LAL112 - Batch 1
LAL112 - Batch 1
STUDY MATERIAL
1999
COURSE E/LAL112
BATCH NO. 1
INTRODUCTION TO LANGUAGE
COMPILED BY DR. N. KATSUVA
E/LAL112 1
Serial No. E/LAL112/99/1
Introduction
Objectives
By the end of the course students are expected to:
Contents
1. What is Language?
E/LAL112 2
2. Linguistics and some other disciplines
3. Phonetics
4. Phonology
5. Morphology
6. Some basic concepts in morphology
7. Morphological processes
Method of Teaching
Distance students will receive intensive instruction during residential school. The
number of contact hours is as determined by the Directorate of Distance Education and
the course Co-ordinator.
Assessment
- Examination 50%
In order to fulfil the conditions of this course students are expected to pass both
continuous assessment (course work) and the final examination. A student who fails
either of these components will be deemed to have failed.
Students are also reminded that attendance at lectures, tutorials and/ or seminars are
compulsory and disciplinary action which, may in some cases, include de-registration
E/LAL112 3
from the course, may be taken against students who habitually are absent from most
course activities.
Assignments should be submitted on or before the due date. Assignments that are
submitted late without any serious reason, will not be marked and will consequently
accrue a failing grade.
We know that students, just like any other person may at some point, face problems.
Some problems may occur just when you are about to submit your assignment. If you
realize that you cannot submit your assignment on time, you should immediately inform
your lecturer and the Directorate of Distance Education.
We also know that some of you may be living or working in the countryside where
libraries are non-existent, and therefore it is impossible to get material for your
assignments. To go round this problem, all assignment questions will be given to you
during residential school. The reason for doing so it is to enable you to do all the
necessary library research while you are on residential school.
E/LAL112 4
BATCH ONE
TABLE OF CONTENTS
E/LAL112 5
UNIT ONE
WHAT IS LANGUAGE
Like most word, the word, language is polysemous, i.e. it has more than one meaning.
The Longman Dictionary of Contemporary English (1995: 789) defines language as
follows:
4. “the kind of words and style used in one kind of writing by people in a particular
job or activity”, as in: medical language, poetic language;
6. “words that most people think are offensive”, as in: You never heard such
language‟ it was disgusting‟
An articulated language is a language using vocal sounds, i.e. sounds produced by human
organs (lips, teeth, larynx, etc).
(a) human language (as opposed to, e.g., computer languages or “animal language”)
need not be articulated since according to definition 5, a human language, may be
made of signs or movements; and that
E/LAL112 6
To define a term belonging to a given language is to talk or write (depending on whether
the definition is oral or written) on that language. This kind of activity (to talk or write
about language) is referred to as a metalinguistic activity. Metalinguistic activities are so
complex, or complicated, that even eminent linguists have defined language in a biased
or incomplete manner. Take for example the following definitions of language proposed
by eminent linguists and discussed by Lyons (1990: 3 – 8):
1. SAPIR (1921: 8)
Language is “the institution whereby humans communicate and interact with each
other by means of habitually used oral – auditory arbitrary symbols.”
While Lyons‟ comments (a) and (c) are correct, his comment (b) is not: studies of the so
called” body language‟, i.e. sign language as used by deaf people is a language in its own
right with possibilities and a complexity comparable to articulated (i.e. spoken/ written)
E/LAL112 7
human language. In connection with comment (a), we shall see some other functions of
language in another lecture). As for comment (c), many, if not most, Linguists will agree
that animals, perhaps with the exception of protozoa (very small unicellular living
beings) have languages to the extent that they interact with other, within the same
species. One of the best known animal language is the bee language.
(a) The definition puts all the emphasis on the social function:
co-operation. It is therefore only indirectly, by implication of the concept of co-
operation, that it makes an appeal to the communicative function of language.
(b) The Bloch and Trager definition also differs from Sapir‟s in that it Brings in the
property of arbitrariness and restricts language to spoken Language (e.g. „vocal
symbols‟ in the definition).
The meaning of the expression „habitually used‟ is connected to the Stimulus – response
theories of he behaviourists, which (theories) strongly influenced linguistics and the
Psychology of language in the first
Half of the century, especially in America. In these theories, the term „habit‟ was used to
refer to bits of behaviour which were identifiable, the assumption being that the same
stimulus calls for the same response. This assumption is untrue. For example, it is not
always the case that when we find ourselves in a situation where we see a bird (=
stimulus) we produce an utterance continuing the term „bird‟ ( = response)
E/LAL112 8
Lyons’ Comment on Chomsky’s Definition
Unlike the other definitions, Chomsky‟s is intended to cover much else besides natural
languages. According to Chomsky‟s definition, all natural languages, in either their
spoken or their written form, are languages. It is the task of the Linguists describing a
particular language to distinguish between what is a sentence and what is not a sentence.
According to Chomsky, the structural properties of language are so abstract, so complex
and so highly specific that they cannot possibly be learned from the scratch by an infact.
They must be known somehow to the child, prior to and independently of his experience.
(a) Chomsky‟s model of language learning in which the infact credited with an
inmate predisposition to acquire linguistic structure is know as Language
acquisition device (LAD) (Crystal 1992; 6.) As pointed out by Crystal (1992; 6),
„This view is usually opposed to those where language acquisition is seen as a
process of imitation – learning or as reflex of cognitive development‟.
(b) Chomsky (1957; 13) explains that all natural languages in their spoken or written
form are languages because they satisfy his definition his definition (namely that a
language is “a set (finite or infinite) of sentences, each finite in length and
constructed out of a finite set of elements‟) since “each natural language has a
finite number of phonemes (or letters in its alphabet) and each sentence is
represented as a finite sequence of these phonemes (or letters), though there are
infinitely many sentences”.
(d) The only problem with Chomsky‟s definition is that it may exclude those‟ animal
languages‟ in which there are no sequences of elements, for instance those
„animal languages‟ in which there are no sequences of elements, for instance
those „animal languages‟ where one cry corresponds to a sentence in a human
language.
One fundamental difference between the Chomsky definition and the other definitions
examined here is that, unlike the others, it does not make an appeal to any function of
language.
E/LAL112 9
CONCLUSION
Theoretical and descriptive linguists generally fail to adequately define the term language
because they tend to define language in one sentence, a tendency which one might
attribute to their assuming that the term language is monosemous, i.e. it has only one
meaning. The only way the term „Language‟ can be defined adequately is to do what
lexicographers do: to fully appreciate that the term is Polysemous (= it has more than one
meaning) and, since it is difficult to extract what is common to all the meanings of the
term, define each meaning separately (see, for example, Longman Dictionary of English)
REFERENCES
Chomsky, N., (1957) Syntactic Structures. The Hague, Paris, New York: Mouton
Publishers.
Hall, R. A. (1968) An Essay on Language. Philadelphia and New York; Chilton Books.
REVISION QUESTION
1. With four examples, show the term „Language‟ is polysemous (= it has more than
one meaning)
“In defining language, it is important to distinguish between a narrow sense and a broader
sense of the term.”
E/LAL112 10
of which a social group co-operates”
(B. BLOCK & G. L. TRAGER).
(d) A language is “a set (finite or infinite) of sentences, each finite in length and
constructed out of a finite se of elements “N. Chomsky).
Why do theoretical and descriptive linguists generally fail to
to adequately define the term „Language‟?
E/LAL112 11
UNIT TWO
The Psychologist B. F. Skinner has emphasised the role of nurture, i.e. training
acquisition, while the linguist N. Chomsky has emphasised nature in the sense that all
normal children are born with the ability to learn any human language just as any animal
belonging to a given species is born with the ability to use the language of that species.
On his debate between the two scholars, debate known in the linguistic literature as the
Chomsky/Skinner debate or the Nature/Nurture controversy, the following conclusions
are arrived at:
(a) language is species – specific, i.e. each species has its own kind of language; and
(b) human language is both innate (or inborn) and learned, in the sense that all normal
children are born with the ability to learn any human language (for example, and
normal child, including a Zambian child, can learn any language (Bemba, Lozi,
English, Chinese, Japanese etc) but for one to know a particular language he must
learn that language through exposure.
(a) the morphology (= shape) of organs, (b) the number of organs and (c) the
number, volume and morphology of cavities, which function as resonators
for sounds, vary from one species to another. Therefore, we should
expect, for example, that only humans can produce some of the kind of
sounds found in human articulated languages (= languages using vocal
sounds). For instance, no worm could produce /d/, /s/ or / z / since the
production of such sounds involves, among others, teeth and worms have
no teeth. Similarly, no human being could produce all the sounds
produced by a bird, or an animal, because he is not
anatomically/physiologically equipped to produce them.
Language is not only species-specific for anatomical reasons, but also due
to quantitative and qualitative differences in nervous activity and,
therefore, the composition of the brain.
E/LAL112 12
“There is increasing evidence that verbal behaviour is related to a
great number of morphological and functional specialisation such
as oropharyngeal morphology (- -); cerebral dominance (- - -);
specialisation of cerebro-corticortical topography: special co-
ordination centres (or foci) for motor speech; specialized temporal
pattern perception; special respiratory adjustment and tolerance for
prolonged speech activities; and a long list of sensory and
cognitive specialisations prerequisite for language perceptions.
“It has been observed that language development in the child follows a
regular pattern, the onset of speech appearing at a certain time in the
child‟s physical development and following a fixed sequence of events, as
if all children followed the same general „strategy‟ from the time they
begin to the period at which they have mastered the art of speaking”
(Lenneberg (1972: 344). This regular, or uniform, language development
can only be explained in terms of (a) the quasisameness of the physiology
of human beings and (b) the quasisameness of physical development of
human beings.
The difficulty in suppressing human articulated language, as illustrated above, can also
only be explained by the fact that human beings are physiologically (i.e. they are born
with the ability) to learn it. This fact, coupled with the fact that no animal can learn
wholly a human articulated language, shows that language is species – specific.
