Capitalism and Modern Social Theory - An Analysis of The Writings of Marx, Durkheim and Max Weber-Cambridge University Press (2000)
Capitalism and Modern Social Theory - An Analysis of The Writings of Marx, Durkheim and Max Weber-Cambridge University Press (2000)
Capitalism and Modern Social Theory - An Analysis of The Writings of Marx, Durkheim and Max Weber-Cambridge University Press (2000)
social theory
An analysis of the writings of
Marx, Durkheim and Max Weber
ANTHONY GIDDENS
professor of Sociology and Fellow of King's College, Cambridge
_CAMBRIDGE
" , UNIVERSITY PRESS
PUBLISHED BY THE PRESS SYNDICATE OF THE UNIVERSITY OF CAMBRIDGE
The Pitt Building. Trumpington Sireel. Cambridge. United Kingdom
CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS
The Edinburgh Building. Cambridge CB2 2RU. UK http://www.cup.cam.ac.uk
40 Wesl20th Streel, New York. NY 10011-4211. USA http://www.cup.org
10 Siamford Road, Oak leigh. Melbourne 3166. Australia
Ruiz de Alarcon 13. 28014 Madrid, Spain
Introduction xi
Part 1: Marx
1 Marx's early writings 1
2 Historical materialism 18
3 The relations of production and class structure 35
4 The theory of capitalist development 46
Part 1: Durkheim
5 Durkheim's early works 65
6 Durkheim's conception of sociological method 82
7 Individualism, socialism and the • occupational groups ' 95
8 Religion. and moral discipline 105
Index 255
v
Acknowledgements
This book is wriuen in the belief that there is a widespread feeling among
sociologists that contemporary social theory stands in need of a radical
revision. Such a revision must begin from a reconsideration of the works of
those writers who established the principal frames of reference of modern
sociology. In this connection. three names rank above all others: Marx,
Durkheim and Max Weber. My objectives in this work are twofold: firstly,
to set out a precise, yet comprehensive, analysis of the sociological ideas of
each of these three authors; and secondly. to examine some of the main
points of divergence between Marx's characteristic views on the one hand,
and those of the two later writers on the other. I do not pretend to provide
any sort of overall evaluation of the relationship between • Marxist' and
• bourgeois' sociology, but I hope that this book may help to accomplish
the preparatory task of clearing a way through the profuse tangle of asser-
tions and counter-assertions which have surrounded the debate on this
issue. I have. inevitably. covered a great deal of familiar ground. However,
recent scholarship has illuminated basic aspects of the writings of all three
authors. and I believe that my analysis departs considerably from some of
the established works in the field.
I do not, of course. wish to argue that the writings of the authors discussed
in this book represent the only significant streams of social thought which
have become embodied into sociology. On the contrary. the most striking
characteristic of social thought over the hundred years from 1820 to 1920 is
the very plethora of diverse forms of theory which were developed over that
period. The works of Marx's contemporaries. such as Tocqueville. Comte
and Spencer. continue to have a definite relevance to the problems of modern
sociology. and it would perhaps have been more logical to have included
these authors as the subject of detailed discussion in this volume. I decided
against this. partly from reasons of space, and partly because the influence
of Marx today is so much greater than any of these writers (and rightly so.
in terms of the more profound intellectual content of Marx's works). More-
over. most of the dominant branches of modern social theory can be traced.
although with numerous intermediate modifications and extensions. to the
three authors upon whom I have concentrated in this book. Marx's works.
obviously, are the primary source of the various forms of contemporary neo-
Marxism; Durkheim's writings may be identified as the dominant inspiration
vii
vui Preface
lying behind 'structural-functionalism '; and at least some of the modern
variants of phenomenology derive, directly or indirectly, from the writings of
Max Weber. Moreover. within more specific fields of sociology, such as in
the study of social stratification, religion, and so on, the influence of Marx.
Durkheim and Weber has been fundamental.
As Durkheim himself pointed out in a preface to a book on Kant by his
friend and colleague Hamelin. anyone who wishes to portray the thought of
men of a different time to his own, faces a certain dilemma. Either he pre-
serves the original terminology in which the author couched his works. in
which case he runs the risk that his exposition appears outdated. and hence
irrelevant to modem times; or he consciously modernises his terms, and faces
the danger that his analysis will be untrue to the ideas of the writer con-
cerned. It says much for the contemporary relevance of the social thought of
the three authors discussed in this book that. in analysing their work, this
dilemma does not offer difficulties of an acute kind. Where there are problems
of this sort, I have opted to preserve the original phraseology. But in the case
of the writers whose works are analysed in this volume. the main difficulties
which are posed concern the rendition of culturally specific German or
French terms into English. Terms such as Geist or representation collective
have no satisfactory English equivalents. and themselves express some of the
differences in social development between Britain. Germany and France
which are touched upon in the book. I have attempted to meet such problems.
as far as is possible. by paying attention to the particular shades of meaning
contained in the original texts, and in making quotations I have frequently
modified the existing English translations.
This is not a critical. but an expository and comparative work. By using
the present tense wherever possible, I have tried to emphasise the contem-
porary relevance of these authors. I have not sought to identify the weak-
nesses or ambiguities in the works of Marx, Durkheim or Weber. but rather
have attempted to demonstrate the internal coherence which can be
discerned in the writings of each author. I have also avoided, as far as
possible, the scholarly travail of identifying the sources of the ideas com-
prised in the writings of the three figures. But inevitably. because all three
wrote in a polemical vein. reference to other authors and traditions of thought
cannot be eschewed altogether. I have given some degree of prominence to
the social and historical' rooting • of the three writers whose work is analysed
here, since this is essential to the adequate interpretation of their writings.
In various ways, of course, the personalities of the three men present dramatic
contrasts, and are also no doubt relevant to the explication of the social
theories which they formulated. I have ignored this. because it is not my
objective to analyse in any amount of detail the' causal' origins of the
writings examined in the book. My concern is directed at disentangling some
of the complex intellectual relationships among the three.
Preface ix
I have not attempted, in the concluding chapters, to compare the works of
Durkheim and Weber directly. but instead have used Marx's writings as the
point of reference. Assessment of the convergences llnd discrepancies be-
tween the writings of Marx on the one hand. and Durkheim and Weber on
the other. is complicated by the fact of the retarded publication of Marx's
early works. It is only relatively recently. since something like a decade after
the death of Durkheim (1917) and Weber (1920). that it has become possible
to assess the intellectual content of Marx's writings in the light of these
works which. while they are of extreme importance to the evaluation of
Marx's thought. were published for the first time almost a century after they
were originally written. In my account of Marx's writings. I have tried to
break away from the dichotomy between the works of the • young • and the
• mature' Marx which has tyrannised most Marxist scholarship since the
last war. Close scrutiny of the notes which Marx originally wrote as the basis
of Capital in 1857-8 (Grundrisse der Kritik der politischen lJkonomie).
leaves no doubt that Marx did not abandon the perspective which guided
him in his early writings. But. in practice. those who have granted the truth
of this. in analysing Marx's thought. have still tended to concentrate upon
one part of Marx's writings to the exclusion of the other. I have attempted
to provide a more balanced and integrated analysis, which preserves the
basic place of Capital in Marx's life's work.
Apart from Marx himself. there can be few social thinkers whose fate it
has been to be so persistently misunderstood as Durkheim. In his own day,
Durkheim's theoretical writings were regarded by most critics as embodying
an unacceptable metaphysical notion of the • group mind '. More recent
sympathetic accounts have largely dispelled this sort of misinterpretation.
but have supplanted it with one which places virtually the whole emphasis
upon Durkheim's functionalism. In this book. I have sought to rescue
Durkheim as an historical thinker. Durkheim always emphasised the crucial
significance of the historical dimension in sociology, and I believe that an
appreciation of this leads to quite a different assessment of Durkheim's
thought from that which is ordinarily given. Durkheim was not primarily con-
cerned with • the problem of order '. but with the problem of • the changing
nature of 9rder ' in the context of a definite conception of social development.
Weber's writings are perhaps the most complex of those analysed in this
book. and they defy easy treatment upon a general level. This fact has led. I
think. to a failure in some secondary accounts to grasp the essential con-
sistency in Weber's work. It is only an apparent paradox to say that the very
diversity of Weber's contributions expresses the epistemological principles
which unify them as a single corpus of writings. Weber's radical neo-Kantia-
nism constitutes the underlying standpoint which combines his various
essays in different fields within a coherent framework. It is this which.
in certain important respects. creates irremediable divergences, some of which
x Preface
I have analysed in the concluding chapters, between Weber's social theory
and tbat-of both Durkheim and Marx.
One final point should perhaps be made. I believe that sociologists must
always be conscious of the social context within which theories are formu-
lated. But to stress this does not entail acceptance of a wholly relativistic
position. according to which the • validity' of a given conception is only
limited to the circumstances which gave rise to it. The fortunes of Marx's
writings bear witness to this. I have argued that Marx's theory was formu-
lated at an early stage of capitalist development, and tbat the subsequent
experience of the leading countries of western Europe helped to fashion a
version of • Marxism' which differed substantially from that originally
framed by Marx. Every form of practical theory has its Saint Paul. and
within certain limits this may be regarded as inevitable. But to admit this is
not to accept the stock view that the subsequent development of capitalism
has • falsified' Marx. Marx's writings today still offer a conception of society
and history which it is valuable to contrast with those of other. later, authors.
I do not believe that these divergences can be settled in the conventional
sense in which scientific theories are • confirmed' or • invalidated' by em-
pirical test. But neither are they refractory to empirical reference in the sense
in which philosophical theories are. If the borderline between sociology and
social philosophy is difficult to draw. it exists nonetheless. It is mistaken. I
am certain. for sociologists to seek to restrict the scope of their discipline
to those areas in which the empirical te'sting of propositions is easily applied.
This is the way to a sterile formalism in which sociology becomes lebens-
fremd. and thus irrelevant to the very issues to which the sociological per-
spective has most of all to contribute.
Anthony Giddens
3 March 1971
Introduction
2 Phyllis Deane and W. A. Cole: British Economic Croll·th (Cambridge. 1969). pp.
182-92.
l cf. David S. Lande;: The Ullhollnd PromC!theus (C:lmbridge. 1969). p. 125.
Introduction xiii
& Differences in level of economic advancement between Britain and the other two
countries can, of course, be traced back well beyond the eighteenth century. cf..
for example, F. Cronzet: • England and France in the eighteenth century: a com·
parative analysis of two economic growths " in R. M. Hartwell: The Causes 0/ th~
Industrial R~~'olutiot/ ill Ellg/and (London, 1967 •. pp. 139-74.
sEW. p. 45.
• EW, p. 51.
xiv Introduction
set of influences which were combined in Marx's writings.' Marx effected a
powerful synthesis of the streams of thought which had developed in con·
junction with the social. economic and political differences between the three
leading western European countries. Political economy. closely intercon·
nected with the philosophy of utilitarianism, remained effectively the only
significant form of social theory in Britain throughout most of the nineteenth
century. Marx accepted several of the key propositions developed by Adam
Smith and Ricardo. but merged them with certain of the perspectives upon
the finite character of bourgeois society contained in the various currents of
French socialism. The latter were the proximate source of the society of the
future first envisaged by Marx in the Economic and Philosophical Manu-
scripts of 1844, written in Paris. The historical dimension integrating political
economy and socialism was provided by the Hegelian dialectic. In this way.
Marx's works reunited. in a coherent fashion. the intelleCtual consciousness
of the diverse experience of Britain, France and Germany, and yet at the
same time offered a basis for the theoretical interpretation of these differences
in social. economic, and political structure.
When Marx died. in 1883. Durkheim and Weber were young men stand·
ing at the threshold of their academic careers. But already by this date. the
social structures of all of the three major countries of western Europe had
changed considerably from the time at which Marx had developed his basic
views. In both France and Germany - in contrast to Britain - working-class
movements of a potentially revolutionary nature came to playa leading role
in the political system. However. the influ~nce of these movements was
counterbalanced by a growing surge of iia1!gnalism: and. especially, in
Germany. which did not experience a successful bourgeois revolution. the
bourgeoisie was kept ~llbordinate to a powerful autocratic order, operating
through control Of the state--bureaucracy. the army. and the established
hierarchy.) Inside Germany. in spite of the anti-socialist laws. the Social
Democratic Party - an explicitly' Marxist' party after 1875 - swelled in
size. but towards the end of the century found its revolutionary posture in-
creasingly out of alignment with its real position in a society which had
largely become transformed into an industrial society' from the top '.
It was in this context, beginning shortly before Marx's death. that Engels
began to publish a set of writings furnishing a defence and an exposition
of Marxism as a systematic doctrine - the most important and influential of
these being Anti-Duhring. In emphasising the 'scientific' character of
Marxist socialism as against utopian and voluntarist forms of socialist theory.
Anti-Diihring prepared the ground for the positivistic interpretation of
Marxism which ruled in Marxist circles until after the First World War. and
, cr. Lenin: • The three IOurcea and three component parts of Marxism'. V. I. Lenin.
Selected Works (London, 1969), pp. 20-32.
Introduction xv
which has become the official philosophy in the Soviet Union. s The decade
foIlowing Marx's death - that is, the time at which both Durkheim and Weber
were each consolidating the views which informed their life's work - was the
crucial period during which Marxism became a really important force, both
politically and intellectually. The philosophical materialism that, under the
influence of Engels, came to be universally identified as ' Marxism " offered
a theoretical framework for Social Democracy which allowed a substantial
divergence between theory and practice: the Social Democrats became more
and more a reformist party in substance. while remaining a revolutionary
party in name. But by this very token. their leading spokesmen failed to
appreciate the significance of the changes which had made it possible to
rapidly cut back the lead in industrialisation which Britain had previously
enjoyed.
The problem of the influence of ' ideas' in social development, which so
dominated the polemical interchanges between Marxists and their critics at
around the turn of the present century. has to be understood against this
backdrop. Both Durkheim and Weber accepted the philosophical materia-
lism disseminated by Engels. Kautsky, Labriola. and others as the object of
their critical evaluations of the claims of Marxism. Liberals and Marxists
alike thus structured their debate around the classical dichotomy between
idealism and materialism. The controversy over the validity of Marx's writ-
ings, then, became concerned primarily with the question of whether or not
ideas are mere' epiphenomena' which have no ' independent' part to play
in social development. One of my concerns in this book is to demonstrate the
essential irrelevance of this debate. in so far as Marx's writings may be com-
pared with those of Durkheim and Weber as contrasting forms of social
theory. Marx, no less than the latter two writers, sought to break through the
traditional philosophical division between idealism and materialism. and it
is the confusion between this time-honoured dichotomy and Marx's own
• materialistic' critique of idealism which has obscured the sources of the
real divergences between Marx and' academic' or ' bourgeois' sociology.
This is a matter which has only fairly recently become apparent, in the
Course of the tremendous revival of western Marxist scholarship since the last
World War. The appearance. in Rjazanov's Marx-Engels Gesamtausgabe.
of various previously unpublished writings of Marx and Engels. has, of course.
played a major role in stimulating this revival. The publication of such works
as the 1844 Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts, however. has given
rise to as many new interpretative problems as it has helped to resolve. These
concern both the • internal' nature and coherence of Marx's own writings.
and the intellectual connections between Marx's theoretical position and that
of other social thinkers. The intricate difficulties which are posed by this
• George Lichtheim: Marxism. all Historic,,/ and Critical Study (londl)n. 1964).
pp.238-43.
xvi Introduction
situation have largely dictated the structure of this book. In evaluating some
of the sources of the contemporary debate between Marxism and' academic'
sociology it seemed necessary, as a prior task, to reconstruct the principal
themes in the writings of the major thinkers whose works are at the origins
of modern social theory. The first two-thirds of the book, therefore. are taken
up with separate treatments of the forms of social theory established by Marx,
Durkheim and Weber respectively (Chapters 1-12). The need to formulate,
in as precise and coherent a manner, the leading themes in the writings of
each author has precluded any attempt at the critical analysis of either the
, logic' or the factual' validity' of their thought.
The first of the three concluding chapters (Chapter 13) sets out an analysis
of the principal ways in which Durkheim and Weber themselves sought to
separate their views from those they attributed to Marx. But these views can-
not simply be accepted at their' face value '. Chapters' 14 and 15 abstract
from the stated positions of Durkheim and Weber in this respect. and provide
a new assessment of some of the main parallels and divergencies between
their writings and those of Marx. It should also be stressed that there are
several important lines of comparison between Marx, Durkheim and Weber
which have been neglected, or ignored altogether. in the three concluding
chapters. The most obvious omission here concerns the question of the diver-
gent methodological views espoused by the three writers: prima facie. the
most basic comparative issues might seem to lie here. In some senses this is
indeed the case; but it is a basic contention of this book that the overwhelm-
ing interest of each of these authors was in the delineation of the characteristic
structure of modern' capitalism' as contrasted with prior forms of society.
The typical emphasis in sociology over the past few decades has been direc-
ted towards the search for a formal • general theory'. Laudable as such an
objective may be, it diverges from the main focus of the works of the men
who established the foundations of modem social thought. and has had im-
portant consequences in obscuring the significance of problems which they
placed at the forefront of social theory. I do not believe that any of the three
authors discussed in this book sought to create all-embracing' systems' of
thought in the sense in which such an intention is ordinarly attributed to
them: indeed. each categorically denied this. Thus while I have accentuated
the integral unity of the works of each writer. I have at the same time endea-
voured to convey the partial and incomplete character which each stressed
as qualifying the perspectives which he established and the conclusions which
he reached.
List of abbreviations used
Abbreviations. as listed below. have been used for titles which are frequently
cited in the references. The particular editions of these works which have been
employed are given in the bibliography. at the end of the book. Where a double
reference is given. this indicates that a quotation in the text is my own translation.
or that I have in some way amended the existing English translation. The first
reference always relates to the English edition, the second to the original.
Works by Durkbeim
DL The Division of LAbour in Society
DTS De la division du travail social
EF The Elementary Forms of the Religious Life
FE us formes eJemelltaires de la vie religieuse
PECM Professional Ethics and Civic Morals
RMS Lt's rigles de Ja methode sociologique
RSM The Rules of Sociological Method
Soc Socialism
Su Suicide
L5 Le Suicide
.Journals
AS Annee sociologique
RP Revue philosophique
I It might be no led that some commentators have attempted to discern in these essays
a number of themes which were fundamental to Marx's later writings (cf. A. Cornu:
Kart Marx el Friedrich Engels (Paris, 1955), vol. 1, pp. 65-6). But the most strikins
cbaracteristic of the essays is their conventional adolescent idealism.
2 WYM, p. 39.
3 WYM. pp. 40-50.
2 Part J.' Marx
spell of Hegel's philosophical system as a student, it is clear that Marx was
at no point a blindly orthodox Hegelian. The genesis of Marx's initial attrac-
tion to Hegelianism is revealed in his description of the notes which, as a
student in Berlin, he made of his readings in philosophy and law.· The Kan-
tian dualism of what' is ' and what' ought to be " seems to Marx - and this
view he continued to maintain throughout the rest of his life - totally irrecon-
cilable with the demands of the individual who wishes to apply philosophy to
the pursuit of his objectives. The philosophy of Fichte is subject to the same
objection: it separates the properties of logic and truth (such as is involved
in mathematics and empirical science respectively) from the intervention of
the human subject in a continuously developing world. This standpoint, there-
fore, has to be supplanted by one which recognises that' the object itself must
be studied in its development; there must be no arbitrary divisions; the
rationale (Vernunft) of the thing itself must be disclosed in its contradictori-
ness and find its unity in itself'. 5
Marx discovered himself unable to resolve these issues alone, and was thus
unavoidably led to pursue in his own thought the process of evolution
followed by German idealist philosophy as a whole - moving from Kant to
Fichte and thence on to Hege!.' However, what first drew Marx to Hegel was
neither the impressive comprehensiveness of the latter's philosophy, nor the
specific content of his philosophical premises as such, but the closure which
Hegel effected bet ween the dichotomous strands of classical German philo-
sophy which formed the principal legacy of Kant. The impact of Hegel upon
Marx was mediated by two partially separate sources, each of which involved
the conjunction of Hegelianism to political standpoints at variance with the
conservatism of Hege!. T One of these influences is to be found in the teachings
of Eduard Gans, whose lectures at Berlin made some considerable impression
upon Marx. Gans seasoned Hegel with a strong element of Saint-Simonian-
ism.' However, Marx had almost certainly been exposed to contact with
Saint-Simonian ideas earlier on in his youth, and a case can be made for the
view that the influence of Saint-Simon's writings over Marx in his formative
years was in some respects almost as great as that of Hegel.'
The second factor conditioning Marx's acceptance of Hegel was Marx's
membership of the' Doctor's Club' in Berlin University. In this circle, Marx
10 For a recent discussion of the influence of Bauer upon Marx, see David McClellan:
The Youn, He,elians and Karl Marx (London, 1969), pp. 48ff and passim; see also
the same author's Marx before Marxism (London, 1970).
11 Ludwig Feuerbach: The Essence of Christianity (New York, 1957).
12 SW, vol. 2, p. 368.
IS cf. McClellan: The YOllng Hegelians and Karl Marx, pp. 92-7. McClellan's claim
that' Engels' description of the effect of the book is completely at variance with the
facts' (p. 93), however, is exaggerated. cf. Marx's well-known statement, written in
the early part of 1842, that' there i8 no other way to truth and freedom but throup
the .. river of fire" , (Feuer-Bach: lit., • brook of fire '). WYM. p. 95.
l~ It might be remarked that Feuerbach's own views were characterised by a number of
deep-rooted ambiguities. and underwent some de&nite changes, over the period
from 1834 to 1843. cf. Feuerbach: Siimmtliclle Werke. vols. 1-3. (There are some
errors, however, in the allocation of writings to particular years in this collection.)
11 Ibid. vol. 2, p. 239.
4 ParI 1: Marx
jected his own highest powers and faculties. who thus is seen as perfect and
all-powerful, and in contrast to whom man himself appears as limited and
imperfect.
But at the same time, according to Feuerbach, the depth of the comparison
between God and man can be a positive source of inspiration to the realisa-
tion of human capabilities. The task of philosophy is to enable man to recover
his alienated self through transformative criticism, by reversing the Hegelian
perspective, and thus asserting the primacy of the material world. Religion
must be replaced by humanism, whereby the love formerly directed towards
God will become focused upon man. leading to a recovery of the unity of
mankind, man for himself. 'Whereas the old philosophy said: what is not
thought, has no existence, so the new philosophy says. on the contrary: that
which is not loved. which cannot be loved. has no existence.' Ie
The effect of assimilating the ideas of Feuerbach was to tum Marx back to
Hegel, in an attempt to draw out the implications of the new perspective. and
especially to apply it to the sphere of politics. The aspects of Feuerbach's
philosophy which attracted Marx were essentially the same as those which
originally drew him to Hegel: the possibilities which seemed to be offered of
fusing analysis and criticism, and thereby of • realising' philosophy. It is
usually held that Marx's early writings on alienation in politics and industry
represent little more than an extension of Feuerbach's 'materialism' to
spheres of society not dealt with by the latter. This is misleading, however:
Marx does not accept. at any point, what Feuerbach considers to be the pri-
mary significance of his philosophy - that it provides an ' alternative' to. and
thereby a replacement of. Hegel. Even when most imbibed with enthusiasm
for Feuerbach. Marx seeks to juxtapose him to Hegel. Marx thus succeeds in
retaining the historical perspective which, while central to Hegel's philosophy.
is. in effect if not in intention. largely abandoned by Feuerbach. 17
political institutions of the state. 20 The real world is not to be inferred from
the study of the ideal; on the contrary, it is the ideal which has to be under-
stood as a historical outcome of the real. For Hegel, civil society (biirgerliche
Gesellschafl), which includes aU those economic and familial relationships
which are outside the political and juridical structure of the state, is intrin-
sically a sphere of unrestrained egoism, where each man is pitted against
every other. Men are rational, orderly beings to the degree that they accept the
order inherent in the state, which is a universal sphere cutting across the
egoistic interests of human actions in civil society. In Hegel's account, there-
fore, the state is not only presented as severed from the lives of individuals in
civil society, but as logically prior to the individual. The acting individual,
the real creator of history, is subordinated to the ideals of political participa-
tion embodied in. the state, which thus appear as the motive-power of social
development.
Feuerbach has shown, Marx continues, that in religion men participate
vicariously in an unreal, fantasy world of harmony, beauty and contentment,
while living in a practical everyday world of pain and misery. The state is,
similarly, an alienated form of political activity, embodying universal • rights'
wbich are as ephemeral as is the idealised world of religion. The basis of
Hegel's view is that political rights of representation mediate between the
egoistic individualism of civil society and the universalism of the state. Bul,
Marx emphasises, there is no existing form of political constitution where this
connection exists in actuality; in extant states, general participation in politi-
cal Ufe is the ideal. but the pursuance of sectional interests is the reality. Thus
what appears in Hegel's account to be separate from and superordinate to the
particular interests of individuals in civil society is, in fact, derivative of them .
• Up to now the political constitution has been the religious sphere, the
religion of the people's life, the heaven of their universality in contrast to the
particular mundane existence of their actuality.' 21
In the Greek polis every man - that is, every free citizen - was a zoon politi-
kon: the social and political were inextricably fused, and there was no separ-
ate sphere of the • political '. Private and public life was not distinct, and the
only • private individuals' were those who, as slaves, lacked public status as
citizens altogether. Mediaeval Europe contrasts with this. In the Middle
Ages, the various strata of civil society themselves became political agencies :
political power was directly contingent upon and expressive of the division
hegelienne do l'Etat et sa critique par Karl Marx', in Etudes sur Marx et He,d
(Paris, 1955). pp. 120-41.
2t WYM, p. 176.
6 Part 1 : Marx
of society into stable socio-economic orders.22 • Each private spbere bas a
political character. is a political sphere .. .' 23 In this form of society, the
various strata become politicised. but there is still no separation between the
, private' or the 'individual'. and the 'political '. The very notion of the
, state' as separable from civil' society' is a modem one because it is only
in the post-mediaeval period that the sphere of interests in civil society,
especially economic interests. have become part of the' private rights' of the
individual, and as such separable from the ' public' sphere of politics. The
distribution of property is now presumed to lie outside the constitution of
political power. In reality. however. the ownership of property still largely
determines political power - no longer in the legalised manner of medi-
aeval society. however, but under the cloak of universal panicipation in
government. 2 '
The realisation of what Marx calls ' true democracy • entails. according to
his analysis. overcoming the alienation between the individual and the poli-
tical community. through resolving the dichotomy between the • egoistic'
interests of individuals in civil society and the • social' character of political
life. This can only be achieved by effecting concrete changes in the relations
between state and society. such that what is at present only ideal (universal
political participation) becomes actual. 'Hegel proceeds from the state and
makes man into the state subjectivised. Democracy proceeds from man and
makes the state into man objectivised. , . In democracy the formal principle
is at the same time the material principle.' 25 The attainment of universal
suffrage. Marx says. is the means whereby this can be brought about. Uni-
versal suffrage gives all the members of civil society a political existence and.
therefore. ipso facto eliminates the 'political' as a separate category. 'In
universal franchise. active as well as passive, does civil society first raise
itself in reality to an abstraction of itself. to political existence as its true
universal and essential existence.' 28
Revolatioaary Praxis
There has been some considerable dispute concerning the relevance of the
views set out by Marx in the 'Critique·', to the writings which he produced
subsequently in 1844. 21 It is evident that the • Critique' represents only a
prefatory analysis of the state and politics; the manuscript is not complete.
and Marx states his intention to develop cenain points without in fact doing
so. Moreover. the tenor of Marx's analysis is in the direction of a radical
22 cf. Marx's discussion of the transformation of the feudal Stiinde. We, vol. 1. pp. 273f1.
23 WYM, p. 176; We, vol. I, p. 232.
2. WYM, pp. 187-8.
U WYM, pp. 173-4.
.. WYM, p. 202; We. vol. I, p. 326.
27 For divergent views on this question, see Lichtbeim, pp. 38-40; Sblomo Avineri:
TIre Sodal and Political Thought 0/ Karl Marx (Cambridge, 1968), pp. 33--40.
Marx's early writings 7
Jacobinism; what is needed in order to progress beyond the contemporary
form of the state is to realise the abstract ideals embodied in the 1789 Revo-
lution. But it cannot be doubted that the' Critique' embodies notions which
Marx did not subsequently relinquish. Indeed, it supplies the key to the
understanding of the theory of the state. and of the possibility of its abolition.
and thus the conceptions contained within it underlie the whole of Marx's
mature writings. But at this stage Marx was. in common with the other Young
Hegelians. still thinking in terms of the necessity for the • reform of con-
sciousness '. as posited by Feuerbach. Immediately priorto leaving Germany
for France in September 1843, Marx wrote to Ruge expressing his conviction
that all • dogmas' must be questioned, whether they be religious or political:
Our slogan, therefore, must be: Reform of consciousness, not through dogmas,
but through analysis of the mystical consciousness that is unclear about itself,
whether in religion or politics. It will be evident, then, that the world has long
dreamed of something of which it only has to become conscious in order to
possess it in actuality ... To have its sins forgiven, mankind has only to declare
tbem for what they are. 2t
The effects of Marx's direct contact with French socialism in Paris are
evident in • An introduction to the Critique of Hegel's Philosophy of Law',
written at the end of 1843. 21 Most of the points in the article are elaborations
of themes already established in Marx's previous • Critique', but Marx
abandons the stress upon • demystificatiOD '. such as urged by Bauer, which
informs his earlier critical analysis of Hegel. • The criticism of religion',
Marx admits. • is the premise of all criticism '; but this is a task which has
been largely accomplished, and the immediate and necessary task is to move
directly to the field of politics.
The abolition of religion as the illusory happiness of the people is the demand
for their real happiness. The demand to abandon illusions about their real
condition is a demand to abandon a condition which requires illusions. The
criticism of religion is thus the germ of the criticism 0/ the vale 0/ tears of which
religion is the halo. 30
But • criticism' in itself, Marx now goes on to say. is not enough. This is no-
where more obvious, he asserts, than in Germany, which is so retarded in its
development. The abstract. philosophical • negation' of the German political
structure is irrelevant to the real demands which have to be met jf Germany
is to be transformed: • Even the negation of our political present is already a
~. EW, p. 63.
10 Part I : Marx
able source of insight into the principal underlying themes of Marx's later
thought.
~9 EW, p. 69.
co EW, p. 121.
<I £W, p. 123. On a broader epistemological level, Marx criticises Hegel for having
mista{(en the nature of the connection between objectification and alienation. Funda-
mental to Hegel's idealism, Marx points out. is the premise that ' thinghood ' is the
same as • alienated self-consciousness' and consequently that objectification is only
I
made possible by human self-alienation. The truth of the matter, Marx avers, i~ the
other way around: the existence of alienation presupposes objectification, and is
(in Marx's use of the concept) consequent upon the specific distorted form of
objectification characteristic of capitalism. Many secondary writers have. unfortu-
4_ nately, failed to grasp this essential distinction between objectification and alienation.
- EW, pp. 122 & 123.
12 Pari I: Marx
force: .3 Obje..f1ificali!m. therefore. wh~~.hls a nec!=_s~!y_~h¥~~eri!!j~ ot~l
labour (involving the transference of labour power to the object which is
created by it) becomes, in_glpitaijsm.J,Q.~Iltic;aLwHlll!l!~~ation. The product of
labour is. in other words. '.J:xt~rnal ' to the wor:ker not only in an ontological
sense but also in the much more profound yet more specific sense that' What
!$_embodied in_the pr<!<Jl!ot of his labour is no longer his own.' U
The alienation of the worker from his product takes a number of distinct
forms. In discussing these. Marx uses terminology which draws heavily upon
Feuerbach; but it is clear that he is thinking in concrete terms of the effects of
capitalism as a particular. historical mode of production. The main dimen·
sions of Marx's discussion of alienation are as follows:
1. The worker lacks control over the disposal of his products, since what
he produces is appropriated by other_sf so that he does not benefit from it.
It is the core principle of the market economy that goods are produced for
exchange; in capitalist production. the exchange and distribution of goods
are controlled by the operations of the free market. The worker himself,
who is treated as a commodity to be bought and sold on the market. thus
has no power to deteJmi!!~t!t~ f~t~~.l what he produces. The workings of
the market act in suchawl!Y as to promote tbei1Uerests Qlth_e_~...n.ilalist at
u
the expense of those __of_ tJ~~....!'Lorker.. Thus • the more the worker produces
the less he has to consume; the more value he creates the more worthless
he becomes '.
2. The worker is alienated in the work task itself: • if the product of
labour is alienation. production itself must be active alienation - the aliena-
tion of~~vity and the activity of alienation.' U The ~ork task does not
_offer jnlrinsk satisla_c.tions which ~~l<~Jt P9ssible lQ~_~he worker • to de-
~19P freely llis__JJlel!tal ~ncl physical ene.rgies '. since it is labour which is
imposed by force of external circumstances alone. Work becomes a means
to an end rather than an end in itself: this is shown by the fact that • as
soon as there is no physic:al or other compulsion. men ftee from labour like
the plague ....
3. Since all economic relationships are also social relatipnships. it follows
that the alienation of labour has directly social ramifications. This takes
Marx back to his starting-point: b_uman relations, in capitalism •.!_end to be·
~jfu.eed to _operations of the market. This is directly manifest in the
significance of money in human relationships. Money promotes the rationa-
lisation of social relationships. since it provides an abstract standard in
terms of which the most heterogeneous qualities can be compared. and re-
U EW, p. 123. In discussing alienation in this context, Marx uses two terms: Entlrem-
dung (estrangement) and Entiillsserung (externalisation). The two are used more or
less interchangeably in Marx's analysis.
U EW. p. 122.
<s EW. pp. 123-4. 46 EW. p. 125; We. Ergd. vol. I. p. 514.
Marx's early writings 13
duced. to one another.• He who can purchase bravery is brave, though a
coward ... Thus, from the standpoint of its possessor, iLexcb.an~sevm
qu!lljt.Yand object1_QL~yery other, ~ven though they are contradictory.' 41
4. Men live in an active inter-relationship with the natural world.
Technology and culture are both the expression and the outcome of this
inter-relationship, and are the chief qualities distinguishing man from the
animals. Some animals do produce. of course. but only in a mechanical.
adaptive fashion. Aliena~abour reduces huma1!J>~o~!!ctive _actiyity to the
le.Yel of ~.daptation to, .rnW~IJhan actjY.LmasteI.Y~f,J!!!!ure. This detaches
the human individual from his 'species-being' (Gattungswesen). from
what makes the life of the human species distinct from that of the animals. U
Marx's discussion at this point closely echoes Feuerbach. But the import of
what Marx says is quite different. Many secondary accounts of Marx's
analysis of alienation in the 1844 Manuscripts, through assimilating Marx's
position to that of Feuerbach, give Marx's discussion a more' utopian'
connotation than in fact it has.· 1 Marx uses Feuerbachian terms in holding
that man is a 'universal producer', in contrast to the animals, who only
produce 'partially' and in limited contexts established by the instinctual
components of their biological makeup: but his analysis is far more
concrete and specific than this terminology suggests.
What c:Jj~tln.8Jlithes hum!lJ1 life Jr.Qmthaj~Llh.e. ..anim~Js, according to
Marx. is that human facutti~.Lc;a~cities_aJldta.Sl~--.S.ba~J~y_s.Qciety.
The ' isolated individual' is a fiction of utilitarian theory: no human being
exists who has not been born into, and thus shaped by, an on-going society.
Each individual is thus the recipient of the accumulated culture of the
generations which have preceded him and, in his own interaction with the
natural and social world in which he lives, is a contributor to the further
modification of that world as experienced by others. 'Individual human
life and species-life are not different things', Marx asserts ' ... Though a
man is a unique individual ... he is equally the whole, the ideal whole.
the subjective existence of society as thought and experienced.' so It is, then,
man's membership of society. together with the technological and cultural
apparatus which supports that society and which makes it possible, which
serves to differentiate the human individual from the animal. which confers
his • humanity' upon him. Some animals have similar sense-organs to man:
but th~ ~t~pjj.9n of ~1,l!Y in _sight. or:$Qund.ilt ~rt or JP1,Isjc. is a huma!)
J~~ty. a creation of society. Sexual activity. or eating and drinking, are
!1QtJQr_men the simple satisfa~JiolL.Q.f bjQ].Qgica] driy~._ Q.ut bave be~QO'1e
HEW ,p. 193.
u
Feuerbach: Es.renu 01 Christianity, pp. 1-12. Marx also makes liberal use of the
., term GauulIgs!eben, literaUy meaning' species-life '.
For two different instances of this, see H. Popit2.: Der ent/remdete Mensch (Frank
.0 fUrt, 1967); also Tucker .
• £W, p. 1S8; We. Ergd. vol. I, p. 539.
14 ParI I : Marx
transformed, during the course of the development of society. in creative
interplay with the natural world, into actions which provide manifold satis-
factions. ~ I • The cultivation of the five senses is the work of all previous
history'; but' it is nOl simply the five senses, but also the so-called spiritual
senses, the practical senses (desiring. loving, etc.), in brief, human sensibi-
lity and the human character of the senses. which can only come into being
through the existence of its object, through humanised nature: 5~
In bourgeois society, men are estranged, in specifiable ways, from the ties
to society which alone confer their' humanity • upon them. Firstly, aliena-
ted labour 'alienates species-life and individual life', and. secondly, • it
turns the latter, as an abstraction, into the purpose of the former. also in
its abstract and alienated form '_~3 In capitalism, both in theory and in prac-
tice, the life and the needs of the individual appear as 'given' indepen-
dently of his membership of society. This finds clear theoretical expression
in political economy (and. in a somewhat different way. in the Hegelian
theory of civil society which Marx previously criticised). which founds its
theory of society upon the self-seeking of the isolated individual. Political
economy in this way' incorporates private property into the very essence
of man '.54 But not only does the' individual' become separated from
the' social '. the latter becomes subordinated to the former. The productive
resources of the community are applied - in the case of the majority of the
population who live in penury - to support the minimal conditions neces-
sary for the survival of the organism. The mass of wage-labourers exist in
conditions where their productive activity is governed solely by the most
rudimentary needs of physical existence:
man is regressing to the cave dwelling, but in an alienated malignant form. The
savage in his cave (a natural element which is freely offered for his use and pro-
tection) does not feel himself a stranger; on the contrary he feels as much at
home as a fish in water. But the cellar dwelling of the poor man is a hostile
dwelling, 'an alien, constricting power which only surrenders itself to him in
exchange for blood and sweat'. 55
As Marx presents it. therefore. the alienation of man from his ' species-
being' is couched in terms of his analysis of capitalism. and is. in consider-
able degree, assymetrical: in other words, the effects of alienation are
focused through the class structure. and are experienced in concentrated
fashion by the proletariat. The transfer of the notion of alienation from a
general ontological category. which is how it is used both by Hegel and by
Feuerbach, to a specific social and historical context, is the main theme of
Marx's approach in the Manuscripts. Marx does not hold, however, that
alienation is wholly confined to the position of the wage-labourer. The
~, Statements such as Meyer's that Marx • posited a noble and intelligent human
species, whose goodness and intelligence are frustrated by the process of civilisation'
(AHred G. Meyer: Marxism. the Unity of Theory tmd Prw:tice (Ann Arbor, 1963).
p. 57) are plainly inadequate. As Meszaros remarks: . There is no trace of a senti-
mental or romantic nostalgia for nature in (Marx's) conception. His programme ...
does not advocate a return to .. nature ", to a .. natural" set of primitive, or
.. simple" needs .. .' Istvan Meszaros: Marx's Theory of A Iienalion (London, 1970).
51 Marx mentions the infiuence of the German socialists; but argues that • the origillal
and important German works on this subject' are limited to certain of the writinl:~
of Hess, Weitling and Engels. EW, p. 64.
n It is not wholly clear whom Marx has in mind here. but the reference is probably
to the followers of Babeuf and Cabet. Engels discusses these groups in his • The
progress of social reform on the Continent', We, vol. I, pp. 480-96.
Marx's early writings 17
little this abolition of private property represents a genuine appropriation is
shown by the abstract negation of the whole world of culture and civilisation,
and the regression to the unnatural simplicity of the poor, crude and wantless
individual who has not only surpassed private property but has not yet even
attained to it.eo
Crude communism, Marx continues. has not grasped the possibility of the
positive transcendence of private property. The destruction of private pro-
perty is certainly a necessary condition for the transition to a new form of
society. But the organising principle of the future socialist society must be
centred upon • the positive abolition of private property. of human self-
alienation. and thus the real appropriation of human nature through and for
man '; it will involve • the return of man himself as a social. i.e., really human,
being (als eines gesellscha/tlichen, d.h. menschlichen Menschen) a complete
and conscious return which assimilates all the wealth of previous develop-
ment.' 11 The recovery of the social character of human existence is integral
to Marx's conception of communism, as stated in the Manuscripts. Com-
munist society will be based, not upon the egoistic self-seeking which the
economists assume to be characteristic of human nature in general, but upon
the conscious awareness of the reciprocal dependence of the individual and
the social community. The social nature of man, Marx stresses, penetrates
to the roots of his being. and is by no means simply manifest in those activities
which are conducted in direct association with others. Communism will not,
however, deny the individuality of each person. On the contrary, the whole
import of Marx's discussion is that communist society will allow, in a way
which is impossible under prior systems of production. the expansion of the
particular potentialities and capabilities of individuals. For Marx, there is no
paradox in this. It is only through the social communitY that man becomes
individualised, via the utilisation of the resources which are collective
products.
This exciting and brilliant formula is integrated with a reiteration of the
limitations of the • critical philosophy' of the Young Hegelians. It is not
enough to supersede private property in theory, to replace the • idea' of pri-
vate property with the • idea' of communism. The actual attainment of
communism • will in reality involve a very severe and protracted process '.12
The first fruit of Marx's association with Engels was the heavily polemical
The Holy Family. which was begun in the latter Jfart of 1844. and was pub-
lished towards the end of 1845. The bulk of the book is the work of Marx.
and it documents Marx's final break with the rest of the Young Hegelians.
It was followed shortly afterwards by The German Ideology. written in
1845-6. also primarily a critical work. but one in which Marx for the first
time outlines a general statement of the tenets of historical materialism.
From this time onwards. Marx's general outlook changed little, and the rest
of his life was devoted to the theoretical exploration and the practical applica-
tion of the views set out in this latter work.
