killing a slave or a piece of livestock entailed the requirement to
offer compensation equivalent to its market value, as was the
case with other damages. It was the creative activity of the
praetors which extended the scope of the law's application and
made it possible to establish analogies with other cases, without
abandoning the pragmatic legal casuistry that characterized the
Roman genius, wary of abstract formulations.
In the Late Republic there were already patricians expert in
legal questions who were fully-fledged jurists: experts dedicated
exclusively and professionally to the study of law and to the
rendering of legal counsel - although never in exchange for
economic remuneration, which was considered beneath their
dignity. What the jurists did not do was act as lawyers or
advocates, an activity that was exercised by a different set of
professionals: the orators and rhetoricians. Nor did they often
serve as judges, and only rarely did they aspire to executive
magistracies. The primary function of the jurists or jurisconsults
was to analyze legal problems and issue expert opinions to
citizens, to orators, to magistrates and judges. In their capacity as
advisors they formed part of the councils assisting the praetor or
judge during proceedings. Their opinions, or responsa, did not
have binding force, but were assigned great social and moral
value (auctoritas), and served as precedents. Jurists also drafted
documents and deeds for acts of sale, contracts and wills, and
helped to draft the exact formula of the first phase of trial
proceedings. Cicero - who was not a jurist, but rather an orator
and politician - summarized the activities of the Roman jurists as
this three-fold role: cavere (drafting the documents of legal acts),
agere (advising litigants and officials during suits) and respondere
(responding to legal questions and giving advice).
Thus far we have used the term ius civile with different
meanings, which must now be more clearly defined. In the first
place, the ius civile (or ius Quiritium) stood apart from and in
contrast to the ius honorarium (or ius praetorium). Its essential
core, which consisted of the custom-based law of the mos
maiorum, the Twelve Tables and the responsa of the pontifical
college (ius civile), was conceived as different from the edicts and
remedies granted by the praetors (ius honorarium). The term ius
civile bore a different meaning when considered relative to the ius
gentium. In this case ius civile was synonymous with ius proprium
civium Romanorum, the "law peculiar to Roman citizens,"
designating the set of institutions and prescripts applying to
holders of Roman citizenship, ius honorarium thus being included.
The ius gentium was, in contrast to this meaning of ius civile, law
that applied to foreigners and the relationships between Romans
and foreigners.
D. Post-classical Law
B. Leges Romanorum
C. Leges Barbarorum
A. Royal Legislation
B. Canon Law
IV. FEUDALISM
Feudalism was the form chosen by the Carolingians to structure
the administrative and military structure of their empire. The
effectiveness of this arrangement varied greatly over time, and
geographically, but there is no doubt that in the Carolingian
heartland (roughly France and Germany) feudalism came to
dominate political and social organization. It was less entrenched,
though certainly played a significant role, in peripheral areas such
as Spain, Italy and England. In Scandinavia and Eastern Europe,
meanwhile, its impact was limited.
Feudalism is characterized by a number of institutions that
combine personal and real property elements. The most important
of these elements were the fief and vassalage, a solemn contract
entailing rights and duties for both parties. The vassal promised to
provide his lord with assistance, mostly of a military nature, in the
form of a pre-established number of mounted knights, in
exchange for protection. Often a real property element formed
part of the agreement: the fief, a tract of land that allowed the
vassal to provide the required help and assistance to his lord.
The vassal could have vassals of his own, in relation to whom he
occupied a position as lord. In principle the contract ended when
the vassal died, and the lord could assign the fief again to
another person of his liking. In practice, however, the fiefs
became almost hereditary, as of the ninth and tenth centuries in
France, and slightly later elsewhere.
This pyramidal structure of individual contracts, with the king or
the emperor at its pinnacle, was the cornerstone of Carolingian
administrative and military organization. The structure worked well
only in times of military expansion, when there was much land to
divide among ambitious vassals. Under such
circumstances feudalism was a useful system for the
concentration of power. Intimes of military difficulty, however, the
system faltered. If the lordcould not honor his obligation to offer
protection, as when Vikingsand Magyars raided Europe at will, or
so it seemed, between theninth and tenth centuries, the great
vassals, such as dukes andcounts, would choose to organize
the defense of their own fiefsrather than sending a military
detachment to a centrally organizedarmy. The increasingly
hereditary nature of the fiefs contributedgreatly to this trend,
which meant that the great vassals actedindependently of their
lords. In times of military pressure, then,feudalism contributed
to a greater fragmentation of political power. Feudalism as the
backbone of the political structure was important until the
thirteenth century in France and the fourteenthcentury in
Germany, when administrative alternatives, based onthe ius
commune, were gradually implanted. However,it
continued to have long-lasting effects in Western Europe into the
eighteenth century.
3. The late middle ages
I. HISTORICAL EVOLUTION
A. Economy
B. Political Institutions
C. The Church
C. Canon Law
Unlike Roman law, which in the West largely disappeared for five
centuries, canon law was continuously transmitted and developed
throughout the Early Middle Ages. The writings of the Church
Fathers, the Bible, the canons of councils and synods, the
decretals of popes and bishops, were fairly well preserved, and
many copies of them were produced.
The authenticity of each text was not, however, assured, above
all if it originated in the Carolingian era. Two examples will suffice
to illustrate this.
The "pseudo-lsidorian" decretals were a major compendium
from the ninth century, composed, on the one hand, of genuine
conciliar canons and papal letters, and, on the other, by forged
decretals, the identity of their authors remaining a mystery. The
apocryphal decretals, supposedly written during the earliest times
of the Church, certify the authority of the bishops, and especially
that of the popes. The forgers introduced, for example, a new
ecclesiastical position, that of the primate, situated in the
ecclesiastical hierarchy between the metropolitan bishop and the
patriarch. Papal authority was reinforced, as the falsified letters
suggested that the pope had headed the Church since the
beginning of ecclesiastical history. They also assigned him
important powers, for example, by establishing that conciliar
decisions required papal ratification in order to enjoy validity. The
pseudo-lsidorian decretals exerted enormous influence, and
would appear in subsequent canonical collections. Without being
cognizant of their falsification, the popes did not hesitate to use
the pseudo-lsidorian decretals to concentrate power in Rome. It
would not be demonstrated that the decretals were forgeries until
the seventeenth century.
Another example is the so-called Donatio Constantini (the
Donation of Constantine), a false document that claimed to be
drafted in the fourth century, through which the Roman Emperor
Constantine had supposedly ceded secular power over the city of
Rome and central Italy to Pope Sylvester I (314-35). In reality it
was an eighth-century falsification created in a context in which
the papacy definitively severed its political bonds with Byzantium
and opted for an alliance with the Carolingians. The Donation of
Constantine later appeared in the Decretum Gratiani, where it
served another function as an argument in the fight against the
German emperors, wielded by the Pope to justify his claim to the
highest political authority. Though during the Middle Ages the
authenticity of the Donation of Constantine was already doubted,
it was not until the fifteenth century that the humanist Lorenzo
Valla(1407-57) proved that it was a fake.
Due to the transmission of canonical material from generation
to generation and the continuous production of new materials, it
became necessary to properly compile the West's enormous
heritage of canon law texts.
Among the most important collections from the Early Middle
Ages, apart from the aforementioned pseudo-lsidorian decretals,
were those of Regino of Prum (d. 915) and Burchard of Worms (d.
1025). The Gregorian reformers needed new collections, as they
had to demonstrate that their arguments were based on canons
and precepts of a respectable antiquity, and also because the
fight against abuses within the Church required the promulgation
of new ones. Therefore, in the second half of the eleventh century
new collections came about, such as those of Anselm of Lucca (d.
1086) and lvo of Chartres (d. 1115).
The most foundational of all medieval canon law collections
was the work that came to be known as the Decretum Gratiani:
literally, the Decree of Gratian, as from the 1160s onwards the
authorship of this fantastic work was ascribed to a certain "Master
Gratian." The only three things that we know with some certainty
about Gratian is that he worked on a version of the Decretum, that
he was in Venice in 1143, together with two Bolognese jurists, and
that he died on an August 10th (though we do not know in what
year!) as the Bishop of Chiusi. Exciting recent research has
brought forward the working hypothesis that Gratian was a
teacher of practical theology, possibly for a very short period at
Bologna in the early 1140s. As a teacher he had started drafting
the Decretum as a didactic tool for his classes, but had left it
unfinished to take up a better-paid job in the ecclesiastical
hierarchy; more specifically as Bishop of Chiusi (where he died
soon afterwards, possibly in 1144 or 1145). Another author
(maybe several) picked up the version of the Decretum where
Gratian had left it and expanded it greatly. The Decretum would
take on its final form close to 1150.
The sources of the work are both ancient and from the Early
Medieval era: canons of councils and synods, patristic writings,
elements of Roman law and the Carolingian capitularia, along
with, to a lesser extent, papal letters and pontifical law. The author
did not consult these sources directly, but rather made use of
previous compilations, such as those of Anselm of Lucca and lvo
of Chartres. The actual title of the work, Concordia discordantium
canonum (A Concordance of Discordant Canons) was every bit a
declaration of intentions: the aim was not only to compile ancient
and medieval canon law and transmit it to future generations, but
also to offer a solution to all those apparent contradictions
between materials in various places and times. To this end he
incorporated his own commentaries into the text.