However, humans are not only endowed with the ability to learn human articulated
E/LAL112 13
languages but in the absence of articulated language they always develop another kind of
language also more sophisticated than any „animal language‟. The best example is sign
language: deaf people living together naturally develop a sign language using manual
gestures, bodily movements and facial expressions. Example of sign languages include
American Sign Language (ASL or Ameslan), British Sign Language (BSL) and Chinese
Sign Language (CSL), to name but a few. Many sign languages are fully – fledged
languages which can be used to „talk‟ about anything (science, philosophy, etc). Not
only do sign languages have a vocabulary and a grammar, just like spoken languages but
just like spoken languages they are creative, discrete and dynamic (they change in space,
time and context), etc.
“No matter how eloquently a dog may bark, it cannot tell you that
his parents were poor but honest.”
E/LAL112 14
languages by the fact that all human languages (except sign languages) use
sounds. The differences must be characterised by other design features.
The difference between human language, on the one hand, and animal
languages, on the other, is due to biological differences especially the
difference in the powers of the brain: the human brain is more developed
than the brains of the animals due to, among others, the size of the human
brain (the human brain has more neurones (i.e. nervecells) than that of any
animal.
Definitions
(a) Dual structure (or double articulation): human language utterances can be split up
into meaningful units such as words (= first articulation)and into meaningless
units such as syllables and individual sounds (= second articulation)
E/LAL112 15
An open-ended system is a system composed of one or more open sub-
systems and one or more closed subsystems. Many experiments to teach
human and other languages to animals have failed. The experiments
include, among others, the following;
(a) Jarvis Bastian‟s experiment with dolphins
The objective was to teach dolphins to communicate messages to each
other, using lights (Fromkin and Rodman 1974: 45 – 46).
What must be concluded from the above and the other attempts to teach human and other
languages to animals is that (a) no animal can fully learn a human language and that (b)
any language learnt by an animal is less complex and less efficient than human language.
However, some animal languages are made of both sounds and gestures.
Chimpanzee‟s language is one such language. The language of the dolphin, the
“monkey of the sea” which is made of squawky sounds and whistles, is an
example of acoustic language. Note the dolphin also produces clicking sounds
but these are used to communicate but they are radar detection sounds: the
dolphin produces such sounds to locate objects (Fromkin and Rodman, 1974: 45)
E/LAL112 16
Animals using gestural languages include, among other, spiders, fiddler crabs
honey bees. On spiders Fromkin and Rodman (op. cit.) report: “Among the
spiders there is a complex system of courtship. The male spider, before he
approaches his lady love, goes through elaborate gestures to inform her that he is
indeed a spider and not a crumb or a fly to be eaten.” According to the same
authors (1b), there exist forty different varieties of fiddler crabs “and each species
uses its own particular‟ claw – waving‟ movement to signal to another member of
its „clan‟. The timing movement and posture of the body never change one time
to another or from one crab to another within the particular species.” Therefore,
we conclude that fiddler crabs‟ like other animal languages are fixed, invariant.
Honeybees language
The honeybees language is one of the most remarkable animal languages. As
pointed out by Atkinson et al. (1988: 6), “honeybees live in highly structured
societies, and efficiency of communication is essential for the survival of the
colony.” When a forager (i. e. foraging bee) returns to the hive, it releases an
attraction pheromone (i. e behaviour – triggering chemical) from the scents she
has taken from the food source and performs a dance to communicate some
information on the food source. There are three types of dance, namely (a) the
round dance, (b) the sickle dance and (c) the tail wagging dance:
In the sickle dance, the dancer describes a figure resembling eight “where a
straight run is followed by a semi-circle in one direction and back to the origin of
the straight run, another straight run, another straight line and a semi-circle in the
opposite direct” (Atkinson et al. 1988: 6 – 7).
In the tail-wagging dance, the dancer makes a straight zigzag, and at one point the
bee describes semi-circle up to the origin of the zigzag, makes another straight
zigzag, then a semi-circle in the direction opposite to the direction of the first
semi-circle, and so on (Fromkin and Rodman 1978: 42).
E/LAL112 17
The piece of information indicated respectively by the number or
repetitions of the basic pattern and the vivacity of the dancing. This holds
for the other two types of dance.
CONCLUSION
Language is species-specific; i.e. each species has its own kind of language due to
biological and physiological differences. If follows that we should note expect to find,
the same design features in language used by different species and hold the view that
something hat does not have all the design features of human articulated language is not a
language.
REFERENCE
Fromkin, V., and R. Rodman (1978) An Introduction to Language, 2nd edition. Holt,
Rinehart and Winston, Inc.
REVISION QUESTIONS
E/LAL112 18
2. What is proved by the sameness of language development schedule?
3. How do you explain the difficulty in suppressing language?
4. Sign language as used by deaf are visual systems while „spoken‟ languages are
auditory systems. Explain.
5. Do animals have languages! Explain
6. Can animals learn a human articulated language? Explain
Discuss any two fundamental differences between human language in general and
animal languages in particular. Refer to Esau‟s (1974) Language and
communication.
7. What do you know about the language of
E/LAL112 19
UNIT 3
This Unit is about the origin of human language in general not the origin of particular
languages. The question of when, how and where man first developed language has
always fascinated scholars and man in general but all attempts to answer the question
have failed and have only yielded speculations. This is so because, as suggested by
Hartmann and Stork (1972: 159), “human speech is probably as old as man. Written
records only go back for about 4000 years”.
1. Monogenesis or Polygenesis?
An issue related to the question of where human language originated is whether all
human articulated languages (Bemba, English, French, German, Japanese, Kaonde, Lozi
etc) originated from the same ancestor language. “The monogenetic theory of language
origin holds that all human articulated languages developed from a single ancestor
language while according to the polygenetic theory of language origin at least some
articulated languages developed from different sources, therefore places. Note that
mono-and Poly – come from Greek: they mean „once / single „and‟ „several‟ respectively,
and genesis also from Greek, means „birth/origin/creaton‟.
2. Some theories – about language origin (Hartmann and Stork 1972: 159 – 60.
(a) According to the Book of Genesis of the Bible (Chapter 2 verses 18 – 20) God
gave Language to Adam so that he can use it to name the other creatures. As
observed by Glatthorn et al. (1971: 116), “This original language was then
supposedly passed down unchanged from generation to generation until the time
of the Tower of Babel “This story in the Genesis, Chapter 11, verses 1- 9, tells
how God punished man by creating many different languages”
(b) In ancient Egypt people believed that the god Thoth was the creator of language.
(c) According to the Babylonians, the god Nabu was the creator of language.
E/LAL112 20
(Fromkin and Rodman 1988: 413)
E/LAL112 21
derived from interjections expressing emotions. The nickname “pool-pooh was
proposed by Max Muller but the theory was proposed by others.
This theory traces language back to cries uttered to co-ordinate collective work.
The motivation of this theory is that “when we do heavy muscular work, we often
breathen heavily”, “At the same time we may also make noises with our voices”
and “If we work with other people, the rhythmic noises may produce a kind of
group work song” (Glatthorn et al 1971: 117). The main objection to this theory
is that group work presupposes prior communication.
Comparative Linguistics, whose method, called the comparative method, was developed
by European scholars in the 19th century, is one such branch of linguistics. The
comparative method aims at establishing relationships between two or more genetically
related languages by comparing cognate words (i.e words related in form and meaning to
similar words in another language) (Hartmann and Stork, 1972; 40) with a view to
reconstructing proto-forms (i.e, hypothetical forms supposedly to the ancestor language,
called the proto-language which is also phypothetical). The method was successfully
applied to the so called Indo-European languages (i.e. most languages of Europe and the
Near East (India, Pakistan and Iran) in the 19th Century in that European comparative
showed the many relationships between the language and reconstructed Proto-Indo-
European forms. The method was so successful that many a scholar thought it could be
used to answer questions on the origin and evolution of human language. However, as
pointed out by Hoijer (1978: 57), „later researches demonstrated (ii) that the methods of
historical reconstruction, even when applied to ancient languages preserved in writing,
yielded a history of only ten thousand years or less, a period much too brief to provide
data on origins.
E/LAL112 22
4. Archaeology and the question of language
4.0 General
All direct archaeological evidence does prove the existence of human language
since at least 5, 000 years.
EXTRACT A
KEESING (1965: 364 – 7)
E/LAL112 23
all cultural behaviour, by virtue of its forms and meaning, may be looked at as a symbol
system. The running of spectators to watch a fire, a smoke signal seen in the distance, the
rhythm of a drum, the scent of perfume may convey “message” by way of sensory
perceptions. Par excellence, however, it is language, that is, the vocal symbolism of
speech with its related bodily gestures and mechanical signals, such as writing, which
gives precision and finesse to communication.
Reference was made in the first chapter to the development within anthropology of a
special sub-science called “linguistics” or “anthropological linguistics.” The field
worker, to penetrate the settings where he does research, has been forced to learn more of
less efficiently the language of the people concerned. From this handling of local
language materials came an interest in comparative language studies, and in the place of
language in culture. Linguistic specialists in the “humanities” have concentrated upon a
relatively few major languages, nearly all with written literary traditions (e.g., Indo-
European languages, the major east Asian languages). It has been left almost exclusively
to the anthropologist to investigate the very great number of other language traditions
over the earth. The development of a general “science” of linguistics has become a joint
enterprise of both these groups, as is seen in the “linguistics department” of some
Universities.
Linguistics has become a highly technical field. Only a small number of anthropologists
consider themselves to be linguistics specialists. They must be skilled in handling what
are often exceedingly complicated symbol systems, oral and written, with sounds,
grammars, meaning, and externalized writing or other supplements quite different from
those familiar Western languages. The trained linguist now may make extensive use of
statistics and of mechanical devices such as recorders, movies, X rays of vocal
movements, special typewriting and other signs needed for recording beyond the
everyday alphabet. Linguistics is a very rapidly moving front of knowledge, as scrutiny
of such professional serials as language and the International Journal of American
Linguistics would show. Any student who wants to pit his wits against the specialists at
work could do so by way of a conference report edited by Hoijer titled language in
Culture (1954). Our discussion here will minimize the more technical phases of the study
and concentrate on the cultural significance of symbolic communication.