The full text of The German Ideology was not published in the lifetime of
Marx or Engels. In 1859. looking back to the period at which The German
Ideology was written. 'Marx wrote that he and Engels were not disappointed
that they could not get the work published: they • abandoned the work to
the gnawing criticism of the mice all the morc willingly', since the main pur-
pose - • self-clarification • - had been achieved. 1 Nonetheless, Marx explicitly
refers to his • Critique' of Hegel. and to the year 1844, as marking the most
significant line of demarcation in his intellectual career. It was the analysis
of Hegel's philosophy of the state, Marx wrote in his preface to A Contribu-
tion to the Critique of Political Economy, which led him to the conclusion
• that legal relations as well as forms of State arc to be grasped neither from
themselves nor from the so-called general development of the human mind
(Geist), but rather are rooted in the material conditions of life '.2
Engels later remarked of The German Ideology that the exposition of the
materialistic conception of history presented therein 'proves only how in-
complete our knowledge of economic history still was at that time ',' But,
although Marx's knowledge of economic history was indeed thin at this
period - the scheme of • stages • of the development of productive systems
set out there was subsequently considerably overhauled - the account of his-
torical materialism which is given in the work accords closely with that later
portrayed by Marx on other occasions. All precise dividing lines are arbit-
rary; but while The German Ideology is sometimes regarded as part of Marx's
1 SW, vol. I, p. 364. For Engels' subsequent appraisal of the significance of the early
writings, up to and including The GErman Ideology, see A. Voden: 'Talks with
Engels', in Reminiscences of Marx and Engels (Moscow, n.d.), pp. 3301f.
2 SW, vol. 1, p. 362; We, vol. 13, p. S.
3 SW, vol. 2. p. 359.
18
Historical materialism 19
f EW. p. 195.
• The Theses on Feue,bach were first published in 1888 by Engels, who remarks that
they contain' the brilliant germ of a new world outlook' (SW. vol. 2. p. 3S9). Here
1 quote from the translation in WYM, pp. 400-2.
, WYM. p. 402.
Historical materialism 21
in another way. Feuerbach's materialistic doctrine, he states, is unable to
deal with the fact that revolutionary activity is the outcome of the conscious,
willed acts of men, but instead portrays the world in terms of the • one-way'
jnfluence of material reality over ideas. However, Marx points out, 'cir-
cumstances are changed by men and... the educator must himself be
educated .. .'.10
In Marx's eyes, Feuerbach has made a contribution of decisive importance
in showing tbat • philosophy [i.e., Hegel's pbilosophy] is nothing more than
religion brought into thought and developed by thought, and that it is equally
to be condemned as another form and mode of existence of human aliena-
tion '.Il But, in so doing, Feuerbach sets out a 'contemplative' or passive
materialism, neglecting Hegel's emphasis upon • the dialectic of negativity
as the moving and creating principle .. .'.12 It is this dialectic between the
subject (man in society) and object (the material world), in which men pro-
gressively subordinate the material world to their purposes, and thereby
transform those- purposes and generate new needs, which becomes focal to
Marx's thought.
18 GT, p. 60. cf. also The Holy Family, 01' Critique 01 Critical Critique (Moscow, 1956),
p.I25.
17 GJ, p. 60. Marx makes the same criticism in reference to Proudhon's use of Hegel's
dialectic. Proudhon simply substitutes economic categories for the Hegelian succes-
sion of ideas, and thus is absolved from studying historical development in detail .
• M. Proudhon considers economic relations as so many social phases engendering
Doe another, resultiog from one another like antithesis from thesis, and realising in
their logical sequence the impersonal reason of humanity,' The Poverty 01 Philo-
sophy (London, n.d.), p. 93.
18 Letter to the editor of Otyecestvenniye Zapisky, translation after T. B. Bottomore
and Maximilien Rubel: Karl Marx: Selected Writings in Sociology and Social
Philosophy (London, 1963), p. 38.
24 Part 1: Marx
'wage-labourer') negates their range of capacities as • universal' producers.
Thus: 'The various stages of development in the division of labour are just
so many different fonns of ownership; i.e., the existing stage in the division
of labour determines also the relations of individuals to one another with
reference to the material, instrument, and product of labour: "
Pre-da.ss systems
Every form of human society presupposes some rudimentary division of
labour. But in the simplest type of society, tribal society, this is minimal,
involving a broad division between the sexes: women, being largely occupied
with tbe rearing of children. playa lesser productive role than men. Man is at
first a wholly communal being; (individualisation is a historical product,
associated with an increasingly complex and specialised division of labour.
A progressively more complicated division of labour goes hand in hand with
the capacity to produce a surplus over and above what is necessary to satisfy
basic wants. This in tum entails the exchange of goods; exchange in its turn
produces the progressive individualisation of men - a process which reaches
its apex under capitalism. with the development of a highly specialised divi-
sion of labour. a money economy. and commodity produ~tion.\M"en thus only
become individualised through the process of history:)' [Man] originally
appears as a species-being. a tribal being, a herd animal. .. Exchange itself
is a major agent of this individuali~ation.' 20 Property is also at first com-
munal; private property does not derive from a state of nature, but is the
outcome of later social development. It is nonsense. Marx asserts, to con-
ceive of human society as originally existing in conditions where separate
individuals, each owning his little piece of private property. at some date
came together to form a community through some kind of contractual agree-
ment. ' An isolated individual could no more possess property in land than
he could speak. At most he could live off it as a source of supply. like the
animals.' 11 An individual's relation to the land he works, Marx emphasises,
is mediated through the community. 'The producer exists as part of a family,
a tribe. a grouping of his people. etc. - which assumes historicalJy differing
forms as the result of mixture with, and opposition to, others.' 22
The simplest form of tribal society is that which follows a migratory ex-
istence, involving either hunting and gathering, or pastoralism. The tribe is
not settled in anyone fixed area, and exhausts the resources in one place
before moving on to another. Men are not settled as part of their nature; they
only become so when at a certain stage the nomadic group becomes a stable
agricultural community. Once this transition has occurred, there are many
II GI, p. 33.
20 PreoCapita/ist Economic Formations (London, 1964), p. 96; arll, pp. 395-6.
~I Economic Formations. p. 81.
22 Ibid. p. 87; am, p. 389.
Historical materialism 25
factors which influence how the community henceforth develops, including
both the physical conditions of the environment, and the internal structure of
the tribe, the • tribal character '. Further differentiation in the division of
labour develops through the related processes of population increase, con-
flicts between tribes thus forced into contact, and the subjugation of one tribe
by. another.~3 This tends to produce an ethnicaUy-based slavery system, part
of a differentiated stratification system involving' patriarchal family chief-
tains; below them the members of the tribe; finally slaves'.24 Contact between
societies stimulates trade as well as war. Since • different communities find
different means of production, and different means of subsistence in their
natural environment ',25 exchange of products develops, stimulating further
specialisation in the occupational sphere, and providing the first origin of the
production of commodities: that is, products intended for sale on an ex-
change market. The first commodities include such things as slaves, cattle,
metals, which are originally exchanged in direct barter. As such exchanges
proliferate, and as they encompass a wider variety of commodities, the use of
some form of money begins to occur. Exchange relations thus set up promote
the interdependence of larger units, and thus make for societies of an ex-
panded size.
While in Marx's earlier works a single line of development is portrayed,
simply using historical materials from Europe, from tribal society to ancient
society (Greece and Rome), Marx later distinguishes more than one line of
development out of tribalism. This includes particularly oriental society
(India and China), but Marx also distinguishes a specific type of tribal society,
the Germanic. which in conjunction with the disintegrating Ronuu:t Empire
formed the nexus out of which feudalism developed in western Europe.
Marx's views on the nature of the' Asiatic mode of production' (oriental
society) underwent some change. In his articles in the New York Daily
Tribune, beginning in 1853, Marx places considerable stress upon factors of
climate and geography which made centralised irrigation important in agri-
culture, and thus led to strong central government, or' oriental despotism '.21
However, Marx's later view is that this is rooted in more integral character-
istics of this type of society, generic to the local community itself. Qriental
s~ety l!-Jt!ghly resistanl_19 _cb_~,Se~_ th!s te!l~e!1c}' to stagqa_tion does pot
deqve-solely from the rigid despotic control of the centralised agency of
govemmenC but also (and primarily) from the internally self-sufficient
character of the village commun.e. The small village community is ' entirely
self-sustaIning and contams within itse1f aU conditions of production and
surplus production '.27 The historical origins of this phenomenon are not at
23 cf. Cap, vol. I, pp. 87-9. The similarity to Durkheim may be noted.
~. Pre-Capitalist Economic Formations, pp. 122-3. 25 Cap, vol. I, p. 35l.
" The American Journalism of Marx and Engels (New York, 1966); Articles on lndiQ
(Bombay, 19SI); Marx on China 1853--60 (London, 1968).
~7 Pre-Capitalist Ecollomic For/llatiolls, p. 70..
26 Part 1: Marx
all clear. but however this came about originally. the result is a • self-sustain-
ing unity of manufactures and agriculture'. which leads to no impetus to
further differentiation.
Population increase in oriental society tends only to produce • a new com-
munity ... on the pattern of the old one. on unoccupied land '.28 An essential
factor in this is the lack of private property in land. Where private ownership
of landed property does develop. as in parts of Europe and particularly in
Rome. population growth leads to increasing pressure for proprietorship
and consequently a constant tendency to expansion. However. in oriental
society the individual • never becomes an owner but only a possessor '. This
type of society is not necessarily despotic; small village communes may exist
as a segmentalised loosely associated grouping. However. the communities
may devote part of their surplus product. often under the inspiration of
religion. the • imagined tribal entity of the god '. as tribute to a despot. But the
unity of the ruler with his subjects is not based upon an integrated society
bound together by extensive economic interdependence; it remains a society
composed basically of segmental units connected by a religious affiliation to
the person of the despot.
The self-sufficient character of the local village communities definitely
limits the growth of cities. and the latter never came to playa dominant role
in either India or China. 2 ' In the type of society represented by Greece and
Rome. on the other hand. the city becomes of central importance. Marx lays
considerable stress upon the growth of urbanisation generally as marking the
clearest index of differentiation within the division of labour. • The opposi-
tion between town and country begins with the transition from barbarism to
civilisation. from tribe to state. from locality to nation. and runs through the
whole history of civilisation up to the present day .. .'.30 The division of city
and country provides the historical conditions for the growth of capital.
which first begins in the city. and its separation from landed property. In the
cities we find the • beginning of property having its basis only in labour and
excbange '.31
Ancient society. a city-based civilisation. is the first definite form of class
society. Although the Asiatic societies show a certain development of state
organisation. they are not regarded by Marx as involving a developed class
system. since property remains wholly communal at the 10calleveI. 32 Classes
2' Cap. vol. 1. p. 358. The structure of the Asian mode of production is eventually
undermined by the impact of western colonialism.
29 This is a point later made by Weber. with reference to both India and China.
30 GI, p. 65; We. vol. 3. p. 50.
31 GI. p. 66.
32 Wittfogel has argued that Marx' failed to draw a conclusion, which from the stand-
point of his own theory seemed inescapable-namely. that under conditions of the
Asiatic mode of production the agro-managerial bureaucracy constituted the ruling
class '. Karl A. WittfogeI: Oriental Despotism (New Haven, 1957), p. 6. Since
Marx refers to Russia as a • semi-Asiatic' society. the class character of the' Asian
Historical materialism 27
only come into existence when the surplus of privately appropriated wealth
becomes sufficient for an internally self-recruiting grouping to be clearly set
off from the mass of the producers. Even in ancient society - and particularly
in Greece - private property is still overshadowed by' communal and public
property'.
~. Pre-Capitalist Economic Formations. p. 84. Marx notes that the outlook prevailing
in the ancient world, although existing in alienated form - in terms of a • narrowly
national, religious, or political' world-view - still places man very much at the
centre of things as compared to bourgeois society, where human ends become
subordinated to production and the ac.:umulation of wealth. But Marx continues:
, In fact, however, when the narrow bourgeois form has been peeled away. what is
wealth, if not the universality of needs, capacities, enjoyments, productive powers,
etc., of individuals, produced in universal exchange? ' Thus while the • childish
world of the Ancients' is in one aspect superior to the modem world, it is so only in
terms of a relatively narrow range of human potentialities. Ibid. pp. 84-5.
3' The phrase is Engels', SW, vol. 2, p. 299.
40 Cap, vol. 3, p. 582.
Historical materialism 29
of the majority of the population into poverty, means that the latifundiae
eventually themselves become uneconomical. A further decline in trade sets
in. together with the decay of the towns. What commerce survives is reduced
to ruin by the taxation imposed by state officials seeking to prop up a dis-
integrating state. Slavery itself begins to be abolished. and the large planta-
tions are broken up and leased to hereditary tenants in small farms.
Small-scale farming against becomes predominant.
Thus Rome, at its height a great empire producing a concentration of
enormous we:alth. eventually decays; while a considerable development of
productive forces is attained, the internal composition of the society pre-
vents growth beyond a certain point. The expropriation of large numbers of
peasants from their means of production - a process upon which Marx lays
great stress in discussing the origins of capitalism - does not lead to the
development of capitalist production. but instead to a system based on
slavery. which eventually disintegrates from within.
43 Pre-Capitalist Economic Formations, pp. 144-5. (From the third draft of Marx's
letter to Zasulich.)
44 GJ, p. 35.
U EW, p. 115.
48 Marx quotes Thierry to the effect that the word capitalia first appears with the rise
of the autonomous urban communes. Letter from Marx to Engels, July 1854,
Selected Correspondence (London, 1934), p. 72.
47 Dobb has arg\led that the primary factor prodUCing the decay of feudalism' was the
inefficiency of feudalism as a system of production, coupled with the growing needs
of the ruling class for revenue .. .'. Maurice Dobb: Studies in the DeveJop/71J!nt of
Capitalism (London, 1963), p. 42. For a discussion of Dobb's book, see Paul M.
Sweezy: The Trallsition from Feudalism to Capitalism (London, 1954).
Historical materialism 31
commercial and manufacturing centres omy really begins in the twelfth
century; these are populated mainly by freed serfs. The growth of com-
merce stimulates an ever-widening extension of the use of money. and conse-
quently of commodity exchange. into the formerly self-sufficient rural feudal
economy. This facilitates the growth of usury in the towns. stimulates a
decline in the fortunes of the land-owning aristocracy and allows the more
prosperous peasant to discharge his obligations to the lord in monetary form.
or to free himself from the latter's control altogether. In England. by the
conclusion of the fourteenth century, serfdom has virtually disappeared.
Whatever their feudal title, the vast mass of the labouring population in that
country are by that date free peasant proprietors. The fate of serfdom, of
course, varies greatly in different parts of Europe, and in some areas serfdom
undergoes periods of • revival ',.. __
Although as early as the fourteenth century we find • the beginnings of
capitalist production' in Italy,...• and in the fifteenth century in England, these
are very restricted in scope. The towns are dominated by strong guild organi-
sations which strictly limit the number of journeymen and apprentices whom
a master may employ. and the guilds keep themselves separate from mer-
cantile capital, • the only form of free capital with which they came into
contact '.60 Moreover, there is no possibility of capitalism developing while
the majority of the labouring population consists of independent peasantry.
The process of • primary accumulation' 51 - that is. the initial formation of
the capitalist mode of production - involves, as Marx stresses many times,
the expropriation of the peasant from his means of production, a set of events
which • is written in the annals of mankind in letters of blood and fire '.
This process occurs at divergent periods, and in various ways, in different
countries, and Marx concentrates upon the example of England. where it
appears in • classic form '. In England, the transformation of independent
peasant into wage-labourer begins in earnest in the late fifteenth century.u
By this time, the great feudal wars Have sapped the resources of the nobility.
The first • mass of free proletarians' is thrown onto the market through the
disbanding of retainers by the impoverished aristocracy, and the declining
position of the feudal aristocracy is hastened by the growing power of the
monarchy. The land-owning aristocracy is increasingly drawn into an ex-
$1 Tbe phrase is usually rendered' primitive accumulation '. Here I follow Sweezy
(p. 17) and others in translating urspriinglich as • primary', which avoids the
POtentially misleisding implications of the usual rendering.
~~ Cap, vol. I. pp. 718ff.
32 Part 1: Marx
change economy. The result is the enclosure movement, to which the rise of
Flemish wool manufacture, leading to a sharp rise in the price of wool in
England, gives a further impetus. In 'defiant opposition to King and Par-
liament' the feudal lords uproot large numbers of the peasantry, forcibly
driving them from their land. Arable land is turned into pasture, which only
requires a few herdsmen. This whole process of expropriation receives in the
sixteenth century' a new and frightening impulse' from the Reformation;
the extensive church lands are handed out to royal favourites or sold cheaply
to speculators who drive out the hereditary tenants and consolidate their
holdings into large units. The expropriated peasantry are ' turned en masse
into beggars, vagabonds, partly from inclination, in most cases from stress of
circumstances '.u This is met with fierce legislation against vagrancy, by
which means the vagabond population is subjected to' the discipline neces-
sary for the wage system '.54
By the early period of the sixteenth century then, there exists in England
the beginnings of a proletariat - a stratum of dispossessed peasants who are
a 'floating', mobile group, separated from their means of production. and
thrown onto the market as 'free' wage-labourers. Marx notes scornfully that
political economists interpret this in a purely positive light, speaking of the
liberation of men from feudal ties and restrictions, neglecting altogether the
fact that this freedom entails 'the most shameless violation of the " sacred
rights of property" and the grossest acts of violence to persons '.55
In themselves, however, these events cannot, Marx indicates, be regarded
as sufficient conditions for the rise of capitalism. At the tum of the sixteenth
century, the decaying remnants of feudalism are poised between further dis-
integration and a movement into a more advanced productive form: capita-
lism. A factor of some importance in stimulating the latter development is
the rapid and vast expansion of overseas commerce which develops as a
result of the startling geographical discoveries made in the last part of the
fifteenth century. These include principally the discovery of America and the
rounding of the Cape, which' gave to commerce. to navigation, to industry,
an impulse never before known, and thereby, to the revolutionary element in
the tottering feudal society, a rapid development '.58 The rapid influx of
capital deriving from this mushrooming trade, plus the flood of precious
metals coming into the country following the discovery of gold and silver in
America, cuts through the existing social and economic arrangements in
England. New manufacturers become established at the sea-ports, and at
inland centres outside the control of the older corporate towns and their
guild organisations. The former undergo rapid growth. in spite of 'an em·
bittered struggle of the corporate towns against these new industrial nur·
5~ Cap. vol. I, pp. 718. 721 &: 734; We, vol. 23, pp. 746. 748 &: 762.
54 Cap. vol. I. p. 737.
"., Cap. vol. I. p. 727.
56 CM. p. 133; GI. p. 73.
Historical materialism 33
series '.IT Modem capitalism thus begins away from the older centres of
manufacture, 'on the basis of large-scale maritime and overland trade'.iii
Organised manufacture does not originate in the craft industries controlled
by tbe guilds, but in what Marx calls the • rural subsidiary operations • of
spinning and weaving. which need little technical training. While rural society
is the last place where capitalism develops in its • purest and most logical
form " the initial impetus is located there. I I Not before this stage is reached
is capital a revolutionary force. While the previous development of mercanti-
lism beginning in the eleventh century acts as a major factor in dissolving
feudal structures, the towns which develop are essentially dependent upon
the old syst.cm. and play an essentially conservative role once they attain a
certain level of power.
The ascendency of those who control capital, the emergent bourgeoisie,
develops progressively from the opening of the sixteenth century onwards.
Tbe in1Iux of gold and silver produces a sharp increase in prices. This acts to
oller large profits in trade and manufacturing, but is a source of ruination to
the great landlords. and swells the number of wage-labourers. The fruit of all
this in the political sphere is the first English revolution, which is one moment
in a rapid extension of state power. The developing mechanisms of centralised
administration and consolidated political power are used • to hasten, hot-
house fashion. the process of transformation of the feudal mode of pro-
duction into the capitalist mode, and to shorten the transition '.10
Not a great deal is known, even today. of the specific origins of the first
capitalists. and Marx has little in the way of concrete historical material to
oller on this matter. He does indicate. however, that there are two contrast-
ing historical modes of progression into capitalist production. The first is
where a segment of the merchant class moves over from purely trading
operations to take a direct hand in production. This occurred in the early
development of capitalism in Italy, and is the main source of recruitment of
capitalists in England in the late fifteenth and early sixteenth centuries. How-
ever. this form of capitalist formation soon becomes • an obstacle to a real
capitalist mode of production and declines with tbe development of the
latter '.11 The second avenue of capitalist development is, according to Marx.
I the really revolutionary way'. Here individual producers themselves accu-
mulate capital. and move from production to expand the sphere of their
activities to include trade. They therefore from the very beginning operate
Outside the guilds and in conflict with them. While Marx gives only a few
hints of how this second mode of development occurs in manufacture. he
35
36 Part 1: Marx
6 GI, p. 51.
7 Gru, p. 22.
s ct. W. Wesolowski: • Marx's theory of class domination: an attempt at systematisa-
tion', in Nicholas Lobkowicz: Marx and the Western World (Notre Dame, 1967),
pp. 54-5. On the problem of He"schaft in Weber's writings, see below, p. 156.
9 • no credit is due to me for discovering the existence of classes in modem society. nor
yet the struggle between them.' Letter to Weydemeyer. March 1852, Selected
Correspondellce. p. 57. cf. Stanislaw Ossowski: Class and C/tJSS Structure in the
Social Consciouslless. London, ]963, pp. 69-88 and pas;im.
The relotions of production and class structure 37
meaniog for granted. It is an irony which has frequently been noted that the
manuscripts which Marx left at his death should have broken off at the point
at which he was entering upon a systematic analysis of the concept of class. 10
Here. for the first time in his writings. he explicitly poses the question. • what
constitutes a class? ' But what Marx says, before the manuscript ends. is
mainly negative. Class must not be identified with either source of income or
functional position in the division of labour. These criteria would yield a
large plurality of classes: doctors, who receive their income from treatment
of the sick. would be a separate class from farmers. who derive theirs from
cultivation of land. etc. Moreover. use of such criteria would cut across the
position of groupings of individuals in the productive process: two men may.
for instance. both be builders, but one may be the propertyless employee of
a large finn. while the other owns a small business of his own.
Marx's emphasis that clas~es are not income groups is a particular as~t
of his FDeraJ premise. stated in Capital. that the distribution of economic
goods is not a sphere separate to and independent of production, but is
determined by tbe mode of production. Marx rejects as • absurd' the con-
tention made by John Stuart Mill. and many of the political economists, that
while production is governed by definite laws, distribution is controlled by
(malleable) human institutions.1J Such a view underlies the assumption that
classes are merely inequalities in the distribution of income. and therefore
tbat class conflict can be alleviated or even eliminated altogether by the
introduction of measures which minimise discrepancies between incomes.
For Mm. then, 51~sses are an as~t Q{ ~~ relations otproduction. The
substance of Marx's conception of class is, in spite of the variability of his
terminology. relatively easy to infer from the many scattered references which
Marx makes in the course of different works. Classes are constituted by the
relationship of groupings of individuals to the ownership of private property
in the means of production. This yields a model of class relations which is
basica])y dichotomous: all class societies are built around a primary line of
division between two antagonistic classes, Q.ne dominant and the other sub-
ordinate. 12 In Marx's usage, class of necessity involves a conftict relation.
On more than one occasion. Marx makes this point by linguistic emphasis.
Thus. discussing the position of the peasantry in nineteenth-century France,
Marx comments :
Tho small-holding peasants form a vast mass, the members of which live in similar
conditions but without entering into manifold relations with one another. Their
mode of production isolates them from one another instead of bringing them
into mutual intercourse... In so far as millions of families live under economic
COnditions of existence that separate their mode of life. their interests and their
10 The section on • The classes'. placed at the end of the third volume of Capital
(edited by Engels) (Cap. vol. 3, pp. 862-3). is a mere fragment.
1\ Gru. p. 717.
12 ct. R.alf Dahrendorf: Class and Class Conflict in lUI Industrial Society (Stanford.
1965), pp. 18-27.
38 Part 1: Marx
culture from those of the other classes, and put them in hostile owosition to the
latter, they fonn a class. In 80 far as there is merely a local interconnection among
these small-holding peasants, and the identity of their interests begets no com-
munity, no national bond and no political organisation among them, they do not
form a class. n
In another context. Marx makes a similar point with reference to the
bourgeoisie: capitalists form a class only to the degree that they are forced
to carry on a struggle against another class. Otherwise capitalists -;re. in
economic competition with each other in the pursuit of profit in the market. 14
2D Gru, p. 735.
11 SW, vol. 1. p. 334. 22 eM, p. 135.
40 Part J: Marx
the economy. Private property as such first emerges in the ancient world, but
remains confined to restricted segments of economic life. In the Middle Ages,
property moves through several stages. from feudal landed property, to
corporative moveable property. eventually giving rise to capital invested in
manufacture in the towns. In both ancient society and in the Middle Ages,
property continues to be bound largely to the community. and thus so also
do relationships of class domination. This means that the operations of
political power are still primarily conducted in a diffuse fashion in the
communitas. Modern capitalism, however, is determined by big industry
I
and universal competition. which has cast off all semblance of a communal
institution '.n
The modem state emerges in conjunction with the struggle of the bour-
geoisie against the remnants of feudalism. but is also stimulated by the
demands of the capitalist economy.
To this modern private property corresponds the modern state, which, purchased
gradually by the owners of property by means of taxation, has fallen entirely into
their hands through the national debt, and its existence has become wholly
dependent OD the commercial credit which the owners of property, the bourgeois,
extend to it. as reflected in the rise and fall of state funds OD the stock exchange.~4
The particular form of the state in bourgeois society varies according to
the circumstances in which the bourgeoisie has gained the ascendancy. In
France. for example. the alliance of the bourgeoisie with the absolute
monarchy has stimulated the development of a strongly established official-
dom. In Britain, by contrast. the state represents • an archaic. timeworn and
antiquated compromise between the landed aristocracy. which rules officially,
and the bourgeoisie. which in fact domiruJtes in all the various spheres of civil
society. but not officially '.2S The specific process which has given rise to this
political order in Britain has minimised the importance of bureaucratic
elements in the state.
:Ie GI, p. 473; We, vol. 3, p. 405. See Karl Korsch: Marxismus und Philosophie
(Leipzia. 1930), pp. Ss-67.
3S G,u, p. 7. This, of course, is basically a transmuted Hegelian standpoint. As LuUcs
remarks, for Marx • the present must be correctly undentood in order for the
31 history of previous times to be adequately grasped .. .o, De, juftge Hegel, p. 130.
GI, p. 52.
44 Part 1: Marx
until • class domination in general ceases to be the form in which the social
order is organised, that is to say, as soon as it is no longer necessary to
represent a particular interest as general or the .. general interest as It
ruling ',If
Every dominant class lays claim to the universality of the ideology which
legitimates its position of domination. But, aocording to Marx. this does not
entail that the social changes effected by the rise of a new revolutionary class
to dominance are equivalent in different types of society, While Marx does
set out an overall schema in terms of which every process of revolutionary
changes shares common characteristics, he also holds that the forms of
revolutionary transformation found in history differ in certain crucially
important respects. The overall schema which Marx employs in the analysis
of revolutionary social change runs as follows. In any relatively stable society,
there exists an equilibrium between the mode of production, the social rela-
tions which are integral to that mode of production. and the • superstructure '
which, through the medium of class domination. is tied in with it. When pro-
gressive changes occur in the sphere of productive activity - such as happened
in Rome with the emergence of manufacture and commerce within a pre-
dominantly agrarian economy - a tension is set up between these new pro-
ductive forces and the existing relations of production. The existing relations
of production then increasingly form barriers to the emergent forces of pro-
duction. These • contradictions' become expressed as overt class confiicts,
terminating in revolutionary struggles fought out in the political sphere. and
manifest ideologically as a clash between competing • principles '. The out-
come of these struggles is either • the common ruin of the contending classes "
as in Rome, or • a revolutionary reconstitution of society at large', as
occurred in the supersession of feudalism by capitalism. ae The class engaging
in a revolutionary struggle for power fights in the name of absolute human
rights, presenting its ideas as 'the only rational, universally valid ones '.31
While only one subordinate class stands to gain from the revolutionary over-
throw of the existing dominant class, it may invoke the aid of others to assist
its movement to power: the French bourgeoisie, for instance, made its revolu-
tion in 1789 with the aid of the peasantry, Once the revolutionary class has
acceded to power, its erstwhile revolutionary character becomes transposed
into a defence of the existing order, i.e., of its own hegemony:
it is in the interest of the ruling section of society to sanction the existing order
as law and to perpetuate its habitually and traditionally fixed limits as legal ones.
Aside from all other matters, this comes about of itself in proportion as the con-
tinuous reproduction of the foundation of the existing order of the relations
corresponding to it gradually assumes a regulated and orderly form. And such
regulation and order are themselves indispensable elements of any mode of pro-
1 Only the first volume of Capital was published in Marx's life-time. but Marx worked
on all three volumes simultaneously. Volumes 2 and 3 were edited and published
by Engels in ]1185 and 1894 respectively. In the preface to the first volume, Marx
speaks of a projected fourth volume. to deal with • the history of theory '. Notes
for this work were published by Kautsky between 19()5 and 1910, as Theorien jiber
den Mehrwen. Sections from this have been translated into English as Theories of
Surplus Value. ed. Bonner &. Bums (London. 1951). Two volumes of a fuIJ English
translation have appeared (London. vol. 1. 1964; vol. 2. 1969).
2 Contribution to the Critique of Political Econtmry, p. 20.
3 Whenever Marx speaks of • value' without qualification. he means' exchange-value'.
• For an account of the development of the labour theory of value, see Ronald L.
Meek: Studies in the Labour Theory of Value (London. 1956).
46
The theory of capitalist development 47
derived from use-value. This can be shown by the example of the exchange-
value of two commodities such as com and iron. A given quantity of corn is
worth a specifiable quantity of iron. The fact that we can express the worth of
these two products in terms of each other, and in quantified form. shows that
we are using some common standard which is applicable to both. This com-
mon measure of value has nothing to do with the physical properties of com
or iron, which are incommensurate. Exchange-value must then rest upon
some quantifiable characteristic of labour. There are obviously many differ-
ences between specific kinds of labour: the actual tasks involved in the work
of growing corn are very different from those involved in manufacturing iron.
lust as exchange-value abstracts from the specific characteristics of com-
modities. and treats them in abstract quantitative ratio. in the derivation of
exchange-value we have to consider only , abstract general labour'. which
can be measured in terms of the amount of time expended by the worker in
the production of a commodity.
Abstract labour is the basis of exchange-value. while 'useful labour' is
the basis of use-value. The two aspects of commodities are simply an expres-
sion of the dual character of labour itself - as labour power. the physical ex-
penditure of the energy of the human organism. something common to all
forms of productive activity; and as a definite kind of labour, a specific set of
operations into which this energy is channelled, something peculiar to the
production of particular commodities for specific uses.
On the one hand all labour is, speaking physiologically, an expenditure of human
labour power, and in its character as similar or as abstract human labour it creates
the value of commodities. On the other hand, all labour is the expenditure of
human labour power in a special form and with a definite aim, and in this, its
character of concrete usefulla;bour, it produces use·valu~?
• Abstract labour' is an historical category, since it is only applicable to com-
modity production. Its existence is predicated upon what are, for Marx. some
of the intrinsic characteristics of capitalism. Capitalism is a far more fluid
system than any which preceded it, demanding that the labour force should
be highly mobile. and adaptable to different kinds of work; as Marx puts it,
• "labour in general ", labour sans phrase. the starting-point of modern poli-
tical economy. becomes realised in practice '.6
There is an obvious problem which presents itself if abstract labour is to
be measured in terms of units of time as the mode of calculating exchange-
value. It would appear to follow from this that an idle worker, who takes a
long while to produce a given item, would produce a more valuable commo-
dity than an industrious man completing the same task in a shorter time. T
into simple labour. it is necessary to assess the amount of labour (expended on his
own part and by those who train him) which goes into the training procedure. But,
in Marx's view. capitalism eventually tends to do away with skilled labour in any
case, through progressive mechanisation. cf. Paul M. Sweezy: T"~ T"~ory 0/
Capitalist D~l'elopmenl (New York, 1954), pp. 42-4.
, As an example of the impact of techr.ological change in this direction, Marx cites
the case of the English clothing industry. Here the introduction of power looms
reduced by something like fifty per cent the labour time necessary to weave yarn
into cloth. Of course a hand weaver still needed the same amount oC time as before .
• but the product of one hour of his individual labour represented aftcr the change
only one-half an hour's social labour, and consequently fell to one-half its former
value '. Cap. vol. I. p. 39: W~. vol. 23. p. 53.
• Cup. vol. I. pp. 50811.
10 SW. vol. I. pp. 84ff.
II Ca". vol. J. pp. \8195. d. Mt!ck. p. 178. I~ Cup. ve.l .. p. 191.
The theory of capitalist development 49
necessary labour lime embodied in them.13 Marx rejects the notion that capi-
talists derive their profits from any sort of dishonesty or deliberate underhand
dealing. Although in actual buying or selling transactions a particular capita-
list might make money by taking advantage of the vagaries of the market.
such as a sudden increase in demand for his product. the existence of profit
in tbe economy as a whole cannot be explained in this way. On the average.
Marx holds. the capitalist buys labour. and sells commodities, at their real
value. As he puts it. the capitalist' must buy his commodities at their value.
must sell them at their value, and yet at the end of the process must withdraw
more value from circulation than he threw into it at starting '.14
This apparent paradox is resolved by Marx with reference to that historical
condition which is the necessary basis of capitalism, the fact that workers are
• free' to sell their labour on the open market. What this signifies is that lao
bour power is itself a commodity. which is bought and sold on the market.
Thus ltS value is determined like that of any other commodity. by the labour
lime socially necessary for its production. Human labour power involves the
expenditure of physical energy. which must be replenished. To renew the
energy expended in labour. the worker must be provided with the require-
ments of his existence as a functioning organism - food. clothing. and shelter
for himself and his family. The labour time socially necessary to produce the
necessities of life of the worker is the value of the worker's labour power. The
latter's value is. therefore. reducible to a specifiable quantity of commodities:
those which the worker requires to be able to subsist and reproduce. • The
worker exchanges with capital his labour itself ... he aliellates it. The price he
receives is the value of this alienation.' 1.1
The conditions of modem manufacturing and industrial production allow
the worker to produce considerably more, in an average working day. than is
necessary to cover the cost of his subsistence. Only a proportion of the work-
ingday. that is, needs to be expended to produce the equivalent of the worker's
own value. Whatever the worker produces over and above this is surplus
value. If. say, the length of the working day is ten hours. and if the worker pro-
duces the equivalent of his own value in half that time. then the remaining five
hours' work is surplus production. which may be appropriated by the capita-
list. Marx calls the ratio between necessary and surplus labour the' rate of
surplus value' or the' rate of exploitation '. The rate of surplus value. as with
all of Marx's concepts. has a social rather than a biological reference. The
labour time necessary to • produce labour power' cannot be defined in purely
physical terms. but has to be ascertained by reference to culturally expected
standards of living in a society. 'Climalic and physical conditions' have an
I~ This statement is only true given the simplified model Marx employs in volume 1 of
Capital; in the real world there is often considerable divergence between values and
prices.
14 Cap, vol. I. p. 166.
I .. Grn. pp. 27(}--1.
50 Part J: Marx
influence. but only in conjunction with' the conditions under which, and con-
sequently on the habits and degree of comfort in which. the class of ·free la-
bourers has been formed ' '6
Surplus value is the source of profit. Profit is. so to speak, the visible' sur-
face' manifestation of surplus value; it is • a converted form of surplus value.
a form in which its origin and the secret of its existence are observed and ex-
tinguished '.11 The analysis which Marx offers in the first volume of Capital
sets out to remove this disguise, and does not discuss the actual relationship
between surplus value and profit. which in the empirical world is a compli-
cated one. The amount the capitalist has to spend on hiring labour is only one
part of the capital outlay he has to make in the productive process. The other
part consists in the machinery, raw materials. maintenance of factory fittings.
etc.• necessary for production. That segment of capital laid out on such mat-
ters is 'constant capital " while that spent on wages is' variable capital '. Only
variable capital creates value; constant capital' does not. in the process of
production. undergo any quantitative alteration of value·. 18 In contrast to the
rate of surplus value. which is the ratio of surplus value to variable capital
(s/v). the rate of profit can only be calculated with reference to both variable
and constant capital. The ratio of constant to variable capital constitutes the
• organic composition' of capital; since the rate of profit depends upon the
organic composition of capital, it is lower than the rate of surplus value. The
rate of profit is given by the formula p=s/c+v: the lower the ratio of expen-
diture on constant capital to that on variable capital. the higher the rate of
profit. 11
In the third volume of Capital. Marx relates the simplified theory of surplus
value presented in volume I to actual prices. It is clear that, in the real world.
the organic composition of capital varies widely from industry to industry. In
some sectors of production. the amount of constant capital involved is far
higher in relation to variable capital than in other sectors: for example. an-
nual capital outlay on machinery and plant equipment in the iron and steel
industry is much greater than it is in the clothing industry. Following the sim-
plified model advanced in the first volume of Capital. this would lead to
widely divergent rates of surplus value. and if profit were directly correlative
to surplus value. would lead to marked variations in profits between different
sectors of the economy. But such a state of affairs. except on a short-term
basis. would be incompatible with the organisation of the capitalist economy
in which capital always tends to flow into those channels which offer the
highest levels of profit.
20 It is upon the relationship between values and prices that most criticism of Marx's
economics has centred. cf Paul Sweezy: BiJhm-Bawerk's Criticism of Marx (New
York. 1949). Two recent discussions of Marx's economics are Murray Wolfson:
A RC'(/ppraisal 01 M(/rximl Ecorlomics (New York. 1964); anJ Fred M. GOllheil:
Marx's Ecorlomic PH'die/iurlS (Evanston, 19(j6).
21 Cap. vol. ~, p. 192; WI', vul. 25. p. 206.
52 Pari J: Marx
skills to unskilled work which allows workers to move from job to job with-
out difficulty. The development of the average rate of profit is thus intrinsi-
cally bound up with the economic structure of capitalist production.
Marx continues to stress that the theory of surplus value presented in the
first volume of Capital underlies the analysis given in volume 3. However
complicated the relationship between prices and value may be, the former
nevertheless rest upon the latter, and any increase or decrease in the total
surplus value will affect prices of production. Most of the subsequent criticism
of Marx's position offered by economists has centred upon the fact that pre-
diction of prices is extremely difficult u!iing Marx's theory, since the connec-
tion between values and prices is so convoluted. But it must be emphasised
that, from Marx's standpoint, such prediction is of secondary importance:
the whole weight of his theory is towards setting out the principles which
underlie the operation of the capitalist economy. Marx's analysis moves upon
the level of an attempt to undercut the influence which physical categories
such as prices, rents, or rates of interest have in the theory of political
economy, in order to expose the social relationships which lie at the root of
them. As he expresses it,
The social character of activity, the social form of the product, and of the parti-
cipation of the individual in production, appear as alienated, reified (sachlich) in
relation to the individual .. Universal exchange of actiyities and products, which
has become the condition of existence of, and the mutual connection between,
particular individuals. take the form of a thing, alienated from and independent
of themselves.22
Marx's theory of capitalist development is founded upon the nature of
capitalist expropriation as set out in the theory of surplus value. The general
tenor of Marx's argument is that, while capitalism is originally structured
around a free-market system in which commodities are allowed to ' find their
own values' on the basis of individual entrepreneurial initiative, the im-
manent tendency of capitalist production undermines the empirical condi-
tions upon which the capitalist economy is based.
24 Cap, vol. 3, p. 230. d. also Sweezy: Theory of Capitalist Development, pp. 98ff.
54 Pari J: Marx
!>ible, it follows from Marx's general analysis that wages are basically deter-
mined by marked forces, not by coercive restrictions on the part of capitalists.
The periodic crises which regularly occur in capitalism are, for Marx, the
most evident manifestation of the internal 'contradictions' of the capitalist
system. Marx did not. however. write a systematic discussion of the nature of
crises. taking the view that crises are the end-result of various possible com-
binations of factors, and ar~ not to be explained in terms of any simple causa-
tive process. He makes no attempt to trace the multiple chains of causation
which actually precipitate crises: such a task could only be accomplished
against the background of the general movements of capitalist production. 23
Marx's analysis is thus limited to an account of the basic factors in the capi-
talist economy which underlie its propensity to regular crises.
Where commodity production exists in forms of society prior to capitalism.
particularly before the widespread use of money. it involves fairly direct bar-
tering between individuals or groups who were generally aware of each other's
needs, and who produced for those needs. In primitive forms of commodity
production. in other words. exchange is controlled in the interests of use-
values. and knowledge of wants furnishes a source of regulation connecting
supply and demand. But as commodity production becomes more and more
widespread, that is, as capitalism develops. this regulative tie is broken. The
use of money plays an important part in this, allowing the parties to exchange
transactions to act autonomously to a far greater degree than is possible in
barter. Capitalism is thus in an important sense an ' anarchic' system,26 be-
cause the market is not regulated by any definite agency relating production
to consumption. It is also an intrinskally expanding system. the basic motor
of which is the restless search for profit. Since the profit motive is dominant,
any state of affairs involving a pronounced imbalance between the volume of
commodities produced and their saleability at the average rate of profit, con-
stitutes a crisis for the system. Capitalism is the first system in human history
where a large volume of overproduction is possible. This is, of course, only
overproduction in terms of the requisites of the capitalist economy, overpro-
duction in terms of exchange-values and not use-values: the commodities
which are' unsaleable ' could normally be made use of. But whenever a suffi-
cient level of return on investment is not made, the modus operandi of capi-
talism is undermined. Production becomes restricted to a fraction of its
potential in spite of the fact that' not enough is produced to satisfy. in a
decent and humane fashion, the wants of the great mass '.2:
25 Theorit's 0/ Surplus Value, cd. Bonner & Burns, pp. 376-91.
26 This does not mean there is r;ot • order' in the operations of the market, but simply
that the principles which govern the market operate outside of men's own conscious
control. as if regulated by, in Adam Smith's famous phrase, • an invisible hand '.
21 Cap, vol. 3, p. 252; see also Marx's note on the • contradictions' between the worker's
position as producer, and his position as consumer. Cap, vol. 2, p. 316. Marx rejects
the more naive • underconsumptionist' theories of his day. See his remarks on
Rodbertus. cap. vol. 2, pp. 410-11.
The theory of capitalist development SS
A crisis is simply an expansion of production beyond what the market can
absorb and still return an adequate rate of profit. Once overproduction occurs,
even only in one segment of the economy, it can set into motion a vicious circle
of reactions. As the rate of profit falls, investment declines, part of the labour
force has to be laid off, which further diminishes consumer purchasing power,
producing another decline in the rate of.profit, and so on. The spiral continues
until unemployment has increased to such a degree, and the wages of those
still in work has been forced down to such a level. that there exist new condi-
tions for the creation of an increased rate of surplus value, and thereby a
stimulus to the resumption of investment. During the crisis, some of the less
efficient enterprises will have gone out of business; those remaining can there-
fore take over their share of the market, and are in a position to begin a new
period of expansion. Thus the cycle is renewed, and another upward phase
gets under way.