The Decretum Gratiani, a private effort undertaken towards
academic teaching ends, would prove to be not just any textbook,
quickly becoming an irrefutable reference work. Gratian's
influence was due to the quality of his work, both in terms of its
compilation - ecclesiastical precepts from antiquity and the Early
Middle Ages not cited in the work henceforth lost all relevance for
ecclesiastical tribunals - and for his efficacious reconciliation of
apparent contradictions through scientific study. The work's
success also owed, in part, to the Gregorian reform, with which it
was perfectly compatible and of which it may be considered, in a
way, the culmination. Spiritual power was placed above worldly
power, the clergy enjoyed preeminence over the laity, and the
Pope was the undisputed head of the Church. Multiple variations
on these basic themes were found throughout the work, which
undoubtedly serves to explain the authority of the Decretum
Gratiani, despite the fact that it was never officially promulgated as
ecclesiastical legislation.
The Gregorian reformers believed strongly in the mission they
had been given: integrating the world into a religious and
ecclesiastical framework. To achieve this, numerous objective
measures were called for in almost all areas of social life. The
most effective tools in the pursuit of this end were legislation,
justice, and administration, as within the Church the pope was
legislator, supreme judge, and supreme administrator.
The decretals were the standard form of pontifical legislation in
the Middle Ages: a case or an issue was submitted to the pope,
whose decision, published in the form of a letter, or "decretal," in
principle applied only to the specific case, and was sent only to
the parties involved. The papal letter, however, also contained the
foundation upon which the pope had based his decision. This
rationale behind the decision, duly explicated and advanced by
the pontiff, was also applicable to other similar cases. Therefore,
the canonists were eager to have access to the content of these
decretals, as it allowed them to ascertain the most recent views of
the pope, the supreme judge of the Church.
Beginning in the second half of the twelfth century there was a
real need to fully compile papal law and jurisprudence. Initially the
compiling of papal decretals was carried out via private initiatives,
but beginning with Pope Innocent Ill the pontiffs came to
recognize the need to promote official compilations of them. In
this way the popes guaranteed the authenticity of the
compilations, the security of the texts, and control over their
contents.
In 1234 Pope Gregory IX (1227-41), who as a canonist
understood the benefits for students and practitioners of having
easy access to the text of the decretals, charged the Catalan
Dominican friar Raymond of Penyafort (1180-1275) with
compiling a systematic collection of decretals to be enacted as
law. The result was entitled simply Decretales Gregorii IX, (The
Decretals of Gregory IX), also known as the Uber extra (from
Uber decretalium extra decretum Gratiani vagantium, or the Book
of the Decretals Outside the Decree of Gratian), and it was
promulgated with the force of law, thus reinforcing the universal
and compulsory nature of the rationale behind papal decisions in
particular cases. The Uber extra represents a remarkable effort to
unify the law throughout the Church and place it under the pope's
control. Before the Gregorian reform relations between Rome and
local churches had been much more lax, and there were
significant differences between the different local congregations.
With the availability of a single, authentic text, the popes expected
all ecclesiastical tribunals to apply the same body of law.
After Gregory IX the popes continued to draft new legislative
materials, compiling collections of decretals and promulgating
them as universal laws. In 1298 Boniface VIII promulgated the
Uber sextus (the "Sixth Book," as a sequel to the five books of the
Uber extra). Pope Clement V took the initiative for the next official
collection, promulgated under the pontificate of his successor,
John XXII (1316-34) in 1317, and known as the Constitutiones
clementinae. These collections did not nullify the works that
preceded them, but rather complemented them.
In summary, throughout the Christian world during the
fourteenth century a number of official collections were in
circulation that placed secure and homogeneous texts at the
disposal of the ecclesiastical courts. However, it was not until the
end of the fifteenth century that there was talk of the Corpus iuris
canonici, after the French jurist Jean Chappuis gathered the
Decretum Gratiani, Uber extra, Uber sextus and Constitutiones
clementinae in a single edition and complemented them with two
lesser collections, the Extravagantes ("lying outside") of John XXII
and the Extravagantes communes of Sixtus IV (1471-84). In 1582
Gregory XIII (1572-85) brought together all of these writings in a
single book, with which the Corpus iuris canonici acquired its final
form. The medieval texts would remain in force until the
promulgation of the Codex iuris canonici in 1917.
The importance of canon law transcended the sphere of the
ecclesiastical organization. In a society where Christianity was the
sole framework of reference for man, canon law exerted
significant influence outside the strictly ecclesiastical domain.
Administrative acts and commercial transactions could fall
partially or entirely under the jurisdiction of canon law, and canon
law was also present in some fields over which secular courts
normally had jurisdiction, but which, ratione peccati ("due to sin,"
that is, to avoid mortal sin) were governed by ecclesiastical
jurisprudence. Canon law frequently encompassed fields which
secular law did not. Because of the importance of the family unit
in Christian morality, and the sacramental nature of marriage, it
was canon law that dealt with the rules related to marriage,
adultery, bigamy, kinship and consanguinity, divorce, annulments
and separations, and donations between spouses and between
parents and children. Canon law also held sway, ratione peccati, in
the criminal sphere with regard to perjury, violence, theft, murder
and rape. And in property law it was applied to purchases,
contracts,
guarantees, donations and wills. The presence of canon law in
society acquired such significance in the Middle Ages that it
rivaled that of Roman law. It is worthy of mention, moreover, that
while canon law was actually implemented and applied, Roman
law remained primarily a subject of university study. In classrooms
the scientific study of canon law took on the same degrees of
complexity as those that characterized Roman law.
B. Legislation
D. Customary Law
During the Late Middle Ages customary law served as the main
source of private law, and would continue to do so until the late
eighteenth century.
Customary law was initially characterized by the fact that,
despite not being recorded in writing, it nonetheless represented
a genuine body of law, its binding force proceeding from a shared
conviction that a prescript should be respected, and that its
violation generated liability. This conviction was also reinforced by
the opinion that a given law was good because the community's
ancestors had recognized it. Customary law prescripts tended to
be so deeply rooted in traditional practices that the groups
employing it could not even recall or conceive of a time before
their existence. As such, custom-based law was by its very nature
conservative, as it was through constant and repeated use that a
custom acquired binding force. Despite this anchoring in tradition,
however, it did undergo a gradual, though barely perceptible,
evolution. Precisely the fact that rules were not set down in writing
allowed them to be gradually adapted to fit new social conditions
and general notions of justice. Precepts could also disappear if
they were no longer compatible with newly prevalent ideas about
justice. But this did not mean that rules were not set, or that they
could not vary depending on certain cases. Rather, it meant that
the community's collective memory could undergo changes,
which would lead to corresponding shifts in the prescripts based
on them.
Customary law's non-written nature has made it difficult for
legal historians to verify its contents, above all during the period
between the ninth and twelfth centuries. With regard to precepts
prior to the ninth century, quite a bit is known thanks to records of
the leges (laws) of the different Germanic tribes. Beginning in the
twelfth century there were official and private codifications of the
then-existing customary law.
The German tribes' different leges (Salic Law, Lex Gundobada,
Lex Visigothorum ... ) in reality were little more than the putting
into writing of Germanic customary law: a snapshot of the
configuration of Germanic law. But these laws were applicable
only to German subjects; Roman or Romanized populations were
subject to other laws, most often variants of Roman law.
Beginning in the ninth century the application of the principle of
the personality of law declined and bodies of customary law
based on territory, rather than ethnicity, flourished. Due to the
difficulty of travel and political fragmentation, the territories where
the same laws were applied were very small, and every religious,
political or administrative unit could have its own body of
customary law. As Voltaire observed in the eighteenth century,
when travelling from the north to the south of France the legal
system changed even more frequently than one had to change
horses. This said, this fragmentation was hardly absolute. Towns,
cities and regions often shared a core of laws, and the closer they
were to one another, the more similar those laws were. Moreover,
in essentially transnational fields, such as trade, and especially
with regards to maritime trade, the trend towards unity was
remarkable.
From among these medieval systems of law, arising from the
consuetudinary tradition, what has been called the "Law
Merchant" (or lex mercatoria) stands out for its originality, creative
force, and subsequent repercussions. The development of
currency exchange and the use of credit during the era led to an
expansion in mercantile relationships, giving rise to many new
legal practices used by organizations of merchants, such as bills
of exchange and other negotiable instruments.
The disputes arising in this field were frequently settled by and
within communities of merchants. Maritime trade on the
Mediterranean, for instance, was subject to its own "consular"
jurisdiction in which non-jurist merchants, dubbed "consuls,"
served as judges and arbitrators, somewhat independent of
political or religious oversight. Procedure in these mercantile
courts was fast, flexible and informal. While adjudicating
commercial disputes, the "consuls" developed a jurisprudence of
mercantile practices and a separate legal system, the basis for the
adoption, in the nineteenth century, of separate commercial codes
and courts in many civil law countries.
When in a legal procedure one appealed to a consuetudinary
law precept, grounded in custom, it was imperative to
demonstrate that the precept actually existed; due to the non-
written nature of such a law, this proof was not always easy. One
also had to prove that a precept was valid and in force, which
could be done only by demonstrating its constant and repeated
use, something difficult when precedents stemmed back into the
distant past and had been lost. Thus, during the thirteenth
century techniques were developed to legally certify the
existence of a custom. These techniques included, for example,
qualified witnesses versed in the law, or a formal request
presented before another court to state whether it had ever
applied the precept cited by the party. These methods had two
effects: the gradual unification of law and the introduction of
written records into the process.