E/LAL112 24
Realization of this basic principle will guard the student against of ten strange and
mystical ideas as the nature of „human communication.
Exercise
Get some person or persons who speak another language than your own to say some
phrases in that language. You hear (and see) the signals involved, but the meaning is not
communicated. Now give a phrase from your own language to be translated, so that you
supply the meaning. You then hear (or see) unfamiliar signals which you will only
recognize as you make the effort to learn them.
Bloomfield, in an important general text (1933), says that “the whole working of human
society is due to language.” Sapir (1931) speaks of society as comprising, in one sense,”
a highly intricate network of partial or complete understandings between the members of
organizational units of every degree of size and complexity, ranging from a pair of lovers
or a family, to a league of nations.” He sees group life as “reanimated or creatively
reaffirmed from day to day by particular acts of communicative nature which obtain
among individuals participating in it.
Animal signals, taken note of earlier, have broadly similar trigger action from one
organism to another. But such communication has none of the exactness, specific
“definition of situation,” which marks the transfer of information between humans.
Speech, especially, tickets experience in terms of precise labels variously for classes of
phenomena (e.g. “man,” “dog,” “movement”) and for exact objects, people, actions (e.g.
“my father, “that terrier there, “they ran!).
Inevitably a great deal of speculation has accrued as to the origins of language. It must
be met with the now familiar critical attitude to the extent hypotheses are dogmatically
stated – the more so because no externalized evidence appears until the identification of
writing in the archaeological record. The main theories are often summarized under
E/LAL112 25
somewhat popularized labels. One has been called the “bow-wow” theory, namely, that
language began with the imitation of characteristic sounds of nature (“splash,” “roor,
“patter” are examples of such onomatopoeic expression); another is the “pooh-pooh”
theory, seeing it as arising out of “interjections,” instinctive,” instinctive utterances called
forth by pain or other intensive emotional states (“oh,” “Ouch,” and so on); still another
is the !Yo-he-ho” theory, considering the earliest language sound as “natural phonetic
accompaniments” of repeated muscular acts performed in common, these coming to stand
as verbs signifying the acts themselves: “heave, “haul,” and the like. Even more wildly
speculative is the “ding-dong” theory of a mystic harmony between sound and sense
which caused speech to be evoked instinctively as the ring emerges from a bell.
Jesperson, a humanities specialist in linguistics (1923), going by way of an analysis of the
laws of linguistic development, sees at or near the beginning a few “half-mystical
unanalysed expressions for individual beings and solitary events.” Another, Vendryes
(1925), sees emotional cries or simple chants taking on symbolic value as being
associated with particular activities. Ingenious as such theories may be, they must be
counted at best as suggestive hypotheses.
Some earlier scholars believed that the beginnings of language might be ascertained by
studying the speech of “savages.” Nowhere, however, do anthropologists find a symbolic
communication system, spoken or otherwise, which is “rudimentary” or simple”; indeed,
they often discover instead that the language of isolated peoples has become specialized
along highly complicated lines of sound and grammar. Another approach, tried out
particularly by early phyologists in the humanities, was to isolate by critical analysis the
oldest ancestral roots of contemporary languages; but this rapidly becomes speculative:
as Vendryes puts it, “Despite all our efforts, between the primitive „bark‟ and our oldest
there a gulf which can never be bridged.”
Still another approach to origins has been the study of how children learn to talk.
Jesperson, for example, speaks of three periods in a child‟s linguistic development: “the
screaming time, the crowing or babbling time, and the talking time” – the last covering
successively the acquisition of the more individualistic “little language” (the child‟s own
form of baby talk), and then of the common language through which his wider social
relations can be exercised. Granting the importance of studying language training in
different socio-cultural settings, not least of all for important clues to personality
development and national character, it s clearly an inadequate source for understanding
language origins in general. As Krowber (1948) has noted, this approach shows us
merely how a child becomes trained to the particular language of his group.
EXTRACT B
LANGUAGE IS SO MUCH A PART of our daily activities that some of us may come
to look upon it as a more or less automatic and natural act like breathing or winking. Of
course, if we give the matter any thought at all, we must realize that there is nothing
automatic about language. Children must be taught their native tongue and the necessary
E/LAL112 26
training takes a long time. Language is now something that is inherited; it is an art that
can be passed on from one generation to the next only be intensive education.
It is difficult to realize the enormously important role that language plays in our social
behaviour. What would a society without language be like? It would of course have no
writing or other means of communication by words, for all these are ultimately dependent
on spoken speech. Our means of learning would therefore be greatly restricted. We
should be obliged, like the animals, to learn by doing or by observing the actions of
others. All of history would disappear, for without language there would be no way of
re-creating past experiences and communicating them to others. We should have no
means of expressing out thoughts and ideas to others or of sharing in the mental
processes of our fellowmen. Indeed, it is very likely that we should not think at all.
Many psychologists maintain that thought itself requires the use of language, that the
process of thinking is really talking things over with ourselves.
A society lacking language would be incapable of engaging in any but the simplest of co-
operative enterprises. An individual or group of individuals would have no way of
planning such activities, of explaining them to others, or of directing the actions of the
participants in co-operative enterprises toward the common goal. Each individual would
be to a large extent dependent on his own strength and ability since he would lack the
means of securing the help of others.
Most important, a society lacking language would have no means of assuring the
continuity of behaviour and learning necessary to the creation of culture. Human society,
without culture, would be reduced to the level of present day societies. Apes have a
bodily structure very like our own. Like humans, they learn readily from experience and
by observing and imitating the actions of others. A number of experimenters have shown
apes not only learn to use tools but also invent them. Despite, however, the fact that
individual apes learn easily and, as individuals, show remarkable progress in the
acquisition of knowledge, apes as a species have never developed a culture.
There are two reasons for this. Lacking language, the apes have no way continuing in
word and though their separate experiences in the use of tolls and techniques. When an
ape has disposed of a problem the knowledge he has derived from that experience
remains static. He may remember it when and if another problem of the same sort arises,
but he does not in between times mull over his knowledge and devise means of applying
it to further problems. Man does. His overt experiences with practical problems are, like
those of the ape, separate and distinct. But because man possesses language, he can
continue his problem-solving activities beyond the actual physical experience and so
develop, in thought and discussion, new applications of his knowledge and improved
means of solving problems. In short, by reason of language, man‟s experiences are
continuous, not discontinuous as among apes, and so show far more rapid development.
Secondly, man‟s possession of language enables him to share the experiences and
thoughts of his fellows and to recreate his personal experiences for their benefit. An
ape‟s knowledge, acquired through experience and observation, is his along except in so
E/LAL112 27
far as he can demonstrate it in physical it in physical activity so that it may be acquired
by another ape. No matter how skillful an ape may became in the use of tools and
techniques, his off-spring will be obliged to begin their learning as he began his, by
experience and observation. The learned ape cannot communicate his knowledge and so
enable his successors to build upon it. Culture among men reveals progress. Each
generation takes over, buy word of mouth and tradition, the accumulated knowledge of
their predecessors, add their own contributions as drawn from their experiences and
observations, and pass the whole on to succeeding generations. This cumulative aspect,
which differentiates human cultures from the kind of knowledge current in animal
societies, is made possible by language.
Studies of the skeletal and cultural remains of ancient man have shown that the first
human beings came into about one million years ago. Man‟s early cultures were very
simple and crude and we know only a portion of their material remains, the tools and
implements made of materials tough to withstand the passage of time. It is highly
significant, however, that these early traces of man‟s cultures reveal a cultural continuity
through time. As we study the several chronological phases of culture in any given area
of the world, there is revealed a slow but steady advance both in the number of tools
made and in the complexity of their manufacture. The men of successive generations did
not begin anew each generation to fashion their cultures but built upon the techniques
which had been discovered in the past and transmitted to them by their ancestors.
The fact that the history of man‟s cultures shows a continuous and cumulative
development extending from their earliest beginnings to the present means of course that
man has possessed language as long as he has possessed culture. Language must be as
old as the oldest of man‟s cultural artefacts; it began when began and has developed
continuously ever since.
This inference as to the age of language is amply born out by other observations which
may be made on modern languages. First, it is clear that all human societies have
possessed a language for as long as we have known them; there is no group of men
anywhere, today or in the past, who lack this important aspect of culture. Secondly, we
may also observe that modern languages are very numerous and exceedingly diverse.
The precise number of distinct languages spoken today cannot even be estimated, but we
know that there are several thousands. Some of these are historically related to one
another; that is, they are clearly derived from a singly earlier tongue. Languages so
derived are said to belong to be same linguistic family or stock, and there are hundreds of
such stocks in the world today. Most of these stocks show no resemblance what so ever
to each other, because, as we may almost certainly assume, all traces of common origin
have long since disappeared.
The universality of language and the amazing diversity of modern idioms can only mean
that language is very old. Studies of languages known for centuries through the medium
of written record reveal that languages change with relative slowness. Thus, though
English and German have certainly been separate languages for well over 2000 years,
they still retain many obvious similarities in both vocabulary and grammar which point
E/LAL112 28
clearly to their common origin. The enormous diversity of modern languages, then must
have taken a very long time to achieve.
A third and final evidence as to the antiquity of language is found in the fact that known
languages, ancient or modern, cannot be classed in terms of their level of development.
There are neither primitive languages nor highly developed ones, if we take into account
only their structural features.
Thus, all the languages we know possess a well-defined system of distinctive speech
sounds. These are finite in number, are carefully distinguished from one another, and are
together to form words, phrases, sentences in accordance with definite rules. In this
respect, there is nor real difference between the languages of people who possess very
and crude cultures and those of the highly civilized peoples of Europe and America.