Crises therefore do not represent a • break-down • of the capitalist system.
but on the contrary form the regulating mechanism which enables the system
to survive the periodic fluctuations to which capitalism is subject. The effect
of a crisis is to restore equilibrium. and make further growth possible. As
Marx expresses it, crises are' momentary and forcible solutions of the existing
contradictions. They are violent eruptions which for a time restore the dis-
turbed equilibrium.' 28 Since the tendency of the rate of profit to decline is
ever present, there is in any case a pressure upon profits at all stages of capi-
ta'list development. The effect of a crisis is to further the centralisation of
capital, temporarily consolidating the system. 2 ' Crises are endemic in capi-
talism, because while the whole impetus of capitalist production is towards
• an unconditioned development of the productive forces of society', the
relations of production, founded upon an exploitative class relationship, are
organised around the expansion of capital alone. Thus Marx reaches his
famous conclusion:
The real barrier of capitalist production is capital itself. It is that capital and its
self-extension appear as the starting and closing point, as the motive and the pur-
pose of production; that production is merely production for capital, and not V«:e
versa, the means of production the means for a constant expansion of the Iife-
process of the society of producers. 30
31 CM. p. 33; We. vol. 4. pp. 467-8. The nearest Marx comes to this is in Gru. p. 636.
32 Cap. vol. 2. p. 411.
33 This analysis, given in volume 1 of Capital. is in terms of the simplified model of
s.
35
value.
Cap, vol. I, p. 632.
It is an undeniable fact that living standards {or the great majority of the working
population have risen in the capitalist societies of western Europe and the USA
over the past one hundred years. There is a theoretical point here of some im·
portance, which bas been noted by various critics. According to Marx's own theory,
The theory of capitalist development 57
tWO themes in Marx's discussion which have to be distinguished, and it is the
tenaency to assimilate these into a single 'prediction' concerning the living
standards of the working class which underlies the common misreading of
Marx on this matter. One of these themes concerns the theory that the course
of capitalist development is characterised by increasing relative disparily be-
tween the earnings of the working class and the income of the capitalist
class; the second is that the development of capitalism produces a Jarger and
larger reserve army, the majority of which are forced to live in extreme
poverty. These two trends are bound up with one another, since it is the
existence of the' relative surplus population' which prevents wages from ris-
ing far above their value. But the confusion of the two has led to the quite un-
warranted conclusion that Marx believed that the whole body of the working
class would increasingly become depressed into increasingly severe physical
poverty. Marx speaks of the ' increasing exploitation' of the worker as capi-
talism proceeds, but it is clear that the rate of eltploitation (rate of surplus
value) can increase without necessarily entailing any change in the rea! wages
of the majority of the working class." With regard to the increasing relative
disparity between the earnings of labour and capital, Marx's main thesis is
simply, jn accord with the general theory of surplus value advanced in Capi-
tal, that while the capitalist class accumulates more and more wealth, the
wages of the working class can never rise far above subsistence levePT What
Marx does specify as the consequences of capitalism for the working class as
a whole in Capital involves reference to the alienating effects of the division
of labour, which serve to • mutilate the worker into a fragment of a man, de-
grade him to the level of an appendage of a machine. destroy the content of
work by his agony, and alienate (entfremden) him from the spiritual potentia-
lities of the labour-process .. .'.31
It is, however, the increase in the' relative mass of the industrial reserve
army' which produces an extension of chronic pauperism; Marx calls this the
• absolute general law of capitalist accumulation " noting that' like all other
laws it is modified in its working by many circumstances '. Pauperism is the
• hospital of the active labour-army and the dead weight of the industrial re-
profits show a tendency to decline; now if it happens that the ratc of surplus value
remains the same, rising productivity must produce an increase in the real wages of
labour. Robinson argues: • Marx can only demonstrate a falling tendency in profits
by abandoning his argument that real wages tend to be constant,' Joan Robinson:
An Essay on Marxian Economics (London, 1966), p. 36.
3& If prOductivity increases. But see note 35, above.
37 Marx makes the point that, even under those conditions of rapid capitalist expansion
which are most favourable to the working class, increases in wages never do more
than parallel increased profits; thus even when standards of living of the working
class rise during a period of boom in the economy, those of the capitalist class rise
equally, maintaining the differential. SW, vol. I, pp. !l4-8.
31 Cap, vol. I, p. 645; We, vol. 23, p. 674.
58 Part 1: Marx
serve army'. 3' Most of the worst forms of material exploitation are concen-
trated in this latter group, among whom there develops an • accumulation of
misery, agony of labour, slavery, ignorance, brutality, moral degradation .. .'.•0
Thus the contrawctory character of capitalism manifests itself in the accumu-
lation of wealth' at one pole " and of poverty and misery at the other.
39 Cap, vol. 1. p. 644. Capitalism' overworks a part of the labouring population and
keeps the other part as a reserve army, half or entirely pauperised '. Theories of
SlIrpllls Value. ed. Bonner & Bums, p. 352.
40 Cap, vol. 1. p. 645; We, vol. 23. p. 675.
41 Cap, vol. 1. p. 625 .
• , Cap. vol. 1. p. 626.
The theory of capitalist development S9
interest levied on loans; but because it develops the ground for the centralised
co-ordination of the economy. the credit system' will serve as a powerful lever
during the transition from the capitalist mode of production to the mode of
production of associated labour.• : .•3
The expansion of the credit system goes hand in hand with a particular
fonn of centralisation of corporate capital: that represented in the develop-
ment of joint-stock companies. This is the type of industrial organisation, ac-
cording to Marx. which is most compatible with large-scale centralisation,
and it represents • the ultimate development of capitalist production '. The
joint-stock company, which serves to effect a separation between the in-
dividual capitalist and the productive organisation, represents' the abolition
of the capitalist mode of production within the capitalist mode of production
itself '.u The separation between the owners of capital and the managers de-
monstrates the superfluousness of the former group, who now play no direct
part in the productive process. In the joint-stock company, the social charac-
ter of production has become apparent, and hence exposes as a • contradic-
tion' the fact that a few individuals are able, through their Own ownership of
capital, to appropriate much of the wealth that is produced. Nevertheless, the
joint-stock company is only a transitional fonn since, as it is still connected
with interest-bearing capital, it continues to be . ensnared in the boundaries
of capitalism '. Moreover, the development of very large companies of this
sort can lead to monopoly control of particular sectors of industry, creating a
basis for various kinds of new exploitative relationships.45
Capital shows in detail that, as in the case of the society which preceded it
in western European history, capitalism is an inherently unstable system.
built upon antagonisms than can only be resolved through changes which
eventually undermine it. These contradictions derive first of all from its class
character: from the asymmetrical relation!;hip between wage-labour and
capital. The operation of the capitalist mode of production inevitably drives
the system towards its dissolution. Here again Marx speaks of the Aufhebung
of capitalism; the historical tendency towards the' abolition' of the capitalist
mode of production must not be thought of as the wholesale destruction of
capitalism. so that socialism has to 'stllrt anew'. On the contrary, the immi-
nent trend of movement of the capitalist system generates the social condi-
tions which provide for its dialectical transcendence.
In these terms, the question of the' inevitability' of the revolution poses
no • epistemological' (as opposed to • practical,) problems. The process of
C3 The preceding four quolc"\lions arc all from Cap, vol. 3. p. S93.
44 Cap, vol. 3, p. 429.
U In the shape of • a new financial aristocracy, a new variety of parasites in the shape
of promoters. speculators and simply nominal directors; a whole system of swindling
lind cheating by means of corporation promotion, stock issuan.:e, and stock specula-
tion '. This is 'private production without the control of private property'. Cap.
vol. 3. p.429.
60 Part J: Marx
development of capitalism engenders the objective social changes which, in
inter-relationship with the growing class-awareness of the proletariat, creates
tbe active consciousness necessary to transform society through revolutionary
Praxis." The relative poverty of tbe mass of the working class, the physical
misery of the' reserve army'. and the rapid diminution in wages and upsurge
of unemployment which occur in crises. all provide a growing reservoir of
revolutionary potential. The industrial system itself provides a source of per-
ception of community of interest, and a basis for collective organisation. since
tbe factory concentrates large numbers of workers together in one place,
Workers' organisations begin on a local level. but eventually merge to form
national units. The self-consciousness of the proletariat expands progres-
sively along with the undermining of the position of the entrepreneurial capi-
talist by the centralisation and concentration of capital. The conjunction of
these circumstances makes possible the achievement of socialist society.
The whole corpus of Marx's writings contains no mOre than fragmentary
or passing references to the nature of the society which will supplant capita-
lism. In separating his own position from that of ' utopian' socialism, Marx
refuses to offer a comprehensive plan for the society of the future. The new
social order. as the dialectical transcendence of capitalism. will be organised
according to principles which can only be vaguely glimpsed by tbose who live
in the present form of society. The construction of detailed plans of the future
society is an enterprise which relapses into philosophical idealism, because
such schemes have no reality save in the mind of the thinker. Consequently,
most of what Marx does have to say about the new society concerns the stage
of its initial formation. in which it is ' still stamped with the birth marks of the
old society from whose womb it emerges '.4T
46 See Georg Lukacs: Geschichre WId Klasullhe","sstsein (Berlin, 1932), pp. 229ff.
t' SW. vol. 2. p. 23.
4R cr. Avineri, pp. 22(}-39. However. it is a mistake to identify too closely, as Avineri
does. Marx's early di;cussioD of . crude communism' with the later treatment of the
transitional stage in the abolition of bourgeois society. Marx's discussion of the
transitional stage is prospective, whereas • crude communism' is identified in a
retrospective fashion as characteristic of the early stages of socialist theory. Crude
communism is not the theory of the transitional stage.
The theory of capitalist development 61
implicit in capitalism in the shape of the growing centralisation of the market,
is completed by putting an end to private property. In this phase. property
becomes collectively owned. and wages are distributed according to a fixed
principle. Out of the total social product, certain amounts are allocated to
cover collective needs of the administration of production, the running of
schools, health facilities, and so on; while each worker
receives back from society - after the deductions have been made - exactly what
he gives to it ... He receives a certificate from society that he has furnished such
and such an amount of labour (after deducting from his labour for the common
funds), and with this certificate he draws from the social stock of means of con-
sumption as much as costs the same amount of labour.· 9
Such a social reorganisation, however, still preserves the underlying prin-
ciples of bourgeois society. since it continues to assess human relationships in
terms of an objective standard. In other words, it preserves the treatment of
labour as an exchange value, but instead of this being confined to a class
group (the proletariat), this now becomes universalised. At this stage, men
are still • regarded only as workers and nothing more is seen in them, every-
thing else being ignored' ,n: • The role of worker is not abolished. but is ex-
tended to all men. The relation of private property remains the relation of
the community to the world of things.' 51 This stage preserves a society in
which the subject is dominated by the object, in which alienation is still con-
fused with objectification.
What is true of production also holds for the sphere of politics. Here again,
Marx's most important discussions span the whole length of his career: the
analysis given in the' Critique of the Gotha Programme' complements that
developed in the early critical evaluation of Hegel's treatment of the state.
That the substance of Marx's views is the same in both of these sources is
indicated by his attack upon the call for the • freeing of the basis of the State'
embodied in the Gotha Programme. Marx's criticism here takes the form of a
repetition of the main point made over thirty years earlier in relation to Hegel.
The state is already almost perfectly' free' in Germany, Marx points out:
the objective of the workers' movement must not be to • free' the state from
society, but on the contrary to convert the state' from an organ superimposed
upon society into one completely subordinate to it. . .'."2 However, the tran-
Sitionill phase following the initial abolition 0f capitalism will again involve
the full realisation of the principles only partially or imperfectly developed in
hourgeois society itself. The ' dictatorship of the proletariat' constitutes this
intermediate stage, and represents a concentration of the political power
Which already exists in a more diffuse manner in bourgeois society. This
makes possible the implementation of the programme of the centralisation of
Production and distribution outlined previously: 'The proletariat will use
65
66 Part 2: Durkheim
~ The publication of The Origin of Species was also regarded by Marx and Engels a~
an event of major significance, offering a direct parallel to their own interpretation
of social development. Marx wrote to Darwin offering to dedicate the first volume of
Capital to him. (Darwin declined the offer.)
S Durkheim: review of Albert Schaff!e: Bau und Leben des Socialen Korpers (2nd.
ed.); (the review covers only vol. 1 (If Schiiff!e's work). RP, vol. 19, 1885, pp. 84-101.
ct. my article: • Durkheim as a review critic " Sociological Review, vol. 18, 1970.
pp. 171-96. which I have drawn upon for part of this chapter.
Durkheim's early works 67
procedure, because SchafHe does not attempt in a direct sense to deduce the
properties of social organisation from those of organic life. On the CO:ltrary.
Scbidle insists that the use of biological concepts represents nothing more
than a • metaphor' which can facilitate sociological analysis.
In fact, Durkheim points out approvingly. SchafHe insists that there exists
a radical and highly significant discrepancy between the life of the organism
and that of society. Whereas the life of the animal organism is governed
'mechanically'. society is bound together' not by a material relation, but by
the ties of ideas '.' The notion of ' society as the ideal '. Durkheim stresses,
occupies a focal place in Schaffle's thought. and is entirely consistent with
the latter's emphasis that society has its own specific properties which are
separable from those of its individual members. For Schaffie, , Society is not
simply an aggregate of individuals, but is a being which has existed prior to
those who today compose it, and which will survive them; which influences
them more than they influence it, and which has its own life, consciousness
(ccmscience), its own interests and destiny '.7 Schaffle thus rejects the concep-
tion of the individual and society given primacy by Rousseau, in which the
hypothetical 'isolated individual' in a state of nature is freer and happier
than when bonded to society. On the contrary, everything that makes human
life higher than the level of animal existence is deri ved from the accumulated
cultural and technological wealth of society. If this be removed from man,
• then you will have removed at the same time. all that makes us truly
human'.'
The ideals and sentiments which constitute the cultural inheritance of the
members of a society are • impersonal " that is, they are socially evolved, and
are neither the product nor the property of any specific individuals. This is
easily shown by reference to the example of language: • each of us speaks a
language which he did not create '. t Schaffie shows, Durkheim continues, that
to treat the conscience collective as having properties which are not the same
as those of the individual consciousness does not imply anything meta-
physical. lo The conscience collective is simply' a composite, the elements of
which are individual minds'. 11
SchafHe's work, together with that of other German authors, according to
Durkheim. manifests the important advances being made in social thought in
Germany - a state of affairs contrasting heavily with the retarded develop-
, Review of Schiffie, p. 85. Quotations are from Durkheim. For Durkheim's views OD
the usefulness of organic analogies in sociology, see my article quoted above, pp.
179-80.
7 Review of Schaffie, p. 84. • Ibid. p. 87.
• Ibid. p. 87.
10 Ibid. pp. 99ft. I have followed the usual practice of leaving Durkbeim's phrase
conscience collective un translated. There is a definite ambiguity in the term which
overlaps with both the English words, • consciousness' and • conscience '.
11 Review of SchafHe. p. 92. Durkheim nevertheless criticises Schaffie for sometimes
relapsing into idealism.
68 Part 2: Durkheim
ment of sociology in France .• Thus sociology. which is French by origin, is
becoming more and more a German science.' 12
In his long survey of • positive moral science' in Germany. published in
1887. Durkheim reiterates some of these points. 13 But the main concern of
this article is to examine the contributions which leading German authors
have made towards founding a science of moral life. 14 In France. Durkheim
asserts. only two broad forms of ethical theory are known - Kantian idealism
on the one hand. and utilitarianism on the other. The recent works of the
German social thinkers. however. have begun to establish - or rather, to
re-establish, since some of their notions were previously stated by Comte -
ethics on a scientific footing. This approach. Durkheim states, has been
worked out primarily by economists and jurists, among whom the most
important are Wagner and Schmoller. 15 The work of these two authors, as
Durkheim describes it, differs considerably from that of orthodox economists.
Orthodox economic theory is built upon individualistic utilitarianism, and is
ahistorical: • In other words, the major laws of economics would be exactly
the same even if neither nations nor states had existed in the world: they
suppose only the presence of individuals who exchange their products.' 16
But Wagner and Schmoller depart substantially from this standpoint. For
them (as for Scbaffle), society is a unity having its own specific characteristics
which cannot be inferred from those of its individual members. It is false to
suppose 'that a whole is equal to the sum of itS parts t: in so far as these
parts are organised in a definite fashion, then this organisation of relationships
has properties of its own. 17 This principle has to be applied also to the moral
12 Durkheim: review of Ludwig Gumplowicz: Grundriss der Sozioiogie, RP, vol. 20,
1885, p. 627.
U • La science positive de la morale en Allemagne', RP, vd!. 24, 1887, pp. 33··58,
113-42 & 275-84. cf. also' Les etude.; de science sociale', RP, vol. 22, 1886, pp.
61-80.
14 Durkheim usually employs the term • la morale' which is ambiguous in English in
that it can mean either' morality' or • ethics' (i.e. the study of morality). I have
rendered the term variably according to context in quoting from Durkheim.
IS This establishes one of the few points of direct connection between the writings of
Durkheim and Max Weber. Adolf Wagrier and Gustav Schmoller were among the
founders of the Yerein fur Sozialpolitik. of which Weber became a prominent
member. But Weber never accepted that aspect of .the views of Wagner and
SchmoUer which appealed most to Durkheim - their attempt to found a • scientific'
ethics. Weber also questioned the policy of state intervention in the economy, as
advocated by Schmoller in particular.
IS • Science positive de la morale', part I, p. 37.
17 This principle was already well known to Durkheim, through Renouvier. Durkheim
applies it frequently in his writings. As he remarks in a review published much later,
• it is from Renouvier that we took the axiom that a whole is not equal to the sum
of its parts' (Review of Simon Dcploige: Le confl;, de la mQraie et de IQ socioiogie.
AS, vol. 12, 1909-]2, p. 326). Deploigc's work is a scathing attack upon Durkheim's
school from a ThomiSl standpoint. It has been translated into English as Tilt
Conflict between Ethics and Sociology (St Louis. 1938); see esp, pp. IS-18S. Some
of the more important reviews written by Durkheim in the AS have been collected
together as Journal .mciologique (Paris, 1969).
Durkheim's early works 69
rules which men live by in society: morality is a collective property and
l11ust be studied as such. In the theory of orthodox political economy. on the
other hand. ' the collective interest is only a form of personal interest " and
, altrUism is merely a concealed egoism'.18
Schmoller has shown, Durkheim states, that economic phenomena cannot
be adequately studied in the manner of classical economic theory, as if these
were separate from the moral norms and beliefs which govern the life of
individuals in society. There is no society (nor could there conceivably be a
society) where economic relationships are not subject to customary and legal
regulation. That is to say, as Durkheim was later to express the matter in
The Division of Labour, 'a contract is not sufficient unto itself '.IQ If it were
not for the existence of social norms which provide the framework within
which contracts are made, then 'incoherent chaos' would reign in the
economic world. 20 The regulations which control economic life cannot be
explained purely in economic terms: 'One can understand nothing of the
rules of morality which govern property, contract, work, etc., if one does not
know the economic causes which underlie them; and, conversely, one would
arrive at a completely false notion of economic development if one neglected
the moral causes which influenced it.' 21
It is a major achievement of the German thinkers to have shown that moral
rules and actions can and must be studied scientifically, as properties of social
organisation. Here Durkheim sets out a precept which was to form a main
connecting thread of his subsequent writings. Up to the present, philosophers
have assumed that ethics can be based upon a deductive system of abstract
principles. But the work of the German authors has shown that it is funda-
mentally mistaken to proceed in this way, as if human social life could be
reduced to a few intellectually formulated maxims. Rather, we must begin
with reality. which means the study of concrete forms of moral rules com-
prised within definite societies. Here Durkheim again quotes Schlif6.e appre-
ciatively: it is precisely Schaffie's major achievement to have shown that
moral rules are shaped by society. under the pressure of collective needs.
There can be no question. therefore. of assuming that such rules, as they
really operate empirically, can be reduced to a few a priori principles of
which all specific beliefs and actions are merely an expression. Moral facts
are actually • of prodigious complexity': the empirical study of different
Societies shows that there exists a ' steadily increasing multitude of beliefs,
Customs and legal provisions '.22 This diversity is not refractory to analysis;
but only the sociologist, through observation and description, can hope to
classify and to interpret it.
Durkheim devotes a large part of his article on the German thinkers to
2S Ibid. part 2, pp. 116-17. Weber's critical discussion of Wundt appears in GAW,
pp.521f.
24 Ibid. p. 117.
25 Ibid. p. 120.
26 Ibid. p. 129. For another source of information upon Durkheim's earlr views on
religion, ct. his review of Guyau's L'irreligion de I'avenir, RP, vol. 23. IS87, pp.
299-311.
21 It is important to emphasise this point, because most secondary interpreters ha\e
concentrated heavily upon the changes which are presumed to have occurred in
Durkheim's thought over the course of his writings. The most influential analysis of
this sort is given in Talcott Parsons: The Structure of Social Actioll (Glencoe. 1949),
pp. 301-450. For a recent, more simplified statement of the same position, see Jean
Duvignaud: Durklzeim, sa vie, son oeuvre (Paris, 1965), pp. 39-50. A similar theme
is reiterated by Nisbet: Robert A. Nisbet: Emile Dllrkheim (Englewood Cliffs.
1965), esp. p. 37. The effect of this is to minimise the importance of Tire Dj~·jsioll of
Durkheim's early works 71
directly influenced by their writings, and how far alternatively these simply
reinforced conclusions which he had already reached from other sources. The
lauer is the most lik~ly. When criticised, much later on in his life, for having
, imported his ideas wholesale from Germany', Durkheim bluntly denied the
assertion, stating that the influence of Comte was much more profound, and
formed the position from which he evaluated the contributions of the German
authors. 2I The important point is that Durkheim's discussions in the early
writings show that he was conscious, at the outset of his career, of notions
which sometimes have been supposed to have appeared only much later."
Of course, these are only stated in a rudimentary way, or have to be inferred
from Durkheirn's presentation of the views of others. But they include a
consciousness of the following elements: the importance of 'ideals' and
moral unity in the continuity of society 30; the significance of the individual
as an active agent as well as a passive recipient of social influences 31; the
dual nature of the attachment of the individual to society, as involving both
obligation and positive commitment to ideals; the conception that an organ-
isation of units (i.e., individuals as the units of organised societies) has
properties which cannot be directly inferred from the characteristics of the
component units considered in isolation from one another; the essential
foundations of what was to become the theory of anomie u; and the rudiments
of the later theory of religion.
It is important to bear these considerations in mind when evaluating the
This second type of social cohesion is' organic solidarity'. Here solidarity
sIems not simply from acceptance of a common set of beliefs and sentimcnts,
but from functional interdependence in the division of labour. Where
mechanical solidarity is~ main basis of societal cohesion, the conscience
conective 'completely e~elops , the individual consciousness, and therefore
presumes identity between individuals. Organic solidarity. by contrast. pre-
supposes not identity but difference between individuals in their beliefs and
actions. The growth of organic solidarity and the expansion of the division of
labour are hence associated with increasing individualism.
The progression of organic solidarity is necessarily dependent upon the
declining significance of the conscience collective. But commonly held beliefs
and sentiments do not disappear~ogether in complex societ~e~~nor isjt--the,
case that the formation of contrlc1ttal relations becomes amoral and simply
the result of each individual following' his best interest '. Here Durkheim
reverts to the theme previously developed in his first writings. and applied
specifically in criticism of Tonnies' conception of Gesellschaft. Herbert
Spencer is Durkheim's target for critical attack in The Division of LAbour.
but the substance of his polemic is the same. A society in which each indi-
vidual solely pursues his own interest would disintegrate within a short space
of time. 'There is nothing less constant than interest. Today, it unites me to
you; tomorrow, it will make me your enemy.' n It is true, Durkheim admits.
that contractual relations generally multiply with the growth of the division
of labour. But the expansion of contractual relations presupposes the develop-
ment of norms which govern contract; all contracts are regulated by definite
prescriptions. However complex the division of labour. society does not
become reduced to a chaos of short-term contractual alliances. Durkheim here
reiterates the point first made in reference to Tonnies: 'It is thus mistaken to
oppose a society which derives from a community of beliefs to one based on
co-operation. according a moral character only to the first and seeing in the
~econd nothing more than an economic grouping. In reality. co-operation has
lls own intrinsic morality.' 52
Utilitarian theory is unable to account for the basis of moral solidarity in
contemporary societies; and it is also fal1acious as a theory of the causes for
the increase in the division of labour. In the latter form, it attributes the
increase in specialisation to the increase in material wealth which is made
53 Here Durkheim repeats the point made in his earlier article on suicide. See footnoU~
32, p. 71.
U DL, p. 249. In primitive societies•• a man kills himself, not because he judges life
bad, but because the ideal to which he is attached demands the sacrifice' (p. 246).
This is, of course, the type which Durkheim later calls altruistic suicide.
JIJI DL, p. 257.
61 DL. p. 262; DTS. p. 244. Durkheim admits that there are partial exceptions to this:
c.g.• traditional China or Russia. Here' the division of labour is not developed in
proportion to the social volume. In fact, increase in volume is Dot necessarily a
sign of superiority if density does not increase at the same time and in the same
degree .. .' (DL. p. 261; DTS. p. 243).
Durkheim's early works 79
what his original assessment of the relation between physical and dynamic
density.1f But, in fact, it is clear in his statement of it in The Division 01
Labour, that the explanation Durkheim offers is a sociological one: physical
density is important only in so far as it becomes transformed into moral or
dynamiC density, and it is the frequency of social contact which is the
explanatory factor. A more convincing case could be made for the supposition
tbat Durkheim employs a ' biological' explanation in the mode in which he
seeks to analyse conflict as a mechanism, within a quasi-Darwinian frame-
work, which accelerates the progression of the division of labour. Darwin and
other biologists have demonstrated, according to Durkheim, that the struggle
for existence is most acute between organisms of the same type. The existence
of such conflict tends to generate complementary specialisation, such that
organisms can exist side by side without the one hampering the survival of
the other. Differentiation of function allows diverse types of organism to
survive. A similar principle, Durkheim concludes, can be applied to human
society:
Men submit to the same law. In tbe same city, different occupations can co-exist
without being obliged mutuaUy to destroy one another, for they pursue different
objects. The soldier seeks military glory, the priest moral authority, the statesman
power, the businessman riches, the scholar scientific renown.5I
~o DL. p. 172.
&I DL. p. 172; DTS. p. 147.
62 Durkheim seems to have adopted the term . anomie' from Guyau (see note 26.
p. 70). Guyau. however. uses the term • religious anomie' in a sense close to
Durkheim's • cult of the individual '.
Durkheim's early works 81
are not necessarily due to any social superiority, the second has an unjust
advantage over the first at law.' 13
The present situation. in which this does still pertain, is a transitional one.
The progressive decline of inequality of opportunity (' external inequality')
is a definite historical tendency which accompanies the growth of the division
of labour. According to Durkheim. it is easy to see why this should be so. In
primitive society, where solidarity is based primarily upon community of
belief and sentiment, there is neither the means nor the need for the equalisa-
tion of talent and opportunity. But the individualising effects of the division
of labour mean that specific human faculties which previously remained
latent increasingly become capable of actualisation. and thus create a pressure
towards individual self-fulfilment:
we may thus say that the division of labour produces solidarity only if it is spon-
taneous and to the degree that it is spontaneous. But by spontaneity we must
understand not simply the absence of express and overt violence, but of anything
that might, even indirectly, shackle the free employment of the social force that
each person carries in himself. This not only supposes that individuals are not
relegated to particular functions by force, but also that no sort of obstacle what-
soever prevents them from occupying in the social framework the position which
accords with their capacities."
I~ DL, p. 384. For further discussion of Durkhejm's \·jews on this question. see below,
I Pp.229-31.
C DL, p. 377; DTS, p. 370.
6. Durkheim's conception of sociological method
82
Durkheim's conception of sociological method 83
depend upon stably distributed phenomena of a geographical. biological. or
social kind. a In Suicide. Durkheim discusses these first two in some detail.
rejecting both as possible explanations for the distribution of suicide rates. 3
It is. therefore. to the third type of factor. the social. that we must look to
explain the patterns of suicide rates.
The distribution of suicide in the countries of western Europe shows a
close relationship between suicide rates and religious denomination: pre-
dominantly Catholic countries everywhere have lower suicide rates than those
which are mainly Protestant. This consistent differential in suicide rates
cannQt be explained by referent:e to variation in the degree to which suicide
is condemned in the credo of the two denominations; both prohibit suicide
with equal stringency. Its explanation must be sought in differences rooted
more generically in the social organisation of the two churches. The most
obvious dissimilarity between the two, according to Durkheim, is that Pro-
testantism is founded upon the promotion of a spirit of free enquiry. The
Catholic church is formed around the traditional hierarchy of the priesthood.
whose authority is binding in matters of religious dogma; but the Protestant
is alone before God: 'like the worshippers, the priest has no other source
but himself. and his conscience '." Protestantism is, in Durkheim's phrase. a
, less strongly integrated' church than Catholicism.
The inference can be drawn from this thai there is nothing specifically
bound up with religion as such which needs to be invoked to explain the
'preservative effect of Catholicism; in other words. that the degree of
t
2 Virtually all of the statistical relationships between suicide and social phenomena
used by Durkheim in Suicide had been established by previous writen. See my
article, • The suicide problem in French sociology'. British Journal of Sociology.
vol. 16,1965. pp. 3-18. a Su, pp. 57-142.
c Suo pp. 160-1. Anglicanism. Durkheim &dmits, is a panial exception to this; but
England has a lower rate than the other Protestant countries.
~ ]n none of these cases. according to Durkheim. can the drop in suicide rates be
attributed to less precise official documentation of suicide in war-time (Su, pp. 206-8).
84 Part 2: Durklleim
stimulating an increased level of involvement within a definite set of events,
, at least for a time. bring about a stronger integration of society'.'
There is, consequently, a relationship between social integration and suicide
which holds regardless of the particular institutional sector of society which
is analysed: the proposition is established that 'suicide varies in inverse
ratio to the degree of integration of the social groups of which the individual
forms a part '.' Thus this type of suicide may be called' egoistic', and it is
the resultant of a state where' the individual self asserts itself to excess in the
face of the social self and at its expense .. :.- Egoistic suicide is particularly
characteristic of contemporary societies; but it is not the only type of suicide
found there. A second type of suicide springs from the phenomenon which
Durkheim discusses at some length in The Division of Labour: the anomie
state of moral deregulation characterising economic relationships. This is
indexed by the correlation which can be demonstrated between suicide rates
and the occupational structure. Suicide rates, Durkheim points out. are higher
in occupations in industry and commerce than in agricultural occupations.
Moreover, within non-agricultural occupations, suicide rates are inversely
related to socio-economic level, being lowest among the chronically poor, and
highest among the well-to-do and those in the liberal professions. This is
because poverty is in itself a source of moral restraint: it is the occupations
above the lowest levels which have become most freed from stable moral
regulation. The relationship between anomie and suicide can also be demon-
strated in reference to another phenomenon which Durkheim discusses in
The Division of Labour as an outcome of the anomic state of industry: the
occurrence of economic crises. In times of economic depression, suicide rates
show a marked increase. This is not explicable simply in terms of the eco-
nomic deprivation involved, since suicide rates increase to equivalent degree
in times of marked economic prosperity. What both upward and downward
fluctuations in the economic cycle share in common is that each has a dis-
ruptive effect upon accustomed modes of life. Those experiencing either a
sudden downswing or uplift in their material circumstances are placed in a
situation in which their habitual expectations come under strain. An anomie
condition of moral deregulation results.
Anomie is thus, like egoism, ' a constant and specific factor in suicide in
our modem societies; it is one of the sources upon which the annual con-
tingent is nourished '.' Durkheim's discussion of the differences between
egoistic and anomie suicide is not always unambiguous, and this has caused
15 Su, p. 299.
11 • La sociologie en France au XIXe si~c1e', Revue bleue, vol. 13, 1900, p. 649.
Durkheim also says in The Rules that the method stated therein is • of course,
contained by implication in the book which we published recently on The Division
of Labour '. RSM, p. ix.
]7 Su, p. 35.
II Parsons has pointed to an epistemological confusion involved in Durkheim's use
of the phrase social' fact' 35 equivalent t(l social' phenomenon' (Parsons, pp. 41-2).
Durkheim's conception 0/ sociological method 87
here can be elucidated without difficulty. There are two related senses in
which social facts are • external' to the individual. Firstly, every man is born
into an on-going society which already has a definite organisation or struc-
ture, and which conditions his own personality: • the church-member finds
the beliefs and practices of his religious life ready-made at birth; their
existence prior to his own implies their existence outside of himself '.11
Secondly, social facts are • external' to the individual in the sense that any
one individual is only a single element within the totality of relationships
which constitutes a society. These relationships are not the creation of any
single individual, but are constituted of multiple interactions between indi-
viduals. • The system of signs I use to express my thought, the system of
currency I employ to pay my debts, the instruments of credit I utilise in my
commercial relations, the practices followed in my profession, etc., function
independently of my own use of them.' 20 It has often been pointed out that
Durkheim uses the term • individual' here in more than one sense. At times
the context makes it apparent that he is speaking of the (hypothetical)
'isolated individual', the asocial being which forms the starting-point of
utilitarian theory; at other times, Durkheim uses the word to refer to a given
'particular' individual- a flesh-and-blood member of an empirical society.21
But. in fact, for Durkheim's purposes, which are in part polemical, the
distinctions which may be drawn between the various senses of the term
'individual' are not important. The main burden of Durkheim's thesis is that
no theory or analysis which begins from the • individual " either in the two
senses mentioned above or in others, can successfully grasp the specific
properties of social phenomena.
Durkheim's point here, in other words, is a conceptual one. It is true that
this is to some extent obscured by Durkheim's insistence upon talking of
social' facts '; but it should be obvious that the criterion of ' exteriority , is
not an empirical one. If it were, it would lead directly to the ludicrous con-
clusion that society exists externally to all individuals: this is, Durkheim
says, • an obvious absurdity we might have been spared having attributed to
us ',22 Durkheim stresses many times that' society is composed only of
individuals '.21 But a parallel statement can be made of the relationship
between chemical elements and the substances which are composed of com-
binations of them:
What is so readily judged inadmissible in regard to social facts is freely admitted
in the other realms of nature. Whenever any elements combine and thereby pro-
19 RSM, p. 2. 20 RSM, p. 2.
21 d. Harry Alpert: Emile Durkheim and his Sociolog)' (New York, 1939), pp.
135-7; Parsons. pp. 367-8; Guy Aimard: Dllrkheim ella science konomique (paris.
1962). pp. 26-31.
22 Su, p. 320.
23 That is, individuals plus the artifacts which they construct; but physical objects only
have social relevance when there are men in society who attribute some kind of
significance 10 Ihem. RSM. pp. Iff.
88 ParI 2: Durkheim
duce, by the fact of their combination, new phenomena, it is plain that these new
phenomena reside not in the original elements but 'in the totality formed by their
union. The living cell contains nothing but mineral particles, as sooiety contains
nothing but individuals; and yet it is patently impossible for the phenomena
characteristic of life to reside in the atoms of hydrogen. oxygen. carbon and nit-
rogen ... Let us apply this principle to sociology. If, as we may say, this synthesis
sui generis which every society constitutes, yields new phenomena. diJfecing from
those which take place in individual minds, we must, indeed, admit that these
facts reside in the very society itself which produces them, and not in its parts, i.e.,
its members.24
The second criterion which Durkheim applies in specifying the nature of
social facts is an empirical one: the presence of moral.' constraint '. Here it
is best to proceed from an illustration which Durkheim himself offers, the
case of 'fatherhood '. Paternity is in one sense a biological relation: a man
, fathers' a child through the act of procreation. But paternity is also a social
phenomenon: a father is obliged, by convention and law, to act in various
definite ways vis-a-vis his offspring (and. of course, other members of his
family also). These modes of action are not created by the individual in
question, but form part of a system of moral duties in which he is enmeshed
with other men. While an individual might flout such obligations, in doing
so he feels their force and thereby confirms their constraining character:
, Even when I free myself from these rules and violate them successfully, I am
always compelled to struggle with them. When finally overcome, they make
their constraining power sufficiently· felt by the resistance they offer.' 25 This
is, of course, most obvious in the case of legal obligations, which are sanc-
tioned by a whole apparatus of coercive agencies: the police, the law courts,
etc. But a large variety of other sanctions exist which reinforce adherence to
obligations not expressed in law.
Durkheim frequently reiterates, however, that conformity to obligations
rarely rests upon fear of the sanctions which are applied against contraven-
tion. In most circumstances individuals accept the legitimacy of the obliga-
tion, and thus do not consciously feel its constraining character: 'when I
conform to them whole-heartedly, this constraint (coercilion) is felt only
slightly. if at all, since it is unnecessary. But it is, nonetheless, an intrinsic
characteristic of these facts, the proof thereof being that it asserts itself as
soon as I attempt to resist it.' 28 Durkheim's emphasis upon the importance
of constraint is evidently directed primarily against utilitarianism. But moral
obligation always has two aspects, the other being the acceptance of an ideal
(however partial that acceptance may be) underlying it. Durkheim later
remarked that he had consistently been misunderstood on this point:
21 EF, p. 239; FE. p. 298 (footnote). cf. Raymond Aron: Main Cunenls in Sociolo6ical
Thoug'" (London, 1967), vol. 2, pp. 63-4.
21 RSM. p. 14. ~. RSM. pp. 14-15.
30 RSM. p. 22. 31 MM, pp. 28-9.
90 Part 2: Durkheim
32 Durkheim warns that • too great a detachment in relation to tested propositions has
the serious drawback of preventing continuity in effort and thought'. • Sur Ie
totemisme ',AS, vol. 5, 1900-1, p. 89.
33 RSM, p. 35. See the penetrating analysis given in Roger Lacombe: La methode
sociologique de Durkheim (Paris, 1926), pp. 67ff.
3. RSM, pp. 35-6. 35 RSM, p. 42. .. RSM, p. 95.
Dltrkheim's conception of sociological method 91
final causes entails the sort of fallacious reasoning which Durkheim criticises
in both The Division of Labour and Suicide:
Thus Comte traces the entire progressive force of the human species to this fun-
damental tendency' which directly impels man constantly to ameliorate his con-
dition, whatever it may be, under all circumstances'; and Spencer relates this
force to the need for greater happiness ... But this method confuses two very
different questions ... The need we have of things cannot give them existence,
nor can it confer their specific nature upon them. 37
The causes which give rise to a given social fact must therefore be identified
separately from whatever social functions it may fulfil. It is appropriate
methodological procedure. moreover, to establish causes prior to the attempt
to specify functions. This is because knowledge of the causes which bring a
phenomenon into being can, under certain circumstances. allow us to derive
some insight into its possible functions. The separate character of cause and
function, according to Durkheim. does not prevent the existence of a reci-
procal relation between the two. • The effect can doubtless not exist without
its cause; but the latter, in tum, needs its effect. It is from the cause that the
effect draws its energy; but it also restores it to the cause on occasion, and
consequently it cannot disappear without the cause showing the effects of its
disappearance.' 31 Thus, in the illustration which Durkheim gives from The
Division 01 Labour, the existence of • punishment' is causally contingent
upon the prevalence of strongly held collective sentiments. The function of
punishment consists in the maintenance of these sentiments at the same
degree of intensity: if transgressions were not punished, the strength of
sentiment necessary to social unity would not be preserved.
SI RSM, p. 48; RMS, p. 48. As an implicit criticism of Weber's view on this matter,
this is a similar point 10 thaI made by Strauss. Leo Strauss: Natural Right and
History (Chicago, 1953), p. 41.
Durklzeim's conception of sociological method 93
its new form " elements of what is normal for the type which is becoming
superseded still exist. It is necessary to analyse' the conditions which deter-
mined this generality in the past and ... then investigate whether these con-
ditions are still given in the present '.CO If these conditions do not pertain, the
phenomenon in question, although' general " cannot be called' normal '.
The calculation of criteria of normality in relation to specific societal types.
according to Durkheim. allows us to steer a course in ethical theory between
those who conceive history as a series of unique and unrepeated happenings,
and those who attempt to formulate transhistorical ethical principles. In the
first view, the possibility of any generalised ethics is excluded; in the second,
ethical rules are formulated' once and for all for the entire human species '.
An example can be taken which Durkheim himself uses on many occasions.
The sorts of moral ideas which pertained in the classical Greek po/is were
rooted in religious conceptions, and in a particular form of class structure
based upon slavery: hence many of the ethical ideas of this period are now
obsolete, and it is futile to try to resurrect them in the modem world. In
Greece, for example, the ideal of the fully-rounded • cultivated man " edu-
cated in all branches of scientific and literary knowledge, was integral to the
society. But it is an ideal which is out of accord with the demands of an order
based upon a high degree of specialisation in the division of labour.
An evident criticism which might be made against Durkheim's position
on this matter is tbat it induces compliance with the status quo, since it
appears to identify the morally desirable with whatever state of affairs is at
present in existence.u Durkheim denies that this is so; on the contrary, it is
only through definite knowledge of the potentially emergent trends in social
reality that active intervention to promote social change can have any success.
, The future is already written for him who knows how to read it. .. .' U The
scientific study of morality allows us to distinguish those ideals which are in
the process of becoming. but which are still largely hidden from the public
consciousness. By showing that these ideals are not merely aberrations. and
by analysing the changing social conditions that underlie them and which are
serving to promote their growth, we are able to show which tendencies should
be fostered and which need to be rejected as obsolete.·' Of course, science will
never be complete enough to allow us to escape altogether from the necessity
of acting without its guidance. 'We must live. and we must often anticipate
science. In such cases we must do as we can and make use of what scientific
observations are at our disposal .. .' 44
40 RSM, p. 61.
41 CritiCs were not slow to make this a~sertion. Durkheim replied to three of his early
critics in the AS, vol. 10, 1905-6, pp. 352-{)9 .
• ~ Ibid. p. 368.
U 'Tbe determination of moral {aCI, " in Sociology and Philosophy (London, 1965),
pp.60ff.
• , Ibid. p. 67.
94 Part 2.' Durkheim
It is not the case, Duckheim argues, that the adoption of his standpoint
renders all abstract • philosophical • attempts to create logically consistent
ethics completely futile. While it is true that • morality did not wait for the
theories of the philosophers in order to be formed and to function '. this does
not mean that, given empirical knowledge of the social framework within
which moral rules exist. philosophical reflection cannot playa part in intro-
ducing changes in existing moral rules. Philosophers, in fact, have often
played such a role in history - but usually without consciously being aware
of it. Such men have sought to enunciate universal moral principles. but have
in fact acted as the precursors and progenitors of changes immanent in their
society."