In order to deal with the problems inherent to customary law as
a result of its lack of record-keeping, in the thirteenth century
multiple private initiatives were undertaken to resolve the
situation. On occasions the members of a given court decided, for
their own use, to put the rules applied in it down in writing. These
"custumals" were initially of a very rudimentary nature: a simple
listing of rules and their precedents, lacking any apparent
systematic order. In a second phase more systematic books
appeared, with laws organized by subject. Once completed, these
writings often took on a life of their own, their influence being felt
beyond the territories in which they were written.
In this way some works contributed to a greater unification of
customary law. Famous examples may be cited from the field of
mercantile law: the Llibre de/ Consolat de Mar (Valencia,
thirteenth-fourteenth centuries), the first work containing the
maritime laws and customs of the Mediterranean. Circa 1250 the
Rolls of O/eron comprised the mercantile law applicable to the
Atlantic coast, and featured a set of judgments issued by the
maritime court on the French island of Oleron on the wine trade.
The Rolls were of decisive importance in the development of
English admiralty law and, as such, their influence extends to
present-day maritime law. The Rolls also provided the core
provisions of the Waterrecht ("Water Law"), a collection of
judgments by the Maritime Court of Damme, near Bruges, and
which was also used at other Hanseatic ports, such as Lubeck
and Danzig. In spite of widespread knowledge of the customary
law contained in the Rolls of O/eron, it would not be correct to say
that the entire Baltic trade was governed by a single corps of
supra-territorial law; many Northern European ports continued to
apply primarily their own customs and regulations, and were only
loosely inspired by the Rolls of O/eron and its derivatives.
Prominent custumals that indirectly inspired a greater unification
of customary law along territorial lines include the Grand
Coutumier de Normandie, drafted in the thirteenth century. This
was one of the earliest drafts of ancient Norman law, which was of
peculiar importance because of the privileged relationships
between Normandy and England. Even today this collection
remains a major source of private law on the islands of Jersey,
Guernsey, Alderney and Stark. This work was widely influential in
Normandy and beyond, because of its jurisprudential rather than
its practical approach; an example of it was the inclusion of a
treatise on the law at the beginning of the work, clearly inspired by
a chapter with a similar approach at the beginning of the
Decretum Gratiani.
In Northern France the Coutumes de Beauvaisis (1280) were a
prime example of a private initiative to record the law in a small
area. It was Philippe de Beaumanoir, bailiff of Clermont, who
wrote down the customary law of the county where he exercised
his official duties. It is one of the most significant and original
contributions of the ius proprium, for its comprehensiveness and
clarity. Even if the author did not include express references to the
legal books of the ius commune, his acquaintance with Roman
and canon law is unmistakable.
The Sachsenspiegel (the Saxon Mirror) by Eike von Repgow (d.
1235) marked the beginning of German jurisprudence. It was
comprised of customary law from Saxony, in the center of
Germany, but the work would have an enormous and enduring
impact on Central Europe as a whole, because of its capacity to
link customary rules and practices with wider theoretical and
political reflections on the origins and workings of legal custom.
Although he had not enjoyed a formal training in the Italian law
schools, the author had sound knowledge of canon law, and was
familiar with the Decretum Gratiani and the papal decretals.
Further north, in Denmark, mention must be made of the laws of
Scania, Zealand and Jutland. These laws were not typical
medieval custumals, for two reasons. Each of these laws covered
one of Denmark's main provinces, instead of only small territorial
units. Moreover, they included royal legislation. However,
customary law certainly was an important source of the contents
of these laws, which remained the basis of Denmark's legal
system until the second half of the seventeenth century, when
they were replaced by a nationwide book of law. The laws include
some technical terms that lead us to the conclusion that their
authors must have had some kind of knowledge of Roman and,
above all, canon law, as taught at foreign universities. The Jutland
Law probably inspired a similar Norwegian legal code in 1275.
The growing systematization of these books containing and
describing customary law revealed the growing infiltration of the
ius commune into the ius proprium. This evolution can be
explained by the training of their authors: the professionals who in
the thirteenth century served in municipal courts were practical
officials without university education. As time passed, due to the
central courts' increased activity and demand for professionals,
more and more university-educated jurists ended up serving in
courts where customary law was applied. The growing importance
of record-keeping also contributed to this development.
Customary law was, by definition, oral. Over time, however, it was
laid down in writing due the combined influence of private
codification initiatives, evidentiary techniques, and efforts by
public authorities to produce records of custom-based law. Also
worthy of mention is the increasingly scientific handling which
customary law was given: the style and methodology governing
the study of the ius commune came to be applied to an ever
greater extent to customary law, and by the fifteenth and
sixteenth centuries one can truly speak of the scientific study of
the ius proprium. Finally, due to the greater unification of
customary law, the common core of shared precepts expanded,
and fragmentation decreased accordingly.
4. The early modern age
A. Economics
From the ashes of the Hundred Years War the territorial state
arose triumphant: in the century following 1453 France, England
and Spain saw the development of states which would wield
effective control over their respective territories. Even the Italian
Peninsula would witness a period of internal peace (Lodi, 1454).
There were many signs of growing "nationalism" - if we can call it
that. Dante (1265-1321) and the humanists portrayed Italy as
boasting a glorious and commonly-held past. Spain unified, both
during and after the Reconquest, drawing upon the image of
supposedly shared enemies: the Jews and Moors within the
country and heretics outside it. France came to view itself as the
country chosen by God, who intervened in human history through
its christianissimus or tres-chretien ("most Christian") king,
assigned miraculous powers. In England anti-papal and anti
French sentiment was widespread, sowing fertile ground for
national fervor.
The idea of the nation as an object of autonomous, quasi
religious worship was not new. During the Middle Ages many
believed in Christendom, extending all across Europe, as a kind
of holy realm inspiring a sense of passionate belonging. The
application of this idea to the territorial state, the notion of a
chosen people, and the corporate, mystical connection between it
and the crown would promote exaggerated forms of patriotism.
Where one of these elements was missing, whether a unified
territory (Italy), a crown (Burgundy), or a national sense of
belonging (the Holy Roman Empire) it was difficult for the state to
establish itself as an effective authority and an abstract object of
veneration.
The construction of the state as a unique power structure
entailed the concurrent elimination of other authorities, inside and
outside, which it perceived as competitors, including the feudal
nobility, autonomous cities, and the Church. The rapid evolution of
military technology had a particularly decisive impact on the first
two; the new applications of gunpowder came to be decisive on
the battlefield; small structures, such as cities or fiefdoms, could
not afford costly investments in the latest military technologies -
only states could. A series of stinging defeats suffered by the
French cavalry at the hands of the English infantry illustrated the
obsolescence of the feudal military model. Massive, combined
attacks by rifles, bows and cannons were much more effective
than the old personal charge on horseback with a sword, spear
and armor. The feudal cavalry would give way to mercenary
infantry and artillery as medieval walls were no longer an obstacle
for heavy artillery and independent cities were left vulnerable.
With nobles and the bourgeois class unable to bear the costs
entailed by the new form of warfare, both would lose political
relevance. The feudal nobility, as a class, would see its influence
gradually undermined as it was replaced by professional
bureaucrats. Cities would also see their power undercut, as a
limited set of clashes would normally suffice for monarchs to
neutralize the influence of their most representative institutions.
The strengthening of the state was the direct result of the
suppression of domestic competition, but was also accompaniedby
other initiatives. The importance of the enormous sums ofmoney
needed for an aspiring power to maintain military viability -amounts
which only kings were ultimately capable of amassing - cannot be
overemphasized. In order to quench its increasing thirstfor tax
revenues an increasingly powerful bureaucratic apparatuswould see
to it that royal power was projected into every lastcorner of
a state's territory. Once again, the hierarchical
institutions of Roman law and the Church were the most important
sources of inspiration. During the fifteenth and sixteenth centuries
institutions were created or reformed, courts of first instance and
appeals courts charged with applying royal law and state
legislation, staffed by professional, learned jurists responsible for
their effective operation. With their new hierarchies in the court
system and the elimination of the feudal nobility and cities as true
centers of power, monarchs would feel capable of imposing theirwill
upon their subjects as law. It was during this era that the figure of
the absolute monarch was conceived, took shape, and was
imposed. The power of these rulers was not, in reality, arbitrary,nor
could it ever have been so. Despite brilliant and drawn-out
theories regarding royal sovereignty and the divine right of kings,
advanced by authors such as Jean Bodin (1530-1596) andRobert
Filmer (1588-1653), the absolute monarch was only"absolute"
according to institutional theory and protocol. Inpractice the
king had to negotiate and grapple with a whole rangeof established
interests, and his power depended, above all, onhis personal savvy
and skill as a politician, and that of his closestadvisers.
Spain constitutes one of the earliest examples of the state
formation process. The marriage of the two princes heir to the
thrones of Castile and Aragon (1469) joined the two realms. Direct
conquests, first of the Moorish kingdom (1492), followed by the
Christian Kingdom of Navarre (1512), brought territorial unity to
the Peninsula, with the exception of Portugal - which, however,
between 1580 and 1640, also fell under the Spanish monarchy.
Existing institutions, such as the representative assemblies, or
Cortes, were not completely eliminated, but were partially
supplanted by new, central institutions such as the Inquisition.
The four feudal military orders (Santiago, Calatrava, Alcantara,
and Montesa), with their extensive domains throughout the
Peninsula's kingdoms, originated during the Reconquest, were
brought under the king's direct control. Even so, Spain would
remain, above all, the sum of several crowns, a dynamic which
periodically became apparent, such as during the Portuguese
and Catalonian revolts of 1640. Administrative centralization and
the elimination of the power of the Cortes were more evident in
Castile than in Aragon, in part due to the silver brought in from
Spain's New World colonies and contributions from the clergy.