Similarly, all human groups, regardless of the crudity of their culture, have a vocabulary
sufficiently detailed and comprehensive to meet every need likely to arise. Languages
vary, of course, in the size of their vocabularies, but this variation is cultural, not
linguistic. The language of a people having a relatively simple or undeveloped culture
may have a smaller vocabulary than one belonging to a group with a relatively complex
and highly developed culture. It is notable, however, that the vocabulary of any group,
however simple its culture, appears to be indefinitely expansible. As new cultural items
are invented or borrowed, the vocabulary increases or changes to meet the new
requirements imposed upon it. Finally, all languages possess a definite and clear-cut
system of grammar. Grammar may briefly be defined as the meaningful arrangement of
sounds or combination of sounds to words, phrases, and sentences. Well defined rules
governing such arrangements are found in all languages, whether they are spoken by the
pre-literate Pygmies of Congo forest or the culturally advanced groups of modern
Europe.
The basic similarities mean, of course, that language has so long been a human
possession as to have developed to about the same level among people the world over.
There remain today no traces of an earlier and cruder stage of linguistic development.
Spoken languages obviously leave no trace in the ancient deposits which mark the history
of man‟s cultures. Written records of human languages began only a few thousand years
ago; before that time no human group possessed the technique of writing. It is evident,
then, that we have no direct evidence as to the origin of language or of the long period of
history that elapsed between its beginnings and the first written records. The problem of
the origin of language will never therefore be solved in the sense that we shall know
directly the circumstances under which language arose or be able to trace in terms of
specific historical events the course of its development.
E/LAL112 29
Many theories have been advanced as to the origin of language. Most of these, however,
are based on two central hypotheses: the interjection and the sound imitative or
onomatopoeic theory of the origin of language.
Both hypotheses fail to solve our problem, however, largely because they fail to account
for the linguistic forms. Neither involuntary cries nor sound imitative words are as such
true linguistic forms. An involuntary cry is really part of an individual‟s response to
strong stimuli. The involuntary ejaculation of surprise is not the same as the
conventional word written oh‟ because the former represents part of the response itself
and does not, like the conventional Oh‟ symbolize the response of surprise. True
linguistic symbols, such as words, are all conventional and arbitrary, and their meanings
must be learned by speakers. No one learns an involuntary cry; a baby may cry out long
before it learns to speak.
Sound imitative words must similarly not be confused with attempts to reproduce sounds
characteristic of man‟s environment. A word like ding dong for example, is
conventionalized representation of the sound of a bell, not necessary self-evident to
anyone except a speaker of English who has learned to associate the sound sing ding
dong with the ringing of bells. To understand how languages come into being we must
know how man came to establish his arbitrary or conventional habits of associating
speech sounds with experience. This is not explained by the sound imitative hypothesis
which point out merely that men sometimes name things and actions by the noises they
make and that on occasion such names became truly a part of language.
It follows, then that a useful theory of linguistic origins must be based on a more careful
analysis and study of modern tongue. Such studies, as we have suggested, reveal that the
elements of speech, such as word phrases, and sentences, are arbitrary symbols. By this
we mean symbols which are themselves no part of the reality or experience symbolized.
Thus, for example, the particular succession of sounds which make up the word horse
have no necessary relation to the class or animals symbolized by it. There is, in short,
nothing horse-like about the word horse; it is simply that speakers of English have
learned to associated the sound written horse with a given class of animal, just as they
have learned to associated the forms dog and cat with wholly different groups of animals.
The fact that linguistic symbols are nearly all arbitrary in nature emphasizes the social
aspect of languages, are always associated with groups of individuals; they never belong
exclusively to a single individual. An individual acquires his language from the group
E/LAL112 30
with which he lives. If he deviates widely in speech from other members of the group, he
runs the risk of being misunderstood or of not being understood at all. Horse is not just a
word peculiar to an individual speaker of English, it is a word used and understood in
much the same way by all English-speaking peoples.
Contrast the action we have just described with a similar incident among, let us say, a
pact of wolves. Here, too, we have a social group albeit one composed of animals who
lack language. When one of the wolves makes a kill along, he will eat as much as he can;
he will not be concerned or be able to inform the pack of his feat. But should the other
wolves come upon him as he makes the kill or while he is eating the carcass, they will
certainly join him uninvited. Each wolf will get as much as he can and if there is not
enough to go around, the weaker wolves will get none at all. The actions of the wolves in
disposing of the meat will be separate and individual, with individual, with no co-
ordination or co-operation whatever.
It is probable that the ancient animals from whom man evolved lived in groups very
similar to those of present-day animals. Their behaviour was only in a small degree co-
ordinated. Each worked for himself alone, with the exception that the very young had to
be cared for by an adult. On occasion, however, necessity must enforced some degree of
co-operation and coordinated effort. Man‟s primitive ancestor was not a formidable
animal in comparison with may others who shared his environment. He must often have
had to defend himself against stronger predatory animals and he probably discovered
very early that such defense was more effective if undertaken in co-operation enterprises
increased in frequency, the habit pattern built up may easily have led to cooperation
under other circumstances, such as, for example, the hunting of large animals for food.
Even wolves hunt together and, while so doing, correlate their efforts, at least to some
degrees.
The development of co-operative did not along bring about language, however, Many
insect groups are effectively co-operative. But co-operation among insects is evidently
on a different basis tham among men. Unlike the social insects men are not born to a
given role in their social groups. Men must learn to adapt their behaviour to the roles
provided by the society, and language provides a vital tool to this kind of learning.
E/LAL112 31
How and in what way man‟s animal ancestors come employ language as an aid in co-
operative labor we shall never know. We may safely assume, however, that man‟s
primitive ancestor could and did make noises and perhaps the noises which accompanied
the tasks undertaken together came slowly to symbolize the several actions and ends
involved in such tasks. In any case, it appears to be fairly certain that language arose as a
result of men learning to work together toward a common end. For what ever reasons,
whatever man‟s primitive ancestors were obliged to acquire such learning, and so they,
along of the animals, stumbled upon the tool, language, which more than any other makes
co-operative and co-ordinated activity effective.
During the nineteenth century, scholars developed a method for reconstructing the early
history, and in some instances the prehistory, of languages spoken today and those
recorded in older writings. Thus it was shown that most of the languages of Europe and
some of those spoken in the Near East and northern India were so related to each other as
to make it certain that they developed in large part from an ancient tongue no longer
spoken and for which no written records existed. The success of these reconstructions
led scholars to the belief that the method might be applied to the reconstruction of the
primeval languages of mankind and so possibly solve the problem of the origin of
language. Later researcher demonstrated, however, that the methods of historical
reconstruction, even applied to ancient languages preserved in writing, yielded a history
of only ten thousand years or less, a period much too brief to provide data on origins.
The number of languages spoken in the world today is estimated at more than four
thousand. Every human group known, from the tiny tribelets of the California Indians to
the great nations of modern Europe, the Americans, and Asia, possesses a language.
Comparative studies of these languages reveal that they may be classified into several
hundred language families, each of which contains from 2 to 100 or more separate but
related languages. Languages so related are said to have diverged from a single ancestral
tongue, called a protolanguage, that is now no longer spoken and for which written
records are not available. English, for example, is closely related to such languages as
German, Dutch, and Swedish, and more distantly related to scores of other languages (for
example, Russian, Persian, and Hindi) spoken in Europe, the Near East and Northern
E/LAL112 32
India. It is not related, so far as we know, to such well-known languages as Arabic and
Chinese or to the many less well-known of aboriginal America. The large number of
unrelated language families points up the great diversity of modern tongues and suggest
that language developed very early in man‟s pre-history, so early that it is quite
impossible to recover, by present methods of historical research, any trace of the original
language or languages of mankind.
Studies of language during much of the present century have not been confined to the
languages of the great civilizations of the modern world. Attention has also been given to
the far more numerous languages of primitive people that is, peoples who, like many
American Indian tribes, were until recently, little advanced in culture. In the nineteenth
century, before the languages of primitives had been precisely described, many scholars
believed that these languages, like the cultures of which they are a part, might be in a
primitive stage of development and so might attest to earlier stages in the evolution of
Australia, New Guinea, and many other regions, failed to confirm the existence of such a
primitive speech.
In the contrary, studies of the languages of primitives clearly reveal that these languages,
though very different from each other and from the languages of the great civilizations,
are fully developed in every essential aspect. Thus, though we can often arrange diverse
cultural systems in an evolutionary sequence, there is in language no evidence of a
parallel evolutionary development. The most primitive peoples known, whose only tools
are of wood, bone, and crudely shaped stones, and who live in very small groups
governed primarily by familial relationships, possess fully developed languages that are
in every essential respect perfectly comparable to such languages as English, French,
German, or Chinese.
It is now clear that the problem of the origin of language is not to be solved by a study of
older records or by comparing the languages of the world with each other. We must,
instead, approach the problem not only with Linguistic studies, but also with the help of
the total context of man‟s biological and cultural evolution. Archaeological data provides
ample evidence that man and his nearest animal relatives, the anthropoid, or manlike,
apes, have a common ancestry. The probable ancestor lived on earth several million
years ago, and the lines of divergence that ultimately led on the one hand to man and on
the other to the modern anthropoids extend far back, perhaps as far as three or four
million years.
Recent archeological discoveries in various regions of Africa and Asia suggest the
presence, some two million years ago, of hominoid, or manlike, forms: animals that lack
certain of the characteristics, such as brain size, found in modern men, that yet are
structurally more advanced than the modern apes. These forms, or some other very like
them, gave way to the earliest hominids-forms belong, like modern man, to the genus
Homo out of more species different from the species, sapiens, to which modern man
belongs. Evidence also exists that the earliest hominids, and possibly even the
hominoids, made and used very crude stone tools and so had acquired at least the
rudiments of culture. In east Africa, for example, professor L S B Leakey found the
E/LAL112 33
bones of an exceedingly primitive hominid form, called Homo habilis, and associated
with the bones evidence that H. Habilise made and used crudely shaped stone tools. It
seems clear, then that certain aspects of culture may have begun as early as two million
years ago, even though evidence of tool-making and tool use, activities that some have
claimed for modern apes, may not be conclusive.