.. RSM, p. 71. Marx makes a somewhat comparable point, discussing the innovatory
character of criminal activity. Theories 0/ Surplus Value (ed. Bonner & Burns),
p.376.
7. Individualism, socialism and the 'occupational
groups'
95
96 Part 2: Durkheim
periods of history. socialism is uniquely a product of the very recent past.
Communist writings typically take the form of fictional utopias: diverse
examples are to be found in the works of Plato. Thomas More. and Cam.
panella. The main notion supporting these utopian constructions is that
private property is the ultimate source of all social evils. Consequently. com·
munist writers regard material wealth as a moral danger which must be
checked by the imposition of severe restrictions upon its accumulation. In
communist theory. economic life is separated from the political sphere: in
Plato's ideal community. for example. those who rule have no right to inter·
vene in the productive activity of the labourers and artisans. nor do the latter
groups have any right to influence the conduct of government.
The reason for this separation, ac:c:ording to Plato. is that wealth and an that
relates to it is the primary source of public corruptioo. It is the thing that, stimu.
lating individual egoisms, sets citizens to struggling and unleashes the internal
conflicts which ruin states... It is necessary therefore to place it outside of public
life, as far as possible from the state which it could only pervert.6
Socialism is a product of the social changes which transformed the Euro·
pean societies in the late eighteenth and nineteenth centuries. While com·
munism is grounded in the notion that policy and economy must be separated,
the very essence of socialism. in Durkheim's use of the term. is that it supposes
that the two should be assimilated. The primary tenet of socialism is not
merely that production should be centralised in the hands of the state. but that
the role of the state should be a wholly economic one - in socialist society, the
management or administration of the economy is to be the basic task of the
state. While communism. which seeks to eschew wealth as far as possible,
usually has an ascetic character. socialist doctrines are built upon the premise
that modem industrial production offers the possibility of abundant wealth
for all. and the attainment of universal abundance is their principal aim.
Socialism advocates' the connection 0/ all economic 1unctions. or 0/ certain
0/ them. which are at the present time diffuse. to the directing and conscious
centres of society t. s
The aim of socialism, therefore, is the regulation and control of production
in the interests of all members of society. But there is no socialist doctrine, in
Durkheim's view, which considers that consumption should be regulated
centrally: on the contrary, socialists hold that each individual should be free
to use the fruits of production for his own individual fulfilment. In com-
munism by contrast, 'it is consumption that is communal and production
which remains private '. 'Without doubt', Durkheim adds, '- and this is
deceiving - in both lhere is to be regulation (reglementation). but it must be
noted that it operates in opposing ways. One aims to moralise industry by
~I As noted previously (p. 76. n. 49). Durkheim emphasises, however, that there is nol a
universal relationship between sociely and state: • Kinds of society should not be
confused with different types of stale ... a cbange in a nation's system of govern-
ment does not necessarily involve a change in the prevailing type of society.' This
forms one element in Durkbeim's critique of Montesquieu. See Montesquieu and
Rousseall (Ann Arbor, 1965), p. 33 and passim.
~, It may assume a pathological form, as in German militarism. cf. Durkheim's analysis
of Treitschke's Politik. in . L'Aliemaglie au-dessus de tout' (Paris, 1915).
,~ PECM, pp. 7)-S; cf. also Moral EducQtion (New York, 1961), pp. 80-1, where
Durkheim says that the nation may be . conceived of as a partial embodiment of
the idea of humanity'.
102 Part 2: Durkheim
conception of democracy, and from thence with his call for the resurgence of
occupational associations (corporations).
Durkheim rejects the traditional notion of democracy, in so far as this
entails that the mass of the population participate directly in government.
Except for the least advanced small tribes, there are no societies where govern-
ment is exercised directly by all in common: it is always in the bands of a minority
chosen either by birth or by election; its scope may be large or small. according
to circumstances. but it never comprises more than a limited circle of individuals. U
A society is more or less democratic, according to Durkheim's terminology,
to the degree that there is a two-way process of communication between the
state and other levels of society. According to Durkheim, there is an extremely
significant consequence which flows from the existence of a democratic system,
which is that the conduct of social life takes on a conscious and directed
character. Many aspects of social life formerly ruled by unthinking custom
or habit become the subject of intervention on the part of the state. The state
is involved in economic life, and the administration of justice, in education,
and even in the organisation of the arts and sciences.
The role of the state in democracy is thus not simply to summarise and
express the views and sentiments held in a diffuse and unreflective way by the
mass of the population. Durkheim calls the state the social ego (i.e., tbe
• consciousness '), while the conscience collective as a whole is the social
• mind ' (i.e., includes many habitual, reflexive modes of thought). The state
is thus often the origin of novel ideas, and leads society as much as being led
by it. In those societies where the state does not assume this directive role.
the result can be a stagnation almost as great as that in societies held in the
yoke of tradition. In modem societies, where the influence of restraining
traditions has been largely dispelled, there are many avenues open for the
display of critical spirit, and changes of opinion and mood among the mass
are frequent: if the government simply reflects these, the result is constant
uncertainty and vacillation in the political sphere, which leads to no concrete
change. Many superficial changes occur, but cancel each other out: • Those
societies that are so stormy on the surface are often bound to routine.' 28 It is
in circumstances where there is a dearth of secondary groups mediating
between the individual and the state that such a situation tends to pertain.
This same condition which, given a strong state, can lead to a tyrannical
despotism. can produce inconstant instability where the state is weak.
Even prior to the publication of The Division of Labour. Durkheim
reached the conclusion that occupational associations should play a larger
31 DL, pp. 29 & 28. cr. Erik Allardt: • Emile Durkheim: sein Beitrag zur politischen
Soziologie', KQJner Zeitschrift fiir Soz;%gie und Sozialpsychologie, vol. 20, 1968,
pp. 1-16.
8. Religion and moral discipline
1 DL. p. 169.
~ DL, p. 383.
3 Preface to the AS. vol. 2. 1897-8. in Kurt H. Wolff: Emile Durklleim I!I 01.• Essays
Oil Sociology and Philosophy (New York, 1964), pp. 352-3.
• Letter to the Editor of the Rente neo·sco/astique. p. 613.
105
106 Part 2: Durkheim
part from the frequent tendency of secondary writers to conflate Durkheim's
functional and historical analysis in a way which is in fact foreign to Durk-
heim's thought. s Durkheim repeatedly stresses, almost as often as did Marx,
the historical nature of man, and emphasises that the causal analysis \1f
historical development is integral to sociology: • history is not only the
natural framework of human life; man is a product of history. If one separates
men from history, if one tries to conceive of man outside time, fixed and
immobile, one takes away his nature.' I The main underlying body of theory
presented in The Elementary Forms of the Religious Life is functional in
character; that is, it concerns the functional role of religion in society. But
The Elementary Forms also has to be read genetically, in relation to the series
of profound changes which have rendered modem societies very different in
form from prior types. In criticising Tonnies at the outset of his career, Durk·
heim emphasises that there is not an absolute break between mechanical and
organic solidarity: the latter type presupposes moral regulation as much as
the first, although this regulation cannot be of the traditional sort. The impor.
tance of Durkheim's novel understanding of religion, as developed in The
Elementary Forms, is that it leads to a clarification of the nature of this con-
tinuity between the traditional forms of society and the modern. • In order
to understand these new forms, one must connect them with their religious
origins, but without thereby confusing them with religious phenomena,
properly speaking.' T
That this allows Durkheim, at the same time, to elucidate certain themes
in his analysis of modem societies in a direct sense cannot, of course, be
doubted. One main element in this is that, in Durkheim's later writings, the
emphasis upon the constraining character of social phenomena cedes place
to a greater stress upon the significance of the specific character of the symbols
which mediate 'positive' attachment to ideals. But this is not a sudden
capitulation to idealism. The heavy emphasis upon constraint and obligation
in Durkheim's early writings is in considerable degree an outcome of the
form of critical attack in which these playa part; and throughout the whole
• cf. above, pp. 67-70. • EF, p. 13; FE, p. I. 10 EF, p. 52; FE, p. 50.
U EF, p. 53; FE. p. 53. 12 EF, p. 62; FE, p. 65. 13 EF, p. 195.
Ie EF, p. 195. Durkheim rejects various theories which hold that totemism is itself
derivative of a previous form of religion (pp. 195-214).
108 Part 2: Durkheim
Totemism is integrally connected with the clan system of organisation
which is characteristic of the Australian societies. A specific feature of the
totemic clan is that the name which denotes the identity of the clan group is
that of a material object - a totem - which is believed to have very special
properties. No two clans within the same tribe have the same totem. Exami-
nation of the qualities which members of a clan believe to be possessed by
their totem shows that the totem is the axis of the dichotomy between the
sacred and the profane. The totem ' is the very prototype of sacred things '. H
The sacred character of the totem is manifest in the ritual observances which
separate it from ordinary objects which may be used to utilitarian ends.
Various ritual prescriptions and prohibitions also surround the totemic
emblem - the representation of the totem which is put on objects, or adorns
the person; these are often even more stringently enforced than those relating
to the totemic object itself.
In addition. however, the members of the clan themselves possess sacred
qualities. While in more advanced religions the believer is a profane being.
this is not the case in totemism. Every man bears the name of his totem, which
signifies that he shares in the:: religiosity of the totem itself, and there are
believed to be genealogical connections between the individual and his totem.
Totemism thus recognises three sorts of objects as sacred: the totem, the
totemic emblem, and the members of the clan themselves. These three classes
of sacred object in turn form part of a general cosmology: 'For the Austra-
lian, things themselves, all the things which populate the universe, are part of
the tribe; they are constituent elements of it and, so to speak, pe:manent
members of it; just like men, they have a determined place in the organisation
of society.' I I Thus, for example, the clouds belong to one totem, the sun to
another: the whole of nature is brought into an ordered classification based
upon the totemic clan organisation. All objects classed in a given clan or
phratry (a combination of a group of clans) are regarded as sharing qualities
in common, and such objects are believed by the members of the clan to be
affiliated to themselves - men 'call them their friends and think that they are
made out of the same flesh as themselves '.17 This shows that the scope of
religion extends much further than might initially appear. 'It not only com-
prises the totemic animals and the human members of the clan, but since
nothing exists that is not classified in a clan and under a totem, there is simi-
larly nothing which does not receive, in varying degree, a certain quality of
religiosity.' 11
Thus no one of the three sorts of sacred objects previously distinguished
derives its sacred character from either of the others. since they all share a
22 I have taken this phrase from H. Stuart Hughes: Consciouslless and Society (New
York, 1958). p. 285.
23 RSM. p. 110.
Religion and moral discipline III
sarily represent it as such '.::6 Thence derives the third feature of totemism.
that the individual members of the collectivity share in the religiosity of the
totem.
This explanation shows why it is futile to attempt to define religion in
terms of the substantive content of beliefs. Whether or not a given object or
symbol becomes sacred does not deper;td upon its intrinsic properties. The
most common-place object may become sacred if it is infused with the
religious force. • In this way a rag achieves sanctity and a scrap of paper may
become extremely precious.' 25 This also shows why a sacred object may be
subdivided without losing its holy quality. A piece of Jesus's cloak is as
sacred as the whole thing.
It remains to account for the second fundamental aspect of religion - the
ritual practices which are found in all religions. Two closely intertwined sorts
of ritual exist. Sacred phenomena are by definition separate from the profane.
One set of rites function to maintain this separation: these are negative rites
or taboos. which are prohibitions limiting contact between the sacred and the
profane. Such interdictions cover verbal as well as behavioural relationships
with sacred things. In the normal way, nothing from the profane world must
enter the sphere of the sacred in unchanged form. Thus special sacred
garments are put on for ceremonial occasions, and all the normal temporal
occupations are suspended.21 Negative rites have one positive aspect: the
individual who submits to them has sanctified himself and has thereby pre-
pared himseU for entry into the realm of the sacred. Positive rites proper are
those which affect fuller communion with the religious, and which constitute
the core of the religious ceremonial itself. The function of both sets of riles
is easily specified. and is a necessary adjunct to the explanation of the deriva-
tion of religious beliefs outlined previously. Negative rites serve to maintain
the essential separation between the sacred and the profane that the very
existence of the sacred depends upon; these rites ensure that the two spheres
do not encroach upon one another. The function of positive rites is to renew
the commitment to religious ideals which otherwise would decline in the
purely utilitarian world.
At this point the relationship between this analysis and that established in
Thf> Division of lAbour may be briefly re-stated. Small-scale, traditional
societies depend for their unity upon the existence of a strong conscience
collective. What makes such a society a • society' at all is the fact that its
members adhere to common beliefs and sentiments. The ideals which are
2. EF, p. 253. For a critical appraisal of Durkheim's analysis at tbis point, see P. M.
Worsley: • Emile Durkheim's theory of knowledge " SOCiological Review, vol. 4.
1956, pp. 47-62.
2:; Sociology and Pllilosoplzy, p. 94.
:. There are undoubtedly close connections between religious ritual and play. Durlt-
heim mentions that games originate in religious ceremonial. On tbis matter, cf.
Roger eaillois: Mall. Play and Games (London. 1962). Religious ceremonials are,
of course. for Durkheim in a literal sense' re-creation'.
112 Part 2: Durkheim
expressed in religious beliefs are therefore the moral ideals upon which the
unity of the society is fopnded. When individuals gather together in religious
ceremonial they are hence re-affirming their faith in the moral order upon
which mechanical solidarity depends. The positive rites entailed in religious
ceremonial thus provide for the regular moral reconsolidation of the group,
necessary because in the activities of day to day life in the profane world
individuals pursue their own egoistic interests. and are consequently liable
to become detached from the moral values upon which societal solidarity
depends.
The only way of renewing the collective representations which relate to sacred
things is to retemper them in the very source of religious life. that is to say, in
assembled groups. .. Men are more confident because they feel thermelves
stronger; and they really are stronger, because forces which were languishing are
now re-awakened in the consciousne6S.21
There exists yet another type of rite: the • piacular' (expiatory) rite. the
most important instance of which is that embodied in ceremonies of mourn-
ing. Just as religious sentiments of joy become raised to fever-point in the
collective excitation produced by the ceremonial. so a • panic of sorrow' is
developed in mourning rituals. 2I The effect of this is to draw together th~
members of the group whose solidarity has been threatened by the loss of one
of its members. • Since they weep together. they hold to one another and the
group is not weakened. in spite of the blow which has fallen upon it ... the
group feels its strength gradually returning to it; it begins to hope and to live
again: 2t This helps to explain the existence of malevolent religious spirits.
There are overywhere two sorts of religious powers: benevolent influences on
the one hand. and evil forces which bring sickness. death and destruction on
the other. The collective activity involved in piacular rites provides a parallel
situation to that which gives rise to the conception of beneficent forces. save
that grief is the dominant emotion. • This is the experience which a man
interprets when he imagines that outside him there are evil beings whose
hostility. whether constitutional or transitory, can only be placated by human
suffering.' ao
is built upon the separation of society into totemic clan divisions. • The unity
of these first logical systems merely reproduces the unity of the society.' JI
This does not imply that society wholly structures the perception of nature.
Durkheim does not declare that there are no biologically given perceptual
discriminations, but points out. on the contrary, that the most rudimen-
tary classification presupposes some recognition of sensory similarities and
differences. The import of Durkheim's argument is that these native discrimi-
nations do not form the axis of the classificatory system. but constitute only a
secondary principle of ordering: 32 , The feeling of resemblances is one thing
and the idea of class (genre) is another. The class is the external framework of
which objects perceived to be similar form, in part, the contents.'
The existence of logical classes involves the formation of clear-cut dichoto-
mies. However, nature itself manifests continuity in space and time. and the
sensory information which we register from the world is not ordered in this
discontinuous fashion, but is made up of • indistinct and shifting images '."
Thus the notion of logical class itself, and the hierarchical distribution of
relationships between categories, derive from the division of society into clans
and phratries. But the mode in which objects are put into one category rather
than another is directly influenced by sensory discriminations. For example,
if the sun is in one category. the moon and stars will usually be placed in an
opposed category; if the white cockatoo is in one category, the black cockatoo
is put in the other.
Just as the axiomatic categories in terms of which abstract thought is
ordered are derived from society, so too are the basic dimensions of force.
space and time. The elemental religious force is the original model from
which the concept of force was derived, and later incorporated into philosophy
and natural science. J4 The same is true of the other of the Aristotelean cate-
gories: the notion of time finds its original prototype in the periodic character
of social life. and space from the physical territory occupied by society. Time
and space are not. as Kant held, inherent categories of the human mind. No
doubt every individual is conscious of living in a present which is distinct
from the past. But the concept of • time' is not personalised; it involves an
abstract category shared by all members of the group.• It is not my time that
is thus arranged; it is time in general. . .' 35 This must have originated from
the experience of the collectivity: the temporal divisions of years, weeks and
days stem from the periodic distribution of public ceremonials, rites and holy-
)1 EF, p. 170.
)2 1?"s· does introduce, however, difficulties of circularity in Durkheim's theory. cf.
arsons, p. 447.
~3 EF, pp. 171-2; FE, pp. 208-9.
.. , ~rkheim notes that Ihis has already been indicated by Cornie. But Comte mistakenly
inferred that the concept of force will eventually be eliminated from science • for
3 Owing to its mystic origins. he refused it all objective value '. EF, p. 234. '
• EF. p. 23.
114 Part 2: Durkheim
days. The notion of • space • similarly presupposes some original fixed point;
there can be no • north • or • south " or • right' or • left • without some common
standard whereby these can be judged. The territory occupied by the society
provides this standard. This can be directly illustrated: in some of the Austra-
lian societies, space is conceived in the form of a circle, mirroring the circular
shape of the camp, and the spatial circle is subdivided according to the
position of each clan in the encampmenL
Durkheim does not advance a simple form of • mechanical materialism .
here, any more than, in other parts of The Elementary Forms, he relapses into
the idealism for which the work is often criticised. He takes some pains, in
fact, to emphasise that this standpoint takes as its premise the dynamic inter-
play between the • substratum' of society, and collectively-evolved ideas:
Certainly we conside!' it to be evident that social life depends upon its substratum
and bear its mark, just as the mental life of the individual depends upon the
nervous system and indeed the whole organism. But the conscience collective is
something other than a mere epiphenomenon of its morpbologic:al basis, just as
individual consciousness is something other than a simple efDoresc:ence of the
DervOUS systan."
As a theory of knowledge, the thesis advanced in The Elementary Forms
is primarily genetic in character: it is not, as it is sometimes taken to be, a
theory which postulates the existence of an unvarying set of connections
between social organisation and collective ideas. Indeed, a basic aspect of
Durkheim's general conception of the process of social development concerns
the changing character of the content of the idea-systems which are found in
contemporary societies, and the increasingly diversified nature of the social
processes which underlie them. Of particular importance here is the relation·
ship between modem rationalism and secularised morality. The importance
of The Elementary Forms, in Durkheim's thought, is that it demonstrates con·
elusively that there can be no collective moral beliefs which do not possess a
• sacred' character. Thus while both the content and the form of the moral
order found in contemporary societies have changed radically, as compared
to traditional societies, there is indeed no solution de continuite between the
traditional and modem forms of solidarity.
The modem world is becoming increasingly penetrated by rationalism.
which Durkheim caUs the • intellectual aspect • of moral individualism. One
consequence of this is the demand for a • rational morality '. Now the main-
tenance of moral authority demands that moral ideas are • as if surrounded by
a mysterious barrier which keeps violators at arm's length, just as the religious
domain is protected from the reach of the profane '.57 This characteristic is
easily preserved when religion and morality are one and the same, because the
symbols and trappings of religion inspire attitudes of veneration. To seek to
" Ibid. pp. 9-11. • Moral life has not been, and never will be, able to shed all the
characteristics that it holds in common with religion '. Sociology and Philosophy,
p.48.
39 • The dualism of human nature and its social ~onditions', in Wolff, p. 327.
en Ibid. p. 338.
<I Suo p. 360. ez cf. L'b-o/urion pUagogiqul'. pp. 3324 & 326-7.
116 Part 2: Durkheim
over himself..• Thus of the two possible poles of all thought, nature on the one
hand, and man on the other, it is necessarily around the second that the thought
of the Christian societies has come to gravitate...n
Christian ethics provided the moral principles upon which the • cult of the
individual' is founded. but now Christianity is becoming surplanted by sacred
symbols and objects of a new sort. This is most clearly exemplified, Durk.-
heim says. in the events of the French Revolution. where freedom and reason
were glorified. and where there was a high level of collective enthusiasm stimu-
lated by public' ceremonial '. But while this helped to give birth to the ideals
which now dominate our life, the collective ardour of these times was
ephemeral. The modem world is consequently in a moral hiatus:
In a word, the old gods are growing old or are dying, and others are not yet born.
This is what made futile Comte's attempt to revive artificially the old historical
memories: it is not a dead past, but life itself which can give rise to a living CUlt.
But this state of uncertainty and bewildered turmoil cannot last forever. A day
will come when our societies will again know those times of creative effervescence
in which new ideas will spring up and new formulae will be discovered to serve
for a while as a guide to humanity...••
The French Revolution gave the most decisive impetu.s to the growth 0f
moral individualism in modem times. But the progression of individualism.
while occurring irregularly in different periods of western history. is not the
specific product of any definite epoch; its development takes place • unceas-
ingly throughout history '." The sentiment of the supreme worth of the human
individual is thus a product of society. and it is this which decisively separates
it from egoism. The • cult of the individual' is based. not upon egoism. but
upon the extension of quite contrary sentiments of sympathy for human suffer-
ing and the desire for social justice. While individualism cannot but produce
an increase in egoism as compared with societies dominated by mechanical
solidarity. it does not in any sense derive from egoism. and thus is not itself
productive of a ' moral egoism which would make all solidarity impossible'. 4&
This can be illustrated by the example of scientific activity. An intellectual
branch of moral individualism is the spirit of free enquiry embodied in
science: but far from entailing anarchy in the sphere of ideas. the pursuance
of scientific enquiry can only be carried on within a framework of moral rules
which enforce respect for the opinions of others. the publication of the results
of investigations. and the exchange of information.
The trend towards increasing individualism is irreversible, since it is the
outcome of the profound societal changes detailed in The Division 0/ Labour.
This is at the root of Durkheim's conception of freedom, and its relationship
1 Durkheim reviews Simmel's Philosophie des Geldes in AS, vol. 5,1900-1, pp. 1~5,
and two articles by Simmel in AS, vol. 7, 1902-3, pp. 646-9. Durkheim also discusses
Simmel's formal sociology in ' Sociology and its scientific field " in Wolff, pp. 354-
75 (originally published in 19(0).
2 cf. above. pp. 66-9.
a e.g., Edward A. Tiryakian: • A problem for the sociology of knowledge " Archive.r
europeennes de sociologje, vol. 7, 1966, pp. 330-6. Tiryakian erroneously says that
there is no mutual reference in the works of Durkheim and Weber. In fact, Durk-
heim mentions Weber in reportins upon the proceedings of the German Sociological
Society (1911), AS, vol. 12, 1909-12, p. 26. (For Weber's contributions to the COD~
gress, see GASS, pp. 43J-83.)
119
120 Part 3: Max Weber
brought back to it by the nature of the questions I met with on my route ' .•
Weber's first works, on the other hand, are detailed historical studies, and
it was from within the context of specific problems brought to light primarily
by the German historical school that Weber went on to expand the range of
his writings to embrace questions of a general theoretic3J nature. From the
flux of competing traditions in history. jurisprudence. economics. sociology,
and philosophy. Weber eventually fashioned a standpoint which borrowed
from many sources.
Early works
Weber's doctoral dissertation (1889) is a technical piece of work. dealing with
the legal provisions governing mediaeval trading enterprise. s In the thesis,
Weber gives particular attention to the Italian mercantile cities such as
Genoa and Pisa, showing that the commercial capitalism which developed
there entailed the formulation of principles of law regulating the mode in
which the distribution of risk and profit should be apportioned among the
collaborators in a business enterprise. At this time Weber was already con-
cerned, although only from this limited aspect, with an issue which was later
to play an important role in his later writings: the impact of Roman law
upon the development of the juridical system of mediaeval and post-
mediaeval Europe. He found himself unable to deal with this matter satis-
factorily, however. within the frame of reference which he had chosen for the
thesis.' Weber's second work. written under the aegis of Mommsen. and
which he finished some two years later, is expressly concerned with Rome
itself.1 Again, the work is heavily technical in character, and is directed to-
wards a current scholarly controversy of the day, providing a detailed analysis
of the evolution of Roman land-tenure, and connecting this with legal and
political changes.' In contrast to those who argued that the economic history
of Roman agriculture was unique in the specific form which it took. Weber
tries to show that it is amenable to treatment in terms of concepts derived
from other economic contexts.
These writings are perhaps rather less important for their substantive con-
tent than for what they indicate of the nascent line of Weber's intellectual
• The quotation is from a letter to Georges Davy, reported in the latter's • Emile
Durkheim " Revue franfaise de soci%gie, vol. I, 1960, p. 10.
S • Zur Geschichte der Handelsgesellschaften im Mittelalter', Gesanrmelte AufsiilU
ZlIr Sozial- und Wirtschaftsgeschichte (Tiibingen, 1924). pp. 312-443. For the
original title of the dissertation, see Johannes Winckelmann: • Max Webers
Dissertation', in Rene Konig and Johannes Winckelmann: Max Weber zum
Gediichttzis (Cologne and Opladen), 1963.
, lugendbriefe. TUbingen, p. 274.
7 Die romische Agrargescllichte in ih,rer Bedeutung fur des Staats- und Privatrecht
(Stuttgart, 1891) .
• For a brief discussion of the background to the work. cf. GUnther Roth: • Introduc·
tion ',ES. vol. I, pp. xxxvi-xl.
Max Weber: Protestantism and capitalism 121
~~ PE, p. 60; GAR. vol. I, p.44. 24 PE. p. 58; GAR. v,,[. I. p. 4J.
~s PE. p. 53; GAR. vol. I. p. 36. 26 PE, p. 67.
Max Weber: Protestantism and capitalism 127
enterprises have been restructured, what has occurred is a rational reorganisa-
tion of production, directed towards maximising productive efficiency. Such
a change cannot be explained, in most cases, by a sudden influx of capital
into the industry in question. It is the result. rather. of the introduction of a
new spirit of entrepreneurial enterprise - the capitalist spirit. Hence the
dominant characteristic which distinguishes the modem capitalist economy
is that it
is rationalised on the basis of rigorous calculation, directed with foresight and
caution towards the economic success which is sought in sharp contrast to the
hand-ta-mouth existence of the peasant, and to the privileged traditionalism of
the guiJd craftsman and of the adventurers' capitalism, oriented to the exploitation
ofpoliticaJ opportunities and irrational speculation.2T
The spirit of capitalism cannot simply be inferred from the growth of
rationalism as a whole in western society. Such a way of analysing the pro-
blem tends to assume a progressive. unilinear development of rationalism:
in fact. the rationalisation of different institutions in western societies shows
an uneven distribution. Those countries, for example, in which rationalisa-
tion of the economy has proceeded further are, in respect of the degree of
rationalism of law, retarded by comparison with some of the more economi-
cally backward states. (England is the most notable instance here.) Rational-
isation is a complex phenomenon, which takes many concrete forms. and
which develops variably in different areas of social life. The Protestant Ethic
is concerned only with discovering' whose intellectual child that particular
concrete form of rational thought was, from which the idea of a calling and
devotion to labour in the calling has derived .. .'.21
The concept of the 'calling', Weber shows. only came into being at the
time of the Reformation. It is not found. nor does any synonym for it exist, in
Catholicism. nor in Antiquity. The significance of the notion of the calling,
and the mode in which it is employed in Protestant beliefs, is that it serves to
bring the mundane affairs of everyday life within an all-embracing religious
influence. The calling of the individual is to fulfil his duty to God through the
moral conduct of his day-to-day life. This impels the emphasis of Protestant-
ism away from the Catholic ideal of monastic isolation, with its rejection
of the temporal, into worldly pursuits.
27 PE, p. 76.
21 PE, p. 78.
128 Part 3: Max Weber
ever, remained in some respects quite traditionalistic. 21 The further elabora-
tion of the conception of the calling was the work of the later Protestant
sects which make up the various branches of what Weber calls • ascetic
Protestantism '.
Weber differentiates four main streams of ascetic Protestantism: Calvinism,
Methodism, Pietism, and the Baptist sects. Of course, these were closely
related to one another, and cannot always be clearly separated. 30 Weber's
discussion of ascetic Protestantism is not concerned with an overall histori-
cal description of their dogma, but only with those elements in their doctrines
which are most consequential in affecting the practical conduct of the
individual in his economic activity. The most important part of the analysis
is concentrated upon Calvinism: not, however, solely upon Calvin's doctrines
as such, but rather upon those embodied in the teachings of Calvinists to-
wards the end of the sixteenth century and in the seventeenth century.
Having made these qualifications, Weber proceeds to identfy three major
tenets as most important in Calvinism. Firstly, the doctrine that the universe
is created to further the greater glory of God, and only has meaning in rela-
tion to God's purposes .• God does not exist for men, but men for the sake of
God.' 31 Secondly, the principle that the motives of the Almighty are beyond
human comprehension. Men can know only the small morsels of divine truth
which God wishes to reveal to them. Thirdly, the belief in predestination: onl}
a small number of men are chosen to achieve eternal grace. This is something
which is irrevocably given from the first moment of creation; it is not affected
by human actions, since to suppose that it were would be to conceive that the
actions of men could in1h:ence divine judgement.
The consequence of this doctrine for the believer, Weber argues, must
have been one of' unprecedented inner loneliness '. • In what was for the man
of the age of the Reformation the most decisive concern of his life, his eternal
salvation. he was forced to follow his path alone to meet a destiny which had
been decreed for him from eternity.' S2 In this crucial respect. each man was
alone; no one, priest or layman, existed who could intercede wi~ God to
produce his salvation. This eradication of the possibility of salvation through
the church and the sacraments, according to Weber, is the most decisive
difference which separated Calvinism from both Lutheranism and Catho-
licism. Calvinism thereby brought about a final conclusion to a great histori-
cal process which Weber discusses elsewhere in detail: the gradual process
of the • disenchantment' (Entzauberung) of the world. 33
~4 PE, p. 105.
33 PE, p. 158; GA.R. vol. 1. pp. 167-8.
130 Part 3: Max Weber
approach his vocation in a methodical fashion as the instrument of God. The
accumulation of wealth is morally condemned only to the degree that it
forms an enticement to idle luxury; where material profit is acquired through
the ascetic pursuit of duty in a calling, it is not only tolerated, but is in fact
morally recommended. 'To wish to be poor was, it was often argued, the
same as wishing to be unhealthy; it is objectionable as a glorification of
works and derogatory to the glory of God.' 31
It is crucial to Weber's analysis that these characteristics are not' logical '.
but' psychological' consequences of the original doctrine of predestination
as formulated by Calvin. These subsequent developments in Puritan doctrine
stem from the phenomenal isolation experienced by believers, and the
anxieties to which this gave rise. The belief in predestination is not unique to
Calvinism, and its consequences for human 'action vary according both to the
other beliefs it is associated with. and the social context in which it occurs.
The Islamic belief in predestination. for example. produced. not the worldly
asceticism of Calvinism, but' a complete obliviousness to self. in the interest
of fulfilment of the religious commandment of a holy war for the conquest of
the world '.3f
The origins of the capitalist spirit thus have to be sought in that religious
ethic which is most precisely developed in Calvinism. It is to this ethic that
we may trace the unique qualities which distinguish the attitudes underlying
modern capitalistic activity from the amoral character of most previous forms
of capital acquisition. 'One of the integral characteristics of the modem
capitalist spirit, and not only of this. but of modem culture: the rational
conduct of life on the basis of the idea of the calling. was born - that is what
this exposition has sought to show - from the spirit of Christian asceticism.' J'
The other varieties of Protestant asceticism, in general, have less of a rigorous
discipline than Calvinism, which Weber speaks of as having an 'iron con-
sistency '. Weber suggests, however. that there may be a historical relation-
ship. in the origin of the capitalist spirit, between the forms of ascetic Pro-
testantism and the social strata at different levels in the capitalist economy.
Pietism, for example. which tended to induce, rather than the persistent
energy of the Calvinist, an attitude of humility and renunciation. may have
been most widespread among employees in the lower ranks of the industrial
order. while Calvinism was probably more directly influential among entre-
preneurs. at
What to the Puritan was compliance with divine guidance. increasingly,
for the world of contemporary capitalism becomes a mechanical conformity
to the economic and organisational exigencies of industrial production. at all
levels of the hierarchy of the division of labour. Weber is careful to disclaim
the suggestion that the Puritan ethos is a necessary component to the function-
40 'Der Puritaner wollte Berufsmensch scin - wir mUssen es scin' (GAR, voL I, p. 203).
Weber stresses that the Puritan emphasis upon the importance of a fixed calling
provided an initial moral validation of the specialised division of labour (PE, p. 163).
ct. also Weber's discussion of the decline of 'church-mindedness' in American
business, in ' The Prom;tant sects and the spirit of capitalism " in FMW, pp. 302-22.
'1 PE, pp. 181-2; GAR, vol. I, pp. 203-4.
42 ct. ' Antikritisches Schlusswort', pp. 556-7.
43 PE, p. 54, pp. 90-91 & p. 183.
132 Part 3: Max Weber
theless Weber is emphatic that the material analysed in The Protestant
Ethic adequately disposes of • the doctrine of naive historical materialism "
according to which ideas such as those involved in Calvinist beliefs are
regarded simply as • reflections' of economic conditioos." • We must free
ourselves " Weber asserts. • from the view that one can deduce the Reforma·
tion, as a historically necessary development, from economic changes.' 4.
But Weber does not attempt to substitute any alternative • theory' for this
conception of historical materialism which he rejects: indeed, as Weber seeks
to show in his methodological essays, which were mostly written at the same
period as The Protestant Ethic, such a theory is impossible to achieve .
The Protestant Ethic concludes with a plea for the rejection of both material-
istic and idealistic interpretations of history as overall theoretical schemes:
• each " Weber says, • if it does not serve as the preparation, but ~s the con-
clusion of an investigation, accomplishes equally little in the interest of
historical truth '.' Weber's methodological writings expound this position in
considerable depth. 2
The genealogy of Weber's methodological essays is complex. however.
and they must also be placed within the framework of the then current con-
troversy over the relationship between the natural and the • human or 1
1 PE, p. 183.
2 For an exposition of the relevant background, especially with regard to idealism,
cr. Alexander von Scbelling: Max Webers WissellSChafts/ehre (fObingen, 1934),
pp. 178-247. Weber's methodological essays represent only a partial treatment of
problems which Weber intended to treat at greater length. See Marianne Weber:
Max Weber: ein Lebensbild (Heidelberg, 1950), pp. 347-8. The' partial' character
of Weber's methodological essays is clearly demonstrated in F. Tenbruck: • Die
Genesis dec Methodologie Max Webers', Kenner Zeilschrilt lur Sozi%gre und
SOl.iaipsych%gie, vol. 11,1959, pp. 573-630.
133
134 Part 3: Max Weber
Subjectivity and objectivity
Weber's critique of Roscher and Knies, the first of his methodological essays,
makes the point that the supposed distinction between the natural and social
sciences may be used to support a spurious intuitionism.' The writings of
Roscher, for example, according to Weber. employ this distinction in such a
way as to introduce an overriding component of semi-mystic idealism into
the author's analysis.' The universe of human action is held to be one in
which natural scientific methods do not apply, and consequently where inexact
and intuitive procedures have to be employed. The human world is thus an
, irrational' one, which is epitomised by the Volksgeist or Volksseele, the
'spirit of the people '. It is impossible, Weber points out, to reconcile the
use of such notions as this with the claim, which is advanced by this same
author. that rigorous historical research is an end which should be striven
for.
Weber concedes that the social sciences are necessarily concerned with
, spiritual' or ' ideal' phenomena, which are peculiarly human characteristics
which do not exist in the subject-matter treated by the natural sciences. But
this necessary differentiation of ' subject' and 'object' need not, and must
not, involve the sacrifice of 'objectivity' in the social sciences, nor does it
entail the substitution of intuition for replicable causal analysis. Weber's
essay entitled '" Objectivity" in social science and social policy' attempts
to show how this is possible.'
The social sciences, Weber points out, originated in a concern with practi-
cal problems, and were stimulated by the concern of men to effect desired
social chanaes. It was from within such a context that there emerged
the impetus towards the establishment of disciplines interested in formulat-
ing 'objective' statements about human social and cultural reality. This
development. however, was not accompanied by a clear understanding of the
significance of the essentiallogica1 discontinuity between factual or analytic
statements, on the one hand. and normative propositions concerning not what
'is', but what' oUght to be 'on the other. Most forms of social thought have
sought to establish a closure between factual and normative propositions.
on the basis of one of two connected SOrts of assumptions. The first is that
the desirable can be identified with what is' immutably existent': invariant
laws governing the operation of social and economic institutioos. The other
is that the assimilation of the desirable and the real come to be located in
general principles of evolutionary development: not in the immutably
existent, but in the inevitably emergent.
Both of these conceptions must be rejected. It is logically impossible for
• MSS, p. 52.
• On the latter point, see ES, vol. 1, pp. 65-8 & 100-7.
136 Part 3: Max Weber
ideals which a person holds. It is very often the case that men are nOl. clearly
aware of the values implicated by the specific objectives which they strive for,
Nld frequently they hold ends which are partially or even wholly incongruent
with one another. H an individual has not' thought through' the ideals upon
which his particular goals rest, we ' can assist him in becoming aware of the
ultimate axioms which he unconsciously departs from, or which he must
presuppose '. T
Further than this, however. we cannot go. The use of empirical science
and logical analysis can show an individual what it is possible for him to
accomplish, what the consequences of that accomplishment will be. and help
to clarify the nature of his ideals; but science cannot, as such, show him what
decision he should take.
No ethics in the world can dodge the fact that in numerous instances the attain-
ment of • good' ends is bound to the fact that one must be willing to pay the
price of using morally dubious means or at least dangerous ones - arid facing
the possibility or even the probability of evil ramifications. From no ethics in the
world can it be concluded when and to what extent the ethically good purpose
• justifies' the ethically dangerous means and ramifications.-
The logical consequence and the necessary support for this position which
Weber adopts is that the human universe is characterised by the existence of
irreducibly competing ideals. Since there is no single ideal or set of ideals
which, at any point of history, can be shown ·by scientific analysis to be
, right' or ' wrong 'I there can be no universal ethics. This methodological
standpoint finds its main empirical counterpart in Weber's writings in his
sociology of religion, which traces the genesis of divergent ideals in history.
But whereas ideals and meanings are created in religious and political
struggles, they can never be derived from science itself :
The fate of an epoch which has eaten of the tree of knowledge is that it must know
that we cannot learn the meaning of the workl from the results of its analysis. be
it ever so perfect; it must rather be in a position to create this meaning itself. It
must recognise that general views of life and the universe can never be the pro-
ducts of increasing empirical knowledge, and that the highest ideals, which move
us most forcefully, are always formed only in the struggle with other ideals which
are just as sacred to others as ours are to us.'
Weber's analysis of politics. and of the logic of political motivation, is
founded upon these considerations. Political conduct may be oriented within
either an • ethic of ultimate ends' (Gesinnungsethik) or an 'ethic of res-
ponsibility' (Verantwortungsethik).lo The man who pursues an ethic of
ultimate ends directs the whole of his political conduct towards the securing
of an ideal, without regard to rational calculation of means:
You may demonstrate to a convinced syndicalist, believing in an ethic of ultimate
ends, that his action will result in increasing the opportunities of reaction, in
11 FMW, p. 121.
12 Save in so far as logical analysis can assist in the clarification of ideals. But, as has
been mentioned previously, this is not a result of empirical science per se.
13 MSS, p. 57. It is worthwhile pointing OUt that each of the three figures treated in
this book developed views which have at times been linked by critics to the philo-
sophy of pragmatism. Durkheim felt the matter to be important enough to devote a
Whole course of lectures to the subject. cf. Pragmatisme et 6ociologie (Paris, 1955).
To over-simplify somewhat, it could be said that all three would object to prag-
matism for the same reason: that it denies the capacity of the acting subject to
rationally effect change in the world.
138 Part 3: Max Weber
ments. As has been mentioned before, for Weber this most definitely does not
involve the elimination of ideals from scientific discussion. It is, in fact.
incumbent upon the social scientist to attempt to be as clear as possible about
his own ideals. If this obligation is rigorously observed. the result will not be
a withdrawal of the values of the social scientist from relevance to his work:
'An attitude of moral indifference (Gesinnungslosigkeit) has no connection
with scielllific " objectivity",' 16
20 MSS, p. 84. Weber frequently stresses the importance of distinguishing the two
senses in which the social scientist may be interested in an • historical individual':
firstly, • in acquiring the most comprehensive knowledge possible' of • historically
.. great" and .. unique" individuals', and, secondly, in analysing • the significance
to be attributed, in a concrete historical relationship, to the causal force of the
actions of certain individuals - regardless of whether or nOl we would actually rate
tbem as .. significant" or .• insignificant" individuals .. .', GAW, p. 47.
21 MSS, pp. 92-3; GAW, p. 193.
142 Part J: Max Weber
vinist ethic' which Weber analyses in The Protestant Ethic are taken from
the writings of various historical figures, and involve those components of
Calvinist doctrines which Weber identifies as of particular importance in
relation to the formation of the capitalist spirit. Such an ideal type is
neither a • description' of any definite aspect of reality, nor, according to
Weber. is it a hypothesis; but it can aid in both description and explanation.
An ideal type is not, of course, ideal in a normative sense: it does not carry
the connotation that its realisation is desirable. It is as legitimate to construct
an ideal type of murder or prostitution as of any other phenomenon. An ideal
type is a pure type in a logical and not an exemplary sense: • In its conceptual
purity. this mental construct cannot be found empirically anywhere in
reality.' 2~
The creation of ideal types is in no sense an end in itself; the utility of a
given ideal type can be assessed only in relation to a concrete problem or
range of problems. and the only purpose of constructing it is to facilitate the
analysis of empirical questions. In formulating an ideal type of a phenomenon
such as of rational capitalism. then. the social scientist attempts to delineate,
through the empirical examination of specific forms of capitalism. the most
important respects (in relation to the concerns which he has set himself) in
which rational capitalism is distinctive. The ideal type is not formed out of a
nexus of purely conceptual thought, but is created, modified and sharpened
through the empirical analysis of concrete problems. and in tum increases the
precision of that analysis.