Until the middle of the seventeenth century Spain would stand
as the premier superpower on the European continent, thanks to
its overseas territories and states associated with the crowns of
Castile and Aragon in Europe: Sicily, Naples, Sardinia, Milan and
the Netherlands, as well as, under the reign of Charles V,
territories in the German Empire, brought under Spanish control
through royal family ties, such as the Archduchy of Austria.
Spain's decline would become patently manifest during the War of
the Spanish Succession (1701-1714), from which the Bourbon
dynasty would emerge triumphant, ultimately subject to the
dictates of Paris - a momentous change in Spanish foreign policy.
England, after its ultimate defeat in the Hundred Years War, in
1453, suffered a bloody period of civil war waged between the
House of Lancaster and the House of York. The Wars of the
Roses concluded in 1485 with a secondary branch of the House
ofLancaster, the House of Tudor, emerging victorious. The
dynasty's first king, Henry VII (1485-1509), stabilized the kingdom
and laid the financial foundation for a policy of centralization, one
successfully continued by Henry VIII (1509-1547) and Elisabeth I
(1558-1603). As from the 1530s English common law was applied
in Wales, from whence the Tudor family hailed. Also, with the help
of shrewd advisers, Parliament was transformed into a docile and
manipulable instrument. In 1603 James VI of Scotland would also
occupy the English throne as James I. The new dynasty, the
Stuarts, would immediately endorse radical ideas about the divine
right of kings, drawing it into a pamphlet war with Catholic authors
such as Francisco Suarez (1548-1617), and a debate ensued,
followed with great interest throughout Europe. The English
monarch aspired to rule without Parliament, but the theory of the
King in Parliament was so solidly established that he was unable
to do so. In 1628, Charles I (1625-1649) accepted the Petition of
Rights, under which he pledged not to impose new taxes and fees
without Parliament's approval, or to arbitrarily deprive anyone of
their personal freedom. A lack of money compelled Charles I to
convene Parliament in 1640, which gave rise to a new civil war,
this time between Crown and Parliament. Charles's enmity
towards the democratic body, and his religious policies, which ran
counter to prevailing sensibilities, brought about his downfall and
execution in 1649. His overthrow precipitated the establishment of
a fleeting republic, the so-called Commonwealth (1649-1660),
under the leadership of Oliver Cromwell (1599-1658), followed by
the restoration of the Stuarts, with Charles II (1660-1685) on the
throne. The latter monarch embraced a policy of pacification, in
1679 accepting the Habeas Corpus Act and promising to refrain
from arbitrary arrests and detentions. But Charles II was
succeeded by his brother, James II (1685-1688), who generated
hostility once again between Crown and Parliament. Suspected of
harboring Catholic and French sympathies, he was toppled by the
Glorious Revolution (1688), the foundation of England's
parliamentary monarchy down to the present day.
The reign of William Ill of Orange, stadtholder of the United
Provinces (1672-1702), marked the beginning of the transition from
the Stuarts, who sought to concentrate power and authority in the
monarch, to the Hanovers, more decided and willing to rule in
collaboration with Parliament. In 1689, just after taking the throne,
William accepted the Bill of Rights, a document designed to clearly
and definitively stipulate the relationship between the king and
Parliament. In 1707 traditional personal ties between England and
Scotland were transformed into a constitutional union with the
formation of the United Kingdom of Great Britain (Treaty of Union).
In 1714 the German House of Hanover took the throne, its first
kings acting more like German princes than kings of
England, which made possible the development and consolidation
of the parliamentary regime.
The territory under the control of the crown in France had
relentlessly expanded during the Late Middle Ages, the construction
of a central administration under the monarch's authority a process
which had already been initiated during the reigns of Philip II
Augustus and Philip IV the Fair. Suddenly suspended during the
Hundred Years War (1337-1453), the process was resumed with
renewed vigor after the final victory in 1453. With the invasion of
Burgundy in 1477 and the annexation of Brittany in 1532, the
territory under the king's direct control was augmented and France's
borders were almost definitively set. Louis XII (1498-1515) and
Francis I (1515-1547) centralized the administration of the kingdom
through the creation of effective administrative institutions, such as
the conseil prive, central courts, and parlements (provincial courts),
which served to provide subjects throughout the realm with access
to central and professional justice administrated by university-
trained jurists expert in Roman law. The feudal nobility, meanwhile,
with much of its political clout having evaporated, dedicated its
energies to enjoying a refined life at the court in Paris.
Religious struggles between Catholics and Huguenots (the
French offshoot of Calvinism), endless civil wars, dynastic
succession problems, and defeats to the powerful Spanish armies
would combine to undermine the French monarchs' centralization of
power during the second half of the sixteenth century. In 1589 Henry
IV took the throne (1589-1610), a Protestant who had converted to
Catholicism remembered for his (possibly apocryphal) phrase:
"Paris is well worth a mass." Henry IV would undertake an active
policy of pacification which would earn him the moniker Le bon roi
Henri and his being remembered as one of the finest rulers France
ever had. Through the Edict of Nantes (1598) he granted freedom of
religion to the Huguenots and madepeace with Spain. After decades
of bloody conflicts French monarchs, jurists and politicians would
eventually acknowledge the need to put an end to them, as they
proceeded to convert the king into an object of veneration and
concentrate power in his hands as a guarantor of peace. In fact,
the Estates-General (Etats
generaux) would not be convened after 1614 until the French
Revolution in 1789. Cardinals Richelieu (1585-1642) and Mazarin
(1602-1661) moved to both raise taxes and strengthen the
Crown's control over the Church and the provincial and local
authorities. In 1661 Louis XIV announced that henceforth he
would rule as absolute monarch, identified with and embodying
the state, a development dramatically illustrated by his purported
assertion "L' etat, c'est mot ("I am the state"). Louis pursued an
aggressive policy of expansion which expanded the boundaries of
his kingdom, and installed his grandson on the Spanish throne.
After ill-advised commitments by the French throne in the War of
the Austrian Succession (1740-48), the Seven Years War (1756-
63) and the American Revolutionary War (1778-83), France was
bankrupted and the country careened into chaos, with the
Revolution breaking out in 1789.
The dream of the dukes of Burgundy of gathering all the
Netherland territories under their crown would never be realized,
ending in fruitless frustration. Some of these territories, such as
Flanders, were subject to the French crown through a feudal
relationship. Others, such as the Duchy of Brabant, were vassals of
the Holy Roman Emperor. Through an astute series of political
marriages the Dukes of Burgundy managed to bring nearly all the
territories under their authority, except for the prince-bishopric of
Liege - a situation which would be inherited by Charles V. Their
holdings, however, would always be based on personal unions
between the different territories. Thus, the Duke of Burgundy cannot
accurately be called the ruler of the Netherlands, but rather the
feudal lord of the seventeen provinces: Count of Flanders, Duke of
Brabant, Count of Holland, etc. Charles V, however, would take
some steps to unify the Netherlands into a single state. The
aforementioned personal unions were legally consolidated in 1546
when he uniformized the succession law in all the provinces:
henceforth all of them would be inherited and fall under the rule of a
single lord. In 1526 the Peace of Madrid had ended the feudal
relationship between Flanders and the French Crown (which spared
Charles V from having to swear allegiance to his archenemy Francis
I of France, while also precluding the possibility of having verdicts
handed down in Flanders appealed to
Paris courts). The Transaction of Augsburg (1548), meanwhile,
undid ties with the Holy Roman Empire, releasing the Netherlands
from the jurisdiction of the Reichskammergericht (the "imperial
chamber court") and unifying them under a single legal
arrangement: the Kreitz of Burgundy. Administrative centralization
also progressed considerably through the creation of new central
institutions.
This centralizing policy generated many misgivings, sparking a
revolt by the provinces' elites against Philip II (1527-98). The
conflict would escalate on both sides, and in the end the northern
provinces, forming the Union of Utrecht (1576), signed the Akte
van Verlatinghe (Act of Abjuration), in which they renounced the
authority of Philip II and declared their independence. The
Republic of the United Provinces had been born: a confederal
structure of seven states with a common foreign policy and army,
and a minimum set of institutions charged with shared fiscal and
administrative affairs. After a number of failed attempts to find a
suitable king, a republic was declared, though a monarchical
element was present in the form of the stadtholder, the army's
commander in chief, always to proceed from the House of
Orange.
Spain's reconquest of the southern provinces prompted mass
emigration to the north. This, along with the blockade of the River
Scheidt, which provided access to Antwerp, shifted power towards
Amsterdam. Boasting an extensive trading fleet and buoyed by their
intelligent economic and diplomatic policies, the Dutch would rise to
become a key power in seventeenth-century Europe. Afterthe Eighty
Years War the Spanish were forced to recognize Dutch
independence via the Peace of Munster (1648). The southern
provinces chose to remain under the authority of the Habsburgs;
until 1714, the Spanish Habsburgs, and, henceforth, that of the
Austrian branch of the family.