Evidence of true cultures, that is, patterned ways of behaviour that are traditionally
transmitted and cumulative, do not appear until about one million years later, with the
coming of the biologically more advanced hominid species. The existence of true
cultures clearly implies the existence of language since language is an obvious
prerequisite of the traditional growth of culture. The beginnings of language, a stage of
evolutionary development that we might call pre-language may well have taken place
among hominids, but it is likely that true language developed among the hominids such
later, and at or about the same time that these forms acquired a true culture. Even then
we must remember that both the languages and the cultures of the early hominids were
exceedingly primitive; so much so that if today we heard them speak, their speech might
sound more like animal calls than human language.
The communication systems of the modern apes, and probably also of the early
hominoids, are in essence closed repetition of calls. Man‟s language, on the other hand,
is an open system, that is capable of producing an almost infinite number of utterances,
some learned but many others formed on patterns common to the speech community
rather than learned. Indeed, man‟s language enables him both to produce and to
understand utterances that are completely new, that have never been spoken or heard
before. The property of language, its productivity, is apparently lacking in the call
systems of the animals.
E/LAL112 34
distinguished from I bit him simply by changing the first phoneme of hit and bit.
Language also has a structure in terms of morphemes, minimum meaningful elements,
such that a pair of utterances like he walks along and he walked along are distinguished
by the contrast between walks and walked; more specifically, by the fact that the
morpheme written – S and marking the present tense appears in the first utterance,
whereas the morpheme written – ed and marking the past tense occurs in the second
utterance.
The fourth distinctive property of language, traditional transmission refers to the fact that
language is taught and learned; it is not, as be the case with call systems, transmitted by
the genes. Human children have no language at birth; they acquire one by hearing and
rehearsing utterances made by adults and, later, by inferring from the utterance made by
adults and, later, by inferring from the utterances they hear the meanings of morphemes
and more importantly, the process by which phonemes and morphemes are built into
complete utterances. Once they have acquired these processes, the children build their
own, often quite novel utterances, ones they have neither heard nor rehearsed.
The problem of the origin of language may now be stated more precisely. It is to
reconstruct the evolutionary changes whereby a call system, almost certainly passed by
one or more groups of hominoids, developed the properties of productivity, traditional
transmission, displacement, and duality of patterning that made it a true language. Such a
reconstruction has been made by Charles F. Hockett and Robert Ascher, and I shall
present here a brief summary of their work as described in their article “THE HUMAN
Revolution.” 1
A call system, as we noted earlier, is closed; that is, it contains a finite and usually a
small number of calls, each of which is unique in both sound and meaning. At some time
in man‟s prehistory, a hominoid form may have encountered a situation that required him
to communicate both the presence of food, let us ay, and the presence of danger. It is
conceivable that in such an instance the animal would emit a single call that combined
part of the call signifying danger. Blended calls very likely occur among modern
animals, although such an occurrence has not been observed.
E/LAL112 35
Should such blends become common, it is clear that an originally small number of calls
would become larger. Thus, if we assume a closed system of ten calls, and assume
further that each of these is blended with each of the others, the result is one hundred
calls. Furthermore, and this point is of far greater importance, each of the blended calls
now has two parts, and each part recurs in other blended calls. The habit is established of
building composite calls out of meaning for parts of calls, whether or not these occur
independently as whole signals. “It is this habit,” according to Hockett and Ascher, “that
lies at the center of the openness of human languages. English allows only a finite
(though quite large) number of sentences only two words long. But it allows an
unlimited number of different sentences because there is no fixed limit on how long a
sentence may be.”
When a closed system of calls becomes open and productive in the manner described, the
properties of traditional transmission and displacement must also be developed. The
existence of blended calls requires that the young learn to infer the meanings of the parts
and the many ways in which these parts are put together to form whole utterances. Such
inferences, it is clear, must be drawn from the contexts in which the composed signals are
used and from the resemblances in sound that exist among the composite calls. A
premium is therefore placed on whatever space for teaching and learning a group may
posses, and there results a selective pressure toward an increase in the genetic basis for
that capacity.
Teaching and learning result in displaced speech, for teaching and learning, if they are to
be effective, must take place apart from the situations in which the utterances that are
being taught and rehearsed are pertinent. It is reasonable to suppose that, in prehistoric
times as now, much of the teaching of speech took place along with other teaching and
learning and that the young acquired not only their patterns of speaking but other patterns
of their culture as well. We should expect, therefore, that the properties of language we
have called productivity, traditional transmission, and displacement came into being at
approximately the same time that much of the rest of culture appeared.
E/LAL112 36
In time, however, and with emergence, possibly one million years ago, of more advanced
hominids, the pre-morpheme came to be heard not as a holistic unit, but in terms of the
same sound components that occurred in it. Similarly, articulation came to be directed
not toward the production of the acoustic pattern of the pre-morpheme as a whole, but
toward an articulation of the smaller sound components sufficiently precise to distinguish
each component from others. When this change took place, the pre-morpheme became a
true morpheme, that is, a minimum meaningful unit of speech made up of phonological
components without meaning, the phonemes. At that point, the pre-language became a
true language, with all the properties that today distinguish language form the
communicatory systems found among animals.
It cannot be said that all problems connected with the origin of language have been
solved, but anyone interested in measuring progress toward a solution need only look at
the speculations on language origin wittily described by Max Muller in the middle of the
last century speculations which sought the beginnings of language largely in imitations or
else in instinctive cries. These were the theories still remembered by their nicknames
rather than their content: the “Ding-dong”, the “Pooh-pooh.” Comparing these theories
with what the work of modern linguists has accomplished, we find that men like Hockett
and Ascher have at least greatly narrowed the problem and made it much more precise.
The problem of how pre-language became language is now narrowed to the specific one
of the development of duality of pattern. Such a precision of definition is a great
advance, yet it can be noted that Hockett and Ascher have succeeded essentially only in
pointing out that for language to develop, the transition to duality was needed, simply
because proliferation of meaningful elements without it would have been too complex to
be useful. They have not been so successful in showing the process by which the need
was met.
E/LAL112 37
Nevertheless-even though the process of development is not clear-there is one minor side
result which is of fascinating suggestiveness: As Hocker and Ascher have defined
duality, its development is so far reaching, so revolutionary, and so fruitful as to suggest
that it was created only, and in one place. Once created, it would have spread to all
hominids irresistibly and speedily. It suggests, in other words, the unitary origin of
language, and the unitary origin of language suggests, in turn, that men are cultural as
well as genetic and biological brothers.
CONCLUSION
While we know a great deal about the nature of human language (see „design features‟),
we do not know when and where human language originated and how it developed. The
last clause of the previous sentence (how it developed‟) implies that when human
language began, it was not as developed as it is now. Archaeological evidence has shown
that contemporary man has developed from earlier forms with a brain less developed than
the brain of contemporary man. Since linguistic activity is controlled by the brain, we
can infer that language too developed, becoming more sophisticated as the brain
developed. On the other hand, we can inter that at the various stages of the physiological
evolution that has produced contemporary man the various forms that are ancestors of
contemporary man were not anatomically equipped enough to produce some of the
contemporary sounds. On the evolutionary nature of language, the consolidated
Encyclopaedia (volume (V) (London: Consolidated world Research Society Ltd, 1936)
Whatever the truth concerning its origin may be it is certain that from the first gestures or
sound by which one human being sought to communicate with another, language has
been a thing of continuous growth”.
REFERENCES
Hoijer, H. (1965) Language and Writing. In H. L. Shapino (ed) Man culture and
Society. Oxford University Press, Pp. 196 – 203.
…….. (1969) „The Origin of Language in A. A. Hill (ed) Linguistics. Voice of America
forum series Pp. 57 -65.
E/LAL112 38
REVISION QUESTIONS
1. Comment on:
3. What is Proto-Indo-European?
5. EXTRACT A.
(a) How does Keesing view the relationship between language and culture?
(b) What are the various views on the origins and antiquity language presented by
the author?
(c) Does man communicate with speech and writing only?
6. EXTRACT B.
(a) With reference to the text, discuss the importance of human language to
mankind.
(b) Briefly summarize the view of the author on:
7. EXTRACT C.
(a) What is the principal tool of reconstructing the prehistory of man and his
cultures? Why.
(b) How can linguistics contribute to the reconstruction of the prehistory of man
and his cultures
(c) What language design features are discussed by the author? In what context
does he do so?
(d) What is the view of the author on the duality of language?
E/LAL112 39
UNIT FOUR
One of the most intriguing questions confronting linguists is the relationship between
human language and the communication systems („languages?) of lower animals. As was
mentioned about one‟s decision n whether or not animals have language depends on how
one defines language. If one defines language broadly, then even animals possess it; if
one defines language narrowly, then only humans possess it. It is with the latter
definition in mind that Crystal (1969: 30) says that:
Note that the quotation above points to the assertion that language is an exclusive
property of the homo sapiens. In the quest to establish if language was exclusively
human, scholars carried out numerous studies on other animals, predominantly the
chimpanzee. The choice of the chimpanzee was not accidental. The chimp is closer to
many than any other creature intellectually, psychologically and even emotionally. As
will be soon later, while some of these studies were complete failure, other scored come
success. It should be stated here that while the effort put in these studies is
commendable, I think it was not fair to expect a chimp to learn and articulate human
language because its vocal apparatus was not designed to do so.
Studies on other creatures (such as the bees) have revealed striking qualities of their
communication systems; to some extent, their ability to communicate is not far lower
than man‟s. in the pages that follow, we present some extracts from published works or
attempts to investigate animal communication (and attempts to teach human language to
other creatures). The student is encouraged to look at these studies critically and
establish their strengths and weaknesses.