Ideal types are thus different in both scope and usage from descriptive con-
cepts (GattungsbegriDe). Descriptive types play an important and necessary
role in many branches of the social sciences. These simply summarise the
common features of groupings of empirical phenomena. Whereas an ideal
type involves • the one-sided accentuation of one or more points of view'. the
descriptive type involves • the abstract synthesis of those traits which are
common to numerous concrete phenomena '.U Weber gives the example of
the concepts of' church' and ' sect '. These may serve as the basis for a classi-
ficatory distinction; religious groups can be said to fall into one category or
the other. However. if we wish to apply the distinction in order to analyse the
importance of sectarian movements for the rationalisation of modem western
culture. we have to reformulate the concept of' sect' to emphasise the specific
components of sectarianism which have been influential in this particular
respect. The concept then becomes an ideal typical one. Any descriptive con-
cept can be transformed into an ideal type through the abstraction and recom-
bination of certain elements: in practical terms, Weber says, this is what is
often done.
Weber concentrates his discussion upon the formulation of ideal types
which relate to the elucidation of specific historical configurations. since this
~4 For analyses of the logical status of • individual' as opposed to • generic' ideal types,
cf. von Schelling, pp. 329ff; and Parsons, pp. 601ff.
~,. MSS, pp. 1-47. For an analysis of the political context against which Weber
developed these views, cf. Wolfgang J. Mommsen: Max Weber und die deutsche
Politik, 1890-1920 (Tilbingen. 1959).
~& MSS, pp. 2-3.
144 Part 3: Max Weber
(2) definitely to recognise facts, even those which may be personally uncomfor-
table, and to distingtlish them from his own evaluations; (3) to subordinate him-
self to his task and to repress the impulse to make an unnecessary spectacle of
personal tastes or other sentiments."
The teacher in the university has all the opportunities which any other
citizen has for the furtherance of his ideal~ through political action, and
should not demand further privileges of his own. The professorial chair is
not a 'specialised qualification for personal prophecy'. A professor who
attempts to use his position in such a way is able to exploit his standing,
moreover, in relation to an audience which is particularly receptive and lack-
ing in mature self-confidence. In taking this position. Weber expresses a
personal conviction. If the university were to be made a forum where values
were discussed. this could only be on the basis of 'the most unrestrained
freedom of discussion of fundamental questions from all value-positions '.
But this does not at all pertain in the German universities, where basic political
and ethical issues cannot be openly discussed; and as long as this is so, ' it
seems to me to be only in accord with the dignity of a representative of science
to be silent as well about such value-problems as he is allowed to treat ' . l l
In saying this Weber does not, of course. mean that the university teacher
should refuse to express political and moral judgements outside the sphere of
the university itself. On the contrary. Weber scathingly dismisses the false
invoking of 'ethical neutrality' outside the academic sphere. It is as illegiti-
mate, in Weber's view. for a man to cloak his value-assertions in the field of
politics with a spurious scientific' neutrality '. as it is for him to openly preach
a partisan position within the university.
In any case it is essential to recognise, according to Weber, that the question
of whether an individual should advance a specific value-position in his teach-
ing should be recognised as separate from the logical relationship of factual
and value-propositions in the social sciences. ' The problems of the empirical
disciplines are, of course, to be solved" non-evaluatively n. They are not pro-
blems of evaluation. But the problems of the social sciences are selected by
the value-relevance of the phenomena treated. .. In empirical investigation.
no " practical evaluations" are legitimated by this strictly logical fact.' 29
Interpretative sociology
Weber's methodological essays were mostly written within the context of
lhe specific problems which occupied him in his early empirical works; they
document a struggle to break out of the intellectual confines of the traditions
of legal, economic and historical thOUght within which he was originally
trained. In the methodological essays, sociology is treated as subordinate to
history: the main problems of interest in the social sciences are deemed to
be those concerned with questions possessing definite cultural significance.
Weber rejects the view that generalisation is impossible in the social sciences,
but treats the formulation of general prin~ples mainly as a means to an end.
The very direction in which Weber's own empirical writings led. especially
as manifest in the massive Economy and Society. caused a certain change in
emphasis in this standpoint. Weber did not relinquish his fundamental stand
upon the absolute logical disjunction 1letween factual and value-judgements,
nor the correlate thesis that the analysis of unique historical configurations
cannot be carried through solely in terms of general principles. these latter
being only of prefatory significance to such a task. In Economy and Society.
however. the focus of Weber's interest moves more towards a direct concern
with the establishment of uniformities of social and economic organisation:
that is, towards sociology.
Sociology, Weber says. is concerned with the formulation of general prin-
ciples and generic type concepts in relation to human social action; history,
by contrast, • is directed towards the causal analysis and explanation of par-
ticular, culturally significant. actions, structures, and personalities '.1 This, of
course, reiterates the basic position established in the methodological essays,
and it may be said that in general the shift in Weber's concerns in the direc-
tion of sociology is a change of emphasis in his own personal interests rather
than a modification of his basic methodological views. The degree to which
Economy and Society represents a new departure in Weber's thinking has
often been exaggerated in secondary accounts of Weber's thought. Economy
and Society forms part of a large-scale collaborative work on different aspects
of political economy: Weber intends his own contribution to provide a pre-
face to the more specialised volumes written by his collaborating authors.'
145
146 Part 3: Max Weber
In describing his objectives in writing Economy and Society Weber indicates
that the sociological analysis contained in it performs a task of ' very modest
preparation • which is necessary to the study of specific historical phenomena .
• It is then the concern of history to give a causal explanation of these
particular characteristics.' 3
In his essay on ' objectivity'. Weber emphasises that' in the social sciences
we are concerned with mental phenomena the empathic" understanding" of
which is naturally a task of a specifically different type from those which the
schemes of the exact natural sciences in general can or seek to solve '.~ One
of the main steps to the analysis of social phenomena. therefore. is that of
'rendering intelligible' the subjective basis upon which it rests; a principal
theme of the essay. of course. is that the possibility of the' objective • analysis
of social and historical phenomena is not precluded by the fact that human
activity has a 'subjective' character. On the other band. this subjectivity
cannot simply be eschewed from consideration by confiating natural and
social science. In outlining his conception of 'interpretative sociology' in
Economy ami Society. Weber preserves this stress upon the significance of
the subjective for sociological analysis. s
'In the sense in which this highly ambiguous word is used here '. Weber
says. sociology' shall be taken to refer to a science concerning itself with the
interpretive understanding of social action and thereby with a causal explana-
tion of its course and consequences'.' Social action or conduct (soziaies
Handeln) is that in which the subjective meaning involved relates to another
individual or group. There are two senses in which the meaning of action may
be analysed: either in reference to the concrete meaning which action has
for a given individual actor, or in relation to an ideal type of subjective
meaning on the part of a hypothetical actor.
There is no clear-cut separation in reality between action thus defined, and
behaviour which is purely unthinking or automatic. Large sectors of human
activity which are important for sociological purposes lie on the margins of
meaningful action: this is especially true of behaviour of a traditional kind.
Moreover. the same empirical activity may involve a fusion of understandable
and non-understandable elements. This may be the case. for instance. in some
forms of religious activity; which may involve mystical experiences which
coUection was terminated. See Johannes Winckelmann: • Max Webers Opus Post-
humum', Zeitschrilt liir die gesamten Slaalswissenschalten, vol. 105. 1949, pp.
368-87.
3 Letter to Georg von Below, June 1914, quoted in von Below: De, deutsche Slaal
des Mittelalters (LeipZig, 1925), p. xxiv.
• MSS, p. 74; GAW. p. 173.
I The ac:c:ount presented in the first volume of ES is a revised version of an eattier
essay' Ober einige Kategorien der verstehenden Soziologie '. GAW, pp. 427-74
(originally published in 1913).
• ES, vol. I, p. 4; WuG. vol. J, p. 1. cr. Julien Freund: The Socio/OD 01 Max Weber
(London, 1968), pp. 90-1.
Fundamental concepts of sociology 147
are only partially understandable to a social scientist who has not experienced
them. The full recapitulation of an e)tperience is, of course, not necessary to
this task of rendering it analytically intelligible: '" one need not have been
Caesar in order to understand Caesar" '. 7
It is important to capture the main drift of Weber's argument here. While
he accepts that subjective meaning is a basic component of much human con-
duct, Weber's point is that intuitionism is not the only doctrine which can
offer the possibility of studying this; on the contrary, interpretative sociology
can and must be based upon techniques of the interpretation of meaning which
are replicable, and thus are verifiable according to the conventional canons
of scientific method. This can be accomplished, according to Weber. either
by rational understanding of logical relationships which form part of the
subjective framework of the actor, or by understanding of a more emotive-
sympathetic kind. Rational understanding is most complete and precise in
the instance of the use by the actor of mathematical reasoning or formal logic.
, We have a perfectly clear understanding of what it means when somebody
employs the proposition 2X2=4 or the Pythagorean theorem in reasoning
or argument. or when someone correctly carries out a logical train of reason-
ing according to our accepted modes of thinking.' • But there is no absolutely
clear line between the comprehensioq of propositions of logic in this strict
sense. and the manner in which we 'Anderstand the actions of a man who
rationally selects and employs a given means to reach a practical end. While
empathy is an important means of obtaining understanding of action which
takes place in an emotive context. it is mistaken to identify empathy. and
understanding: the latter demands not merely a sentiment of emotional sym-
pathy on the part of the sociologist. but the grasping of the subjective intelli-
gibility of action. In general. however. it is true thaL the more the ideals
towards which human activity is directed are foreign to those which govern
our own conduct. the harder it is to understand the meaning they have for
those who hold them. We must accept. in these circumstances, that only par-
tial comprehension is possible, and when even this cannot be attained, we hav~
to be content to treat them as' given data '.
Sociology, must of course, take account of objects and events which influ-
ence human activity. but which are devoid of subjective meaning. These
phenomena (which include. for example. climatic, geographical and biological
factors) are' conditions' of human behaviour. but do not necessarily have any
relationship to any human purpose. But in so far as such phenomena do be-
Come involved with human subjective ends. they take on meaning, and become
elements within social action. An artifact such as a machine' can be under-
stOod only in terms of the meaning (Sinn) which its production and use have
had or were intended to have ...•.•
: ES. vol. I, p. S. Carlo Antoni: From History to Sociology (London, 1962). p. 170.
& ES, vol. I, p. S. • ES. vol. I, p. 7; WllG, vol. 1, p. 3.
148 Part 3: Max Weber
The scientific analysis of social action. in so far as it proceeds beyond mere
description. proceeds through the construction of ideal types: and. given the
difficulties involved in the understanding of many forms of value-directed or
emotively influenced action. it is normally useful to construct rational types.
Having specified in the ideal type what constitutes rational action. deviation
from it can be examined in terms of the influence of irrational elements. The
main advantage of rational ideal types has already been demonstrated. Weber
considers. in economics: they are precise in formulation and unambiguous in
application. Weber emphasises this as a procedural point; it is a methodolo-
gical device the use of which does not in any sense imply the existence of a
• rationalist bias '.
Weber distinguishes two basic kinds of interpretative grasp of meaning,
each of which may be subdivided according to whether it involves the under-
standing of rational or of emotive actions. The first kind is 'direct under-
standing '. In this case. we understand the meaning of an action through direct
observation: the rational subdivision of direct understanding can be illus-
trated by the example quoted previously. of the comprehension of a mathe-
matical proposition. We understand the meaning of the sum 2X2=4 at once
if we hear it spoken. or see it written. Direct understanding of irrational con-
duct, on the other hand. is shown. for example. where we ' understand an out-
break of anger as manifested by facial expression. exclamations or irrational
emotional reactions '. The second ki!td of understanding. 'explanatory under-
standing' (erkliirendes Verstehen) differs from this in that it involves the
elucidation of an intervening motivationalIink between the observed activity
and its meaning to the actor. Here there are similarly two subsidiary forms.
The rational form consists in the understanding of action where an individual
is engaged in an activity which involves the use of a given means to realise a
particular purpose. Thus. in the example which Weber adduces. if an observer
sees a man chopping wood, and knows that he wishes to get some fuel in to
light his fire. he is able without difficulty to grasp the rational content of the
other's action. The same sort of indirect proCess of motivational inference
can be made in relation to irrational conduct. So. for instance. we are able to
understand. in this sense. the response of a person who bursts into tears if we
know that he has just suffered a bitter disappointment
In explanatory understanding. the particular action concerned is 'placed
in an understandable sequence of motivation. the understanding of which
can be treated as an explanation of the actual course of behaviour. Thus for a
science which is concerned with the subjective meaning of action. explanation
requires a grasp of the complex of meaning (Sinnzusammenhang) in which an
actual course of understandable action thus interpreted belongs.' 10 This is
extremely important in Weber's conception of the application of interpretative
10 ES, vol. I, p. 9. For an analysis of the theoretical significance of this, see Parsons,
pp.63Sff.
Fundamental concepts of sociology 149
sOCiology to empirical analysis. The understanding of 'motivation' always
involves relating the particular conduct concerned to a broader normative
standard with reference to which the individual acts. In order to reach the
level of causal explanation, a distinction has to be made between' subjective •
and' causal • adequacy. The interpretation of a given course of action is sub-
jectively adequate (adequate 'on the level of meaning ') if the motivation
which is attributed to it accords with recognised or habitual normative pat-
terns. This entails showing. in other words. that the action concerned is mean-
ingful in that it 'makes sense' in terms of accepted norms. But this is not
enough. in itself. to provide a viable explanation of the particular action.
Indeed. it is the basic fallacy of idealist philosophy to identify subjective
adequacy with causal adequacy. The essential flaw in tbis view is that there
is no direct and simple relationship between • complexes of meaning',
motives. and conduct. Similar actions on the part of several individuals may
be the result of a diversity of motives and. conversely. similar motives can be
linked to different concrete forms of behaviour. Weber does not attempt 10
deny the complex character of human motivation. Men often experience con-
flicts of motives; and those motives of which a man is consciously aware may
be largely rationalisations of deeper motives of which he is unconscious. The
sociologist must be cognisant of thes.~ possibilities. and ready to deal with
them on an empirical level - althouglt. of course, the more it is the case that
an activity is the result of impulses that are not accessible to consciousness,
the more this becomes a marginal phenomenon for the interpretation of
meaning.
For these reasons, ' causal' adequacy demands that it should be possible
'to determine that there is a probability. which in the rare ideal case can be
numerically stated, but is always in some sense calculable. that a given observ-
able event (overt or subjective) will be followed or accompanied by another
event '.11 Thus, in order to demonstrate explanatory significance, there must be
an established empirical generalisation which relates the subjective meaning
of the act to a specified range of determinable consequences. It fo])ows from
the intrinsic suppositions of Weber's method. of course, that if any such
generalisation, however precisely verified. lacks adequacy on the level of
meaning. then it remains a statistical correlation outside the scope of
interpretative sociology :
Only those statistical regularities are thus sociological generalisations which cor-
respond to an understandable common meaning of a course of social action, and
constitute understandable types of action, in the sense of the term used here.
OnJy those rational formulations of subjectively understandable action which
can at least with some degree of closeness be observed in reality, constitute socio-
11 ES, vol. I, pp. 11-12. Given this condition. as Weber makes clear in his critique of
Roscher and Knies. . The .. interpretative" motive-research of the historian is
~ausalattribution in exactly the same sense as the causal interpretation of any
mdividual process in nature .. .'. GAW. p. 134.
ISO Part 3: Max Weber
logical types relating to real events. It is by no means the case that the actual
likelihood of the occurrence of a given course of overt action is always propor-
tional to the clarity of subjective interpretation. 12
There are many sorts of statistical data which, while they may relate to
phenomena which conceivably influence human behaviour, are not meaning-
ful in Weber's sense of that term. But meaningful action is not refractory to
statistical treatment: sociological statistics in this sense include, for example,
crime rates or statistics of the distribution of occupations.
Weber does not limit the range of information which is of value in the
study of human social conduct to that which can be analysed according to
the method of interpretative sociology. There are many sorts of processes
and influences which have causal relevance for social life which are not
'understandable'. but the importance of which Weber by no means dis-
counts. It is essential to stress this, since it has become commonplace to
suppose that, according to Weber, interpretative sociology is the sole basis of
generalisation in relation to human social conduct Weber is conscious that
his own limitation of the term 'sociology' to the analysis of subjectively
meaningful action cross-cuts other conceptions of the ranse of the field which
are often applied: 'sociology in our sense ... is restricted to " interpretative
sociology" (verstehende Soziolog;e) - a usage which no-one else should Or
can be compelled to follow.' 13
Weber's specific reference to organicist sociology, &uch as represented by
SchafRe's BOll und Leben des Socialen Kiirpers - which Weber calls a 'bril-
liant work • - is of relevance here. Functionalism. Weber notes, has a definite
utility in approaching the study of social life : as a means of • practical illus-
tration and for provisional orientation ... it is not only useful but indispen-
sable '.14 Just as in the case of the study of organic systems. in the social
sciences functional analysis allows us to identify which units within the
• whole • [society] it is important to study. But at a certain point the analogy
between society and organism breaks down. in that in the analysis of the
former it is possible. and also necessary. to go beyond the establishment of
functional uniformities. Rather than being a barrier to scientific knowledge.
however. the achievement of interpretative understanding should be regarded
as offering explanatory possibilities which are unavailable in the natural
sciences. This does not come wholly without cost though: it is paid for by
the lower level of precision and certainty of findings characteristic of the
social sciences.
Where Weber does differ sharply with Schaffie is on the issue of the logical
status of holistic concepts. Those sociologists who take their point of depar-
ture from the' whole' and from thence approach the analysis of individual
U ES, vol. I, p. 13; WuG, vol. I, p. 6. For an cxtcnsive critical consideration of this
and other points in Weber's outline of interpretative sociology, see Alfred Schutz:
"~
.:.S, voL I, p. 19. .
The Phenomenology of the Social World (Evanston 1967).
11 FMW, p. 120.
Fundamental concepts of sociology 153
action is that which is carried out under the sway of some sort of emotive
state, and as such is on the borderline of meaningful and non-meaningful
conduct. It shares with value rational action the characteristic that the mean-
ing of the action is not located, as in purposively rational conduct, in the
instrUmentality of means to ends. but in carrying out the act for its own sake.
The fourth type of orientation of action. ' traditional • action. also overlaps
the margins of meaningful and non-meaningful conduct. Traditional action
is carried out under the influence of custom and habit. This applies to the
• great bulk of all everyday action to which people have become habitually
accustomed .. .'.JQ In this type, the meaning of action is derived from ideals
or symbols which do not have the coherent, defined form of those which
are pursued in value rationality. In so far as traditional values become
rationalised, traditional action merges with value rational action.
This fourfold typology which Weber delineates underlies the empirical
substance of Economy and Society, but it is not intended as an overall classi-
fication of social action; it is an ideal typical schema which provides a mode
of applying Weber's stated dictum that the analysis of social action can best
be pursued through the use of rational types against which irrational devia-
tions can be measured. Thus a particular empirical instance of human con-
duct can be interpreted according to which of the four types of action it most
closely approximates. But very few en'fpirical cases
will not in fact include. in
varying combinations, a mixture of elements from more than one type.
In his discussion of the difficulties posed by the problem of verification in
interpretative sociology. Weber stresses that causal adequacy always is a
matter of degrees of probability. Those who have argued that human
behaviour is ' unpredictable • arc demonstrably mistaken: • the characteristic
of II incalculability ..... is the privilege of - the insane '.21 But the uniformities
which are found in human conduct are expressible only in terms of the pro-
bability that a particular act or circumstance will produce a given response
from an actor. Every social relationship thus may be said to rest upon the
• probability' (which must not be confused with • chance' in the sense of
, accident') that an actor or plurality of actors will direct their action in a
specified manner. To affirm the element of contingency in human conduct. in
Weber's view. is not to deny its regularity and predictability; but it is to
emphasise once again the contrast between meaningful conduct and the
inVariant response characteristic of. for example. a subconsciously mediated
Withdrawal reaction t~ a painful stimulus.
In setting out a conceptual taxonomy of the principal types of social
relationship and more inclusive forms of social organisation. Weber thus
couches his description in terms of probability. Every social relationship
~. Weber distiDguishes at one point between' guaranteed' law and • indirectly guaran-
teed' law. The first type is backed directly by a coercive apparatus. The second type
refers to the case of a no~ ~e. transgression of which is not legally punished, but
has the consequence of lnfnngmg other norms which are guanu.teed laws. But
Weber normally uses' law' without qualification to denote guaranteed law.
156 Part 3: Max Weber
exists in any circumstance in which a group - such as a kinship group or a
religious body - assumes the task of applying sanctions to punish trans-
gressions. In fact, the influence of religious groups upon the rationalisation
of law is a main theme in Weber's empirical writings. In more general terms,
the inter-relationships between the 'legal 'J ' religious' and' political' are of
decisive significance to economic structures and economic development.
Weber defines a ' political' society as one whose' existence and order is con-
tinuously safeguarded within a given territorial area by the threat and applica-
tion of physical force on the part of the administrative staff '. This does not
imply. of course, that political organisations exist only through the continual
use of force. merely that the threat or actual employment of force is used as an
ultimate sanction. which may be utilised when all else fails. A political
organisation becomes a 'state' where it is able successfully to exercise a
legitimate monopoly over the organised use of force within a given territory.27
Weber defines' power' (Macht) as the probability that an actor will be
able to realise his own objectives even against opposition from others with
whom he is in a social relationship. This definition is very broad indeed: in
this sense, every sort of social relationship is. to some degree and in certain
circumstat!ces. a power relationship. The concept of 'domination' (Herr-
schaft) is more specific: it refers only to those cases of the exercise of power
where an actor obeys a specific command issued by another.2I Acceptance
of domination may rest upon quite different motives. ranging from sheer habit
to the cynical promotion of self-advantage. The possibility of obtaining
material rewards and of securing social esteem, however. are two of the
most pervasive forms of tie binding leader and follower." But no stable
system of domination is based purely upon either automatic habituation or
upon the appeal to self-interest: the main prop is belief by subordinates in
the legitimacy of their subordination.
Weber distinguishes three ideal type..'1 of legitimacy upon which a relation-
ship of domination may rest: traditional, charismatic. and legal. Traditional
authority is based upon the belief in the 'sanctity of age-old rules and
powers '.30 In the most elementary kinds of traditional domination, those who
rule have no specialised administrative staff through which they exercise their
authority. In many small rural communities, authority is held by the village
elders: those who are oldest are considered to be most steeped in traditional
wisdom and thereby qualified to hold authority. A second form of traditional
31 ES, vol. I, p. 231. I have also used here Weber's earlier account of patrimonialism in
ES, vol. 3, pp. 1006-10.
32 Weber's alternative exposition is to be found in ES, vol. 3, pp. 956-1005; the later
version is in vol. I, pp. 217-26.
33 ES, vol. I, p. 217; WuG, vol. I, p. 125.
158 ParI 3: Max Weber
owe no personal allegiance to a superordinate, and follow his commands only
within the restricted sphere in which his jurisdiction is clearly specified.
The pure type of bureaucratic organisation shows the following charac-
teristics. The activities of the administrative staff are carried out on a regular
basis, and thus constitute well-defined official • duties '. The spheres of com·
petence of the officials are clearly demarcated, and levels of authority are
delimited in the form of a hierarchy of offices. The rules governing conduct
of the staff, their authority and responsibilities, are recorded in writte!l
form. Recruitment is based upon demonstration of specialised competence
via competitive examinations or the possession of diplomas or degrees giving
evidence of appropriate qualifications. Office property is not owned by the
official, and a separation is maintained between the official and the office.
such that under no conditions is the office • owned' by its incumbent. This
type of organisation has distinct consequences for the position of the official:
1. The career of the official is governed by an abstract conception of duty; the
performance of official tasks in a faithful manner is an end in itself rather
than a means of obtaining personal material gain through rents, etc. 2. The
official obtains his position through being appointed, on the basis of his tech-
nical qualifications, by a higher authority; he is not elected. 3. He normally
holds a tenured position. 4. His remuneration takes the shape of a fixed and
regular salary. S. The occupational position of the official is such as to Pf(l-
vide for • career' involving movement up the hierarchy of authority; the
degree of progression achieved is determined either by manifest ability or
seniority, or by a combination of the two.
It is only within modem capitalism that organisations are found which
approximate to this ideal typical form. The main examples of developed
bureaucracies, prior to the emergence of modem capitalism, were those of
ancient Egypt, China, the later Roman principate, and the mediaeval Catholic
church. These bureaucracies, particularly the first three, were essentially
patrimonial, and were based largely upon the payment of officials in kind.
This shows that the prior formation of a money economy is not an essenti;'ll
prerequisite to the emergence of bureaucratic organisation, although it has
been of great importance in facilitating the growth of modem rational bureau-
cracy. The advance of bureaucratisation in the modem world is directly
associated with the expansion of the division of labour in various spheres of
social life. It is basic to Weber's sociology of modem capitalism that the
phenomenon of specialisation of occupational function is by no means limited
to the economic sphere. The separation of the labourer from control of bis
means of production which Marx singled out as the most distinctive feature
of modem capitalism is not confined to industry, but extends throughout the
polity, army, and other sectors of society in which large-scale organisations
become prominent. 3' In post-mediaeval western Europe, the bureaucratisation
34 cf. GASS, pp. 49811. The importance of this point is amplified, in relation to Marx's
position, sec below, pp. 234-8.
Fundamental concepts oj sociology 159
of the state has preceded that in the economic sphere. The modem capitalist
state is completely dependent upon bureaucratic organisation for its continued
existence. 'The iarger the state, or the more it becomes a great power state,
the more unconditionally is this the case...' 3$ While sheer size of the adminis-
trative unit is a major factor determining the spread of rational bureaucratic
organisation - as in the case of the modem mass political party - there is not
a unilateral relationship between size and bureaucratisation. u The necessity
of specialisation to fulfil specific administrative tasks is as important as size
in promoting bureaucratic specialisation. Thus in Egypt. the oldest bureau-
cratic state, the development of bureaucracy was primarily determined by the
need for the regulation of irrigation by a centralised administration. In the
modern capitalist economy, the formation of a supra-local market is a major
condition stimulating the development of bureaucracy, since it demands the
regular and co-ordinated distribution of goods and services. 31
The efficiency of bureaucratic organisation in the performance of such
routinised tasks is the main reason for its spread.
The fully developed bureaucratic apparatus compares with other organisations
exactly as does the machine with the non-mechanical modes of production. Pre-
cision, speed, unambiguity, knowledge of the files, continuity, discretion, unity.
strict subordination, reduction of friction and of material and personal costs -
tbese are raised to the optimwn point in the strictly bureaucratic orgall!i5ation ...31
These qualities are demanded above all by the capitalist economy, which
requires that economic operations be discharged with speed and precision.
Weber's position on this point has often been misunderstood. Weber was
obviously aware of the view - common since the turn of the nineteenth cen-
tury - that bureaucracy is associated with' red tape ',and • inefficiency '.38 Nor
was Weber ignorant of the importance in the substantive operation of bureau-
cratic organisations of the existence of informal contacts and patterns of
relationship which overlap with the formally designated distribution of
authority and responsibilities. 40 Bureaucratic organisation may produce' de·
finite impediments for the discharge of business in a manner best adapted to
the individuality of each case '.41 It is from this latter fact that the concern
3. ES, vol. 3, p. 971; WuG, vol. 2, p. 568.
31 Weber thus criticises Michels for exaggerating the' iron' character of the tendency
towards the formation of oligarchy in bureaucracies. ES. vol. 3, pp. 1003-4.
37 It is important to emphasise that the modem state and economy do not become
totally bureaucratised. For those at • the top " specialised qualifications of a technical
kind are not required. Ministerial and presidential positions are filled through some
kind of electoral process, and tbe industrial entrepreneur is not appointed by the
bureaucracy he beads .• Thus at tbe top of a bureaucratic organisation. tbere is
necessarily an element which is at least not purely bureaucratic.' ES, vol. I, p. 222.
31 ES, vol. 3, p. 973.
39 cf. Martin Albrow: BureQucracy (London, 1970), pp. 26-54.
fO cf. Weber's contributions to the discussions of the Verein fiir Sozialpolitik in 1909,
G.4SS, pp. 412-16.
fl ES, vol. 3, pp. 974-5.
160 Part 3: Max Weber
with • red tape derives. and it is not wholly misplaced. because by its very
I
Because of its antipathy to the routine and the everyday. charisma neces-
sarily undergoes profound modification if it survives into anything like per-
manent existence. The ' routinisation • (VeraUtiiglichung) of charisma hence
involves the devolution of charismatic authority in the direction of either
traditional or legal organisation. Since charismatic authority is focused upon
the extraordinary qualities of a particular individual. a difficult problem of
succession is posed when that person dies or is in some other way removed
from the scene. The type of authority relationship which emerges as a conse-
quence of routinisation is determined in large degree by how the ' succession
problem' is resolved. Weber distinguishes several possible avenues whereby
this may take place.
One historically important solution to the succession problem is where the
charismatic leader. or his disciples who share in his charisma. designates his
successor. The successor is not elected; he is shown to possess the appropriate
charismatic qualifications for authority. According to Weber. this was the
original significance of the coronation of monarchs and bishops in western
Europe." Charisma may also be treated as a quality which is passed on
through heredity. and is consequently possessed by the closest relatives of
the original bearer. It is mainly in feudal Europe and Japan. however. that
this has become linked with the principle of primogeniture. When charismatic
domination is transmuted into a routine. traditional form. it becomes the
sacred source of legitimation for the position of those holding power; in this
way charisma forms a persisting element in social life. While this is ' alien to
its essence '. there is still justification. Weber says. for speaking of the persis-
tence of 'charisma '. since as a sacred force it maintains its extraordinary
character. However. once charisma has in this way become an impersonal
force. it no longer is necessarily regarded sa a quality which cannot be taught.
and the acquisition of charisma may come to depend partly upon a process
of education.
The routinisation of charisma demands that the activities of the adminis-
trative staff be placed upon a regular basis, which may be achieved through
either the formation of traditional norms or the establishment of legal rules.
H charisma becomes transmitted through heredity, the officialdom is likely
to become a traditional status grouP. with recruitment to positions itself being
based primarily upon inheritance. In other cases, criteria for admission to
office may become determined by tests of qualification, thus tending to the
rational legal type. Regardless of which of these lines of development is fol-
lowed, routinisation always requires the setting up of a regular series of
economic arrangements which, if the trend is towards traditionalism. will be
benefices or fiefs. and if it is towards the legal type. will take the shape of
salaried positions.
The content of the ideals promoted by the emergence of a charismatic
so The earlier rendition is in ES. vol. 2, pp. 926-40; the later analysis is to be found iu
ES. vol. I, pp. 302-7.
81 ES, vol. I. p. 63. For an earlier formulation of the concept of the • economic '. see
MSS, p. 6S.
sa ES, vol. 1, pp. 80-2.
164 Pan 3: MtU Weber
terms. Economic relationships thus free themselves from the particular ties
and obligations of local community structure, and become fluidly determined
by the material chances which individuals have of using property, goods or
services which they possess for exchange on the competitive market .• There-
with " Weber says, ." class struggles to begin.' U
The • market situation • of any object of exchange is dofined as • all the
opportunities of exchanging it for money which are known to the participants
in exchange reJationships and aid their orientation in the competitive price
6.
struggle.' Those who own comparable objects of exchange (both goods and
services) share 'in common a specific causal component of their life
chances '.66 That is to say, those who share the same market or • class situa-
tion • are all subject to similar economic exigencies. which causally inftuence
both the material standards of their existence. and what sorts of personal life
experiences they are able to enjoy. A • class' denotes an aggregate of indivi-
duals who thus share the same class situation. In these terms, those who are
propertyless, and who can only offer services on the market, are divided
according to the kinds of services they can ofter. just as those who own
property can be diJlerentiated according to what they own and how they use
it for economic ends.
Weber admits, with Marx. that ownership versus non-ownership of pro-
perty is the most important basis of class division in a competitive market. He
also follows Marx in distinguishing. among those who possess property. rentier
classes and entrepreneurial classes. which Weber calls respectively • owner-
ship classes' (Besit1.klossen) and • commercial classes' (Erwerbsklassen).
Ownership classes are those in which owners of property receive rents through
their possession of land. mines, etc. These rentiers are • positively advan-
taged , ownership classes. • Negatively advantaged' ownership classes include
all those without either property or skills to ofter (for example. the declasse
Roman proletarians). Between the positively and the negatively advantaged
groups fall a range of middle classes who either own small properties or who
possess skills which can be offered as marketable services. These include such
categories of persons as officials. artisans and peasants. Commercial classes
are those where the positively advantaged groups are either entrepreneurs
offering goods for sale on the market. or those who participate in the financ-
ing of such operations. such as bankers. u Wage-labourers constitute the
negatively advantaged commercial classes. The middle classes include the
petty bourgeoisie and administrative officials in government or in industry.
Most secondary discussions of Weber's conception of class have C(>Dcen-
trated upon his earlier discussion (see below. note 59. p. 166). and have
S1 ES, vol. 1. p. 305!'cf. Paul Mombert: • Zum Weseo der sozialen Klasse', in Melchior
Palyi: Erinnerungsgabe fur Max Weber (Munich and Leipzig, 1923), pp. 239-75.
a8 ES, vol. 2, p. 931. It is this fact, Weber points out, which has made possible the
growth of patriarchal socialism. Similarly, in the army, the soldier resents the
corporal rather than the higher echelons of command. GASS, p. 509.
166 Part J: Max Weber
for instance, in modem factory production, the workers are concentrated
together in large-scale productive units. 4. The class in question is provided
with leadership - such as from the intelligentsia - which supplies clear antJ
comprehensible goals for their activity.
, Class' refers to the objective attributes of the market situation of numbers
of individuals, and as such the influence of class upon social action operates
independently of any valuations these individuals might make of themselves
or others. Since Weber rejects the notion that economic phenomena directly
determine the nature of human ideals, it follows that such valuations have to
be conceptualised independently of class interests. Weber therefore dis-
tinguishes class situation from' status situation' (stiindische Loge). The status
situation of an individual refers to the evaluations which others make of him
or his social position. thus attributing to him some form of (positive or nega-
tive) social prestige or esteem. A status group is a number of individuals who
share the same status situation. Status groups, unlike classes, are almost
always conscious of their common position. ' In relation to classes, the status
group comes closest to the .. social Of class and is most unlike the .. com-
mercial Of class.'~· However, there is no necessary or universal connection
between status situation and any of the three types of class which Weber
distinguishes. Property classes often, but by no means always, constitute
definite status groups; commercial classes rarely do so.
Status groups normally manifest their distinctiveness through following a
particular life-style, and through placing restrictions upon the manner in
which others may interact with them. The enforcement of restrictions upon
marriage, sometimes involving strict endogamy, is a particularly frequent way
in which this may be achieved. Caste represents the most clear-cut example
of this; here the distinctive character of the status group is held to rest upon
ethnic factors, and is enforced by religious prescriptions as well as by legal
and conventional sanctions. While it is only in traditional India that a whole
society is organised according to strict caste principles, caste-like properties
are also characteristic of the position of 'pariah • peoples. These are ethnic
minorities, the most notable historical example of which is that of the Jews,
whose economic activities are limited to a particular occupation or range
of occupations, and whose contacts with the ' host • population are limited.
Stratification by status is not, for Weber. simply a • complication' of class
hierarchies: 00 the contrary. status groups. as differentiated from classes.
are of vital significance in numerous phases of historical development. More-
owr, status groups may act to influence in a direct way the operation of the
market. and so may causally affect class relationships. One historically im-
portant way in which this has occurred is through the restriction of the
at ES, vol. I, pp. 306-7; WllG, vol. I, p. 180. For Marx's use of the term Stand, see
above, p. 6, D. 22.
Fundamental concepts 0/ sociology 167
spheres of economic life which are permitted to become governed by the
market:
For example, in many Hellenic aties durin8 the • status era ' and also orisiDally in
Rome, the inherited estate (as is shown by the old fonnula for placing spend-
thrifts under a auardian) was monopolised, as were the estates of knights, pea-
sants, priests, and especially the clientele of the craft and merchant guilds. The
market is restricted, and the power of naked property per se, which gives its stamp
to class formation, is pushed into the background.'o
Many instances can be adduced in which men draw clear distinctions
between economic possession and status privilege. The possession of material
property is not by any means always a sufficient basis for entry into a
dominant status group. The claims of nouveaux riches for entry to an estab-
lished status group are not likely to be accepted by those within it, although
the individual can ordinarily use his wealth to ensure that his offspring can
acquire the necessary criteria for membership. Nevertheless, Weber does
stress that, while status group membership' normally stands in sharp opposi-
tion to the pretensions of sheer property'. it is still the case that property is
• in the long run' recognised • with extraordinary regularity' as a status
qualification. t1 The degree to which status stratification is prevalent in any
given social order is influenced by how far the society in question is subject
to rapid economic transformation. Where marked economic changes are
occurring. class stratification is a more pervasive determinant of action than
in a situation wbere there is little cbange. In the latter case, status differentials
come increasingly to the fore.
Both class and status group membership may be a basis of social power;
but the formation of political parti:s is a further. analytically independent,
influence upon the distribution of power. A • party' refers to any voluntary
association whicb has the aim of securing directive control of an organisation
in order to implement certain definite policies within that organisation. In
this definition. parties can exist in any form of organisation in which the
formation of freely recruited groupings is permitted: from a sports club up
to the state. la The bases for the establishment of parties, even of modem
political parties, are diverse. A common class or status situation may provide
the sole source of recruitment to a political party but this is fairly rare. • In
any individual case, parties may represent interests determined through class
situation or status situation.... But they need be neither purely class nor
purely status parties; in fact. they are more likely to be mixed types, and
sometimes they are neither.' I I
The growth of the modem state has brought witb it the development of
mass political parties. and tbe emergence of professional politicians. A man
Whose occupation is concerned with the struggle for political power may
Weber collectively entitles his studies of Judaism and the religions of China
and India, 'The economic ethics of the world religions '.1 The title is indica-
tive of the main thrust of Weber's interests, and manifests a line of immediate
continuity with the themes of his earlier essay on Calvinism and the spirit of
western capitalism. But in fact these subsequent studies embrace a much
broader range of social and historical phenomena than is suggested by the
relatively modest heading with which Weber prefaces them. The relationship
between the content of religious beliefs and the forms of economic activity
which characterise a given social order is often indirect. and is influenced by
other institutions within that order.
Weber stresses that his studies of the world religions
do not in any way constitute a systematic • typology' of religion. On the other
hand, they do not constitute a purely bistorical worlc. They are • typological' in
the sense that they consider what is typically important in the historical realisa-
tions of religious ethics. This.is important for the connection of religioDS with the
great contrasts of economic mentalities. Othe'l' aspects will be neglected; these
presentations do not claim to offer a well-rounded picture of world religiooa.2
More particularly, Weber states, the inftuence of religious ethics upon
economic organisation is to be considered above all from one specific stand-
point: in terms of their connections with the advance or retardation of
rationalism such as has come to dominate economic life in the West.
In using the term • economic ethic', Weber does not imply, then. that each
of the sets of religious beliefs which he analyses contains an explicit and
clearly formulated directive as to what sorts of economic activity are con-
sidered to be permissible or desirable. The degree of immediacy. as well as
the nature. of the influence of religion upon economic life is variable. As in
The Protestant Ethic, the focus of Weber's attention is directed not upon the
internal • logic' as such of a given religious ethic. but upon the psychological
and social consequences for the actions of individuals. Weber continues to
maintain his aloofness from either materialism or idealism as providing a
viable general interpretation of either the sources or the effects of the religious
phenomena: • externally similar forms of economic organisation are com-
patible with very different economic ethics and. according to their particular
character. may produce very different historical results. An economic ethic
is not a simple" function" of a form of economic organisation; and just as
169
170 Part 3: Max Weber
little does the reverse hold.' 3 Of course, religious beliefs are only one among
various sets of influences which may condition the formation of an economic
ethic, and religion itself is heavily influenced by other social, political and
economic phenomena.
3 FMW, pp. 267-8; GAR, vol. 1, p. 238. 4 ES, vol. 2, pp. 399-634.
• But Weber does not sUess, as Durkheim does, the radical nature of the dichotomy
of the • sacred' and • profane '. Weber holds that • religious or magical behaviour
or thinking must not be set apart from the range of everyday purposive conduct,
particularly since even the ends of the religious and magical actions are pre-
dominantly economic'. ES, vol. 2, p. 400.
• cf., for example, Gerth and Mills: • Introduction' to FMW, pp. 53-5.
, Weber notes: • The belief in the universality of toternism, and certainly the belief
in the derivation of virtually all social groups and all religions from totemism,
constitutes a tremendous exaggeration that has been rejected completel}' by now.'
ES, vol. 2, p. 434.
Rationalisation, the • world religions' and western capitalism 171
stitute truths the denial of which is considered to be heretical. The most im-
portant of these are those of transmigration of souls and compensation
(karma). Both of these are directly bound up with the social ordering of the
caste system. The doctrine of karma • represents the most consistent theodicy
ever produced by history '.1$ Because of it, Weber says. adopting a slogan from
the Communist Manifesto. the Hindu of the very lowest caste can • win the
world': he can realistically aspire. within the context of these beliefs. through
successive incarnations. to reach the very highest levels. to reach paradise
and obtain divinity. Through the doctrinal stipulation that the conduct of
the individual in his present life has irremediable consequences in his next
incarnation. and because this is directly tied into the caste system. Hindu
orthodoxy places insuperable barriers in the face of any challenge to the
existing social order.
Estranged castes might stand beside one another with bitter hatred - for the idea
that everybody had • deserved' his own fate. did not make the good fortune of
others more enjoyable to the socially underprivileged. For so long and insofar
as the Karma doctrine remamed unshaken, revolutionary ideas or the striving fOT
• progress' were inconceivable.a
During the era in the early history of India in which Hinduism became
firmly established. about four or five centuries before the birth of Christ. the
development of manufacture and trade reached a peak. Merchant and craft
guilds in the cities had an importance in urban economic organisation com-
parable to the guilds of mediaeval Euro~. Moreover. rational science was
highly developed in India, and numerous schools of philosophy flomished
there at different periods. These existed in an atmosphere of tolerance which
has been almost unrivalled elsewhere. Juridical systems were formed which
were as mature as those of mediaeval Europe. But the emergence of the caste
system. together with the ascendancy of the Brahmin priesthood. effectively
prevented any further economic development in the direction of that taken in
Europe.