The Holy Roman Empire entered the modern age as a collection
of semi-autonomous kingdoms and territories. Beginning in 1440
the imperial title was held by the Habsburgs, but this did not mean
that they did not have to secure this title with each election, often
paying a political price to do so. Both Maximilian of Austria and
Charles V sought to put an end to this
state of affairs through the establishment of a central court, the
Reichskammergericht (1495), as well as through wars inspired by
political and religious factors: against the Turks, aginst the
Schmalkaldic League, (1546-55) and, above all, in the Thirty Years
War (1618-48). In the end, however, the Peace of Westphalia
(1648) established the German territories' autonomy and freedom
from imperial authority. The emperor henceforth focused on
administrating those territories which he controlled directly: Austria,
Bohemia and Hungary, never managing to centrally administrate all
the Empire's holdings.
In the twelfth and thirteenth centuries the papacy had laid the
foundations for a centralized and hierarchical Church - the first
modern state, according to some historians - and, without any
hesitation, utilized this powerful apparatus in the political struggles
with the emperor, first, and, later, though with less power to exert,with
the king of France. France's subordination of papal power was
made manifest by the relocation of the papacy to Avignon, where
the pope was accused of frequently exploiting the ecclesiastical
apparatus in a manner that was, at best, ethically dubious. The
reactions, both from within and outside the Church, were swift.
Locating the Holy See in Avignon was considered extremely
detrimental to the Church and the most illustrious Catholics of the
time - Catherine of Siena, most prominently - advocated a return to
the Eternal City. The result of these constant struggles was the so-
called Western Schism, during which there were actually two (and
even three) popes at the same time. The Council of Constance
(1414-17) resolved the situation by deposing the "anti-popes" John
XXIII and Benedict XIII and accepting the resignation of Gregory XII,
before nominating a single pope, Martin V (1417-31), and returning
the Chair of Peter to Rome. As is hardly surprising, this entire
situation sparked numerous and heated controversies, among them
a decisive debate as to whether a general council could be ascribed
powersto depose the pope in certain cases.
After his election Martin V refused to recognize the conciliarist
doctrines that had emerged from the Council of Constance, but
was forced to endorse the periodic holding of councils and certain
measures to reform the Church in the pursuit of greater austerity
and spirituality. His Renaissance-era successors, however, did not
feel bound by such commitments, and would dispense with
councils, further concentrate power in Rome, and draw severe
censure for their desire for glory and riches. Reformers such as
Girolamo Savonarola (1452-98) and Erasmus of Rotterdam
(1466-1536) openly criticized the Church's excessively worldly
ambitions.
The emergence of figures such as Martin Luther (1483-1546)
and John Calvin (1509-64) must be viewed in this broader context
of appeals for general internal reform of the Church. The forces
they would unleash would forever alter the course of European
history. Indeed, what came to be called the Reformation was, in
reality, nothing less than a profound and radical revolution.
An underestimation of the magnitude of Luther's social support, as
well as the disastrous political backlash to his rebellion, secured the
short- and long-term success of the Protestant churches. Political
support for the Protestants, first in the Empire, but also in France,
the Netherlands, England and Scotland, was often the result of
political considerations rather than religious convictions. In England,
as in other places, the temptation on the part of the Crown to
confiscate extensive ecclesiastical assets explains, in large part, the
foundation of the Anglican Church through the 1534 Act of
Supremacy. In 1555, after a war waged by Charles V against the
union of Protestant princes known as the Schmalkaldic League, the
Peace of Augsburg established the principle of cuius regio, eius
religio ("Whose realm, his religion"): the religion of each territory
would be determined by its feudal lord. This policy represented a
momentous recognition of the religious division which had come to
split Europe. Many subsequent wars were waged under the pretext
of religious motives, but this principle stood. By 1555 Protestantism,
though always internally divided, was firmly established in the
northern half of Europe.
It was, paradoxically, the Counter-Reformation, a movement for
deep and genuine renewal which emerged victorious from the
Council of Trent (1545-63), which aspired to reform the Church's
morality and customs and enhance its education and
organization. Driven by the fervor that followed the Tridentine
Reform, the Church managed to halt Protestantism's territorial
expansion and salvage some measure of Catholic unity. Even so,
the popes had to make concessions to Catholic monarchs, in
particular with regard to the right to appoint key officers in the
Church hierarchy, and in relation to taxes and fees on the clergy
and ecclesiastical assets.
The end of religious unity also had important consequences in
the field of private law. Luther maintained that true faith could be
found only in the Holy Scriptures, rather than in the Christian
tradition and the Church that sustained it. He believed that the
centralization of ecclesiastical and papal power were based on
canon law, largely a product of that tradition. Well known is
Luther's symbolic burning of a copy of Gregory IX's Decretals. In
the countries which adopted Protestantism, however, the courts
continued to apply canonical precepts to matters such as
marriage, wills, etc., not because they acknowledged the authority
of Rome or of the Decretals, but because they had come to
constitute customary law.
II. JURISPRUDENCE
A. Legal Humanism
Humanism did not mark the end of the scholastic method. Its
refined techniques - distinctio, aequiparatio, etc. - would prove
indispensable for the study of law. Moreover, as a philosophical
theological framework, scholastics would remain attractive for the
fruitful way in which they reconciled - following Thomas Aquinas
(c. 1225-74) - faith and reason, the universal and the particular,
morality and law.
It was in Renaissance Spain, above all, where scholastics
enjoyed a new period of splendor after Francisco de Vitoria (c.
1480-1546) established Thomas Aquinas's Summa Theologica as
the premier book for theological education in Salamanca, rather
than Peter Lombard's (d. 1160) Sententiae. This marked a small
revolution in theological education and, to no lesser extent, in
legal education also. The Summa theologica brims over with
profound reflections on the law and justice. These passages from
the lofty work would be, at the same time, the object of
commentaries, appearing in large numbers with ambitious titles
such as De legibus (On Laws) or De iustitia et iure (On Justice
and Law), with theologians and jurists from Salamanca bringing
their extensive knowledge of Roman, canon, and local law to the
analysis of excerpts by the "Universal Doctor." Thus was born a
new type of legal commentary, which no longer followed the order
or systematics of the Corpus iuris civilis, but rather that of
Aquinas. The model was not imposed in an absolute or rigid way,
and authors were at all times free to structure their work according
to their personal tastes.
The Dominican friar Francisco de Vitoria would have a very
profound impact on the study of law, despite the fact that he
published nothing during his lifetime. His ideas have come down
to us through the notes taken by its students, who revered him.
The scholar's works featured painstaking and independent
analysis of the many disputes which arose during an era rife with
new developments, garnering him great prestige and influence,
both during his life and posthumously. His reflections on the
legitimacy of the Spanish conquest of the Americas, rooted in a
strikingly modern conception of natural law and human dignity,
would be crucial to the development of the doctrine of
independent international law.
The towering figure of Vitoria presides over several generations
of authors in what has been called the School of Salamanca, as
its first adherents taught at that university, sharing the system and
methods of this "late scholasticism." Its main authors led an
eminently academic life of teaching and writing. That does not
mean that they lived in an ivory tower; on the contrary, they
frequently engaged the most pressing issues of their times, such
as the challenges posed by the new economic realities of global
trade and finance; the plight of the natives in the colonies;
international relations between states; Church reform; and political
theory.
Domingo de Soto (c.1494-1560), a student of Vitoria and a
fellow Dominican, wrote important commentaries on the Summa
theo/ogica and the sections De legibus and De iustitia et iure, as
well as independent treatises, including works on property law. De
Soto was also involved in the organization of the famous debate of
Valladolid, where another Dominican, Bartolome de las Casas
(1474-1566) denounced the brutal fate of the natives in the
Spanish colonies. His adversary in the debate was the humanist
Juan Gines de Sepulveda (1490-1573), then Europe's expert on
Aristotle, who claimed that atrocities against the "savage" and
"inferior" Indians were justified if they refused conversion to the
Catholic faith. Las Casas, in contrast, stressed the equality of the
native peoples, an idea rooted in an elementary but fundamentally
democratic political theory. The Jesuit Francisco Suarez is one of
the most modern figures of the Salamanca School, a father, along
with Vitoria, of international law and a theorist in the areas of
sovereignty and the social pact. Juan de Mariana (1536-1624),
also a Jesuit, emphatically defended tyrannicide in a book that the
king of France ordered to be burned. Luis de Molina (1535-1600),
a professor at Coimbra and Evora, argued in his De iustitia et iure
that legitimate power is derived from the citizenry as a set of
individuals with rights, portending philosophies that would prevail
in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries. In the fields of trade
and commerce the Spanish scholastics were also among the most
innovative thinkers of their time. Martfn de Azpilcueta (1492-
1586), a prominent canonist, heralded concepts key to the
modern economy and defended the free market as an instrument
for the determination of fair prices. Fernando Vazquez de
Menchaca (1512-69), a jurist sent by Philip II to the Council of
Trent, argued that the seas could not be appropriated,
anticipating Grotius by one century. Finally, Leonardo Lessius
(1554-1623), a Jesuit professor at Leuven, addressed with great
sagacity, in his De iustitia et iure, novel issues related to financial,
banking and insurance law, his work seeing over 20 editions in
the seventeenth century alone.
The importance of the School of Salamanca to the field of
political theory and its influence on the development of a doctrine
of autonomous international law have long been recognized. Its
contributions to private law, however, have been largely
overlooked. At most it is mentioned as a precursor of Grotius and
the proponents of natural law. The works of the School's scholars,
nevertheless, were fundamental to the development of basic legal
concepts, such as contract and property. The late scholastic
authors were unique in their synthesis of Roman law, canon law,
ius proprium, theology, philosophy, morality and ethics, and for the
extraordinary ease with which they assimilated the Bartolian and
humanistic methods. They would lay down the foundations upon
which subsequent natural law apologists would stand.