E/LAL112 40
ANIMAL “LANGUAGES”
No matter how eloquently a dog may bark, he cannot tell you that his parents were poor
but honest.” (Bertrand Russell).
“Talking Parrots”
Most humans who acquire language utilize sounds to express sounds to express
meanings, but such sounds are not a necessary aspect of language, as evidenced by the
sign language of the deaf. The use of speech sounds is, therefore, not a basic part of
what we call language. The chirping of birds, the squeaking of dolphins and the dancing
of bees may potentially represent systems similar to human languages. If animal
communication systems are not like human language, it will not be due to a lack of
speech.
Conversely, when animals vocally imitate human utterances, it does not mean they posses
language. Language is a system that relates sounds (or gestures) to meanings, “talking”
birds such as parrots and mynah birds are able to faithfully reproduce words and phrases
of human language that they have heard; but when a parrot says “Polly wants a cracker,
“she may really want a ham sandwich or a drink of water or nothing at all. A bird that
has learned to say “hello” or “goodbye” is likely to use one as the other, regardless of
whether people are arriving or departing. The bird‟s utterances carry no meaning. They
are speaking neither English nor their language when they sound like use. Talking birds
do not dissect the sounds of their imitations into discrete units. “Polly” and Molly” do
not rhyme for a parrot. They are as different as “hello” and “goodbye” (or as similar).
(One property of human language, as is discussed in this batch, is that of discreteness.) A
parrot says what it is taught, what it hears and nothing more …. Therefore, the ability to
produce sounds similar to those used in human language cannot be equated with the
ability to learn a human language.
It must be emphasized, in conclusion, that the principle that there are no primitive
languages is not so much an empirical finding of linguistic research as a working
hypothesis. We must allow for the possibility that language do differ in grammatical
complexity and that these differences have not far been discovered by linguists. It would
E/LAL112 41
be as unscientific to deny that this possibility exists as it is to say that Latin is
intrinsically noble or more expressive than Hottentot or one of the Australian Aboriginal
languages.
Most animals posses some kind of “signalling” communication system. The male spider,
before he approaches lady love, goes through an elaborate series of gestures to inform her
that he is indeed a spider and not a crumb or a fly to be eastern. These gestures are
invariant. One never finds a “creative” spider changing or adding to the particular
courtship ritual of his species.
A similar kind of “gesture” language is found among the fiddler crabs. There are forty
different varieties and each variety uses its own claw – waving movements to signal to
another member of its clan. The timing, movement and posture of the body never
changes from one time to another or from one crab to another within the particular
variety. Whatever the signal means, it is fixed. Only one meaning can be conveyed.
There is not a finite set of fiddler crab “sentence”.
The imitative sounds of talking birds have little in common with human language, but the
calls and songs of many species of birds do have a communication function, and they
resemble human languages in that they are “dialects” within the same species. Bird calls
convey messages associated with immediate environment, such as danger feeding,
nesting, flocking, and so on. Bird songs (which are more complex) are used to “stake
out” territory and to attract mates. There is on evidence of any internal structure of these
songs nor can they be segmented into independent meaningful parts as words of human
language can be. In a study of the territorial song of the European robin, it was
discovered the rival robins paid attention only to be alternation between high-pitched and
low-pitched notes, and which came first did not matter. The messages varied only to the
extent of how strongly the robin feels about his possession and to what extent he is
prepared to defend it and start a family in that territory. The different alternations
therefore express “intensity” and nothing more. The robin is creative in his ability to sing
the same thing in many different ways, but not creative in the ability to use the same
“units” of the system to express many different messages with different meanings.
To what degree human language is biologically conditioned (or innate and to what degree
it is learned is one of the fundamental questions of linguistics (i.e. the nature-nurture
controversy).
Despite certain superficial similarities to human language, bird calls and songs are
fundamentally different kinds of communicative systems. The number of messages that
can be conveyed is finite, and messages are stimulus-controlled.
This distinction is also true of communication used by honey-bees. A forager bee is able
to return to the hive and tell other bees where a source of food is located. It does so by
forming a dance on a wall of the hive that reveals the locating and quality of the food
E/LAL112 42
source. For one species of Italian honey-bee, the dancing behaviour may assume one of
three possible patterns:
(a) round dance indicates Location near the hive, within 20 feet or so:
(b) sickle dance: indicates locations at 20 to 60 feet distance from the hive and
(c) tail-wagging dance: indicates distances exceeding 60 feet.
The number of repetitions per minute of the basic pattern in the tail-wagging dance
indicates the precise distance, the slower the repetition rate, the longer the distance.
E/LAL112 43
REPRINTED FROM: FOUNDATIONS OF GENERAL LINGUISTICS
BY
PP. 14 – 20
Considerations such as those just mentioned are supportive of the long-held belief that
non-human animals simply do not possess the innate mental structures which are
essential for the acquisition of language. If so, it would appear to follow that no amount
of training can lead to the use of a human language by animals. Undeterred by such
inauspicious prospects, two American couples, the Kelloggs and the Hayseses, attempted
to train two young chimpanzees (Gua and Viki) in their own family environments, in the
1930s and 1950s, respectively. The choice of the chimpanzee as a subject was of course
not random, since, besides their well-attested intelligence, these animals are closest to
human anatomically, genetically and even emotionally. The results were none the less
disappointing; Gua did not learn any word, and Viki barely managed to pronounce mama,
papa, cup and up.
In the mid-1960s another American couple, the psychologists Allen and Beatrice
Gardener, speculated that possibly the responsibility for these failure ought to be
apportioned not so much to the animals themselves as to the medium, speed simply being
inappropriate for the chimpanzee (cf. E.g. the research by Lioberman mentioned in
Section 1).
The Gardeners embarked on a project designed to exploit the renowned manual dexterity
of the chimpanzee, adopting as a medium American Sign Language (ASL), the
communication system used by deaf in most of North America. Crucially, although
articulated with the hands and thus lacking the feature „vocal-auditory channel‟, ASL
shows very strong parallels with ordinary vocal language: largely arbitrary relationships
between signifier and signified, meaning word order differences, regional divergences,
incomprehensibility to other deaf communities, translation difficulties, and so on.
The subject of the experiment was a female chimpanzee named Washoe, captured wild in
Africa and about 1 year old when the training began in 1966. all efforts were made to
provide an environment conducive to spontaneous and creative behaviour, and Washoe
enjoyed a freedom of movement similar to that of human children. The use of ASL was
strictly adhered to in Washoe‟s presence, to the extent of repressing all human sound not
vocalisable by chimpanzees. The instruction procedures were deliberately eclectic, and
included imitation (immediate or delayed) instrumental conditioning (the „shaping‟ into
ASL of apparently random signals; cf. Chapter 2, Section 5, for a general discussion of
this technique, pioneered by the psychologist B. F. Skinner) and moulding (the direct
physical guiding of the animal‟s hands into the target sign).
E/LAL112 44
Before enumerating and evaluating the results, we shall briefly refer to a few of the
growing number of studies prompted by Washoe‟s apparent success.
In the Gardners‟ tradition is the experiment by Herbert Terrace with the Chimpsky (the
name is hardly coincidental 1), a 2 – month-old male chimpanzee born in captivity. Here,
too, eclectic teaching was adopted, with the emphesis no moulding and imitation, and the
ape was provided with an informal environment where socialisation and emotional
bonding with his trainers (about sixty in all) could take place. Possibly the most
significant difference was the subjection of Nim to a daily sign-tuition routine on a
school-like schedule in a special cell-type „classroom‟, bare but for a few objects related
to the learning task, to prevent distraction, and where the basic pedagogic principle was
to focus on only one activity at a time.
Similarly, Francine (penny) Patterson‟s Koko, a 1 – year old captive born female gorilla,
lived mostly in a house trailer in conditions comparable to those of her chimpanzee
counterparts, including a substantial amount of daily sign instruction (ten hours on
average), which Patterson purposely describes as „non-„regimented‟. The specific
interest of this experiment is of course the extension of the investigation to a different (if
very closely related) biological species, one which has traditionally been regarded
(perhaps unfairly) as inferior to the chimpanzee in both intelligence and social adaptation.
The series was completed with the addition of the orang-utan, the third of the great apes.
Departing slightly from his predecessors, Lyn Mile, was deliberately treated as a wild, if
sociable, creative (i.e not as a human child), and a „junglegym‟ was accordingly provided
adjacent to the house-trailer where he was ledged.
E/LAL112 45
fadin), and it is relatively easy to ascertain what type of difficulty may be involved in any
particular problem.
Lana‟s „room‟ contained several objects and goods-dispensers, screen for the projection
of slides and motion pictures, stereo equipment, a sliding door and an outside window,
which was normally closed. He interacted with this environment took place exclusively
through the manipulation of her linguistic facilities. In addition, conversations could be
held between ape and trainer, who had access to a similar computer-linked keyboard.
Like Sarah‟s Lana‟s training was based on conditioning, although guiding, both verbal
and direct, was also used.
Taken at face value, the results of these and other similar experiments are impressive. In
all cases precautions were taken to ensure the objectivity and robustness of the field
observations. Thus the Gardners stipulated that, in order for a sign to be „officially‟
declared acquired, it had to have been reported by three independent observers as
occurring unprompted daily over a fifteen-day period under conditions of contextual
appropriateness. Such strict control was somewhat relaxed in other studies, in ways
which were deemed not to jeopardise the significance of the results (Terrace, for instance,
required a period of only five days). A particular misinterpretation risk is presented by
the so-called „Clever Hans‟ phenomenon, so named after a German horse that tapped
numbers with his hoof in tune with visual cues unconsciously given out by his trainer.
Accordingly, the Gardners chose a „double-blind‟ testing procedure, where the stimulus
is out of the visual field of the judge, and Premack used testers ignores of the chimp
language. Finally, the apes were generally submitted to routine psychologist testing with
the aim of ascertaining the general cognitive or perceptual strategies which may underlie
their linguistic performance.