The uniqueness of the development of India, however, lay in the fact that these
beginnings of guild and corporate organisatien in the cities led neither to the city
autonomy of the Occidental type nor, after the coming into being of the great
patrimonial states, to a social and economic organisation of the territories corres-
ponding to the • territorial economy' of the Occident Rather, the Hindu caste
system, whose beginnings certainly preceded that era, became paramount. In
part, this caste system entirely displaced the other organisations; in part. it
crippled them ; it prevented them from attaining any considerable importance. IS
The main influence of caste upon economic activity has been to ritually
stabilise the occupationaJ structure, and thereby to act against the further
advance of ration'ilisation of the economy. The emphasis of caste ritualism
in labour is upon the dignity and value of traditional ski11s in the production
13 RI. p. 21.
1. RI, pp. 122-3; GAR. vol. 2. p. 122. 15 RI. pp. 33-4; GAR. vol. 2. pp. 35-6.
174 Pan 3: Max Weber
of objects of beauty. Any attempt upon the part of an individual to break free
of these vocational prescriptions damages his chances of a more favourable
incarnation in his next life. It is for this reason that it is just the lowest-
caste individual who is likely to adhere most rigorously to his caste obliga-
tions. The negative influence of the caste system upon economic development.
however. is diffuse rather than specific. It would not be true to say. for ex-
ample. that caste organisation is completely incompatible with the existence
of large-scale productive enterprises with a complex division of labour. o(
the sort which are characteristic of modem industry in the West. This can be
seen by the partial success of colonialist firms in India. Nevertheless. Weber
concludes.
it still must be considered ~tremely unlikely that the modem organisation of in-
dustrial capitalism would ever have originated on the basis of the caste system. A
ritual law in which every change of occupation. every change in work technique.
may result in ritual degradation is certainly not capable of giving birth to econo-
mic and technical revolutions from within itself... 1.
There were important similarities between the position of the Brahmins in
India and that of the Confucian literati in traditional China. Both were status
groups whose domination rested largely upon their access to classical scrip-
tures written in a language separate from that of the laity. although. accord-
ing to Weber. Hindu intellectualism was much less of a purely written
culture than the Chinese. Both groups disclaimed any connection with magic
even if this was not always successful in practice; both rejected every sort of
Dionysian orgiasticism. 11
However, there were equally important dilferences between the two groups.
The Chinese literati were an officialdom. within a patrimonial bureaucracy;
the Brahmins were originally a priesthood, but were also employed in a
variety of occupations, as chaplains to princes. jurists. theological teachers
and counseUors.18 But among the Brahmins an official career was unusual.
The unification of China under a single monarch allowed the linking of
admission to official positions to literary qualification. Those having intellec-
tual training became the source of recruitment to the bureaucratic official-
dom. In India, on the other hand, the Brahmin priesthood became strongly
established prior to the development of the early universal kingships. Thus
the Brahmins were able to avoid incorporation within a hierarchy. and at the
same time laid claim to a status position which was. in principle. superior to
that of the kings.
In traditional China there were, at certain periods, a number of important
developments which Weber distinguishes as conducive to the rationalisation
of the economy. These include the emergence of cities and of guilds nol
11 Ri, p. 112.
11 In neither India nor China was magic eliminated from the activity of the bulk of the
general population; magical cults often flourished in India and in China.
11 RI. pp. 139-40.
Rationalisation. the • world religions' and western capitalism 175
unlike those of India: the formation of a monetary system: the development
of law; and the achievement of political integration within a patrimonial
state. But there were certain significant differences between the nature of
some of these developments in China. and those which played a role in the
rise of European capitalism. In spite of the relatively high degree of urbanisa-
tion achieved in China in ancient times. and of the volume of internal trade.
the formation of money economy only'reached a comparatively rudimentary
leve1. Moreover. the Chinese city differed considerably from that character-
istic of Europe. This was in part a result of the failure to develop a money
economy beyond a certain point: 'In China, there were no cities like
Florence which could have created a standard coin and guided the State in
monetary policies.' 19 Equally important. the Chinese city did not acquire
the political autonomy and legal indl!pendence which were possessed by the
mediaeval European urban communities.
The citizen of the Chinese city tended to retain most of his primary kinship
ties with his native village; the city remained embedded in the local agrarian
economy. and did not set itself up against it, as happened in the West. No
equivalent to the • chalter' of the English burgesses ever existed in China.
Thus the potential importance of the guilds. which had a great deal of inter-
nal autonomy, was effectively curbed by the lack of political and legal
independence of the urban administrations. The low level of political auto-
nomy of the cities is partly to be attributed to the early development of the
state bureaucracy. The bureaucrats played a major part in the promotion of
urbanisation. but thereby were also able to regulate its subsequent develop-
ment, a control which they never completely relinquished. This again COll-
trasts with the West. where governmental bureaucracy was in large degree
a product of the prior formation of the autonomous city states. 20
One of the most important features of the social structure of traditional
China was that the Emperor combined both religious and political supre-
macy. China lacked a powerful stratum of priests, and did not generate pro-
phecy which offered a decisive challenge to the imperial order. While the
charismatic component in the Emperorship became heavily overlain with
traditional elements. even up to modem times the Emperor was expected to
manifest his charisma in controlling rainfall and the rivers. If the rivers broke
through the dykes, the Emperor had to perform public penitence, and in
common with all the officials was subject to censorial reprimand.
The actual degree of effective administrative centralisation in traditional
China. as in all large patrimonial states having poor communications, was
low, as compared to the modem European nation state. But the centrifugal
tendencies which might have permanently devolved into feudalism were
effectively countered by the system of using educational qualifications as a
I. RC. p. 13.
20 RC, p. 16.
176 Part 3: Max Weber
basis for appointment to bureaucratic positions: this had the consequence
of binding the officialdom to the Emperor and to the state. The record of each
otJicial was reassessed every three years, and he was thus subject to the con-
tinuous supervision of the state educational authorities. The officials were
salaried in theory, but in practice their salaries were not paid or only
accounted for a fraction of their income. Their economic interests were
highly conservative, because of the systematic use of official positions to
obtain income from tax revenues:
Profit opportunities were not individually appropriated by the highest and domi·
nant stratum of officialdom; rather, they were appropriated by the whole estate
of removable officials. It was the latter who collectively opposed intervention and
persecuted with deadly hatred any rational ideologist who called for • refonn '.
Only violent revolution from above or below could have changed this. 21
The lack of political autonomy of the urban communities in China must
not be taken to imply the absence of local power. Much of Weber's analysis
is in fact concerned with documenting the fluctuating tensions in the relation-
ship between the central authority and the provinces. Particularly important
in this connection were the powerful extended family units which provided
a major focus of economic activity and Co-operdtion. The kinship group
(tsung-tsu) was either the direct basis or the model for virtually all forms
of economic enterprise larger than the household. The tsung-tsu typically con-
trolled food-processing. weaving. and other domestic handicraft industries.
and also provided credit facilities for its members. In both rural and urban
production, co-operative control by the kinship group was supreme, mini-
mising individual entrepreneurial activity and free mobility of labour. both
o( which were essential characteristics of European capitalism. The power
of the local elders provided a major counterweight to the rule of the literati.
Irrespective of how qualified the official, in certain matters within the juris-
diction of the kinship grouP. he was subject to the authority of the most
illiterate clan elder.
The Chinese educational system gave no training in calculation in spite of
the fact that some forms of mathematics were already developed by the
sixth century B.C. The methods of calculation which were used in commerce
hence had to be learnt in practice, and were cut off from formal education.
In content, education was wholly literary, and directed towards the intimate
knowledge of classical writings. Because of their familiarity with these
writings, the literati were believed to possess charismatic qualities. But they
were not a hereditary priesthood like the Indian Brahmins, and Con-
fucianism is very different from the mystic religiosity of the Hindus. Weber
remarks that Chinese has no synonym for the English word ' religion '. The
Dearest approximations are terms meaning • doctrine' and • rite', which
make no distinction between the sacred and the secular.
21 Re, p. 60.
Rationalisation, the • world religions' and western capitalism 177
In Confucianism. the social order is regarded as a particular case of the
cosmic order in general. the latter being considered to be eternal and
inevitable.
The great spirits of the cosmic orders obviously desired only the happiness of the
world and especially the happiness of man. The same applied to the orders of
society. The • happy' tranquillity of the Empire and the equilibrium of the soul
should and could be attained only if man fitted himself into the internally har-
monious cosmos.22
What is most valued in Confucianism is the • cultivated man '. who be-
haves with universal dignity and propriety. and who is in unison with
himself and the outside world. Self-control. the regulation of emotion. is
demanded by this ethic; since the harmony of the soul is the ultimate good,
passion must not be allowed to disturb this balance. The notion of sin. and
the corresponding concept of salvation, are absent. The Confucian emphasis
upon self-control is most emphatically not wedded to an asceticism. such as
is found in Hinduism. which seeks salvation from the toils of the woc1d.
Weber concludes his study of China by drawing an explicit comparison
between Confucianism and Puritanism. There ace two primary. although
interrelated. criteria in terms of which the degree of rationalisation of a
religion may be determined: how far magic has been eliminated. and ho"
far there has developed an internally consistent and universally applicable
theodicy. With regard to the first. ascetic Protestantism has been more radical
than any other religion: in terms of the second. however. Confucianism ranks
with Puritanism as having attained a high level of formal rationality. But the
content of Confucian rationalism and consequently its relationship to the
imperfections or irrationalities of reality. was quite difterent from that of
rational Puritanism. Whereas the Puritan ethic introduced a deep tension
between religious ideals and the earthly world. that of Confucianism centred
upon the harmonious adaptation of the individual to an inevitably given
order.
For the Confucian ideal man, the gendeman, • grace and dignity • were expressed
in fulfilling traditional obligations. Hence. the cardinal virtue and goal in self-
perfection meant ceremonial and ritualist propriety in all circumstances of life...
The Confucian demanded no other kind ·of • redemption' save that from the bar-
baric lack of education. As the reward of virtue he expected only long life, health,
and wealth in this world and beyond death simply the maintenance of his good
name. As for truly Hellenic man any sort of transcendental anchorage of ethics,
any tension between obligations to a supra-mundane God and world of the flesh,
any pursuance of a goal in the beyond. or conception of radical evil. was lack-
ing... The relentlessly and religiously systematised utilitarianism peculiar to ra-
tional asceticism [i.e., ascetic Protestantism]. to live • in ' the world and yet not
be • of' it, has helped to produce superior rational aptitudes and therewith the
spirit of the specialised man [Berufsmensch] which, in the last analysis, was denied
to Confucianism ... The contrast can teach us that mere sobriety and thriftiness
22 Re, p. 153.
178 Part 3: Max Weber
combined with· acqui9.itiveness • and valuation of wealth. were far from represent-
ing and far from releasing the' capitalist spirit'. in the sense that this is found in
the specialised economic man of the modern economy.23
Thus, in spite of the various factors which might have acted to promote its
rise, rational capitalism did not develop spontaneously in China. As in the
case of Japan. China would probably offer a fertile soil for the assimilation of
capitalist production introduced from the outside; but this is quite different
from providing the original impetus towards capitalist development.
It is important to specify the relationship between this conclusion and
Weber's analysis of the emergence of western European capitalism. In China,
Weber makes clear, the emergence of rational capitalism was inhibited • by
the lack of a particular mentality', due to the existence of normative prescrip-
tions which were • rooted in the Chinese .. ethos .. '. 2t In western Europe, this
• mentality' did come into being, with the formation of ascetic Protestantism.
But it is misleading to regard Weber's studies of India and China as constitut·
ing, in any simple sense, an ex post facto • experiment • in which the relevant
material factors (i.e.• those economic and political conditions conducive to
capitalism) are held constant. and the • independent • in1Iuence of the content
of ideas is analysed. While it is the case that in China, for example, there
existed, at particular periods, a number of 'material • factors which can be
designated as necessary or favourable to the emergence of capitalism, these
were connected in a specific combination. different from that pertaining in
Europe. There were important differences, then. in both the 'material • and
the' ideal • circumstances characterising the West as compared to the Orient. n
23 Re, pp. 228 &. 247; my parenthesis; GA.R, vol. 1, pp. 514 &. 534.
26 Re, p. 104.
U Weber places some emphasis upon the special geographical position of Europe. In
India and China, the large continental land masses were formidable barriers to the
extensive development of commerce. In Europe, the Mediterranean, together with
many rivers providing easy transportation, offered a situation much more favour'
able to trading enterprises on an extensive scale. General E~onomic History, p. 260.
In addition, Weber analyses at length the special properties of the western city, and
the significance of the early dissolution of the solidarity of the extended kinship
group. ES. vol. 3, pp. 1212-372.
2' EMW, p. 94. my parenthesis.
Rationalisation, the 'world religions' and western capitalism 179
talism first took root in England, but that country was much less influenced
by Roman law than other continental countries were. The prior existence of a
system of rational law was only one influence in a complicated interplay of
factors leading to the formation of the modem state. The trend towards the
development of the modem state, characterised by the presence of a profes-
sional administration carried on by salaried officials, and based upon the con-
cept of citizenship, was certainly not wliolly an outcome of economic rationali-
sation, and in part preceded it. Nevertheless, it is true that the advance of the
capitalist economic order and the growth of the state are intimately connected.
The development of national and international markets. and the concomitant
destruction of the influence of the local groups, such as kinship units, which
formerly played a large part in regulating contracts, all promote' the mono·
polisation and regulation of all "legitimate" coercive power by one
universalist coercive institution .. .'.27
Essential to modem capitalistic enterprise, according to Weber, is the
possibility of rational calculation of profits and losses in terms of money.
Modem capitalism is inconceivable without the development of capital
accounting. In Weber's view, rational book-keeping constitutes the most inte-
gral expression of what makes the modem type of capitalist production dis-
similar to prior sorts of capitalistic activity such as usury or adventurers' capi-
taUsm.28 The circumstances which Weber details as necessary to the existence
of capital accounting in stable productive enterprises constitute those which
Weber accepts as the basic prerequisites of modem capitalism, and include
those factors upon which Marx placed most emphasis: 1. The existence of a
large mass of wage-labourers, who are not only legally • free ' to dispose of
their labour power on the open market, but who are actually forced to do so
to eam their livelihood. 2. An absence of restrictions upon economic exchange
on the market: in particular, the removal of status monopolies on production
and consumption (such as existed, in extreme form. in the Indian caste
system). 3. The use of a technology, which is constructed and organised On
the basis of rational principles: mechanisation is the clearest manifestation
of this. 4. The detachment of the productive enterprise from the household.
While the separation of home and workplace is found elsewhere, as in the
bazaar, it is only in western Europe that this has proceeded very far. 1I
But these economic attributes could not exist without the rational legal
administration of the modern state. This is as distinctive a characteristic of
the contemporary capitalist order as is the class division between capital and
labour in the economic sphere. In general terms, political organisations can
be classified in the same way as economic enterprises. in relation to whether
the • means of administration' are owned by the administrative staff or are
separated from their ownership. As has been mentioned (in the previous cbap-
" ES. vol. I, pp. 85-6. d. Friedmann's comments on Marcuse's paper 'Industi-ialisier-
ung und Kapitalismus " in the Verhandlungen des IS. deutschen Soziologentages:
MIlX Weber und die Soziologie heute (TllbiDgen, 1965), pp. 201-5.
184 Part 3: Max Weber
about his tools.' However. these principles are nevertheless • known • in the
sense of being available to the individual should he wish to ascertain them.
and his conduct is governed by the belief that • there are no mysterious
in<:alculable forces that come into play. but rather that one can. in principle.
master all things by calculation '.31
The relationship between the spread of formal rationality and the attain-
ment of substantive rationality - that is. the application of rational calculation
to the furtherance of definite goals or values - is problematic. Medern rational
capitalism. measured in terms of substantive values of efficiency or produc-
tivity. is easily the most advanced economic system which man has developed.
But the very rationalisation of social life which has made this possible has
consequences which contravene some of the most distinctive values of western
civilisation. such as those which emphasise the importance of individual
creativity and autonomy of action. The rationalisation of modem life.
especially as manifest in organisational form in bureaucracy. brings into being
the • cage , within which men are increasingly confined. This is the sense of
Weber's concluding observations in The Protestant Ethic:
Limitation to specialised work, with a renunciation of the Faustian universality
of men which it involves, is a condition of any valuable work in the m~m
world; hence deeds and renunciation inevitably condition each other today.
This fundamentally ascetic trait of middle-class life, if it attempts to be a way
of life at all, and not simply the absence of any, was what Goethe wanted to
teach, at the beight of his wisdom, in the Wanderjahren, and <in the end which
he gave to the life of his Faust. For bim the realisation meant a renunciation, a
departure from an age of full and beautiful humanity, wbich can no more be
repeated in the course of our cultural development than can the flower of the
Athenian culture of antiquity .'0
In this sense. western society can be said to be founded upon an intrinsic
antinomy between formal and substantive rationality which. according to
Weber's analysis of modem capitalism. cannot be resolved.
3. FMW. p. 139.
"0 PE. p. 181.
Part 4: Capitalism, socialism
and social theory
13. Marx's influence
The intellectual relationship between the writings of Marx on the one hand.
and those of Durkheim and Weber on the other. cannot be analysed satis-
factorily without reference to the social and political changes which both
conjoined and disconnected the works of the three writers. Durkheim and
Weber were each critics of Marx, and consciously directed part of their work
to the refutation or qualification of Marx's writings: indeed. the remark that
the bulk of Weber's intellectual output represents a prolonged' dialogue with
the ghost of Marx ',' has often been reiterated in the secondary literature.
But in both France and Germany, in the late nineteenth centwy, the influence
of Marx's thought was far more than purely intellectual in character: in the
shape of ' Marxism " Marx's writings became the primary impetus within a
vital and dynamic political movement. As such, Marxism, and ' revolutionary
socialism' more generally. formed a major element in the horizon of
Durkheim and Weber, especially so in the case of the latter.f
Marx conceived his works to furnish a platform for the accomplishment of
a definite Praxis, and not simply as academic studies of society. The same is
true, although not of course in an exactly comparable manner, of both Durk-
heim and Weber; each directed his writings towards the prophylaxis of what
they considered to be the most urgent social and political problems confront-
ing contemporary man, and attempted to provide an alternative standpoint
to that set out by Marx. It is worth remarking upon the fact that no British
author of comparable status to Durkheim or Weber emerged in their genera-
tion. While the reasons for this are no doubt complex. it is unquestionably
true that one factor responsible was the absence, in Britain. of a really signi·
ficant revolutionary socialist movement.
185
186 Part 4: Capitalism. socialism and social theory
were both major European powers: their very rivalry was one factor hinder-
ing German unification. The hopes of German nationalists were also obstruc-
ted by the internal ethnic composition of Prussia and Austria. Austria. after
1815. had more non-Germans than Germans in her population; and Prussia
incorporated large numbers of Poles within her territories to the east. Espousal
of the nationalist doctrine could forcibly entail, for Prussia. the return of these
lands to Polish dominion. The Austrian government was flatly opposed to any
movement towards the formation of an integral German slate.
But of greater weight than these factors in hindering the development of
Germany were more basic characteristics of the social and economic structure
of the country. Compared to the most advanced capitalist country, Britain.
Germany was still almost in the Middle Ages, both in terms of the level of her
economic development, and in terms of the low degree of politicalliberalisa-
tion within the various German states. In Prussia the Junker landowners,
whose power sprung from their ownership of the large ex-Slavic estates to the
east of the Elbe, maintained a dominant position within the economy and
government. In the early part of the nineteenth century, as Landes has re-
marked, ' the further east one goes in Europe the more the bourgeoisie takes
on the appearance of a foreign excrescence on manorial society, a group apart
scorned by the nobility and feared or hated by (or unknown to) a peasantry
still personally bound to the local seigneur '.'
But Germany could hardly remain isolated from me sweeping currents of
change which had been set in motion in France by the events of 1789. Marx's
early works were written in the anticipation of a German revolution. Indeed,
it might be said that Marx's awareness of the very backwardness of Germany
in its social and economic structure was at the root of his original conception
of the role of the proletariat in history. In France, Marx writes in 1844. 'par-
tial emancipation is a basis for complete emancipation '; but in Germany, so
much less developed. a ' progressive emancipation' is impossible: the only
possibility of advancement is through radical revolution, which in turn can
only be accomplished through a revolutionary proletariat. A proletariat at
this time barely existed in Germany, and by 1847 Marx was clear that the
imminent revolution in Germany would be a bourgeois one, and that 'the
bourgeoisie in that country had just begun its contest with feudal absolutism '."
But the peculiar circumstances of the social structure of Germany, so it
seemed to Marx, would make it possible for a bourgeois revolution to be
closely followed by a proletarian one.'
of the in1luence of Marx's writings on sociology at the tum of the century, see
Maximilien Rubel: • Premiers contacts des sociologues du XlXe si~le avec la
pen~ de Marx" Colliers internalionaux de sociologie. vol. 31, 1961, pp. 175-84.
• Landes, p. 129. 5 CM, p. 167.
, d. Engels' views on this matter, as set out in his' Der Status Quo in Deutschland'.
We. vol. 4, esp. pp. 43-6 and 49-51; and Germany,' Revolution and Counter·
revolution (London, 1933).
Marx's influence 187
The failure of the 1848 revolutions. however. dispelled Marx's optimism
about an immediate' leap into the future' in Germany. The 1848 uprisings
were also something of a salutary experience for the ruling circles in the
German states. and especially in Prussia. but did not break their dominance.
The failure of 1848 to produce any radical reforms served as a death-knell,
not only to the hopes of the small grou~ of socialists. but also to those of the
liberals. The maintenance of Junker economic power. of their dominance in
the officer corps in the army, and in the civil service bureaucracy. led the bulk
of the German liberals to acceptance of a series of compromise measures
introducing nothing more than a semblance of parliamentary democracy. as
well as fostering lasting divisions within their ranks.
The events of 1848 mark a line of direct historical connection between Marx
and Weber. For Marx. the result was physical exile in England. and an intellec-
tual recognition of the importance of showing in detail the 'laws of move-
ment' of capitalism as an economic system. Within Germany. the failures of
1848 paved the way fot the inept character of liberal politics which. as com-
pared to the bold successes of Bismarck's hegemony, forms such an important
background to the whole of Weber's thought! Moreover. the persistence of
the traditional social and political structure in Germany after 1848 drastically
affected the role of the labour movement. It is not relevant in this context to
analyse the complicated nature of Marx's relationship to Lassalle and to the
movement which Lassalle founded. but certain aspects of this relationship are
pertinent. There was from the beginning of the Social Democratic movement
an inbuilt ambivalence towards Marx's doctrines which formed a permanent
source of schism within the party. While on the one hand Lassalle was deeply
indebted in his theoretical views to Marx's writings on the development of
capitalism. in his practical leadership of the new movement he frequently
acted in ways opposed to Marx's views on specific issues. and advocated
policies difficult to reconcile with the theory he professed to accept. Thus. in
contrast to Marx's opinion that the German working class should throw in its
weight with the bourgeoisie in order to secure the bourgeois revolution which
would subsequently provide the conditions for the assumption of power by the
proletariat, Lassalle led the working class movement away from collaboration
with the liberals. As Mehring remarked. Lassalle ' based his policy on the
assumption that the Philistine movement of the progressive bourgeoisie would
never lead to anything. "not even if we wait for centuries, for geological
eras " .. .'.'
Lassalle died the same year that Weber was born. By this time the imme-
diate future of Germany had already been set. The detachment of the labour
~ In his copy of Simmers book Schopenhallt!r lind Nietzsche, where Simmel says:
• Society ultimately resides in what the individual does', Weber noted: 'Quite
correct. cf. Bismarck '. Quoted in Eduard Baumgarten: Max Weber: Werk und
Person (Tilbingen, 1964), p. 614.
• Franz Mehring: Karl Marx (Ann Arbor, 1962), p. 313.
188 Part 4: Capitalism, socialism and social theory
movement from the liberals, in conjunction with other factors. set the scene
for Bismarck's unification of Germany, in which. as Bismarck said, • Germany
did not look to Prussia's liberalism, but to her power '.' In 1875, when Liebk-
necht and Bebel, Marx's leading advocates in Germany, accepted union with
the Lassallean wing of the labour movement. Germany was in both political
and economic terms a very different nation from that which Marx originally
wrote about in the 18405. Political integration had been achieved. not through
the rise of a revolutionary bourgeoisie. but largely as a result of a policy of
Realpolitik and nationalism founded essentially upon the bold use of political
power' from the top' and occurring within a social system which - in spite of
achieving some of the trappings of a • welfare state • - in large degree retained
its traditional structure. The difficult phases of initial political unification,
and the • take off ' into industrialisation. were accomplished in quite a different
fashion in Germany from the typical process of development in Britain. From
the beginnings of his career, Marx remained conscious of the variations in his-
torical development which have created social and economic differences
between Germany. France and Britain. It is quite mistaken to suppose that,
according to Marx's view, there is a unitary relationship between level of
economic development and the internal character of the capitalist state (see
below, p. 197). Nevertheless, Marx bases his writings upon the assertion that.
in analytic terms. economic power is everywhere the foundation of political
domination. Therefore. in Capital. Marx logically accepts Britain as providing
the basic model for his theory of capitalist development. and in spite of his
awareness of the complicated issues possessed by the peculiar character of the
German social structure, he never abandoned the basic standpoint summed
up in his use of the phrase • De te tabula narratur ': • It is of you that the story
is told.' ' The country that is more developed industrially oniy shows, to the
less developed. the image of its own future.' 10
Thus neither the Marxist socialists nor the liberals in Germany of the late
nineteenth century had an adequate historical model in terms of which they
could satisfactorily comprehend the peculiarities of their position. Both
• Marianne Weber has testified to the strength of the emotional impact which the 1870
war had upon the household in which the young Weber was living. Marianne Weber,
pp. 47-8. For a recent analysis of Weber's personality and psychological develop-
ment (written, in part, in conscious attempt to revise aspects of Marianne Weber'!
biography), see Arthur Mitzman: The Iron Cage,' An Historical Interpretation of
Max Weber (New York, 1970).
10 Preface to the first German edition of the first volume of Capital, SW, vol. I, p. 449.
Many economists and sociologists even today continue, explicitly or otherwise, to
take the British experiern:e as the model against which to analyse industrial I
political development. But it is probably more appropriate, in some respects, to
treat Britain as a • deviant' case. cf. on some relevant issues, Barrington Moore:
Social Origins of Dictatorship and Democracy (London, 1969), pp. 413-32 and
passim. A Marxist account of German social thought in relation to the' backward-
ness' of the country is given in Georg Lukacs: Die Zerstorllng der Vernunft
(Berlin, 1955).
Marx's influence 189
looked to theories developed in an earlier epoch, and based primarily upon
the experience of Britain in the late eighteenth and early nineteenth centuries.
In the Social Democratic Party, this situation forced out into the open the
inherent tension between Marx's stress upon the revolutionary overthrow of
capitalism, and the Lassallean emphasis upon the appropriation of the capita-
list state through the achievement of a fully universal franchise. Bernstein's
Die Voraussetzungen des Sozialismus, although itself based partly upon a
British model, was the most concrete theoretical expression of the realisation
that the relationship between the political and economic development of
capitalism could not be adequately a>mprehended in tenus of what most
Marxists look to be the main theses of Capital: the progressive formation of
a two-class society, the • pauperisation' of the vast majority,· and the
immanent collapse of capitalism in a final catastrophic crisis. Bernstein's
• revisionism' was rejected by the SPO orthodoxy, but at the cost of strength-
ening the trend towards a mechanical materialism which effectively reverted
to the 'passive' materialism which Marx had criticised and discarded in the
early phases of his career. This trend was given a definite theoretical backing
by the fact that • Marxism ' came to be identified, in the eyes both of its
adherents and its liberal critics, with the systematic exposition set out by
Engels in Anti-Duh,ing. l l Today it is usual among western scholars to
emphasise the fundamental discrepancies between the thOUght of Marx and
Engels. The differences have undoubtedly been exaggerated.l~ Nevertheless.
the implications of the position which Engels takes in this work are certainly
at variance with the subject-object dialectic central to Marx's formulations.
By transferring the dialectic to nature, Engels obscures the most essential
element of Marx's conception, • the dialectical relationship of subject and
object in the historical process '.13 In so doing Engels helped to stimulate the
notion that ideas simply' reflect' material reality in a passive sense. u.
The partial disappearance of the principle upon which Marx's original
writings were based - the creative dialectical interaction between subject and
object - has two possible outcomes on the level of ethical theory, both of which
11 For a lengthy description of Weber's political writings. see Mommsen. This work
underplays, bowever, Weber's commitment to classical liberal values, towards what
Weber cans' man's personal autonomy', • tbe spiritual and moral values of man-
kind '. Quoted in Marianne Weber, p. 159. d. Eduard Baumgarten, p. 607; and my
Politics and Sociology in the Thollg"t of Max Weber.
Marx's influence 191
mic progress .. .' 11 Weber dissociates himself, however, from the ' mystical '
conception of the state as advanced by conservative idealism. and condemns
the Junkers as an economically declining class not capable of leading the
nation. But the .working class is a]so politically • infinitely immature' and
not able to provide the requisite source of political direction. Consequently,
the main hope for leadership is to be found in the bourgeoisie; but this class
has been stunted by its history of subordination to Bismarck's rule, and is
itself not yet ready for the political tasks which it eventually must be called
upon to assume. Weber derides the timidity of the bourgeoisie in the face of
the' red spectre' :
The threatening thing in our situation, however, is that the bourgeois classes as
the bearers of the power interests of the nation seem to wilt away, while there are
as yet no signs that the workers are beginning to show the maturity to replace
them. The danger ... does not lie with the masses. It is not a question of the
economic position of the ruled, but rather of the political qualifications of the
ruling and ascending classes ...17
It is wholly mistaken, according to Weber. to regard radical revolution as the
only means for the political emancipation and economic advancement of the
working class. In fact. the growth of the political power and the improvement
in the economic circumstances of the working class are both possible within
capitalism. and are actually in the interests of the bourgeoisie.
The strengthening of the liberal boUl'geoisie, as Weber came to recognise
with increasing clarity at later stages of his political career, entails developing
a governmental system which would vest real political power in parliament.
and create a reservoir of genuine political leaders. The result of Bismarck's
rule, according to Weber. has left Germany without the parliamentary auto-
nomy necessary to generate the political leadership which can take control of
the bureaucratic machine of government bequeathed to the country from the
past. and which threatens Germany with ' uncontrolJed bureaucratic domina-
tion '.11 Weber's attitude to the possibility of establishing socialism in Ger-
many - including the transitory Eisner government - is directly bound up with
these views upon the German social and political structure. Weber notes early
on in his career that much of the revolutionary fervour of the leaders of the
main body of the Social Democratic movement is quite divergent from the
real trend of its development. As Weber expresses it. the German state will
conquer the Social Democratic Party and not vice versa; the party will move
19 GASS, p. 409.
70 ES, vol. 3, p. 1453. For Weber's views on revolutionary Russia, in the early part of
the nineteenth century, cf. GPS, pp. 192-210. Of the domination of Bolshevism,
Weber observed in 1918, it • is a pure military dictatorship, not simply that of
generals, but of corporals' (GPS, p. 280).
21 GPS, p. 472. Weber's views of the more radical attempts at socialist reconstruction
were very severe: • I am absolutely convinced that these experiments can and will
only lead to the discrediting of socialism for 100 years' (letter to Luk:1cs. quoted in
Mommsen, p. 303); • Liebkrtecht belongs in the lunatic asylum and Rosa Luxem-
burg in the zoological gardens' (quoted ibid. p. 300).
22 On the relationship between Weber and Sombart, cf. Talcott Parsons: • Capitalism
in recent German literature: Sombart and Weber '0 Journal 01 Political Econom~.
vol. 36, 1928. pp. 641-61; on Weber and Michels, see Roth, pp. 249-57. On the
reception of Marx's ideas by the Kalhedersozialislen, see Lindenlaub, pp. 272-384.
Marx's influence 193
direct wayan intellectual response to Marx's works. Weber Wldoubtedly had
a general acquaintance with Marx's writings at an early stage in his career;
but other influences were far more important':" Most of Weber's interests.
especially in the early part of his career. stemmed from orthodox problems
of historical economics and law. Moreover. when Weber uses the tenn . his-
torical materialism '. the reference is often to the spate of scholarly works
claiming Marxian ancestry which appeared in the 18905. These sometimes
represent what Weber takes to be a vulgarisation of Marx's ideas, or other-
wise depart notably from what Weber considers to be the main tenets of
Marx's posiLion.24 Thus The Protestant Ethic has a complicated genealogy.
Weber was interested from his youth in religion as a social pbenomenoo.7S
While his studies of law and economics diverted him from following this
interest directly in his first academic writings. the work is in some part an
expression of concerns which had remained in the forefront of his mind.
Weber's views upon the validity and usefulness of Marx's original work
thus have to be partially disentangled from his assessment of 'vulgar'
Marxism. Nevertheless. the numerous scattered references to Marx contained
in Weber's writings do furnish a clear exposition of the main sources of simi-
larity and di1ference as Weber conceived them. Weber recognises. of course.
that Marx had made fundamental contributions to historical and sociological
analysis. But. according to Weber. Marx's developmental conceptions can
never be regarded as anything other than sources of insight. or at most as
ideal typical concepts. which might be applied to illuminate specific historical
sequences. In Weber's eyes. Marx's attribution of overall rational • direction'
to the course of history is. within the terms of the framework which Marx
adopts. as illegitimate as that embodied in the Hegelian philosophy which
helped to give it birth. While Weber admits, with strong reservations. the use
of developmental ' stages' as theoretical constructs which can be applied as
a 'pragmatic means' to aid historical research. he rejects completely the
formulation of 'deterministic schemes' based upon general theories of
development.
Z3 As Roth has pointed out, Weber's early writinss embodied a preliminary critique of
historic:al materialism, but this was by no means central to Weber's interests until
later on. GUnther Roth: • Das historische Verhliltnis der Webersc:hen Soziologie
7.um Marxismus', Kolner Zeitschrilt liir S01.iologie und SoziIJlprychologie, vol. 20.
1968, pp. 433ff. .
2' See, for example, Weber's discussion of Stammler, in • R. Stammlers .. Uberwin-
dung" der materialistischen Gesc:hichtsauffassung', GAW. pp. 219-383. The
sarcastic reference which Weber makes to Debel at the end of his thesis on Roman
agrarian history is not untypical of various asides on contemporary Marxist
theoreticians in Weber's writings. Die romische Agc.argesc/Uchle, p. 275.
zs It is interesting to note that Weber was impressed at an early aae by his reading of
Das Leben lesu, by David Strauss: the same work which played a prominent part
in forming the views of the Young Hegelians. c:f. Marianne Weber, pp. 117-20;
lugendbriele (Tllbingen, n.d.), pp. 205ff. In addition to the stimulus provided by
the work of Sombart, Georg Jellinek's Erkfiirung der Menschen- und Biirgerrechle
(1895) was probably important in influencing Weber's direction of interest.
194 Part 4: Capitalism, socialism and social theory
It follows from this that there can be no more than contingent validity in
the conception that economic relationships constitute the source of historical
development. The specific importance of the 'economic' is variable, and
must be assessed by empirical study of particular circumstances. Weber
accepts that ideas and values, while most definitely not being • derivations'
of material interests in any simple sense. nevertheless must always be
analysed in relation to such interests:
Liberated as we are from the antiquated notion that aU cultural phenomena can
be deduced as a product or function of the constellation of • material' interests.
we believe nevertheless that the analysis 01 socia/and cultural phenomena with
special reference to their economic conditioning and ramifications was a scienti-
fic principle of c:.reative fruitfulness, and with careful application and freedom
from dogmatic restrictions, will remain such for a very long time to come. 2I
But a theory which seeks to deny the independent historical significance of
the content of ideas (which itself is variable) cannot be acceptable. The theory
that economic factors in any sense • finally , explain the course of history,
Weber asserts, • as a scientific theorem, is utterly finished '."
Weber recognises that Marx's writings vary in the degree of sophistication
with which his materialist interpretation of history is presented. The Com-
munist Manifesto, for example, sets out Marx's views • with the crude
elements of genius of the early form '." But even in the more thorough formu-
lation in Capital, Marx nowhere defines precisely how the • economic' is
delimited from other spheres of society. Weber's distinctions between • econo-
mics '. • economically relevant', and • economically conditioned' phenomena
are aimed at clarifying this deficiency. There are many modes of human action,
such as religious practices, which while they are not themselves • economic'
in character, have relevance to economic action in so far as they inftuence the
ways in which men strive to acquire or make use of utilities. These are econo-
mically relevant types of action. Actions which are economically relevant can
in tum be separated from those which are economically conditioned: the
latter are actions, which are again not 'economic' but which are causally
in1luenced by economic factors. As Weber points out, ' After what has been
said. it is self-evident that: firstly, the boundary lines of .. economic ..
phenomena are vague and not easily defined: secondly the .. economic ..
aspect of a phenomenon is by no means only "economically conditioned ..
or only .. economically relevant" .. .' 21
Weber also points to another source of ambiguity in Marx's writings: that
Marx fails to distinguish in a clear manner between the • economic' and th~
• technological'. Where Marx slips into a more or less direct technological
determinism, Weber shows, his work is sometimes manifestly inadequate.
Marx's famous assertion that • The hand-mill gives you society with the feudal
30 Poverty of PhUosophy, p. 92. Weber does not, however. take account of the polemical
context in which this statement is made. For Weber's own distinction between
• economy' and • technology', see ES. vol. 1. pp. 65-7.
31 GASS. p.4S0.
32 FMW. p. 153. cf. Weber's remark on socialist parties: • I shall not join these
churches.' Quoted in Baumgarten, p. 607.
196 Part 4: Capitalism. socialism and social theory
France in the nineteenth century: Marx and the growth of Marxism
Marx and Marxism were parts of Max Weber's intellectual universe to a
degree which was not the case for Durkheim. Marx was a German. and wrote
most of his major works in that language; and no other country in the nine-
teenth century possessed as large or as politically significant a Marxist party as
the German Social Democratic Party. In spite of the fact that be spent a period
studying in Germany in the early part of his career. Durkheim's intellectual
perspective remained almost obstinately French. Nonetheless. the formative
social and political context in which Durkheim developed his sociology was
comparable in certain important respects with that which influenced Weber.
Like Weber. Durkheim lived and wrote in a situation in which two divergent
streams of political thought and activity threatened to submerge the liberal
principles bequeathed from the French Revolution: a conservative nationa-
lism on the one hand, and a radical socialism on the otber. In common with
Weber, Durkheim accepted some elements from each of these competing
systems of thought, and embodied them within his own political standpoint.
and within bis social theory more broadly. The conclusions which each author
reached. however. are in some respects quite divergent, and this is in part to
be traced to the specific ways in which the overall development of France
contrasted with that of Germany in the latter part of the nineteenth century.
Marx's attitude towards France in the 1840s was. naturally enough. domi-
nated by a consciousness of the relative superiority of the level of political
advancement of that country as compared to Germany. Whatever the strength
of the reaction which bad set in against the Revolution in France. it was
obvious that the political sophistication of the French socialist thinkers was
rooted in a social structure which had already made its decisive break with its
feudal past. One of the principal criticisms wbich Marx directs against the
majority of German socialists was that they • imported • ideas from France
without appreciating the depth of the disjunction between the material
differences between the two countries. As Marx writes in 1843:
If one were to begin with the status quo itself in Germany, even in the most
appropri:.te way, i.e. negatively, the result would still be an anachronism. Even
the negation of our political present is already a dusty fact in the historicallum-
her room of modern nations. I may negate powdered wigs, but I am still left
with unpowdered wigs. If I negate the German situation of 1843 I have, accord-
ing to French chronology. hardly reached the year 1789. and still less the vital
centre of the present day.33
But the course of development taken after the Paris risings of 1848-9 made
it apparent that the degree to which the liberal bourgeoisie in France had
achieved a stable footing in the control of government prior to this date was
open to serious question. Engels documents at some length the reconsidera-
tions of previous views which were forced upon Marx and himself by the con-
41 ct. Hayward. For Durkheim's views on revolutiODary syndicalism, see tbe account
of his discussion witb Lagardelle, in Libres entretiens, 1905. pp. 425-34.
47 Including leaders of the syndicalist movement. For Sorel's views on Durkheim's
influence, see Georges Sorel: • Les tMories de M. Durkheim', u devenir social.
vol. I, 189S, pp. 1-26 &: 148-80.
•• R.eview of Antonio Labriola: Essais $IIr Ia conception mtllirialiste tk rhistoire.
RP, vol. 44, 1897. pp. 645-S1. Labriola's work leans heavily on Engelsj Anti·
Diihring is called • the unexcelled book in the literature of socialism '. Antonio
Labriola: Socialism and Philosophy (Chicago, 1918), p. S3. 4. Soc, p. 283.
Marx's influence 201
Durkbeim adds, that these three tendencies are again re-emerging strongly
towards the end of the nineteenth century, in times which are as eventful and
critical as the decades following the 1789 Revolution. At first sight, these
appear to be three contrary currents of thought, which share little in common.
The movement calling for a religious revival is conceived by its adherents to
be hostile to rationalism and to science. The socialist movement, in general,
is based upon the rejection of religion, and also upon the notion that sociolo-
gical study must be subordinated to the normative demands of political
action. But in fact these three streams of thought seem to be contradictory
because each expresses only one side of social reality. Each expresses some
of the needs which men feel when social change has radically upset accepted
habits such that • the unsettled collective organisation no longer functions
with the authority of instinct '.10
The stimulus to sociology derives from the need to understand the causes
of the changes which have called forth the exigency for far-reaching social
reorganisation. But scientific study proceeds slowly and with caution. Durk-
heim often stresses in his writings that scientific activity is worthless if it does
not in some way lead to practical results. Nevertheless, it is of the essence of
science that its procedures and objectives be detached from immediately
practical requirements; only by the maintenance of a • disinterested ' attitude
can scientific enquiry attain its maximal effectiveness. Science must not be
made • a sort of fetish or idol'; it allows us • only a degree of knowledge,
beyond which there is nothing else '.11 The needs for solutions to urgent social
problems, however, often go far beyond that which can be based upon scien-
tifically established knowledge: hence the spur to the development of socialist
doctrines, which present overall programmes for the necessary reorganisation
of society. The reactionary call for a revival of religion similarly indicates
the shortcomings of science. The moral hiatus which results from a situation
in which old beliefs have come under question, but have dot yet been replaced
by new ones, produces a concern with the mom consolidation of society:
hence the resurgence of religious ideals.
Durkheim does not except Marx from his overall judgement of socialism.
Marx's writings offer a complete system of thought which is presented as a
scientifically established body of propositions. But such a system in fact pre-
supposes an enormous fund of knowledge, far and above that which is avail-
able at the present time. A great deal Ilf research would be necessary to
substantiate even some of the more limited generaIisations contained in
Capital. Thus, reviewing Gaston Richard's Le soc;aiisme et Ia science sociale.
Durkheim comments: • of all the criticisms which Richard has directed at
Marx, the strongest appears to us to be that which limits itself to setting in
so Soc, p. 284.
51 • L'enseignemcnt philosophique et l'agn!ption de philosophie', RP, vol. 39, 189S,
p.I46.