The Spanish scholastics were closely involved in some of the
most novel, urgent and controversial legal issues of their time,
which required solutions which transcended national borders,
religion, and even civilizations. In their search for elements
through which humanity could build an order fair for all, all of them
arrived at a concept which would be the subject of legal debate for
the next three centuries: natural law.
Following Thomas Aquinas, late scholastics considered natural
law as one created by God, eternal and universal, common to all
humanity, and, of course, transcending nationality and religion.
According to their thinking, there are two ways to ascertain the
precepts of natural law: divine revelation and human reason. Man
is capable of knowing natural law through the use of his intellect
and reason, his birthrights as a being created in God's image.
One of the first problems the Salamanca School authors
addressed is that concerning the legitimacy of property. Is
property an institution of natural law? If so, cannot then anyone,
even if they do not know the true faith, acquire property? What
right, then, has the king of Castile to seize overseas territories?
This development of independent natural law offered a key
advantage: in an era that had seen the notion of absolute truth
wane, natural law made it possible to keep alive the alluring and
cherished ideal of a universal and eternal system of law. But all
the problems were not thus solved, of course.
The political model of Francisco Suarez offers a good example
of this. According to Suarez God created nature and, with it,
natural law. It is a principle of natural law that man forms political
communities, and it is only within them that he is capable of living
in peace and order. He cannot be extracted from this situation, but
he can determine the political form of the community: monarchy,
republic, aristocracy, democracy. Of all these models, monarchy
is the best (here Suarez follows a long tradition of Aristotelian
origin). At some point in its history, in some way, the political
community decided to organize itself as a monarchy. For Suarez it
was clear that the monarch wielded power thanks to his subjects:
the community delegates part of its political power, which belongs
to it, to its government. The nature of this pact was, and is, an
object of debate. According to Suarez, the pact itself proceeds
from natural law, although there may be other options chosen by
man. In some specific cases obedience to the monarch ceases to
be compulsory and resistance is legitimate, depending on the
conditions of the original contract and the requirements of natural
justice, provided that one can substantiate these conditions or
immemorial custom with documents. It may also happen that the
monarch behaves like a tyrant and leads the community into ruin,
in which case there can be no doubt: the people may rise up
against their monarch. When the original transfer of political power
was made to the monarch the community retained its right to
defend itself, which might be invoked to throw off tyranny.
In this diagram of a contractual monarchy it is perfectly
conceivable for the original contract to place legislative power on
the side of the community. And yet, clearly, it may also lie on the
side of the king. This transfer implies a fair possession of political
power, granting the king legal and, in some respects, ethical
superiority vis-a-vis the community. Thus, the monarch's will is
law, and there exists the obligation to obey it. The monarch can
also override customary law.
This is not to say that the monarch may exercise his power
capriciously. According to the definition of Aquinas, the law is
nothing more than a prescription of reason, organized to serve the
"common good" and promulgated by he who is charged with
overseeing the community. This concept of the common good,
key in the Aristotelian-Thomistic tradition, is not equivalent to the
sum of the assets of each of the community's members; it is
indivisible
and it is only through prudential collaboration that it can be
achieved, increased, and protected. Law and political power exist
only in order to serve the common good. Without it, political power
is devoid of any raison d'etre.
The king stands, therefore, above the law and custom, but as a
source of law himself he remains linked to the law insofar as the
common good forms part of it. If a king places himself above the
law without organizing his policies to promote the common good,
he becomes a tyrant and may be legitimately deposed. In short:
the constitutional pact entails both rights and duties; or, better put,
expectations of conduct and fields of action whose precise
boundaries it is not possible - due to their prudential character -
to define a priori.
This model does not aspire to distinguish clearly between
natural law, divine law and human law. It is clear that the
monarchy is not established by divine law in the sense that the
king receives political power directly from God. Rather, it
proceeds from natural and human law, as the submission of
political power to the common good, and of the community to
political power - in the way decided by man - are principles of
natural law.
A. Legislation
C. Customary Law
I. HISTORICAL EVOLUTION
We can define the Bourgeois Age as the period spanning the
eighteenth and nineteenth centuries. As historical bookmarks
demarcating the beginning and end of this era we can cite the War
of the Spanish Succession (concluding in 1713 with the Treaty of
Utrecht, in which Spain lost its European possessions), and the
Great War, or World War I, waged from 1914 to 1918, which
devastated and utterly mangled the social, political, economic and
military structure of Europe. Traditional historiography has tended
to identify the French Revolution as the end of the Early Modern
Age, which is also a valid criterion, given its enormous symbolic
value. The most important thing to recognize is the profound
continuity between the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries.
A. Economy
The changes which occurred in the West during this period were
profound and far-reaching, as an essentially rural economy
developed into an industrial one. Three factors contributed to this
fundamental shift: a surplus of agricultural production, the
existence of sufficient capital, and major technological
advances.
Over the course of the eighteenth century key improvements
were made in agricultural production. The surface area cultivated
was expanded, and new crops, such as corn and potatoes,
offered an alternative when cereal crops failed. Technological
breakthroughs and innovations were applied: new tools, crop
rotation, and specialization, which together made possible a
surplus in agricultural production.
Overseas territories also contributed to the general prosperity.
English colonies in North America and Australia, and Spain's
Virreinato de/ Rio de la Plata (basically today's Argentina,
Paraguay and Uruguay) featured sprawling agrarian holdings that
were soon able to supply markets with an abundance of products.
A recurring phenomenon which had haunted Europe throughout
its history was finally coming to an end: hunger.
The surplus of foodstuffs, along with advances in medical
science, allowed Europe's population to grow exponentially. It is
estimated that in 1700 Europe's population stood at
approximately 118 million. By 1800 it had risen to some 187
million, and by 1900 it was up to 400 million. The population spike
led to a greater number of workers engaged in trade and industry,
where James Watt's (1736-1818) improvements to the steam
engine sparked a genuine revolution. Steam engines, followed by
electricity and the internal combustion engine, supplied necessary
quantities of energy, while the population increase provided
cheap labor. Mass produced products were manufactured and
launched onto the European markets. European powers also
found vast markets for their manufactured products in their
colonies. It is no wonder that the English, buoyed by their huge
seafaring fleet, were those most capable of trading large numbers
of products, followed by France, Germany, Belgium and the
Netherlands. Massive investments in railways in the nineteenth
century assured sustained economic growth, while technologies
such as the telegraph drove another revolution in
communications. These interrelated trends towards
industrialization, mass production, and the internationalization of
commerce came to constitute what was dubbed the Industrial
Revolution.
Without capital, of course, neither industry nor trade would have
been possible. In pre-eighteenth century Europe the circulation of
capital was very limited, as land was still the main asset. This
situation changed over the course of the eighteenth century, when
the foundations of the monetary economy were laid down and the
accumulation of capital became essential for investments in large
factories equipped with machines and the assumption of massive
economic risks. The foundation of central banks was key to this
process, with the Bank of England (1694) leading the way.
The economic revolution, of course, also entailed a whole
series of social consequences. The surplus labor in the
countryside precipitated massive immigration into cities, where
populations skyrocketed. The clergy and the nobility, whose
essential wealth
was rooted in the possession of land, were economically undercut
and superseded by the rising bourgeoisie, which, capable of
amassing colossal fortunes, began to dictate economic policy.
Private property and free enterprise would be the essential
principles upon which the bourgeois economy rested.
With industrialization it would be not only the bourgeois classes,
however, which drove social changes; little by little, the proletariat
laboring in the factories also came to the fore. This low-skilled
working class, inhabiting industrialized urban areas, languished
amidst miserable living conditions - though often no worse than the
bleak situations they had left behind in the countryside. The
concentration of so many people in confined spaces, masses torn
from their traditional ways and tossed into an entirely new social
and cultural context, would make conflicts inevitable. It was in this
context that the work of Karl Marx (1818-83) appeared.
B. Politics
A. The Enlightenment
B. Revolutionary Projects
IV. JURISPRUDENCE
C. Pandectism
The Romanists built their system - a key catchword during the era
- on the basis of Roman legal texts. They thereby embraced the
rationalist constructivism for which they had reproached natural
law and enlightened jurists, turning to the same logical and
deductive methods. The difference is that they would not work
with axioms or principles, but with Roman materials.
The founder of the Historical School, in both its Germanist and
Romanist versions, was Friedrich Carl von Savigny. In his Oas
Recht des Besitzes (The Law of Possession, 1803), Savigny takes
a legal institution from the Roman material - possession - and
presents it as an organic and coherent unit. He did not undertake a
historical study in the sense of reconstructing the evolution of
possession over the course of history. On the contrary, he
considered it a fixed and unchanging concept, whose essence was
the intention to possess. But historical evolution was necessary to
manifest and lay down this unitary concept. In this lay, for Savigny,
the jurist's function: deducing from historical material, which he
considered a set of empirically observable data, general principles
and institutions. This creative work of thejurist made him the linchpin
sustaining and the engine driving juridical evolution. He rejected the
role of legislation and, with it, efforts at codification. Thibaut, after
ridding the German territoriesof French soldiers in 1814, had argued
for a single German codein his On the Need for a General Civil Law
for Germany. Savignyresponded that same year with his famous On
the Vocation of Our Age for Legislation and Jurisprudence. In
Savigny's view the jurist,
not the legislator, was the interpreter of the people's legal spirit.