The number of signs mastered by the apes over the average four year training period falls
typically between 100 and 150. moreover, after the initial learning period, the signs are
reported to have been transferred to other objects of the same class and used creatively
and appropriately, in a manner which resembles the communicative activities of young
children. Much quoted, for instance, is Washoe‟s utterance water-bird at the sight of a
duck. Errors are relatively infrequent (Sarah‟s and Lana‟s test).
Performances are reported often to have been over 80 per cent accurate and, when they
occur the are open to alternative interpretations, such are breaking up boring situations
(Terrace on Nim) or indulging in verbal abuse (Patterson on Koko). Terrace also reports
on Nim‟s capacity for deuplicity, and Patterson on Koko‟s for humour.
Word order, a significant trait of human language including ASL, was strictly required of
Sarah and Lana, and interestingly, the sign sequences produced by the „natural‟ apes
show a spontaneous preference for certain permutations. Because of the controlled
nature of Sarah‟s experiment, the list of her overall achievements is particularly detailed
and will be given here as exemplification: naming, sentence formation (including
compound sentences. Sarah insert banana pail apple dis‟), comparison („same‟ v.
„different‟), questioning, negation, pluralisation, qualification, (use of „all‟, „none‟,
E/LAL112 46
„several), questioning „several‟), conjunction („and‟), logical connection („if Sarah take
apple, then Mary give Sarah chocolate‟) and expression of spatial relations (as in „red on
green‟ on presentation of the appropriate visual stimulus).
Sarah has also shown a capacity to name classes such as colour, shape, or size. Also,
more interestingly for the linguist, she exhibited some metalinguistic ability (cf. the
design feature „reflexiveness‟) by performing an activity involving linking a symbol with
an object by means of the operator „name of‟ (also represented by a symbol) Another
design feature worthy of mention in the context of the present experiments is learnability,
a property of all human languages, including ASL, which, rather obviously, can be said to
be learnable by human organisms (some other system, such as a computer program,
might not be). The interest of the research is to course that it directly addresses the
question of the biological prerequisites of such learning. More specifically, the argument
could be made that, if ASL is learnable by both humans and apes, then apes must share
the appropriate biological structures with humans. And if the list of design features
defines the scope of human language, it would appear that at least the „natural‟ apes have
successfully acquired one of such language. The only feature open to question appears to
be „displacement‟, but even here, Patterson explicitly mentions reference to past and
future events by the animal.
The argument above assumes that the apes have indeed acquired ASL, and we shall now
review some of the criticisms which question both aspects of this assumption: that the
system is, it was indeed acquired as a human-like language.
The next question relates to the nature of the animals‟ feats. In particular, is there
evidence that they used the system in a manner approximating language? It is
questionable whether the apes involved in the „artificial‟ experiments did, their
performances being probably explainable as a chain-of-conditioned responses (cf. chapter
2); pigeons also have been shown to be able to peck a sequence of coloured keys
(reminiscent of Lana‟s sentences‟ e.g. „please machine make window open‟), but it is not
clear that it is legitimate to interpret this behaviour as „language‟.
E/LAL112 47
The „natural‟ apes, on the other hand, invariably produced unrequested sign sequences.
For instance, some 20, 000 such utterances by Nim with anything up to sixteen signs in
each were recorded over a two-year period. However, the critics of the experiments (and,
interestingly, these include Nim‟s trainers Herbet Terrace and Laura Petitto) have
forcefully pointed out a collection of flaws which seriously vitiate the interpretation of
this output as language.
First, it is not always easy to establish what the accomplishments of the animals really
are, since the data are typically under-reported and‟ „leaned up‟. In particular, errors are
hardly mentioned, and repetitions are deleted as a matter of general policy, for instance,
an utterance like Nim‟s give orange me give and orange me eat orange give me eat
orange give me you‟ could well have been transcribed as „give orange me eat‟. This, of
course gives the false impression of a carefully thought-out sentence, similar to that of a
human child. In actual fact, however, not only are children‟s utterances free of such
redundancies, but typically they are drastically reduced.
It has been suggested that the strategy underlying the apes overproduction might be one
of maximising signing correspondingly to maximise the reward. Obviously, this has little
to do with the expression of meaning, the primary aim of language as normally used by
humans, children included.
The apes‟ tendency to repetition extends to the domain of discourse, where it has been
observed that a substantial proportion of their utterances simply show the trainer‟s output.
The consequences of this are fairly serious, critically undermining the claims made in the
literature about the contextual appropriates of their use of signs. It also highlights
another shortcoming of the animals‟ performance, namely, their general lack of
motivation and spontaneity, since they usually require considerable prodding by the
trainers before an adequate response is elicited. Finally, they have difficulties as regards
conversational structure, typically interrupting the trainer in ASL) who are known to
initiate conversations and to the turns in didactic exchanges.
As hinted at above, one of the most characteristic traits of human language relates to the
use of word order to express different meanings. Importantly, each such order is relatable
to the semantic classes present in the sentence, and is thus not contingent on the specific
identity of the lexical items. The best documented case of syntactic tendencies in the
„natural‟ experiments is provided by Nim. It is telling however, that for each putative
„semantic role‟ in his sentences, only one lexical item was normally used, thus weakening
the likelihood that a general semantic base underlay his performance. Also, and perhaps
not unrelatedly, the average length of his utterances failed to show any significant
increase throughout his training. Finally, because of the redundancies mentioned above,
greater sentence length did not necessarily result in greater sentence length did not
necessary result in greater information content. Once more, these traits contrast sharply
with those found in the speech of human children, whose sentences, even when reduced,
also exhibit hierarchical structure, as is typical of human syntax (cf. Chapter 6, Section
2).
E/LAL112 48
In the fact of such unfavourable assessment of the apes‟ performance, it would appear
that only their ability to name remains as a solid achievement. But here again the
differences with children are significant. In effect, while the latter go through a „naming
stage‟ of relentless questioning, the animals have to be submitted to intensive teaching,
sometimes involving thousands of hours for any one sign. Moreover, particularly in the
habitual absence of „displacement‟, it is not obvious that their comprehension of the
meaning of individual words greatly exceeds that of lower organisms conditioned to
particular behaviours in the presence of certain stimuli (cf. Chapter 2). Thus, while the
apes have undoubtedly grasped the utility of the signs (e.g. „Banana‟ can bring about the
obtainment of fruit), it appears unlikely that they have understood that the signs refer to
particular objects (on „reference‟ cf. Chapter 7, p 201). Accordingly, it seems more
parsimonious and perhaps more realistic to adopt a pragmatic (cf. Chapter 7, Section 6)
rather than a linguistic interpretation of their sign behaviour, reminiscent of children‟s
earliest steps in language.
Faced with this barrage of criticism, the advocates of the linguistic ape have striven for a
higher level of refinement in experimental design, which allegedly has overcome some of
the shortcomings of previous attempts, and have examined critically some of their
opponents‟ changes. A typical strategy has been to remove the burden of failure from the
biology of the animal to the experimental procedures. In the context of the social and
communicational aspects of language, the stilted learning conditions prevailing in the
„artificial‟ experiments and to some experiments and to some extend also in Nim‟s have
the target of social attack. Also, possession of language has been claimed to be a
gradient, rather than an all-or-nothing, affair, and this would subtract legitimacy from the
use of a rigid defining set of necessary conditions such as the design features. Finally,
and importantly, there are reports of the spontaneous teaching of signs by Washoe (now
„retired) at the Institute for Primate Studies, in Norman, Oklahoma) to her adopted infact,
who has apparently begun to use them. All this leads us to conclude that the ape
language controversy is still very must alive, and that it will probably take years of
patient but dispassionate research and interpretation before the final word on the matter is
said.
E/LAL112 49
Extra From: AITCHSON, J. (1976 The articulate Mammal.
London: Hutchinson Publishing Group (pp. 34 – 50)
Our first task is to find out whether any animals naturally have a true language. In order
to answer this question, we must compare human language with animal communication.
But such a comparison presents a number of perhaps unsolvable problems. Two in
particular need to be discussed before we can start to give a coherent reply to the query.
„Do animals talk naturally?
The first problem we must consider is this: are we comparing systems which differ
quantitatively or qualitatively? On the one hand, human language may have gradually
evolved from a more primitive animal mans of communication in a continuous line of
growth – a – viewpoint sometimes known as a „continuity‟ theory on the other hand,
human language may be something different from our basic animal heritage, and
superimposed on it. This is a „discontinuity‟ theory.
Supporters of continuity theories suggest that language grew out of a primate call system,
like the ones used by apes today. They assume that humans started out with a simple set
of cries in which one meant something different such as “Danger” or “follow me. “Don‟t
touch that female, she is mine‟. “These cries gradually became more elaborate, and
eventually evolved into language…..
Proponents of discontinuity theories claim that man still retains his basic set of animal
cries, which exist alongside language. Yelps of pain, shrecks of fear, and the different
types of crying observed in babies may be closely related to the call system of monkeys.
If this view is correct, then it is fairly difficult to compare human and animal means of
communication. It may be like comparing two things as different as the Chinese
language and a set of traffic lights. But at the moment the question is an open. We do
not yet know whether the continuity or discontinuity theories are correct. But we must
keep both possibilities in mind when discussing the main topic of this chapter.
The second major problem we face is that it is not always easy to decide what counts as
communication in animals. As one researcher notes “students of animal behaviour have
often noted the extreme of restricting the notion of communication to anything less than
every potential interaction between an organism and its environment,” (Marshall, 1970:
231).
E/LAL112 50
TEACHING ANIMALS TO TALK: WASHOE AND SARAH
Although psychologists have spent considerable time experimenting with mynah birds, it
is perhaps not surprising that the results have been disappointing. Apes seem more
promising candidates. Over the past forty years several attempts have been made to teach
human language to chimpanzees.