202 Part 4: Capitalism, socialism and social theory
relief what a distance there is between the fundamental propositions of the
system and the observations upon which it rests.' 62
These views are amplified in Durkheim's discussion of Labriola's exposi-
tion of Marx's thought. Durkheim expresses his agreement with certain of
the most important notions embodied in historical materialism. It is a fruit-
ful conception, Durkheim states, which regards social life not merely from
the point of view of the consciousness of the individuals involved, but which
examines the influence of factors which escape consciousness and help to
shape it. Moreover, it is also valid to hold, as Marx does, that these factors
must be sought in the organisation of society. • For in order for collective
representations to be explicable, it is certainly necessary that they derive from
something and, since they cannot form a circle closed upon itself, the source
from which they derive must be located outside of themselves: U It is quite
correct to locate the source of ideas in a definite substratum; and what else,
Durkheim asks rhetorically, can this substratum be composed of, if not the
members of society organised into definite social relationships?
According to Durkheim, however, there is no reason to presume that this
perspective commits whoever adopts it to the acceptance of the whole corpus
of Marx's thought. Durkheim remarks that he himself arrived at this concep-
tion without accepting the rest of the principles upon which Marx's work is
founded, and that his own formulations have in no way been influenced by
Marx. One can, as follows from the general. conclusions concerning the
relationship between sociology and socialism stated above, study social or-
ganisation in this manner without accepting the additional premises entailed
by Marxian socialism. The perspective which examines the interplay between
ideas and their • material' substratum is simply the substance of sociological
method, and is a necessary condition for studying society in a scientific
manner. lust as Weber emphasises that socialism is not a conveyance which
can be stopped at the wish of those who travel in it - socialist beliefs must
themselves be made subject to the sort of analysis which socialists apply to
other forms of belief - so Durkheim stresses that socialism itself must, from
the point of view of the sociologist, be treated as a social fact like any other.
Socialism is rooted in a definite state of society, but it does not necessarily
express accurately the social conditions which gave rise to it. 54
Moreover, the central thesis of historical materialism. which ties the origin
of ideas directly to economic relationships, is • contrary to facts which seem
established '. It has been proved, Durkheim declares, that religion is the
original soun:e out of which all more differentiated systems of ideas have
52 Review of Gaston Richard: Le socialisme et la science socia/e, RP, vol. 44, 1897,
p. 204. Durkheim expresses his approval of those socialists in Germany and Italy who
were trying • to renew and extend the formulae which they have been prisoner of
for far too long' - especially • the doctrine of economic materialism, the Marxist
theory of value, the iron law [of wages] ... [and1 the pre-eminent importance attri-
buted to class conflict '. Review of Merlino: Formes et essence du socialisme, RP.
vol. 48, 1889, p. 433. 63 Review of Labriola. p. 648. 54 Soc, pp. 40ft.
Marx's influence 203
developed. But in the simplest forms of society. 'tbe economic factor is rudi-
mentary, while religious life is, on the contrary, luxurious and enveloping '.n
In this case, the economy is influenced much more by religious practice and
symboJism than the other way around. It does not follow from this that, with
the growth of organic solidarity and the consequent decline of the all-encom-
passing character of religion. the influence of economic relationships becomes
predominant in determining the nature of the beliefs which occupy the pri-
mary place in the conscience collective. Once a set of beliefs are established,
• they are, in virtue of this, realities sui generis, autonomous, capable of being
causes in their turn and of producing new phenomena'. 51 Tn primitive socie-
ties, which have a simple structure, all ideas are connected to a single system
of religious representations, and are consequently closely tied in their content
to the form of the organisation of the society. But with the growth of differen-
tiation in the division of labour. and of the application of critical reason. pro-
ducing the clash of divergent ideas. the relationship between beliefs and the
substratum in which they are rooted becomes more complex.
In conjunction with this emphasis. Durkheim rejects the Marxian supposi-
tion that economic relationships - the class structure - are the major focus
of political power in society. According to Durkheim, there is wide variability
in the political organisation of societies which are otherwise structurally
similar. It follows that the importance of classes, and of class conflict gener-
ally, in historical development, is minimised by Durkheim. It is significant. of
course, that Durkheim does not use either the Saint-Simonian term • indus-
trial society " or the economists' 'capitalism' in his writings, but talks rather
of 'modem society' or 'contemporary society'. Durkheim's model of de-
velopment. while recognising the significance of definite ' stages' of societal
advancement, emphasises the importance of cumulative changes, rather than
of revolutionary dynamism, in history. According to Durkbeim, those socie-
ties in which political revolutions are most frequent are not those which
manifest the greatest capacity for change, Indeed. the opposite is the case:
these are societies in which the basic traditions remain the same. 'On the
surface there is an uninterrupted stream of continually new events. But this
superficial changeability hides the most monotonous uniformity. It is among
the most revolutionary peoples that bureaucratic routine is often the most
powerful.' aT If the past development of society cannot be understood in terms
of the primacy which Marx gave to class conflict, the same is true of the
present. The prevalence of class conflicts in contemporary societies is symp.-
tomatic of the malaise of the modem world, but not its root cause. Qass con-
flict derives from a disorder which has its origins elsewhere. • From which it
Marx's writings have their initial source in the critique of religion as formu-
lated by David Strauss. Bruno Bauer and Feuerbach. Behind these looms the
intluence of Hegel. whose philosophy. as Feuerbach commented. 'negated
theology in a theological manner '.1 Hegel's philosophical system unites two
basic elements which Marx later identified as characteristic of religion as a
form of • ideology': the transmuted representation of values which are in fact
created by man in society. and the provision of principled support for an
existing social and political order - in this case. that of the Prussian state. The
intluence of religion upon social life is also a leading concern of both Durk-
heim and Weber. and forms one most significant dimension along which some
of the themes intrinsic to the writings of the latter two authors may be com-
pared with those of Marx. There are two connected sets of problems in the
analysis of the' ideological' character of religion which are important here:
the derivation of the content of religious symbolism. and the consequences of
the • secularisation ' of modem life.
The first serves to focus some of the issues involved in the great, protracted
debate over the nature of the ' materialistic' interpretation of history in the
latter part of the nineteenth century. Both Durkheim and Weber. in common
with all other liberal critics of Marx, reject what they take to be Marx's con-
ception of the relationship between ideas and 'material interests'. In dis-
cussing this matter in this chapter. most attention is given to an examination
of the relationship between Marx and Weber. The writings of Max Weber.
as has been mentioned in the previous chapter. are much more directly aimed
at the critical elucidation of historical materialism than are those of Durk-
heim. Moreover. the publication of The Protestant Elhic sparked off a con-
troversy over the role of ' ideas' in historical development which has barely
abated today.2
The second set of problems. to do with 'secularisation " relate not to the
nature of the interplay between' ideas • and ' material reality' as such. but to
the implications of the declining influence of religion in the modem world.
The consequences of the diminishing hold of religion upon s9Ciallife concern
each of the three writers discussed in this book. on both a practical and a theo-
205
206 Part 4: Capitalism, socialism and social theory
retica1 level. All three attribute tremendous importance to the progressive
displacement of religious thought and practice by the penetration of rationa-
lism into all spheres of social life. Clarification of some of the main points of
similarity and divergence on this issue provides another source of insight into
some of the most significant contrasts between tbe works of Marx as compared
to those of Durkheim and Weber.
S ES, vol. 2, pp. 48111. For Kautsky's theory of the • proletarian' character of
Christianity - which Weber rejects - see his Der Ursprung des Clzristentums
(Stuttgart, 1908).
e • Contribution to tho critique of Hegel's Philosophy of Right', translation as per
On Religion (Moscow, 1957), p. 51. Nonetheless, Marx is unequivocally hostile to
Luther and Lutheranism; Luther' freed the body from chains because he enchained
the heart '.
: EW,p. 43.
B WYM, p. 402.
• The • fourth volume' of Capital is Theol'ien uber dea Me/ml'eTl.
208 Part 4: Capitalism, socialism and social theory
Marx qualifies the nature of his intentions in the 1844 Manuscripts could
equally accurately be applied to Capital: • in the present work, the relation-
ships of political economy with the state, law. morals. civil life. etc.• are
touched upon only to the extent that political economy itself expressly deals
with these subjects.' 10
Marx did not. therefore, ever write a systematic exposition of his materia-
listic conception of history. even as applied to that societal form which occu-
pied the prime focus of his attention. bourgeois society. Nevertheless. in the
light of his early writings. it is no longer possible to doubt that Marx's con-
ception of historical materialism does not represent a simple ' inversion • of
Hegelian idealistic philosophy. Feuerbach's writings. on the other hand, are
fcunded upon such an inversion, and for this reason Feuerbach's philosophy
of materialism remains confined to a transposed religious humanism. The
consequence of Feuerbach's position is that religion is a symbolic' represen-
tation' of man, and that to eliminate human self-alienation religion has to be
demystified, and placed upon a rational level. Marx's view is different. Feuer-
bach's errors, as Marx sees them, are to speak of 'man' in the abstract. and
thus to fail to understand that men only exist in the context of specific societies
which change in the course of historical development; and, secondly, to treat
ideas and 'consciousness' as simply the 'reftection ' of human activities in
the material world.
Feuerbach, in other words, preserves that philosophical connotation of the
term' materialism " which Marx seeks to break away from. In Marx's words,
• The chief defect of all previous materialism (including Feuerbach's) is that
the object, actuality, sensuousness, is conceived only in the form of the
object or perception, but not as sensuous human activity, Praxis, not subjec-
tively '.11 It is just such a conception of materialism which stands behind the
notion that ideas are mere' epiphenomena " and consequently that the analy-
sis of the content of ideologies is irrelevant to the explanation of human
action. It must be admitted that there is more than a trace of this conception
in Marx's writings. Thus. in The German Ideology, Marx writes that' in all
ideology man and their circumstances seem to be standing on their heads, as
in a camera obscura. . .'. But it is made clear that such statements are to be
understood in a historical context. Human consciousness is, in the early
stages of social development, 'the direct outcome' of material activity; it is
'mere herd-consciousness '. With the expansion of social differentiation, how-
ever, , consciousness is in a position to emancipate itself from the world and
to proceed to the formation of "pure" theory, theology, philosophy, ethics,
etc.'. (This' emancipation' is fallacious in the sense that ideas can never be
wholly' free' of the social conditions which generate tthem.) This first be-
10 EW, p. 63.
11 WYM, p. 400; We, vol. 3, p. S. For a recent discussion of Feuerbach. see Eugene
Kamenka: The PhilosoplJy 01 Ludwig Feuerbach (London, 1970).
Religion. ideology and society 209
comes possible with the appearance of a division of labour allowing the emer-
gence of a stratum concerned with • mental labour " which occurs historically
in the shape of the development of a priesthood. l t The fonowing paragraph
expresses Marx's standpoint clearly:
This conception of history depends on our ability to expound the real process of
production, starting out from the material production of life itself, and to com-
prehend the form of intercourSe connected with this and created by this mode of
production (Le., civil society in its various stages), as the basis of all history; and
to show it in its action as state, to explain all the different theoretical products
and forms of consciousness, religion, philosophy, ethics, etc., etc., and trace their
origin and growth from that basis; by which means, of course, the whole thing
can be depicted in its totality (and therefore, too, the reciprocal action of these
various sides on one another).13
Ideologies are thus • rooted in the material conditions of life', but this does
not entail that there is a universal or unilateral relationship between the ' real
foundation' of society - the relations of production - and 'legal and political
superstructures '. The specific conclusion which Marx reaches in criticising
Feuerbach is that ideas are social products, which cannot be understood by
the philosopher who stands outside history. The decisive characteristic of
Marx's materialism is to be found in the links which are drawn between class
structure and ideology. Simple and obvious although this appears, it is this
which is fundamental to Marx's ' materialism " rather than any notion of
ideas as epiphenomena of material relationships. Where Marx generalises
about the relationship between ideology and material' substructure " this is
in terms of the specification that the class structure is the main mediating
link between the two_ The class structure of society exerts a determinate effect
upon the ideas which assume prominence in that society; similarly. the emer-
gence of ideas which can serve as an effective challenge to the dominant order
depends upon the formation of class relationships which generate a structural
base for the new ideology. Thus. while.the • idea of communism • has been
'expressed a hundred times' in history. the real possibility of a communist
revolution ' presupposes the existence of a revolutionary class '.14
It may be pointed out that. even in Feuerbach's philosophy, religion is
something more than a complete reflection of material reality: it is also the
source of ideals towards which man should strive. God is man as he oUght to
I~ G1, pp. 37 &: 43; We, vol. 3, pp. 27 &: 31. As Poulantzas says, according to this
analysis' the realm of the" sacred" would appear to be closer to the infrastructure
than that of "law", at least from the moment that we can speak of a juridical reality
which begins to become distinct: it is the religious level which constitutes the most
imponant medium whereby law can be undentood in relation to the infrastructure'
Nicos Ar. Poulantzas: Nature des choses et du droit (Paris, 1965), p. 230.
13 GI, p. SO.
II GI, pp. 51 &: 62. Failure to grasp Marx's point on this matter is one element which
has confused much of the recent discussion of so-called' integration' and' coercion'
theory in sociology. cf. My article'" Power" in the recent writings of Talcott
Parsons', Sociology. vol. 2, 1968, pp. 268-70.
210 Part 4: Capitalism. socialism and social theory
be. and therefore the image of the deity holds out the hope of what man could
become. Marx mates this conception with the dialectical view that it is the
reciprocal interaction of such ideas with the social organisation of ' earthly
men • which must form the core of an historical perspective. This reciprocity
must be understood in terms of the empirical study of concrete forms of
society, and cannot be grasped if we ' abstract from the historical process '.16
The particular character of the relationship between class structure and
ideology is thus itself historically variable. Capitalism. which strips away an
the pelsonalised ties of feudalism, substitutes for them the impersonal opera-
tioDS of the market; and by applying science to the construction of rational
technology, cuts through the ideological embellishments of the traditional
order - so much so, that the influence of religious beliefs upon the origins of
the capitalist order tends to be forgotten:
Wholly absorbed in the production of wealth and in peaceful competitive struggle,
it [bourgeois society] no longer comprehended that ghosts from the days of Rome
had watched over its cradle. But unheroic as bourgeois society is, it nevertheless
took heroism, sacrifice, terror, civil war and battles of peoples to bring it into
being •.. Similarly, at another stage of development, a century earlier, Cromwell
and the English people had borrowed speech, passions and illusions from the
Old Testament for their bourgeois revolution. When the real aim had been
achieved, when the bourgeois transfonnation of English sooiety had been accom·
plished, Locke supplanted Habakkuk'"
Such considerations make clearly manifest that there is indeed a substantial
order of truth in Schumpeter's assertion that' The whole of Max Weber's
facts and arguments (in his sociology of religion) fits perfectly into Marx's
system '.11 That is to say. given an understanding of the dialectic, as the active
interplay between subject and object. it follows that ideology or ' conscious-
ness • provides a necessary set of meanings whereby the individual acts upon
the world at the same time as the world acts upon him. Reality is not merely
, external • to man. shaping his consciousness. but is adapted to human ends
through the active application of consciousness and the modification of the
pre-existing environment. In this approach. ideology is quite definitely not
to be treated as an • effect' which can be 'deduced' from material reality.
The conception of Marx's thought adopted by Weber, on the other hand. is
the characteristic' interpretation' of Marx in the social thought of the late
nineteenth century. Engels' later writings certainly played an important role
in offering a basis for the legitimacy of such a transmutation of Marx. But,
as had been indicated in the previous chapter. such an 'interpretation' was
also generated by the practical exigencies of the position of the leading
European Marxist party in the country of its origin. If the dialectic is deemed
15 WYM. p. 40.
16 SW, vol. I, p. 248.
17 Joseph A. Schumpeler: Capitalism, Socialism and Democracy (New York, 1962).
p.lI.
Religion, ideology and society 211
to exist in nature, as in Anti-Dilhring, the way is clearly laid open to a philo-
sophical materialism which removes from the historical scene the role of
ideas as the active source of social change: ideology is the • effect " and
material conditions are the • cause '. This provokes the characteristic problem
of philosophical materialism which Marx perceived early on in his career:
if ideology is simply the passive • reftection ' of material circumstances, then
there is no place for the active role of men as creators of social reality. U
Weber's writings on religion brilliantly refute the standpoint of • reflective
materialism' as a viable starting-point for sociological analysis. But in this
respect, considered in relation to Marx, it might be said that Weber's writings
almost bring the wheel full circle. Weber refused to wear the straitjacket of
philosophical materialism which the followers of Marx sought to impose upon
history in the name of historical materialism. From this regard, Weber's writ-
ings on the sociology of religion, beginning from the standpoint of subjective
idealism, partially vindicate Marx against his own disciples. Weber treats as
Marx's premise the contention that ideology can be rationally transposed to
expose its • real' content. But in fact, it is precisely this conception which
Marx repudiates in breaking with the Young Hegelians. Thus Weber's use of
the conception of • elective affinity', It in analysing the relationships between
idea-systems and social organisation, is perfectly compatible with Marx's
treatment of ideology. Weber employs this conception to indicate the con-
tingent nature of the connections between the symbolic content of beliefs
which individuals • elect' t!l follow, and the consequences which adherence
to those beliefs entails for social action. Vice versa, the mode of life of a given
social class or status group can generate an affinity to accept certain sorts of
religious ethic, without • determining' the nature of the beliefs involved.
Thus urban artisans and traders, whose life is founded upon the use of prac-
tical calculation in economic enterprise, have an • affinity' towards • the
attitude of active asceticism, of God-willed action nourished by the senti-
ment of being God's .. tool", rather than the possession of the deity or the
inward and contemplative surrender to God, which has appeared as the
supreme value to religions inftuenced by strata of genteel intellectuals '.20
Nevertheless, • active asceticism' has not been limited to the religions of
urban strata, nor have all urban groups by any means adhered to religious
el hies of this type.
The phraseology in which Marx expresses his position is actually very
similar to that often adopted by Weber. Thus, in Marx's words: • Ideas can-
not carry anything out at all. In order to carry out ideas men are needed who
dispose of a certain practical force.' 21 Weber always stresses the contingent
II WYM, p. 401. The importance of this point is not fully brought out in the otherwise
excellent discussion given in Norman Birnbaum: 'Conflicting interpretations of
the rise of capitalism: Marx and Weber', BritisiJ JOllrnal of Sociology, vol. 4,
]953. pp. 125-41. 18 cf. for example; PE, pp. 90-2.
20 F/I,fW, p. 285. 21 Holy Family. p. 160.
212 Part 4: Capita/ism. socialism and social theory
nature of the relationship between the content of an ideology and the social
position of the group who are its' carriers I, but. like Marx. Weber frequently
identifies instances where ideas express material interests in a very direct way.
For both Marx and Weber, religious systems express the creation of human
values, which are not ' given' in the biological makeup of man, but are the
outcome of the historical process. Both agree that stable religious orders
characteristically legitimise relationships of domination: and also that. prior
to the modem age, ' breakthroughs • in the accomplishment of rctdical social
change are achieved within a framework of religious symbolism. Moreover,
Marx does not dispute the fact that, in pre-capitalist societies, religion pro-
vides a cosmology which makes existence intelligible to those who accept it.
The comparative analysis of these points. then. makes clear that the stan-
dard view that Weber's sociology of religion constitutes a 'refutation I of
Marx's historical materialism. by showing the role of ideology as an ' inde-
pendent' influence upon social change. is misconceived. Schumpeter's judge-
ment, in this respect. must be considered apt. That this should not be allowed
to overshadow the fundamental elements of diJIerence between Marx and
Weber which in fact - in the polemical context in which he wrote - made
possible Weber's critique of philosophical materialism. For, according to
Weber's premises, there can be no question of constructing the sort of rational
scheme of historical development which Marx attempts to establish. In the
sense that Weber denies the possibility of deriving objectively verifiable norms
from the study of society and history, those who have stressed the similarity
of his view to that of existentialism are perfectly correct. The moral faith of
the individual. at least as regards acceptance of ultimate values, cannot be
validated by science. On the other hand, the attribution of a discoverable
rationality to history is an essential element in Marx's thought. As Marx
says: 'My dialectic method is not only di1ferent from the Hegelian. but is its
direct opposite.' 22 This does not entail that Marx's thought preserves Hege-
lian ideology in simply the ' reverse' form of that found in Hegel's writings.
In fact, Marx is at some pains to reject such a standpoint. It is, according to
Marx, a 'speculative distortion' which treats later history as 'the goal of
earlier history': 'what is designated with the words" destiny", "goal",
" germ ", or " idea" of earlier history is nothing more than an llbstraction
formed from later history. from the active influence which earlier history
exercises on later history '.13 However Weber is obviously perfectly right in
assuming that Marx's writings constitute a philosophy of history. insofar as
this term is taken to refer to a theoretical position which asserts that there is a
definite' Jogic' of development which can be derived from the empirical
study of historical process.
On the more directly empirical level, these differences are expressed in
:. GI, p. 52.
:s It is important to recognise that, while the influence of Nietz~che on Weber is very
profound, Weber rejects the Nietzschian view of the • slave's revolt' as a reduc-
tionist theory of religion. But the significance which Weber gives to Nietzsche is
indicated by the statement, made just before his dealh, that Marx and Nietzsche are
the two most significant figures in the modem inteUectual world.
214 Part 4: Capitalism. socialism and social theory
interests which is progressively resolved. in favour of the latter, in the develop-
ment from feudalism through capitalism to socialism.28 On an empirica1level,
this divergence is manifest in Marx's assumption that class relationships
constitute the source of political power. The assimilation of economic and
political power is a key theorem in Marx's writings. For Weber. by contrast,
both political and military power are historically as significant as economic
power and do not necessarily derive from it.
29 Gm, pp. 133-4. Marx's position here is close to that latcr formulatcd in detail by
Simmd: Georg Simmel: Philosophie des Geldes (Leipzig, 19(0). Weber remarks of
Simmer, book: 'money economy and capitalism are too closely identified, to the
detriment of his concrete analysis '. PE, p. 185.
30 eM, p. 1%. n EW, p. 44.
216 Part 4: Capitalism, socialism and social theory
ganisation of a • secular' society are such that they necessarily involve the
submergence or denial of some of the dominant values which stimulated the
development of that society: there are no other possibilities open. In Marx's
thought. on the other hand. the alienative characteristics of modem capitalism
stem from its class character. and will be eliminated through the revolutionary
restructuring of society. Weber's description of the effects of bureallcratic
routine is almost identical to Marx's account of the consequences of
alienation in capitalism:
Fully developed bureaucracy stands, in a specific meaning, under the principle
sine ira ac studio. Its speoific character, which is welcomed by capitalism. de-
velops the more, completely the more the bureaucracy is • dehumanised " the
more completely it succeeds in eliminating from official business, love, hatred,
and all purely personal, irrational and emotional elements which escape
calculation.32
Weber thus perceives a primary irrationality within capitalism. The formal
rationality of bureaucracy, while it makes possible the technical implementa-
tion of large-scale administrative tasks, substantively contravenes some of the
most distinctive values of western civilisation, subordinating individuality
and spontaneity. But there is no rational way of overcoming this: this is • the
fate of the times " to live in a society characterised by • mechanised petrifica-
tion '. Only the charismatic rebirth of new gods could conceivably offer an
alternati ve. ~3
Integrity, however, compels us to state that for the many who today tarry for
new prophets and saviours, the situation is the same as resounds in the beautiful
Edomite watchman's song of the period of exile that has been included among
Isaiah's oracles: • He calleth to me out of Seir, Watchman. what of the night?
The watchman said, The morning cometh, and also the night :if ye will enquire,
enquire ye: return. come.' The people to whom this was said has enquired and
tarried for more than two millenia ... 34
The most deeply rooted divergence between Marx and Weber, therefore.
concerns how far the alienative characteristics which Marx attributes to capi-
tllism as a specific form of class society in fact derive from a bureaucratic
rationality which is a necessary concomitant of the modem form of society.
whether it be • capitalist' or • socialist '. ~5 This will be taken up in more detail
in the next chapter.
S6 EF. p. 464.
31 EF, p. 476; FE, p. 603. Hence it is a notable misunderstanding to pose the question
• why. after all, is the worship of society any more readily explicable than the
worship of gods? ' W. G. Runciman: : The sociological explanation of .. religious ..
beliefs " Archi~'es europeennes de sociologie, vol. 10, 1969. p. 188.
218 Part 4: Capitalism, socialism and social theory
useless to try to find out which has determined the other; suffice it to say that
they are inseparable.' a8 The changes which lead to the differentiation of the
division of labour are both social and moral, and each is dependent upon the
other; moral individualism. the' cult of the individual " is the normative
counterpart of the emergence of a complex of division of labour: 'as indivi-
duals have differentiated themselves more and more and the value of an
individual has increased, the corresponding cult has taken a relatively greater
place in the totality of the religious life .. .' 31
It is in emphasising the relativity of the connection between social organisa-
tion and systems of ideas that Durkheim seeks to separate his position from
that of Marx :
Therefore it is necessary to avoid seeing in this theory of religion a simple resur-
rection of historical materialism: that would be a singular misunderstanding of
our thought. In showing that religion is something essentially social, we do not
at all mean to say that it confines itself to translating into another language the
material fonns of society and its immediate vital necessities.40
The historical implications of this are evident: Durkheim dissociates him-
self from a theory of knowledge which specifies a unilateral relationship
between ideas and their social' base '. This has to be placed in the forefront
when considering how far Durkheim's thesis does in fact differ from that
established in Marx's writings. The Elementary Forms is thus explicitly con-
cerned with the simplest extant form of religion; the theory of knowledge
set out in the work cannot be applied en bl.oc to more differentiated types of
society. The main theoretical connection linking the simplest to the more
complex societal types may be said to constitute a theoretical elaboration of
the principle which Durkheim slated at the outset of his career: that, while
there are very profound differences between traditional and modern societies,
there is still, between mechanical and organic solidarity, a definite moral
continuity.41
According to Durkheim's thesis in The Elementary Forms, the categories
of thought in totemism are formed of representations of social facts: the
notions of 'space', 'time', etc., are derived from' social space', 'social
time " and so on. As Durkheim says, this rests upon the general premise that
content of religious beliefs' cannot be purely illusory '.42 Since Durkheim
rejects the view that the elementary forms of religious belief are founded upon
representations of natural phenomena, or upon categories innately' given'
in the human mind, it must be the case that they rest upon the only other
• reality', that factual order which is society. The effect of Durkheim's insis-
tence upon a strict separation between' nature' and' society' is definitely to
draw something of an opposition between the two. This is responsible for a
.1 EW, p. 44.
u Su, p. 254. This is why it is misleading to take Durkheim's • favourable' and Marx's
• hostile' attitudes towards religion at their' face value' in drawing a sociological
comparison between them. For an example of this sort of simpliste viewpoint. see
Robert A. Nisbet: The Sociological Tradition (London. 1967), pp. 22S~ and
243-51.
Religion. ideology alld society 221
50 DL, p. 129.
Religion, ideology and society 223
aged by Marx would only be conceivable given a reimposition of a pervasive
conscience collective. which would necessarily entail a vast re-extension of
the realm of the sacred.
The contrast between Durkheim and Marx concerning the consequences
of secu1arisation in modem societies becomes most significant in relation to
their respective diagnoses of the primary trends of development which are
emergent in those societies. This leads into one major theme in the writings
of Marx, Durkheim and Weber which both unites and expresses some of the
main points of difference in their works: that which concerns their various
interpretations of the effects of the social differentiation entailed by the
growth in complexity of the division of labour.
15. Social differentiation and the division of labour
The writings of Marx, Weber and Durkhei.m, in their varying ways, fuse
together an analysis and a moral critique of modem society. Weber's insist-
ence upon the absolute logical dichotomy between empirical or scientific
knowledge, and value-directed action, should not be allowed to obscure his
equally emphatic affirmation of the relevance of historical and sociological
analysis to active involvement in politics and social criticism. Both Marx and
Durkheim reject Kant's ethical dualism, and attempt more directly to inte-
grate a factual and a moral assessment of the characteristic features of the
contemporary social order. Durkheim maintained a lifelong commitment to
the formulation of a scientific foundation for the diagnostic interpretation of
the • pathological' features of the advanced societies. Marx's work and
political actions are predicated upon the argument that • Man must prove the
truth, that is, the actuality and power, the this-sidedness of his thinking, in
Praxis ".1
In the works of the latter two writers, the concepts of • alienation' and
• anomie' respectively provide the focal point of their critical interpretation
of modem society. The conception of ali~nlltio!l is th~l!l_liin prop of Ma!'!'s
critigu~. 0.£ capitalismLand therefore of his thesis that the bourgeois order
can be transcended by a new kind ot society. It does not merely represent an
early utopian position which Marx later abandoned, nor does it become re-
duced to the relatively minor place which Marx's discussion of the • fetish-
ism of commodities' occupies in Capital. The same is true of Durkhhim's
notion of anomie: it is integral to his whole analysis of the modem • crisis '
and the mode in which it can be resolved.
2 See for example, John Horton: • The de-bumaDisation of anomie and alieaatioD '.
Pp. 283-300; Sheldon S. Wolin: Politics and Vision (Boston. 1960), pp. 399-407; a
more sophisticated discussion is offered in Steven Lukes: • Alienation and anomie '.
in Peter Laslett and W. G. Runciman: Philosophy, Polilics and Society (Oxford.
1967), pp. 134-56.
3 Vivolution pidllgogique. p. 21. 6 RSM, pp. 121 & 124.
s Su, p. 360; cf. also DL, vol. II, 272-4 & 403-4.
• DL, p. 399.• Although a child is naturally an egoist ... the civilised adult •.. has.
many ideas, feelings and practices unrelated to organic needs.' Su, p. 211.
226 Port 4: Capitalism, socialism and social theory
rationalists endowed man in a state of nature with faculties which are in
reality derived from society. The early forms of human society, which are
dominated by the relatively uncontrolled vagaries of nature, are accom-
panied by a restricted range of human qualities and capacities. It is precisely
the social character of man which, for Marx, makes him • human ': that is,
distinguishes man from the animals. All the senses and biological urges of
the human being are capable of this transformation. Sexual activity, or eating
and drinking, for instance, are not for human beings the simple satisfaction of
biological drives, but have become transformed, during the course of the
development of society, into actions which provide manifold satisfactions.
As Marx writes: • Our desires and pleasures spring from society; we measure
them, therefore, by society and not by the objects which serve for their satis-
faction. Because they are of a social nature, they are of a relative nature.' ,
In this sense, then, there is a much closer similarity between the • constants •
lying behind the concepts of alienation and anomie than might appear from
superficial comparison.' Both Marx and Durkheim emphasise the fact that
human qualities, needs and motives are in large part the product of social
development. Both perceive a primary flaw in the theory of political economy,
which treats egoism as the foundation of a theory of social order. As Marx
comments: • The division of labour and exchange are the two phenomena
which lead the economist to vaunt the social character of his science, while
in the same breath he unconsciously expresses the contradictory nature of
his science - the establishment of society through unsocial, particular
interests.' • Similarly, Durkheim criticises Tonnies because the latter's con-
ception of Gesellschllft treats society in the manner of utilitarian theory, as
an aggregate of independent, individual • atoms', which only constitutes a
unity insofar as it is cohered by the • external' influence of the state. Accord-
ing to Durkheim, this is completely inadequate: the activity of individuals in
forming contracts expresses a broad network of social ties in the division of
labour; and this is in fact the foundation of the state. Marx makes almost
exactly the same point in a different polemical context. The individual in
civil society is not comparable to en atom, because an atom ' has no needs'
and • is self-sufficient '. The fallacy of the conception of the atomic indivi-
dual, adopted by the economists. is that the member of civil society is bound
to others by relationships of interdependence. It is these unacknowledged
relationships which are the real foundation of the state: in reality it is the
10 Holy Family, p. 163. Marx also makes the point that the' atomic' position of the
individual in civil society is legitimised by norms of contract and property. As
contrasted with feudalism, ' Right has here taken the place of privilege' (p. 157).
11 Philosophy of Right, ed. Knox (London, 1967), p. 230. For Weber's conception of
, freedom ',see his discussion of Roscher and Knies, in GAW.
228 Purt 4: Capitalism. socialism and social theory
accept a complete historical relativism in this respect: every man. no matter
whether' primitive' or ' civilised '. is a homo duplex. in the sense that there
is an opposition in every individual between egoistic impulses and those
which have a ' moral' connotation. Marx does not adopt such a psychological
model; in Marx's conception. there is no asocial basis for such an implicit
antagonism between the individual and society. For Marx. 'The individual
is is the social being . .. Individual human life-.arul.spccies-Jjfe are nO.1different
things.' 12 The egoistic opposition between the individual and society which
is found in a particularly marked form in bourgeois society is an outcome
of the development of the division of labour. Durkbeim's identification of the
duality of human personality, on the other hand. is founded upon the sup-
position that the egoism of the infant. deriving from the biological drives with
which he is born. can never be reversed or eradicated completely by the sub-
sequent moral development of the child.
This can again be connected to the discrepant role of productive activity in
the model of society employed by Durkheim and Marx respectively. For
Durkheim. the emphasis upon the causal specificity of the 'social • - the
autonomy of sociological explanation -leads to a general neglect of the inter-
relationships between society and nature. In a specific way. this is manifest in
the proposition that those needs connected with physical survival in the
material world are not assimilated to those impulses which are rooted in
social commitments. Marx. by comparison. makes the interplay between
society and the natural world the focus of his analysis. and thereby emphasises
the socialised character of the ' sensuous needs • which mediate between the
individual organism and his adaptation to the physical environment. But this
must not be exaggerated: as has been shown above. both Marx and Durk-
heim stress the historical dimension in the conditioning of human needs, For
Durkheim. egoism becomes a threat to social unity only within the context
of a form of society in which human sensibilities have become greatly
expanded: 'all evidence compels us to expect our effort in the struggle
between the two beings within us to increase with the growth of civilisation.' 13
11 DL, p. 371.
11 DL. p. 373; DTS. p. 365. For a critique of Durkheim's position, see Georges
Friedmann: The Anatomy of Work (London, 1961), pp. 72-81 and passim.
11 The views set out by Engels, however, are much closer to Durkheim's position. cf.
Engels, • On authority', SW, vol. I, pp. 636--9.
Social differentiation and the division of labour 231
Division of LAbour: 'Is it our duty to seek to become a thorough and com-
plete human being. one quite sufficient unto himself; or. on the contrary, to
be only a part of a whole. the organ of an organism? • 1_ The analysis con-
tained in the work, in Durkheim's view, demonstrates conclusively that
organic solidarity is the' nonnal • type in modem societies. and consequently
that the era of the ' universal man' is finished. The latter ideal, which pre-
dominated up to the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries in western Europe.
is incompatible with the diversity of the contemporary order.20 In preserving
this ideal. by contrast, Marx argues the obverse: that the tendencies which
are leading to the destruction of capitalism are themselves capable of effect-
ing a recovery of the 'universal' properties of man. which are shared by
every individual :
the abolition of division of labour is conditional upon the development of inter-
course and productive forces to such a degree of universality that private pro-
perty and division of labour become fetters on them ... private property can be
abolished only on condition of an all-round development of individuals... With-
in communist society. the only society in which the original and free development
of individuals is not a mere phrase. this development is determined precisely by
the interrelationship of individuals, an interrelationship which consists partly in
the economic prerequisites and partly in the necessary solidarity of the free
development of all, and, finally, in the universal character of the activity of in-
dividuals on the basis of the existing productive fC?rces. 21
Contrary to what is often held, this conception does not entail any commit-
ment to a metaphysical 'perfectibility' of man. The imputation of such a
view to Marx rests upon a confusion of alienation and objectification - which
is precisely the charge which Marx levels at utilitarianism. If the overcoming
of alienation is read to mean the complete disappearance of any barriers to
the activity of the subject-man - then this would indeed suppose a utopian
world in which human self-detennination reigns supreme, and ~ human
of
potentialities are finally realised. But the transcendence- alienation does not
involve the end of objectification; society (and the material environment) will
continue to be • external' to the individual. They will not. however. as in a
condition of alienation, represent worlds which are opposed to or cut off
from conscious Praxis, but will be recognised to be integrated with it. In all
previous eras, according to Marx, the ideal of the universal man has been
either achieved only at the expense of the alienation of man from nature - as
in primitive societies - or has remained exclusive to minority classes. Through
2~ ct. Thilo Ramm: . Die kilnftige Gesellschaftsordnung nach der Theorie von Marx
und Engels', Marxismllsstlldi£'II, vol. 1.1957, pp. 77-179.
Social differentiation and the division of labour 233
23 Gerth and Mills: 'Introduction: the man and his work '. FMW. p. 51.
2t FMW, p. 138.
234 Part 4: Capitalism, socialism and social theory
modem economy, with the introduction of methods of rational calculation,
exemplified in book-keeping, which promote that methodical conduct of
entrepreneurial activity which is so distinctive of contemporary capitalism.
The conduct of rational capitalism in tum entails unavoidable consequences
in the sphere of social organisation, and inevitably fosters the spread of
bureaucracy.
Weber does not, of course, deny that modem capitalism entails the forma-
tion of a class system based upon capital and wage-labour, and he recognises
the importance of the historical expropriation of the peasantry upon which
Marx places so much stress. But this is not in itself, according to Weber's
standpoint, the main structural axis in the differentiated division of labour
which characterises capitalism. By emphasising the significance of the
rationalisation of activity as characteristic of modem capitalist production,
and by stressing iu, partial independence of class relationships. Weber separ-
ates (but in a different manner from Ourkheim) the class system of capitalism
from differentiation in the division of labour as such. In other words, bureau-
cratic specialisation of tasks is treated by Weber as the most integral feature
of capitalism. This is reinforced upon a more empirical level by Weber's
analysis of the partly separable processes of bureaucratisation in the economy
and the polity. The growth of the rational state, which has its corpus of
bureaucratic officials, is not wholly derivative of economic rationalisation, but
has to some extent preceded the development of capitalism - and indeed, has
created conditions which promoted its rise.
Thus Weber expressly denies that the expropriation of the worker from his
means of production has been confined to the immediate sphere of industry,
and instead applies the conception to other institutional contexts. In Weber's
thesis, any form of organisation which has a hierarchy of authority can
become sub!ect to a process of ' expropriation': for the Marxian notion of
the 'means of production' Weber substitutes the 'means of administration '.
Oversimplifying somewhat, it might be said that Weber gives to the organisa-
tion of relationships of domination and subordination the prominence which
Marx attributes to relationships of production. Any political association,
according to Weber, may be organised in an 'estate' form, in which the
officials themselves own their means of administration. Thus in the Middle
Ages, vassals were in direct control of the financing of their administrative
districts, and were responsible for providing tbeir own soldiery and military
equipment. The formation of the modem state apparatus was promoted by
the actions of the monarch in gathering the means of administration into his
own hands:
No single official personally owns the money he pays out, or the buildings, stores,
tools, and war machines he controls. In the contemporary • state' - and this is
essential for the concept of state - the' separation' of the administrative staff. of
Social differentiation and the division of labour 235
the administrative officials, and of the workers from the material means of
administrative organisation is completed. 23
These developments were the most important factors promoting the
emergence of the modem state in which 'expert officialdom. based on the
division of labour' 21 is wholly separated from ownership of its means of
administration. In general. the advance of the division of labour progresses in
step with the centralisation of the means of administration. and the con-
comitant • expropriation' of officials. This can be documented. Weber points
out. in military organisations. In feudal armies, each soldier supplies his own
weaponry: this is the case with militia of all types. But in states where there
is a need for a permanent army at the disposal of the monarch, such as in
ancient Egypt, a bureaucratised structure develops, in which the king owns
and supplies the arms and military equipment. In western capitalism. under
the twin influences of centralisation of administration and the rational calcula-
tion of tasks, the process of expropriation from the means of administration
penetrates into many spheres, including not only that of the military. but also
into other organisations in which there is a specialised division of labour -
universities. hospitals, and so on. The spread of bureaucratic specialisation
is mainly promoted by its technical superiority over other types of organisa-
tion in co-ordinating administrative tasks. This in turn is partly dependent
upon the filling of bureaucratic positions according to the possession of
specialised educational qualifications. • Only the modem development of ful1
bureaucratisation brings the system of rational. specialised examinations
irresistibly to the fore.' 21 The expansion of bureaucratisation hence neces-
sarily leads to the demand for specialist education, and increasingly fragments
the humanist culture which, in previous times. made possible the • universal
man " the • thorough and complete human being' whom Durkheim speaks
of. Weber expresses an essentially similar point in holding that the' cultivated
man ' of earlier ages is now displaced by the trained specialist. Since the
trend towards bureaucratisation is irreversible in capitalism, it follows that
the growth of functional specialisation is a necessary concomitant of the
modem social order.
According to Weber•• the further advance of bureaucratic mechanisation •
is • inevitable' in the modem world.28 But. as has been pointed out in a
previous chapter. in Weber's eyes the progression of bureaucratisation
increasingly reveals a tension between the demand for technical efficiency of
administration on the one hand. and the human values of spontaneity and
autonomy on the other. The bureaucratic division of labour constitutes the
• cage • in which modem Berufsmenschen are compelled to live: • The Puritan
IS FMW, p. 82.
21 FMW. p. 88.
n ES, vol. 3, p. 999; W/lG, vol. 2, p. 585; cf. also GASS, pp. 500-1.
I I GASS, p. 413.
236 Part 4: Capitalism, socialism and social theory
wanted to work in a calling; we are forced to do so.' 21 The Faustian' uni-
versal man' has to be renounced in favour of the specialisation of labour
which is the condition of the efficiency of modem production - ' specialists
without spirit, sensualists without heart '. The main normative issue, in
Weber's view. is not how the process of bureaucratisation can become
reversed. because that is impossible in a society which requires calculative
precision in the administration of its various institutions: 'the great question
thus is ... what we can set against this mechanisation to preserve a certain
section of humanity from this fragmentation of the soul. this complete
ascendancy of the bureaucratic ideal of life? '.30
It should be clear that. in Weber's terms. there can be no possibility of the
transformation of the bureaucratisation of social life through the occurrence
of socialist revolution. Precisely the opposite is the case. In the capitalist
economy. a considerable number of operations are left to the play of market
forces: but in a socialised economy. these would be taken over by the state.
and would then become subject to bureaucratic administration. A socialist
society would hence inevitably be more imprisoned within the toils of bureau-
cratic control than is already the case in capitalism: the elimination of pri-
vate property in the means of production would not enable this process to be
reversed. but would further hasten its advancement. Marx's view of bureau-
cracy is quite different, and again the difference lies primarily in the connec-
tion which Marx establishes between market alienation and technological
alienation - that is. between the class structure and bureaucratic specialisa-
tion. The substance of Marx's thinking on the question of bureaucracy is set
out in his early critique of Hegel's writings on the same question.
In Hegel's treatment of the matter. the state bureaucracy is represented as
the ' universal class' which is responsible for implementing what is in the
general interest of society. and which hence cuts across the egoistic bellum
omnia contra omnes which exists in civil society. According to Hegel. the
'division of labour in governmental affairs '. the civil service bureaucracy.
forms the organisational mediation between the particular. individual
interests of men in civil society, and the universal qualities of the state. The
hierarchical character of bureaucracy is explained in terms of the necessity
of establishing levels of co-ordination between the 'concrete' interests of
individuals in civil society and the 'abstract' character of state policy.