Savigny also championed the figure of the jurist in his History of
Roman Law in the Middle Ages (1815-31), which featured the
biographies of glossators and commentators and demonstrated
the continuity between ancient Roman and medieval law.
Savigny also followed Thibaut's lead by integrating all Roman
law into a single system: System of The Modem Roman Law
(1840-49), in which he built an ahistorical scientific system based
on historical material. Roman law, in its classic version, was not
systematic, but rather quite piecemeal; Savigny took its casuistic
material and sought to structure it in a system which could also be
applied to contemporary Germany. This was the genesis of
Pandectism.
Savigny did not achieve his objective, but his successors would.
The methodology of conceptual and systematic thinking
(Begriffsjurisprudenz, or Jurisprudence of Concepts) would be
applied to Roman law, which would eventually completely
overshadow the historic material which constituted its foundation.
Friedrich Puchta (d. 1846) was a student of Savigny's, but his
Lehrbuch der Pandekten would end up making a considerable
impact on his teacher's system. Puchta, even more than Savigny,
proposed the construction of a logical and internally coherent
conceptual system. Puchta's successors included the outstanding
Bernhard Windscheid (1817-92), whose textbook of Roman law,
Pandekten (1862-91), constitutes the most complete expression
of the great project undertaken by Puchta and Savigny.
The pandectists' critics included Rudolph von Jhering (1818-
92), who had begun his career as a pandectist before ultimately
abandoning his belief in a logical and systematic approach to the
law. In his The Spirit of Roman Law in the Various Phases of Its
Development (1852), he presented with great originality the moral
and sociological aspects which had influenced and motivated the
ancient Romans, with particular attention to the archaic and
preclassical periods, in which he located its authentic "spirit." Law
serves certain ends, which must be pursued if one is to study it
and make legal decisions. According to Jhering, law is, in reality,
something that is kept alive by constant individual action, as he
expressed in his booklet Das Kampf urn's Recht (The Struggle for
Law, 1872), a genuine juridical bestseller.
Also rejecting the excesses of the pandectists was Nobel Prize
recipient Theodor Mommsen, the author of the masterful and
monumental Romische Geschichte (Roman History, 1854-56)
and other historical treatises on Roman public law, and Roman
criminal law, in addition to his editions of the Codex Theodosianus
(1901) and the Corpus iuris civilis (1868-70), the standard edition
even today.
Classicism and Romanticism did not shield Germany from the
positivist thinking which spread throughout nineteenth-century
Europe. However, the form positivism took in Germany differed
notably from that advanced by the Exegetic School, with its radical
adherence to legislation as the sole source of law. In Germany
what could be called "dogmatic formalism" spread, according to
which principles and concepts were deduced from the system
itself and political, economic, sociological, religious, moral, and
scientific considerations were dispensed with, precisely because
they fell outside the system. Thus, the legal positivism of
nineteenth-century Germany was based not on legislation, but on
the system itself. According to this line of thinking, all that was
necessary to find the correct solution to a particular problem was
the logical operation of placing a hypothetical judgment within a
systematic set of principles and concepts.
This extreme legal formalism had its roots in the thoughts of
Kant, whose influence Savigny himself acknowledged. Kant
believed that the function of the law was to protect subjective
rights. According to the philosopher the individual is capable of
complete moral development provided that this does not infringe
the rights of others. It is the role of law to protect these areas
where the individual acts and develops. The moral end which
objective law serves is achieved not by converting moral precepts
into legal mandates, but rather by creating and protecting the
domain in which the individual can live and realize his potential.
The law has an existence independent of moral and social
conditions. It may, therefore, be the object of autonomous, formal
elaboration - which was precisely the ambitious task at which
Savigny and his pandectist disciples endeavored.
V. PANDECTIST CODIFICATION
The 8GB had a significant influence on the states which formed part
of the Austro-Hungarian Empire, then on its way towards
fragmentation. Austria (1904) took it very much into account when
revising its own civil code in 1904, and Poland's law of obligations of
1927 was also influenced by it. Much can be said of the
preparations for a civil code in Yugoslavia. We already know that
Pandectism deeply influenced Italian jurisprudence; the conceptual
clarity of the 8GB was a source of inspiration for the Codice civile of
1942, though this did not mark an end to the traditional French
influence on Italy.
Outside Europe the 8GB had a great impact on the civil code of
Brazil (1916), and, through this, that of Peru (1936). The initial
draft of the 8GB even influenced the civil codes of Japan (1898),
Siam (Thailand, 1925) and China (1929).
After World War II the BGB's influence waned somewhat,
though it and Windscheid's Pandekten would have a major impact
on the civil codes of Greece (1946) and Hungary (1959).
The Swiss Civil Code also proved very successful. In 1927 it
was adopted outright, with just a few minor amendments, by
Turkey, where AtatOrk (President of Turkey from 1923 until his
death in 1938) sought to westernize and secularize his country. Its
influence and inspiration, particularly its decision to unify the civil
and commercial law of obligations, can generally be detected in
most civil code reforms of the twentieth century, such as that of
the Dutch Burgerlijk Wetboek in 1992.
6. Common law
Ill. WRITS
B. Chancery
Common law was too rigid to allow the king to take additional
measures or create new institutions to address such problems.
The Magna Carta had stated that no one could be deprived of his
freedom, his life or his property without due process, and to
ensure this a procedure before common law courts was
established. Over the centuries it came to be understood that the
common law courts, despite originally being based on a cession of
royal jurisdiction, functioned independently from the monarch. At
the beginning of the seventeenth century the courts made it clear
to James I that he was not to meddle with their jurisdiction. The
monarch was permitted, however, to retain a sort of residual
judicial authority. Thus, outside the regular system, the king
maintained a certain degree of responsibility for the correct
administration of justice, provided that life, liberty and property
were not involved. On the basis of this residual authority "equity"
was born to supplement common law without modifying it. The
most important institution to which the king turned for this purpose
was the Court of Chancery.
The Lord Chancellor, head of the Court of Chancery, became
one of the most prominent members of the curia regis, and
frequently acted as Prime Minister. He was also responsible for
the conservation of the great seal, and with it, public faith. In this
function the department which he headed, the Chancery, was
responsible for the issuance of official documents, such as writs.
The Chancery had been able to issue new writs when existing
ones did not provide a suitable solution for the particular problem
presented, but the limitation on the number of writs introduced in
the middle of the thirteenth century greatly curtailed this
possibility. From then on it was almost impossible to issue new
writs if they were not approved by the king and Parliament. Such a
procedure was too complex for most cases not covered by
existing writs. Thus, as of the fifteenth century the Chancellor was
authorized to issue, in his own name, decrees which would be
applicable only to the specific case in question. These decrees
contained orders to perform an act which at common law was not
permitted, or, conversely, to prohibit a conduct permitted by the
common law. In this way, returning to the example cited of a debt
settlement certification not returned at the time of payment, if the
debtor was then sued at law he could ask the chancellor to issue a
decree to obviate the abusive claim for double payment.
The chancellor's judicial powers were originally to be
considered exceptional. The chancellor did not stand in opposition
to the common law, but rather supplemented and perfected it:
equity followed the law, as did statutory law.
Initially, it lay at the chancellor's discretion whether to emit the
requested decree or not, ruling according to the specific
circumstances of the case and based exclusively on his own
conscience. His jurisdiction was a "court of conscience."
Beginning in the fifteenth century the chancellor's jurisdiction had
become so popular that a need was perceived for it to possess its
own court: the Court of Chancery. It is not difficult to explain the
reasons for its success: new remedies, more flexible procedures
via decree and bill instead of the rigid writs, the absence of juries,
investigation and judgment carried out by the judge himself, and
greater attention to the facts and circumstances of the case.
Along with this success, however, there came complaints
regarding the unpredictable, arbitrary, and excessively personal
manner (divers men, divers consciences) in which the Chancellor
exercised his powers. Protests against the Court of Chancery
were also driven by political motives, as Parliament wielded the
common law as a weapon in their fight against the king's absolute
power. Equity, in the hands of a Chancellor who tended to be the
king's right-hand man, was seen as a tool in the hands of absolute
political power, especially following James l's decision to place it
above common law in the event of conflicts between the two
("equity shall prevail").
All this made it untenable for the decisions of the Court of
Chancery to continue to depend only on the individual
chancellor's judgment. The court would have to decide in
accordance with general principles and issue similar decrees in
similar cases. Consequently, equity developed until forming a
body of coherent standards and principles separate from the
common law and juxtaposed to it. Originally highly adaptable,
equity grew progressively more rigid, particularly at the close of
the seventeenth century, before becoming a separate legal
system; rigor aequitatis had set in, and equity lost the dynamism
necessary to incorporate new doctrines and concepts.
The Court of Chancery was also criticized for being too
expensive and too slow. Its procedure - heavily influenced by the
Romano-canonical procedure, as the Lord Chancellor was,
initially, almost always a cleric or bishop - was very costly,
especially due to the widespread and accepted habit of offering
perquisites and gifts to accelerate procedures. Its slowness was a
problem inherent to the system, as the Chancellor tended to
supervise the court's entire workload.
During the nineteenth century the coexistence of two legal
systems was considered an anomaly and a set of reforms from
1873 to 1875 (Supreme Court of Judicature Acts) led to the fusion
of the courts of common law and equity into a single judicial
structure. This did not mean, however, the merger of the two legal
systems: the plaintiff, now always appearing before the same
court, chose whether to pursue his case "at law" or "in equity."