Appointment of officials on the basis of examinations. and the separation into
salaried offices. together with the conception of impersonal moral • duty'.
ensures that the member of the' universal class' renunciates the • capricious
satisfaction of subjective purposes ... So far as public business is concerned.
21 PE, p. 18t. The individual worker today is • a small wheel' in the bureaucratic
machine, and • asks himself only whether or riot he can progress from this small
wheel to being a bigger one " GPS, p. 413.
~o GASS, p. 414.
Social differentiation and the division of labour 231
here lies the link between universal and particular interests. constituting the
concept of the state and its inner stability.' 31 In Marx's terms. however.
Hegel's discussion of bureaucracy merely exemplifies in a particularly direct
way the general errors contained in the Hegelian concept of the state. Bureau-
cracy does not represent the common interest. but a particular interest;
bureaucratic authority rests upon an illusory universality which in fact cloaks
a specific class interest. The state bureaucracy is thus the administrative
organ through which the sectional power of the dominant class is institu-
tionalised. The formal hierarchy of authority which is embodied in bureau-
cratic organisation hence does not create the link between civil society and
the state which Hegel specifies. but instead acts to concentrate political power
and to separate it from the control of those in civil society: the bureaucratic
state is • an organ superimposed upon society '.32 Moreover. because of its
tightly integrated character. bureaucracy is an especially irresponsible form of
political administration: • Bureaucracy is a circle no-one can leave ...
Bureaucracy possesses.the state's essence. the spiritual essence of society, as
its private property. The universal spirit of bureaucracy is the secret. the
mystery sustained within bureaucracy itself by hierarchy and maintained on
the outside as a closed corporation.' 33
For Marx, then. the state bureaucracy is the archetype of bureaucratic
organisation. and the possibility of its eradicatien is given as one consequence
of the revolutionary transition to socialism. According to Marx, the countries
which are marked by the existence of a highly developed bureaucratic state -
both France and Germany fall into this category - are those in which the
struggle of the bourgeoisie against the land-owning aristocracy for political
power has been particularly severe. Thus the French bureaucratic machine
originated in the days of the absolute monarchy. and was given mighty a
thrust forward by the Revolution of 1189. As regards its historical content,
Marx's analysis of bureaucracy hence shares certain central points with that
of Weber. Marx agrees that the bureaucratic state in Europe arose as an
instrument serving the monarchy in its attempts to reduce the feudal dispersal
of powers: the centralisation of the state in the hands of the monarch was a
major condition allowing the rise of bourgeois interests. which then appro-
priated power to themselves. 34 But in Marx's view this is not. as it is for
Weber, one part of an irreversible general trend towards bureaucratic special-
isation of the division of labour in all spheres of social life. To Marx. bureau-
cratic centralisation is rather one particular manifestation of the bourgeois
state. and consequently is as transitory a social form as is capitalism itself.
SOme indication of how Marx envisages the elimination of bureaucracy in
socialist society is given in his remarks upon the bureaucratisation of the
31 Hegel. quoted by Marx. WYM, p. 181.
32 SW, vol. 2, p. 32.
33 WYM, pp. 185-6. cf. Iring Fetschcr: Karl Marx und der Marxismus (Munich,
1967). pp. 164-73. 34 SW, vol. I, p. 516.
238 Part 4: Capitalism, sociali,sm and social theory
French state. In France, this' parasitic body' has acquired • a ubiquity, an
omniscience' which surpasses even that in Germany. Marx specifically com-
ments upon the persistent growth which has characterised the French bureau-
cracy since the late eighteenth century: • All revolutions perfected this
machine instead of smashing it: 35 But the existence of such an independent
bureaucratic order is not intrinsically necessary to the maintenance of a
centralised economy; socialism will make it possible to' simplify the adminis-
tration of the state', and to 'let civil society and public opinion create organs
of their own, independent of the governmental power '.38 Such a programme
of change, as Marx makes clear in discussing the Commune in The Civil War
in France, is equivalent to the abolition of the bourgeois state altogether. The
Commune was to be composed of officials who were • chosen by universal
suffrage ... and revocable at short terms'. The judiciary and police were
also to be • turned into the responsible and at all times revocable' agents of
the Commune. In such conditions, the bureaucratic state, as an agency of
political power independent of civil society, has ceased to be: 'Public func-
tions ceased to be the private property of the tool of the central government.' 11
The differences between this standpoint and that adopted by Weber are
evident. Weber generalises the influence of bureaucratisation on the basis of
linking the advance of bureaucracy to the administrative requisites of rational
authority. Consequently, for Weber. the analysis of the growth of the bureau-
cratic state provides a paradigm for the explanation of the progression of
bureaucratisation in all spheres. For Marx, on the other hand. the ' systema-
tic and hierarchical division of labour' 31 in the administration of the state
represents a concentration of political power which will be aufgehoben when
the bourgeois state itself is transcended. The problem of bureaucratisation in
the sphere of industry is not discussed by Marx in relation to the question of
the bureaucratic state. but is nevertheless handled in comparable terms. The
authority system of the modem factory. according to Marx. is intrinsically
linked to the necessities engendered by the capitalist economy. But the various
forms of co-operative factory which have been set up show that a quite
different type of authority structure can be created, which will break down
the bureaucratic hierarchy. In the co-operative factories. there is no longer a
unilateral distribution of authority. at
•• FMW, pp. 126-7. ct. Uwith: I The ideal-typical II CODStructiOU" bas as its basis a
specifically" disillusioned" humanity •. .', Uwith, part I, p. 75.
" • Quito correctly did the Communist Manifesto emphasise the economic - Dot the
political - nvolutioruuy character of the work of the bourpois capitatiat entre-
preneur: GPS, p. 448.
Postscript: Marx and modem sociology
There are two polar sorts of orthodoxy in terms of which the relationship
between Marx's writings and those of the other two authors discussed at
length in this book, is usually presented. The first, adopted by many westem
sociologists, holds that Marx's works belong to the ' pre-history' of social
thought; and that the history of sociology proper only begins with the genera-
tion of writers to which Durkheim and Weber belonged.1 The second is that
usually expressed by Marxists, and holds that the works of this subsequent
generation of social thinkers represent nothing more than a bourgeois
response to Marx - and that, consequently, most of what passes for' socio-
logy , can be dismissed as simply a latter-day expression of liberal bourgeois
ideology. Each of these orthodoxies contains more than a substance of truth;
and each is dangerously misleading.
The first standpoint rests upon straightforward acceptance of the stated
views of the writers of the generation of Durkheim and Weber, that their own
work was 'scientific' in its formulation, and thereby different substantially
from the grandiose, ' speculative' constructions of earlier nineteenth-century
writers. Those who have accepted this view, by and large, have defined as
irrelevant the social and political circumstances in which Durkheim, Weber,
and their contemporaries developed their ideas, and have consequently
largely ignored the broader Weltanschauung which, in each case, was intrinsi-
cally bound up with the academic writings of the thinker in question. Latter-
day Marxists, by contrast. in mounting their critiques of sociology, have con-
centrated upon the identification of the social context in which Durkheim and
Weber wrote, and the political interests which their writings are presumed to
mask. i The content of their works is thus defined, in the cruder versions of
such attacks, as 'fallacious', since they represent a more or less direct parti-
san defence of liberal bourgeois society in the face of the Marxist challenge.
This latter view is not even consistent with Marx's own epistemology,
which avoids such a naive relativism. Marx accepts, for example, a great deal
of bourgeois economic theory as valid for the explanation of capitalist
development, while recognising its truth to be only partial and, in some ways,
distorted. In Manist terms, both Durkheim and Weber are committed to a
, bourgeois' political position, but this is hardly an adequate basis for dismis-
1 See Talcott Parsons: • Some comments on the sociology of Karl Marx', in Socio-
logical Theory and Modern Society (New York, 1967), pp. 102-3S.
i cf. Herbert Marcuse: • Industrialisierung und Kapitalismu5 " pp. 161-80.
243
244 Postscript: Marx and modern sociology
sing the content of their writings as false and thus to be discounted. The fact
of the matter is that Weber's own critique of Marxism, departing from pre-
mises of neo-Kantian idealism, reaches conclusions which are in some
respects closer to the original Marxian dialectic than are the deterministic
doctrines of some of Marx's declared followers. It is no accident that the
political· views of both Durkheim and Weber are difficult to categorise in
terms of the traditional division between liberalism and socialism. Weber's
methodological position is more' individualistic' than that of Durkheim. but
both reject - as Marx did before them - the theoretical solipsism of the
utilitarians. and with it certain of the suppositions of nineteenth-century
political liberalism. As I have tried to show in the foregoing chapters, the
social and political background to this can be understood in terms of the
development of Britain, France and Germany in the latter part of the century.
This stands at the back both of the critique of Marx contained in the works
of Durkheim and Weber, as well as of the main differences between the latter
two authors. which I have not analysed in this book.
The writings of both Durkheim and Weber have their origin in an attempt
to defend - or rather to re-interpret - the c1aims of political liberalism within
the twin pressures of Romantic hypernationalistic conservatism on the one
side, and revolutionary socialism on the other. Marx's writings, on the other
hand, constitute an analysis and critique of early capitalism. As the source
of a political mass movement, however, Marx's work achieved prominence
during the period of the consolidation of capitalism in the latter part of the
nineteenth century. This occurred within a context which transmitted Marx's
original conception into one which appeared much more as the direct expres-
sion of the main intellectual trends of the nineteenth century than as a critical
analysis and an attempt to supersede them. The result is that the Marx's
writings share a good deal more in common with those of Durkheim and
Weber than was apparent to either of the latter two authors: in perceptible
measure, the polemical foils of the three writers were the same. since Marx's
works, like those of the two later writers, constitute an attempt to transform
and supersede both Romantic conservatism (in German philosophy) and
utilitarianism as manifest in classical economics.
This having been said. it must, of course. be recognised that there are
irreconcilable differences of theoretical perspective and empirical interpreta-
tion between Marx and the other two authors. I have attempted to show that
some of the most basic differences centre upon divergent explanations of the
consequences of the growth of the division of labour - understood not in
sheerly economic terms, but as social differentiation - in modern society. For
those, however. who recognise the significance of Marx's contribution to
sociology. but who are able to treat Marx not as 'a dead saint' but rather as
a 'living thinker'.s there are many significant problems which can be
3 Erich Fronun: • Foreword '. EW, p. i; cr. Iring Fetscher, pp. 91(.
Postscript; Marx and modern sociology 245
conveniently posed through the comparative analysis of Marx's writings and
those of other social thinkers, considered in terms of their intellectual content.
It is no exaggeration to say that a major process of theoretical re-thinking
is taking place today within both Marxism and in academic sociology." In
large degree, this has been stimulated by the same circumstance: the apparent
• convergence' in the social structure of capitalist and socialist societies. At
the time at which Durkheim and Weber wrote the bulk of their works, there
was no extant society which either called itself • socialist' or claimed to
derive its primary inspiration from Marx. However, large-scale working
class movements, of a self-professed revolutionary character, existed in both
France and Germany, and the occurrence of a socialist revolution was by no
means beyond the bounds of possibility. But the October Revolution in
Russia took place in a country which was one of the least advanced. in
economic terms. in Europe. It was not the clarion call fo~ the revolutionary
overthrow of western European capitalism which Marx anticipated when.
late in his career, he accepted the possibility that the communal organisation
of the mir could allow Russia to move directly to socialism. Instead. it was a
stimulus to revolutionary change only to countries of comparable or of a
lower level of economic development than Russia itself.
If the advanced capitalist countries have changed, it has not been by means
of revolution, but by the gradual accumulation of change from within them-
selves. Today it is no longer possible to deny the profound nature of some
of these internal modifications in such things as the increasing intervention of
the state in the economy, the growth in the white-collar sector. and the partial
replacement of the old propertied upper class by a more amorphous pluralism
of elites. But just as the western capitalist countries have changed in con-
siderable degree over the past three or four decades. so have Russia and the
European countries which followed it in experiencing socialist revolutions.
In these countries. Marx's anticipations of an order in which class domina-
tion would be replaced by a rational order • in which the free development of
each is the condition for the free development of all ' & appears as far from
attainment as in the western liberal democracies. Rather, an epistemologically
distorted form of Marxism has been employed to legitimate a commitment to
industrialisation, in which the • overtaking' of the economic level of the
western countries has become the primary goal.
As a consequence, at least until quite recently. Marxist social thought has
utterly failed to come to grips with the problems posed by the trends of
development in both capitalist and socialist societies over the past few
decades. The Hobson-Lenin theory of . imperialism' has been used to bolster
" d. Norman Birnbaum: . The crisis in Marxist sociology', in Hans Peter Dreitzel:
Recent SOdology No. J (London, 1969), pp. 12-42. See also JUrgen Habcrmas:
Theorie und Praxis (Ncuwied and Berlin, 1967). pp. 261-335.
• CH, p. 162.
246 Postscript: Marx and modern sociology
the assumption that these trends are not to be explained in terms of any
important intrinsic modifications in the structure of these societies, but derive
from the exploitative relationship between them and the • underdeveloped ,
countries. Any theoretical reassessment of the development of the socialist
societies themselves has been precluded by the ideological dogma which
Marxism has itself become in these countries. The imnical outcome of this
is that • sociology' in these countries has come to be understood as a
peculiarly narrow descriptive discipline. But neither have western sociolo-
gists yet come to grips with these problems. In general, those writings which
have attempted to comprehend the changes that have occurred in the
capitalist societies. have been simply extrapolations of views given in the
writings of the generation of social thinkers to which Durkheim and Weber
belonged. The most important emphasis. however. has been placed upon the
attempt to formulate a body of ahistorical • general theory', a concern which
consciously directs attention away from problems of social change or develop.
ment. 1 Until recently, as in Marxist social thought, where the study of
development has been undertaken. interest has been concentrated upon the
non-industrial countries.
The impact of western technology and culture upon the non-industrialised
countries is obviously an area of theory and research which is of enormous
significance for sociology. But the framework within which this is approached
normally betrays an implicit assumption that the main characteristics of the
, developed societies' are known. and that the question is simply how far the
societies of the ' third world' will successfully match this model at some time
in the future. The way in which the term' industrial society ',or more recently
'post.industrial society '. has slipped into almost universal usage in socio-
logy to denote both societies which are nominally' capitalist • and those which
are socialist ',signifies the assumptions which underlie this standpoint. But
the various debates which have recently arisen concerning the question of the
• convergence' of capitalist and socialist societies,' and of the supposed dis-
solution of class relationships in the form in which these are traditionally
conceived.- are symptomatic of a resurgence of interest in the analysis of the
trends of development within the ' advanced' societies.
In important respects. this represents a return to the issues which were of
over· riding significance in the writings of the three authors discussed in this
book. Their works must still form the main point of departure if this is to
effect an important reorientation of social theory. It may be granted that
Marx's model of capitalism. in its entirety. 'is inappropriate to the post-
I See, above all, Talcott Parsons: The Social System (London, 1951).
1 See John H. Goldthorpe: 'Social stratification in industrial society', in Paul
Halmos: The Development of Industrial Society. Sociological Review Monograph.
no. 8, 1964, pp. 97-122.
• Ralf Dabrendorf: Class and Class Conflict in Industrial Society; Norman Birnbaum:
The Crisis of Industrial Society (New York, 1969).
Postscript: Marx and modern sociology 247
bourgeois industrial society in which we live ... '.' It does not follow from this
that some of the major elements of Marx's analysis of bourgeois society are
not of considerable significance today. This does not imply the reiteration of
the familiar theme that Marx accurately • predicted' some of the important
characteristics of contemporary societies, or that others of his supposed • pre-
dictions' have subsequently been falsified. It is to hold that Marx's analysis
poses issues which must still be regarded as problematic for modem socio-
logy: exactly the same is true of the writings of Durkheim and Weber. To
argue that it must be one of the main tasks of modem sociology to revert to
some of the concerns which occupied its founders is not to propose a step
which is wholly regressive: paradoxically, in taking up again the problems
with which they were primarily concerned. we may hope ultimately to liberate
ourselves from our present heavy dependence on the ideas which they
formulated.
65-95.
• La sociologic en France au XlXe si~le', Revue bleue, vol. 13, 1900, part I,
pp. 609-13, part 2, pp.647-52.
I Sur 10 totem1sme', Annie sociolog;que, vol. S, 1900-1, pp. 82-121.
Review of Merlino: Formes et essence du socialisme. Revue philosophique, vol.
48, 1889, Pp·433--9.
Debate with Lagardelle, Libres entretiens, 1905, pp. 425-34.
Review of works by Fouille, Belot and Landry, Annee sociologique, vol. 10,
19O5-6. pp. 352-69.
Review of Deploige: Le conflit de la morale et de la sociologie, Annee Socio-
lDgique, vol. 12, 1909-12, pp. 326-8.
• La famiDe conjugale I, Revue philosophique, vol. 91, 1921, pp. 1-14.
Secoadary works
H. B. Acton: The Illusion of the Epoch. London, 1955.
Lord Acton: Lectures on Modern History. London, 1960.
Guy Aimard: Durkheim et La science economique. Paris, 1962.
Martin Albrow: Bureaucracy. London, 1970.
Erik Allardt: • Emile Durkheim: sein Beitrag zur politischen Soziologie '. Kolner
Zeitschri/t fUr SoZiologie und Sozialpsychologie. vol. 20,1968, pp. 1-16.
Harry Alpert: Emile Durkheim and his Sociology. New York. 1939.
Louis Althusser: For Marx. London, 1969.
Louis Althusser et al.: Lire Ie Capital. Paris. 1967.
Carlo Antoni: From History to Sociology. London,1962.
Raymond Aron: Main Currents in Sociological Thought. Vols. 1 & 2. London,
1968 & 1967.
Shlorno Avineri: The Social and Political Thought of Karl Marx. Cambridge,
1968.
J. A. Barnes: • Durkheim's Division of Labour in Society " Man (New series),
voL 1,1966, pp. 158-75.
Eduard Baumgarten: Max Weber: Werk und Person. TUbingen, 1964.
Georg von Below: Der deutsche Staat des Mittelalters. Leipzig, 1925.
Reinhard Bendix: Max Weber, an Intellectual Portrait. London, 1966.
• Social stratification and the political community', Archives europeennes de
sociologie, vol. I, 1960, pp. 181-210.
Norman Birnbaum: The Crisis of Industrial Society. New York, 1969.
• Con1licting intcJ'pretations of the rise of capitalism: Marx and Weber',
British Journal oj Sociology, vol. 4, 1953, pp. 125-41.
H. Bollnow: Engels Auffaasung von Revolution und Entwicklung in seinen
I
Acton, H. B., 21n, 250 Calvinism, 127-31, 141, 142, 169, 177,
Acton, Lord, xi, 250 178, 183, 214
adventurers' capitalism, 126 Capital, 9, II, 28, 34, 37, 45, 46, 48,
Aimard, Guy, 87n, 250 SO, 52, 57, 59, 60, 64, 188, 189, 194,
Albrow, Martin, 159n, 250 197, 207, 224
alienation, see Marx, Karl capitalism, xvi, 9, 10-15, 19, 20, 28, 30,
Allardt, Erik, 104, 250 33, 34, 38-40, 45, 46-64, 121, 125,
Alpert, Harry, 87n, 250 126, 130, 131, 139, 142, 158, 159,
Althusser, Louis, 190, 35, 199n, 250 178, 179, 185-204, 205, 210, 214-16,
Annie soclologique, founding of, 200 232,239-47
anomie, see Durkheim, Emile Catholicism, 83, 125, ISS, 171
Anti-Diihring, xiv, xv, 189, 210 causal explanation, see explanation,
Antoni, Carlo, 147n, 250 causal
Aron, Raymond, 890. 250 causal imputation, 140, 141, 149, 153,
ascetic character of capitalism, 214, 215 228
ascetic Protestantism, see Calvinism charismatic authority, see Weber, Max
Asiatic mode of production, see Oriental China, 26, 78, 158, 169, 172-8, 206
society Christian ethic, 206, 207, 221
Aufhebung, 7, 59, 63, 222, 238 church and sect, 142
Avineri, Shlomo, 6n, 6On, 250 city, development of, 26, 27, 30, 175
civil society, 5~, 226, 227, 241
Civil War in France, The, 238
Baptist sects, 128
Barnes, J. A., 72, 250 class. see Durkheim, Emile; Marx,
Bau und Leben des Socialen Korpers, Karl; Weber, Max
66, ISO classification of knowledge, 108, 112-14,
Bauer, Bruno, 20, 205 217-23
Baumgarten, Eduard, 187n, 19On, 195n, Class Struggles in France, The, 38, 197,
250 198
Bebel, A., 188, 193 'coercion theory', 2090
Bellah, Robert, 100n Cole, W. A., xiin, 251
Below, G. von, 146n, 250 commercial classes, 164
Bendix, Reinhard, 121n, 250 Communist Manifesto, The, 64, 194
Bernstein, E., 189 Comte, A., 65, 68, 71, 72, 89, 91, 113n,
Birnbaum, Norman, 211n, 245n, 246n, 116, 133
250 Confucianism, 174-8
Bismarck, O. von, xiii, 187, 188, 190, conscience collective, 67, 75, 77, 79, 80,
191, 198 85, 92, 101, 102, lOS, 111, 114, 203,
Weber and, 190 223
Bollnow, H., 189n, 250 constant capital, SO, 51
Bottomore, T. B., 23n, 248 contradiction, 44, 52-5, 240, 242
bourgeoisie, see Marx, Karl Contribution to the Critique of Political
Boutroux, E., 65 Economy. A, 18
bureaucracy co-operative factories, 238
Durkheim on, 101, 102, 203, 204
Marx on, 236-8, see also Weber, Max Cornu, A., In, 250
corporations, 101-4, 199, 200
Coulanges, Fustel de, 65, 107
Caesarism, 181 crises, 5H, 189, 197, 198, 240
Caillois, Roger, ll1n, 250 Cronzet, F., xiiin
calling, concept of, 127, 129-31, 235, • cult of the individual " 72, 73, 80, 115,
236 116, 218, 241
2SS
256 Index
Dahrendorf. R., 37n, 191n, 250 Durkheim and Marx, 6S, 96-8. 196-
Darwin, C .• 66, 79 204, 205, 206, 216-32. 239-41
Davy, Georges, 12011, 199n. 251 Duvignaud, Jean, 7On, 251
Deane, Phyllis, xim, 251 dynamic density, 78, 79, 217, 218
declining profit, law of, 52, S3, 240
dehumanisation, 229, 230 Easton, Loyd D., 248
democracy Ecole Normale, 65
Durkheim on. 99, 101-4 EcolIDmic and Philosophical Manu-
Weber on, 180-2 scripts, xiv, xv, 3, 9-17, 19-21. 23,
Denis, E., 65n, 249 60
Deploige, Simon, 68n, 71n, 249, 2S1 economic as distinct from technological,
descriptive concepts, 142, 143 194, 195
determinism economic conditioning, 194
dialectic and, 189, 190 economic ethic, 131, 169, 170
Marx on, 40-5, 207-10 economic relevance, 194
revolution and, 60 economic traditionalism, 125-7
Weber on, 131, 139, 140, 141, 193-5 Economy and Society, 145, 146, 153,
dialectic. 20, 21-3, 59, 60, 189, 207, 208, 170
education, 101, 103, 143, 144, 198
212,240 egoism
direct understanding, 148 Durkheim on, 69, 70, 77, 84
.division of labour, see Dillision of individualism and, 115-18
. Labour in Society, The; Durkheim, Marx on, 5, 6, 10, 35
Emile; Marx, Karl; Weber, Max Egypt, 158, 159, 181, 182, 192
Dillision 01 Labour in Socfety, The, 69, Eighteenth Brumaire of Louis Bonaptllte,
72, 7~9, 82, 84, ~2, 9S, 97, 98. The, 197
102, 103n, lOS, 111, 116, 117, 217 eighteeath-century philosophers, 22S
Dobb, Maurice, 30u, 34n, 2S1 elective affinity, 131, 211, 212
domination Elementary Forms of the Religious
authority, 156--63 Life, The, 106, 107, 110, 114, 217,
class structure, 36-40, 163-7 218
concept, 1S6 Engels, Frederick, xiv, xv, 3, 9, 16, 18,
Dreitzel, Hans Peter, 24Sn, 251 28, 29, 30, 31, 34, 37, 46, 66, 125,
Ikeyfiq Case, 6Sn, 19~ 199 186n, 189n, 196, 197, 210, 23011,
Durkheim, Emile 248
anomie, 69, 71, 79-81, 84, 85, 99, 103, and Marx, 189, 190, 230n
liS, 117, 204, 224-8, 230, 232, 241 Entiiusseru"" 12
class. 8~1, 97-9, 103, 203, 204, 219, Entfremdun" 12
220, 229-31, 240. 241 ethical neutrality, 143, 144
division of labour, 69, 70-9, 92, 93, ethical theory, 93, 94, 116, 136, 169, 189,
97, 118, 228-32, 240, 241 190, 19S
externality, 86-8, 90, 222. ethic of responsibility, 136-8
mecbanical solidarity, 75-9, 105, 112, ethic of ultimate ends, 137, 138, 195,
222, 223 212
moral authority, 88, 89, 103, 106, exchange-value, 46-8, 64, 239, 240
114-18, 199, 200, 2J8-23, 240, 241 explanation
normality and pathology, 91-4, 104, and history, 22, 23, lOS, 106, 141-3
220, 224, 231, 240 and interpretative sociology, 146-S1
organic solidarity, 76-80, 92, 93, 103, causal, 89-91, 139-41
222, 223, 23~2 types of, 90, 91, 139, 140
psychology, 72, 86, 87 expropriation
reliajon, 71, 75, 83, 99, 105-18, 199, and alienation, 239
2~2, 216-23 and division of labour, 158, 159, 119-
science of moral life, 66-70 81,234-42
socialism., 95-7, 198, 200-4 ~arx on, 30-2, 236-42
socioloajcal method, 82-94 Weber on, 179-81,234-6
state, the, 96-101, 156, 241 external inequality, 81
suicide, 71, 78, 82-5 externality, see Durkheim, Emile
Index 257
Fetsch~r, Iring, 237n, 244n, 251 Hobson-Lenin theory of imperialism,
feudahsm, 29-31, 39, 51, 64, 227, 235, 245,246
239 Hodges, Donald. 380, 25 1
Feuer, Louis. 19n, 251 Holy Family, The, 18, 206
Feuerbach. Ludwig. 3-6, 12, 13, 2~2, homo duplex, 228
205, 206, 208n, 221, 251 Horton, Iohn, J17n, 225n, 251
Fichte. I. G., 2 Hubert, Henri, 100n, 251
forced divisioo of labour, 80, 204, 240 Hughes. H. Stuart, 1100, 251
formal and substantive rationality, 183, Hyppolite, lean, 5n, 251
184, 216
Fraoce, developmeot of in nineteenth
century. 196-8 ideal types, see Weber, Max
freedom, concept of, 116-18, 123, 127, ideas, role of, xv, 21-3, 40-4, 190, 194,
230,242 195, 202, 203, 204, 21~12
French Revolution, xi, xii, xiii, I, 7, 44. ideology, see Marx, Karl
72, 116, 186, 196, 197, 201 India, 26, 169, 172-8, 206
Freud. S., 226n individual, concept of, 86-8, ISO, lSI,
Freund, Iulien, 1460, 251 226,227
Friedmann, G., 183n, 2300, 251 individualism, 35, 72, 73, 79-81, 95, 101,
Fromm. Erich. 244n 114-17, 199, 216-23, 225, 240
function, 90, 91, 106, ISO, 151 Industrial Revolution, xii, 188
industrial society, xii, 246
inheritance, 99, 204
Gehlke, Charles Elmer, ]06n, 251 Instleure, 122, 123
Gemeinscha/t und GeselIschaft, 71 n, 72 'integration' theory, 2090
German Ideology, The, 18-21, 22, 63, interpretative sociology, 143-51, 213
208 • iron cage', 235, 236, 242
Germany, development in nineteenth
century, 185-8
Gerth, H. H., 1700, 233n, 249 Iellinek, Georg, 193n
• ghost of Marx', 185 Johnson, Barelay. 85, 252
Giddens, Anthony, 251 Iordan, Z. A., 21n, 252
Goldthorpe, Iohn H., 2460, 251 Iudaism. 169, 171, 172
Gotthei1, Fred. M., 51, 251 Junker' aristocracy', 186, 187, 191
Gouldner, Alvin, 65n
grande bourgeoisie, 197, 198
Guesdism, 200 kadi-justice, 161 n
Gumplowicz, L., 68n. 71n, 249 Kamenka, Eugene, 208n, 252
Gurvitch, Georges, 2n, 1850, 251 Kantianism, 2, 67, 91, 92, 113, 134, 135,
Guyau, M. I., 70, 80, 249 138, 195, 220, 222, 224, 233, 244
Kathedersozialisten, 95, 119. 192n
Kautsky, Karl, xv, 46, 123n, 200, 206n
Habermas, lUtgen, 245n, 251 Klages, Helmut, 19n, 252
Hartwell, R. M., xiiin. 251 Knies, K. G. A.• 134, 1490, 227n
Hayward, I. E. S., 740, 200n, 251 Kocka, E. 11lrgen, 216n, 252
Hegel, G. W. F., 1-6, 14, 16, 18-21, 100, K<Snig, Rene, 252
205-7, 212, 227, 236, 237, 251 Korsch, Karl, 430, 252
Herrschaft, 36, 156
Hess, Moses, 15n, 16
Hinduism, 172--4 Labedz, L., 19n. 252
historical materialism, xiii, xv, 18-34, labour
132, 133, 190, 193, 202, 203, 204, abstract, 47
211, 218 and capital, II, 12, 14-15, 33, 34, 39,
historical school, 120 46-64
history and sociology, xi-xii, 20, 22, 23, labour-power, 47, 240
68, 90, 91, 106, 117, 133, 141, 163, theory of value, 46-8
193, 194. 210, 225, 226, 246, 247 Labriola, Antonio, xv, 200, 202, 2030,
Hobbes, T., 225, 226n 204o, 249, 252
258 Index
Lacombe, Roger, 900, 252 Marx. Karl-cont.
Landes, David S., xiin, 252 communism, conception of, 16, 17,
Laski, Harold 1., 189n, 248 60-4, 204n, 206, 209, 21S. 227, 240,
Laslett, Peter, 225n, 252 245
LassaUe, F., 187-9, 200 division of labour, 19, 24, 25, 26, 209,
lati/undiae, 28, 29 226, 228-32, 239
laws in social science, 138, 139, 187, 193, and Hegel, 1-6, 14, 16, 18-21, 193.
212, 213 212
leadership problem in Gennany, 190-2 ideology, ~5, 205, 206-16
materialism, xv, 4-5, 20. 21-3, 204,
Le Bon, G., IS2 207-10
legal authority, see Weber, Max peasantry, 37-9, 44
Lenin, V. I., lOvn, 252 proletariat, 8, 19, 32, 34, 50, 61, 186,
liberalism 197, 198
in France, 196-8 religion, 7, 9, 11-12, 206-16
in Gennany, 187, 188, 19~2 stages in development of society, 22-
liberalism and sociology, 244 34
Lichtheim. George, xvn, 6n, 27n, 198, state, 4-6, 16, 18, 19, 26, 40, 61-3,
1990, 247n, 252 97,226,227
Uebknecbt, W., 188, 192n Marxism, 123, 163, 185-93, 198, 200,
Ulienfeld, P., 66 207, 243-7
Lindenlaub, Dieter, 1240, 134n, 1920, and modem sociology, 243-6
252 materialism, lee Marx, Karl
Lobkowicz, Nicholas, 36, 252 Mauss, Marcel, 95, lOIn, 1000, 1120,
logical classes, 113 249, 251, 252
USwith, Karl, 241n, 2420, 252 meaDS of administration, 234, 235
LukAcs, Georg, 20, 43n, 600, 188n, mechanical solidarity, see Durkheim,
189n, 1920, 252 Emile
Lukes, Steven, 225n, 252 Meek, Ronald L., 46n, 48, 252
Mehring, Franz, 187n
Lumpenproletariat, 38 Menger, A., 1340
Lutheranism, 127-9, 207
M6aztr08. Istvtn, 160, 252
Luxemburg, Rosa, 192n methodism, 128
Meyer, Alfred, G., 160, 252
Meyer, Eduard, 140
McLellan, David, 3n, 252 Michels, R., 145n, 159n, 180, 181, 192n
Macpbenon, C. B., 226, 252 Mil:la, C. Wright, 170n, 233n, 249
magic and religion, Weber on, 214, 2IS Mitzman, Artbur, 188n, 252
mona. 109, 170 Mombert, Paul, 1650
Mandel, Ernest, 64, 252 Mommsen, T .• 120
Marcuse, H., 183n, 243n Mommsen, Wolfgang 1., 143n, 190ft,
market,the 1920.252
centralisation, 58-60 Montesquieu, C. de S., 65, lOIn, 102n
concentration, 58-60 Moore, Barrington, 188n, 252
and feudalism, 29-33, 38-40 Moore, Wlibert E., 1850
and growth of capitalism, 33, 34, 64 moral authority, see Durkheim, Emile
• market alienation', 228, 229
market situation, defined, 164 natural religion, 219
stock market, 121, 122 nature and society, 218-20
Marx, Karl Nietzsche, F., 213n
alienation, 9-16, 19, 52, 57, 64, 215, Nisbet, R. A., 70, 22On, 252
216, 219, 220, 222, 224-32, 239 nomothetic venus ideographic dicho-
bourgeoisie, 33, 34, 38, 39, 44, 186, tomy, 133, 139, 140
187,196-8,207,210
capitalist development, ~
class, 27, 28, 36-40, 195, 197. 198. objectification, 11-12, 222, 231
209, 210. 213. 215. 219, 220. 229. occupational groups, see corporations
232. 239. 240. 245 organicism, 65, 150, 151
Index 259
organic solidarity, see Durkheim, Emile Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of
Oriental society, 25-7, 76, 157 Capitalism. The. 121, 124, 12S, 127,
Origin of the Family, Private Property 131, 132, 133, 142, 169, 184, 193,
and the State, 29 205
Ossowski, Stanislaw, 36n, 2S2 Protestantism, 83, 115, 119-32, ISS, 206,
ownership classes, 164 2J)7
Proudhon, P. J., 23n, 200
Prussia, 186-8
Palyi, Melchior, 165n, 252 psychology, see Durkheim, emile;
Paris Commune, 62, 198, 238 Weber, Max
Parsons, Talcott, 7On, 710, 72n. 86n, purposively rational conduct, 1S2
87n, 1060, 113n, 1430, 1480, 1920,
209.n,241n, 243,2460,2S3
pathology, see Durkheim, Emile: Radical Party in France, 198, 200
normality and pathology Ramm, Tbilo, 232n, 253
patrimoDialiam, 1S7, 1S8 rate of exploitatioo, 49
pauperisation, 55-8, 189, 240 rationalisatioo, see Weber, Max
peoal law, 74-6 reflective materialism, 211, 212
perfectibility, 231, 232 Reissner, Hans Gtlnther, In, 253
Peru, 36 relations of production, 35-8, 209
pietism. 128 religion
Pizzomo, Alessandro, 71, 253 ceremonial in, 110-12
Plamenatz, John, 42n, 253 concept, of, 107, 170-2
political ecooomy disenchantment, 128, 136, 239, 241
conception of society in, 10-11, 68. 69 Feuerbach on, 5
critique of. 43, 44, 68-70, 226, 227 Hegel on, 20S
politics ideology. 206-14, 219-22
and communism, 96. 97 kno~edge. 108-10. 112-1S, 216-17
concept of, 4-6, 39-40, 62, 1S6 magic, 170-2, 174n
French, 196-9 secularisation, lOS, 214-16, 221-3
German, 185-90 transcendence of, 3, 4, 206, 214-16,
Hegel on, 4-6 222,223
Plato on, 96 ue also Calvinism; Catholicism; China;
Popitz, H.. 13n, 253 Christianity; Durkbeim, Emile; India;
post-industrial society, 246 Marx, Karl; Weber, Max
Poulantzas, Nicos Ar., 209n, 253 Renouvier, C.. 65n. 72
power repressive sanctions, 74, 15
and authority, 4-6, 61. 62, 98-100, reserve army, S6-8, 240
1S4-7, 190 . restitutive sanctions. 74, 75
and class. 38-40, 42-4, 80, 81, 97, 19S revolution, 44, 45, 59, 60, 116, 135, 182,
defined, IS6 185-7, 1920, 196, 200n, 203, 204,
lctrltimacy, 154-7 237
and parties, 167, 168 Ricardo. D., 46
Prades, J. A., 1240, 253 Richard, Gaston, 201, 202n. 249
pragmatism, 137 Rickert, H., 133, 138, 139
Praxis, 6-8, 20, 41. 42, 60. 18S, 208, ritual, 110-2 •
224,231 negative rites, 111
predestination, 128, 129 piacular rites, 112
primitive accumulation, 31 positive rites. 111, 112
private property Robinson, Joan, 57n, 2S3
and alienation, 11-14, 228-32 Roman law, 120, 178, 179
and class structure, 36-40, SO, 98, 99, Roman society, 23, 27-9, 40, 44, 120,
164-6, 192. 204, 228-32 121. 167. 206
and communism, 16, 17, 60-4, 239, romantic conservatism, 244
240 Roscher. W., 134. 149n.2270
proletariat, see Marx. Karl Roth. GQnther. 12On, 156n, 181n. 1920,
prophecy, 171, 172 193n. 253
260 Indu
Rousseau, J.-J., 65, 67, lOin, 102n, 224, state and politics, see Duritbeim, Emile;
225 Marx, Karl; Weber, Max
routinisation of charisma, 162 state in Britain, 197
Rubel, Maximilien, 23n, 186n, 248, 253 state of nature, 224-6
Ruge, Arnold, 4n, 7n status position, 166, 167, 195
Rules 01 Sociological Me/hod, The, 78, Stirner, Max, 206, 2260
82, 86, 89, 91, 104 stock exchange, 121, 122
Runciman, W. G., 217n, 225n, 253 Strauss, D., 20, 193n, 205
Russia, 78, 1920 Strauss, Leo, 92n, 253
Russian revolution, I, 192n, 245 suicide,
altruistic. 78, 85
anomie, 84, 85
egoistic, 84, 85
sacred and profane, 107-9, 217, 221 see also Suicide; Durkheim, Emile
Saint-Simon, H. de, 65, 98, 200, 204 Suicide, 82, 83, 86, 91, 95
Salomon, Albert, 185, superstructure, 39-44, 194, 195. 218, 219
Schllflle, A., 66-9, 72, 95n, I SO, 249 surplus, value, 46-52
Schelting, A. von, 133n, 143n, 253 Sweezy, P., 31n, 48, 51, 53, 253
Schiller, F. von, 231n, 253
Schmidt, Alfred, 21n, 253
Schmidt, Gustav, 191n, 253 • technological alienation " 228, 229
technological rationality, 215, 216
Schmoller, G., 68, 69, 119 Tenbruck, F., 133n, 253
Schumpeter, J., 145n, 210, 212, 253 Theses on Feue,bach, 20, 21
Schutz, Alfred, 151n, 253 Tiryakian, Edward A., 1190, 253
science of moral life, see Durkheim, Tonnies, F., 71, 77, 106, 226, 249
Emile totemism, 107-13, 1700
secular humanism, 221, 222 traditional authority, 156, 157
Simmel, Georg, 119, 152, 187n, 214n, Treitschke, H. von, 101, 191n
253 tribal society, 24-7
Smith, Adam, 35, 46, 54n Tucker, Robert C., 20, 13n, 253
social action, 146, 147
Social Democratic Party (SPD), xiv, xv,
187-92, 196, 210 usage and custom. 154, 155
social facts, 87-90, 110, 202 use-value, 46, 47, 239
social integration, 83, 84 utilitarianism, 72, 77, 78, 91, 92, 100,
socialism, see Durkheim, Emile; Marx, 199
Karl; Weber, Max
social morphology, 219, 220
society value-judgements. 138. 139, 212, 213
and economy, 10, 11, 12-14, 21-3, 35, value rational action, 152, 153
36, 99, 100, 164-7, 193-5, 239-42 values and prices, 48-52
mode of study of, 21-2, 86-8, 145-51 variable capital, 50-I
stages in development of, 24-34, 44, Vere;n iiJ, Sozialpoli/ik, 119, 124n.
45,76-9 1590
and state, 4-6, 19, 20, 40, 61-3, 98- verstebende Soziologie, see interpreta-
104, 159, 167, 168, 18<r2, 234-42 tive sociology
Voden, A., 18n
sociological method, see Durkheim, Volksgeis/, 134
Emil-: sociological method
Volksseele. 134
sociology, development of, xii, 67, 68,
89,90, 243-7
Sombart, W., 145n, 1920, 193n Wagner, A., 68
Sorel, Georges, 200n, 253 Weber, Alfred, 119, 145n
soul. concept of, 115 Weber, Marianne, 133n, 134n, IS8n,
species-being, 13, 14, 16 19On, 193n, 253
Spencer, Herbert, 65n, 77 Weber, Max
spontaneity, 216, 241 bureaucracy. 158-60, 175, 180-3, 191,
Stammler, R., 193n 192, 216, 234-S
Index 261
Weber, Max-cont. Weber, Max-cont.
charismatic authority, 160-3, 170, 213 spirit of capitalism, 124-32, 142, 169,
classes. 163-7, 190, 191, 19S, 213, 234 184
critique of Marxism, 123, 124, 131, Weber and Marx, 123-'5, 131, 132. 158,
132, 190-6, 244 159, 164, 179, 180, 190-6, 205-16,
ideal types, 141-3, 148, 242n 232-8, 241, 242
law, definition of, ISS, 156 Weitling, W., 16n
legal authority. 157-9 Wesolowski, W., 36n
legitimacy and domination, 154-63, WinckeImann, Johannes, 1200, 146n,
190-2 2S2, 253
objectivity, 134--8 W'mdelband, W., 133, 138
Wittfogel, Karl A., 26n, 27n, 254
political society and the state, 1S6, WoltI, Kurt, 10Sn, 1190, 254
IS9, 167, 168, 17S-6, 178-82, 234--8 Wolfson, Murray, SI, 2S4
and psychology, lSI, 169 Wolin, Sheldon S., 225, 254
rationalisation, 36, 127, 128, 139, 142, Wonley, P. M., 1lin, 254
178-84, 214--16, 220, 233, 241 Wundt, W., 70
religion, 124--32, 136, 137, 170-8, 192,
193, 206-16
socialism, 135, 165n, 181-2, 191, 192, Young Hegelians, XIU, 2, 3, 7, 17, 18,
19S, 202, 216. 236 193n, 206, 211