V. OTHER COURTS
After the separation of the common law courts and the Court of
Chancery, the judicial competencies of the curia regis were
curbed, but did not disappear, with some transferred to new
institutions, such as the Star Chamber and the Court of Admiralty.
The Star Chamber (so named for the decorative patterns which
adorned the ceiling of Westminster where the court's sessions
were held) gained importance in 1487 when the Star Chamber Act
charged the body with oversight of law and order. Competent to
hear civil matters, with some limitations, the Star Chamber was
best known for its criminal jurisdiction. In the first half of the
seventeenth century its reputation suffered greatly due to abuse
of it by absolutist kings who exploited it as an instrument to
persecute their political opponents. It was abolished in 1641, an
important step towards the consolidation of the political ideal of
the rule of law.
The Court of the Lord High Admiral of England, or High Court of
Admiralty, was responsible for all cases related to navigation on
the high seas. As there were many merchants seeking recourse to
this court, it was perceived as a threat to the common law, and
Parliament intervened several times to curtail its purview. Its
procedure followed Romano-canonical patterns, and the law
applied was largely based on rules shared with the Continental
merchant community, with roots extending as far back as the
Rolls of O/eron. This caused misgivings among common law
judges. In the seventeenth century its purview was limited to
collisions on the high seas and disputes regarding booty seized
from the capture ofenemy vessels.
The ecclesiastical courts and the Corpus iuris canonici they
applied, of extraordinary importance on the Continent, were also
relevant in England, especially during the Middle Ages. As a
Christian kingdom England belonged to the same politico-religious
unit as the rest of medieval Europe. Canon law, a supranational
legal order reflecting the common heritage of Christian values,
would thus be applied throughout English territory. In fact, it would
have a considerable influence on the development of common
law.
Some conflicts between secular monarchs and Church
dignitaries (such as that which led to the murder of the Archbishop
of Canterbury, Thomas Beckett, in 1170, the result of a dispute
with Henry II) contributed to a clear delimitation of the boundaries
between ecclesiastical jurisdiction and common law. The
ecclesiastical courts would be competent to judge matrimonial
matters and those involving children born out of wedlock,
inheritance law in relation to personal property, and with regard to
a range of sins, such as adultery. Theft and murder fell exclusively
under common law, as did contracts. Disputes over land in the
hands of the Church were reserved for the ecclesiastical courts
only if they were free of liens.
The shift to Anglicanism would mean that appeals against the
decisions of the ecclesiastical courts would no longer be sent to
Rome, but otherwise canon law continued to be applied without
major changes, except when conflicting with common law. In the
sixteenth century the possibility of fusing the ecclesiastical courts
with the common law courts was considered, but the operation
proved too technically complex, leaving the ecclesiastical courts
functioning separately until the nineteenth century.
B. Jurisprudence
The common law was born and essentially grew case by case
through the decisions of judges; its characterization as "judge
made law" is very accurate. In the words of the American Oliver
Wendell Holmes, Jr. (d. 1894), a judge himself: "the life of the law
has not been logic, it has been experience." It is, therefore, not
surprising that medieval and early-modern jurisprudence is
based, above all, upon practical cases: compilations of writs,
formulas, collections of cases, etc. It was mainly these materials
which were transmitted in the learning of common law, which did
not take place in universities or via the scholastic method, but
rather at the four major inns of court (Inner Temple, Middle
Temple, Gray's Inn and Lincoln's Inn), where apprentices were
taught the details of
judiciary practice by experienced attorneys.
Ranulf of Glanvill, Chief Justiciar from 1180 to 1189, produced a
landmark compilation of writs featuring a brief description of their
corresponding procedures: the Tractatus de /egibus et
consuetudinibus regni Angliae ("Treatise on the Laws and
Customs of the Kingdom of England"). The fact that this text,
which does not contain any references to royal legislation or local
customary law, became (together with the work by Bracton) the
fundamental cornerstone of common law jurisprudence gives one
an idea of the writ's central position in the English legal system.
In the middle of the thirteenth century there circulated several
manuscripts of the De legibus et consuetudinibus Angliae ("On the
Laws and Customs of England"), attributed to Henry of Bracton
(d. 1268), a judge at one of the royal courts. The Bracton text
features a great stress upon writs. Like Glanvill's Tractatus, the
work only addressed common law. However, Bracton introduced
some commentaries that were clearly inspired by canon law and
Roman law. He seems to have been familiar, in particular, with the
writings of the jurist Azo of Bologna.
After Bracton, systematic works on common law would not be
undertaken for a long time. Efforts were limited to modest
attempts at the systematization of isolated parts. A work of great
interest on real property law was the introduction to the subject by
Thomas Littleton (d. 1481), directed at future lawyers. John
Fortescue (d. 1479), Chief Justice of the King's Bench, wrote,
among other works, the De laudibus /egum Ang/iae
("Commendation of the Laws of England"), in which he set forth a
very influential constitutional account of the Crown of England
and, in this context, compared English common law with the law in
France, reaching the conclusion that the English common law was
superior. Fortescue's influence was noticeable in the treatise
Doctor and Student written by Christopher St. Germain (d. 1540),
an interesting dialogue between a doctor of Theology and a law
student on the relationships between law and morals.
This relative lack of systematic works corresponded to the way
future lawyers were trained. Universities such as Oxford and
Cambridge offered undergraduate courses in Roman law, but for
centuries the future serjeants-at-law, attorneys, solicitors,
barristers and judges learned the craft by professional practice at
the Inns of Court rather than through academic training. Legal
education was highly practical, initially under the direct supervision
of the existing practitioners of the law, but from the thirteenth
century onwards a collegiate system, with its corresponding
lectures, evolved as well. Reports on cases, such as the Year
Books, were produced for their analysis in class; students served
in moot courts to acquire practice, and the observation of court
proceedings at Westminster Hall was a basic component of legal
education.
As of the sixteenth century, some legists very gradually adopted
a more doctrinal approach to the common law. Faced with the
evident difficulties of the common law, such as its rigidity, the
overlapping jurisdictions of courts, and the lack of apparent order, as
a consequence of the fact that the organic growth of the law
centered around the system of writs, the English legists turned to
doctrine in order to further the systematization of the common law.
This scientific approach to the common law matches a similar
evolution on the Continent, where from the sixteenth century jurists
would approach the ius proprium in an increasingly scientific
manner. It appears that early-modern English legal authors were
well aware of the contemporary scientific movement in the rest of
Europe.
Edward Coke (1552-1634) was Chief of Justice of the King's
Bench until 1616, when James I dismissed him for his
maintenance of positions hostile to the interests of absolute
monarchy, at which point he dedicated himself to politics and the
study of common law. Coke set about writing the Institutes of the
Law of England, an extensive introduction to the common law, of
which only the first part would be published: A commentary upon
Littleton; "Coke on Littleton" would stand as the leading reference
work on property law until the twentieth century. Even though
Coke's book has the word Institutes in its title, the focus was
thoroughly on the traditional English common law. Posthumously,
a synopsis by Coke on the court system was published, along with
another on criminal law, and, finally, a commentary on old
legislation.
Matthew Hale (1609-76), also Chief Justice of the King's
Bench, was the author of an introduction to criminal law which is
still cited in English and American courts. He wrote, among other
works, treatises on the historical law of England: History of the
Common Law and the outstanding History of the Pleas of the
Crown. Hale had thoroughly studied Roman civil law, and this
familiarity probably helped him to improve the systematization of
English law as proposed by Coke. Hale introduced the idea that
the institutions of English law dated back to at least the Anglo
Saxon period.
William Blackstone (1723-80) was the author of the most
important work on common law since Bracton: Commentaries on
the Laws of England, which acquired almost legendary status. It
was the first successful attempt to systemize the entire common
law within the scope of a single book. As such, it fit perfectly with
the ideals of eighteenth-century Enlightenment. The author's
achievement was particularly meritorious because he could only
build on partial introductions to common law, such as those by
Hale and Coke. The work's systematization and structure was,
therefore, derived from the only possible reference work covering
an entire system of law: Justinian's lnstitutiones. Particularly
influential was Blackstone's reliance on natural law as an overall
legal theory. Blackstone, who was familiar with the works of
Grotius, Pufendorf and Barbeyrac, set out to prove that the
principles of common law embodied the principles of natural
justice. It was his approach to natural law that would ensure
Blackstone's tremendous influence in the courts of the young
United States. Post-revolutionary American courts struggled with
the question of why they should continue to enforce the rules laid
down in the past by judges appointed by a king they had abjured.
Blackstone's combination of common law and natural law
endowed it with a universality that provided the American judges
with a theoretical framework that allowed them to continue to
adhere to the common law.
While American federal and state courts cited heavily from
Blackstone's Commentaries, in his own country he became the
subject of ferocious mockery by Jeremy Bentham (1748-1832).
Bentham was an eccentric genius whose work must be framed in
the context of the Utilitarianism movement and the corresponding
rejection of natural law theories. Bentham sought to develop an
ideal system based on a principle of utility, providing the greatest
possible good to the greatest possible number of people. Parting
from this premise, he became an implacable critic of common law,
with its unnecessary formalism, division into courts with
overlapping competencies, the dualism between common law and
equity, etc. While during his own life his legal ideas were not
widely embraced, the succeeding generation would profoundly
reform common law - the Judicature Act 1873 is just an example
- in response to some of them.
A. Europe
C. Scots Law