The first experiments was a failure. An animal named GUA was acquired by professor
and Mrs. Kellog in 1931, when she was seven months old. She was brought up as it she
was a human baby, and was fed with a spoon, bathed, pinned up in nappies, and
continuously exposed to speech although she eventually managed to understand the
meaning of over seventy single words, she never spoke‟. Gua showed clearly that is not
just lack of opportunity which prevents a chimp from learning language. The Kellogs‟
son Donald, who was brought up alongside Gua, and was approximately the same age,
grew up speaking normally.
A second chimp acquired by Keith and Cathy Hayes in 1947 also proved disappointing,
Vicki was given intensive teaching in English; she eventually learned four words:
MAMA, PAPA, CUP, UP. But these were very uncleared, articulated, and remained the
sum total of Vicki‟s utterances after three years of hard training.
It is now clear why these attempts failed, chimps are not physiologically capable of
uttering human sounds. More recent experiments have avoided this trap and used sign
language, the manipulation of tokens or button pressing. Let us consider some of this
research.
We shall confine our discussion to Washoe (Garden and Garner, 1969; Gardner and
Allen, 1971) and Sarah premack 1970, 1971, 1972). These are the two chimps who, so
for seem to have acquired most “language” and whose achievements have been most
widely reported.
Washoe exact age is unknown. She is a female chimp acquired by professor and Mrs.
Gardener in 1966, when she was thought to e approximately a year old. She has been
taught to use American deaf-and-dumb sing language (ASL). In this system signs stand
for words…
Washoe acquired her language in a fairly natural‟ way. The Gardeners kept her
continuously surrounded by humans who communicated with her and each other by
means of signs. They hoped that some of these would “rub off” on her. Sometime they
E/LAL112 51
asked her to imitate them, or tried to correct her. But there ware no rigorous straining
Schedules …
Washoe‟s progress was impressive and, at least in the early stage, her language
development was not unlike that of a human child.
First, she acquired a number of single words, e.g. COME, GIMME, HURRY, SWEET,
TICKLE – which amounted to thirty – four after twenty-one months, but crept up to well
over one hundred….”
Washoe‟s speech clearly had semanticity” she had no difficulty in understanding that a
certain sign means a certain object or action, as was shown by her acquisition of the word
for toothbrush.”
Washoe could also generalize from one situation to another, as was clear from her use of
the sign meaning „more‟… Her „speech‟ also incorporated a limited account of
displacement, since she could ask for absent objects and people.
But most impressive of all was Washoe‟s creativity – her apparently spontaneous use of
combinations of signs. She produced two – and three – word sequences of her own
invention such as GIMME TICKLE, OPEN DRINK, HURRY GIMME TOOTHBRUSH,
OPEN THE FRIDGE ETC. Washoe‟s signs were not just accidental juxtapositions.
Unlike human children, however, Washoes did not care in what order she gave her signs.
She was as likely to say “SWEET GO” as “GO SWEET” to mean “Take me to the
raspberry bushes”.
E/LAL112 52
UNIT FIVE
The various properties of human language have been termed „design features‟ of human
language by the American linguist Charles Francis Hockett. Commenting on Hockett‟s
design features of human language, Atkinson et al. (1982: 11) had this to say:
“The usefulness of the features resides in the fact that they permit a fair
characterisation of human language as well as a straight forward means of
comparison with other communication systems but it must be noted that their
choice is ultimately motivated by the arbitrary decision of the individual
researcher at a particular time, the list having undergone various changes over the
years, and there is no indication that it has reached its final format”.
(b) Arbitrarines
Arbitrarines as a design feature of human language does not mean that one can
speak, or write anyhow. One can‟t speak, or write anyhow because human
language has accepted norms of pronunciation and is rule-governed. Rather, it
means that human language is conventional in the sense that there is no natural
relationship between words and their meanings or things they are used to refer to.
Sound symbolism (= situation where there is a link between sound and meaning)
is an exception to linguistic arbitrariness, as defined above but only to some
extent. Examples:
E/LAL112 53
(i) onomatopoeia or onomatopoeic words
However, to some extent, even onomatopoeias are arbitrary. For instance, it is not all
languages which mimick the sounding of slapping by “pa” or the noise of a sudden
breaking by “mpo”. Traugott and Pratt (1980: 4) observe that while the long and loud cry
of a cock is mimicked by „cock-a-dooble-doo‟ in English, it is mimicked by „cocorico‟ in
French and „kekoko‟ in Japanese. The above and similar examples show that even
onomatopoeias are language-specific.
(ii) Synaesthesia
E/LAL112 54
(ii) the fact that, although in any language the number of elements (sounds,
words, etc) and rules is finite, the number of sentences that can be
produced using such elements and rules is potentially infinite;
(iii) there is no limit to how long a sentence can be. For example any sentence
can be lengthened using coordination or subordination, as in
Crystal (1992: 89) advises to take care to “avoid confusing this sense of
„creative‟ with that found in artistic or literary contexts, where notions such as
imagination and originality are central.”
- The sounds of a particular language do not combine anyhow but they combine
into syllables following certain rules that define permissible sequences of sounds
in that language. Thus although the sounds f and I in both English and most
Bantu languages, English permit the sequence fl (as in flower) while Bantu does
not.
- Words do not combine anyhow. For example, the English words he, party,
defected, our and to can combine into he defected to our party but not e.g.,
*defeated the be party our to or* party to he defected our (the asteristic or star* is
used in linguistics to mean among others, that what follows is not accepted as
correct or appropriate).
E/LAL112 55
(e) Human language is discrete
When one says that human language is discrete (not discreet!) what is meant is
that any human language is made of distinct (= separate) elements, e.g. sounds,
syllables, words, phrases and sentences. Such distinct (or discrete) elements are
put together when speaking or writing.
This refers to the fact that the continuum of speech is split up into
meaningful units (= units which have meaning) such as words.
Any human language changes in time and space. Furthermore, language use
changes according to contexts of use. The study of how particular languages have
changed in time is called historical linguistics or diachronic linguistics. The study
of how particular languages have changed in space, that is, the study of regional
variations of the same language, is referred to as dialectology. The study of how
languages are used according to contexts of use is known as sociolinguistics.
Examples:
- A glance at English literary and other texts produced different time shows
that English changes in time.
E/LAL112 56
communication. It is important to note that even within the same country
English, like any other language, varies according to regions.
- Bemba as spoken in the Kasama area is not exactly the same as the Bemba
spoken in Mansa or Mukushi.
(Here we have such variables as „who is speaking to whom‟, „what is being talked
about,‟ „where the speech event is taking place,‟ etc).
- The English used in church is different from the English spoken during
lecturers or conversations.
(h) Displacement
- any normal child can learn any language (whether or not the language is
its „mother tongue‟) provided the child is adequately exposed to it;
- it is possible to teach some animals (e.g. chimpanzees) to respond to and
even produce some utterances.
E/LAL112 57
Chomsky‟s argument is that it is not possible to teach a human language as a
whole to any animal, including chimpanzees (animals that are closest to man) and,
similarly, it is not possible for a human being to learn fully an animal language.
The conclusion is that human language is both innate, or inborn, and learned. To
say that human language is both a matter of nature and nurture is to say that
human language is transmitted both genetically (= ability to learn any human
language) and culturally (= learning).
(j) Semanticity
(k) Reflexiveness as a design feature of human language refers to man‟s ability to use
language to talk or write about language. The language used to talk/write about
language is known as metalanguage and the language talked/written about is a
target language. Note, however, that the term „target language‟ is also used to
refer to the language into which an original text is translated (Hartmann and Stork
1972: 234). For instance, if an English text is translated into Bemba, English is
the source language and Bemba the target language.
(I) Prevarication
E/LAL112 58
case where the user of a language does not present the real state of affairs out of
ignorance or misunderstanding.
This is a design feature of human language that refers to the fact that particular
human languages must be learned and are transmitted from one generation to
another. However, such transmission does not imply that language is static (=
does not change) (see design feature (g).
(n) Learnability
This is a property of human language that simply refers to the fact that any normal
child can learn any human language (Atkinson et al 1982: 17 – 18). Any human
language is learnable by normal humans.
(o) Interchangeability
Anyone who knows a language can both transmit a message in that language and
receive and understand a message in the same language (Atkinson et al 1982: 21).
The “speaker himself can perceive the totality of his own signal, through the sense
of hearing” (Atkinson 1982: 21). This means that if someone says something it is
not only the addressee who hears the message but also he (= the speaker) himself.
In fact, under normal circumstances the speaker always hears all that he says
while the addresses may not.
Because of the very physical nature of sounds, “the signal vanishes fast, thus
freeing the channel for the next unit of transmission” (Atkinson et al. 1982: 9).
This is design feature referring to the fact that the transmission of sound is
“omnidirectional, thus increasing the efficiency of the signal, albeit at the expense
of privacy, a potentially disadvantageous fact” (Atkinson et al 1982: 10).
E/LAL112 59
REFERENCES
Atkinson, M., et al. (1982) Foundations of General Linguistics, 2nd edition London:
Unvin Hyman Ltd.
Traugott, E. C., and M. L. Pratt (1980) Linguistics for students of Literature. New York:
Harcourt Brace.
REVISION QUESTIONS
E/LAL112 60
(n) learnability
(o) interchangeability
E/LAL112 61
UNIT SIX
LANGUAGE ACQUISITION
0. GENERAL
0.1 Definition
The term language acquisition is used in this lecture as synonym (i.e. equivalent)
of child language acquisition, i.e. the mergence and growth of language in
children. However, the term child language acquisition also refers to the field of
study involved, a branch of psycholinguistics, a branch of linguistics which is
concerned with the correlation between “linguistic behaviour and the
psychological process thought to underlie that behaviour” (Crystal 1992: 284).
One recurrent topic of child language acquisition has been the postulation of
several stages in the chronological development of language in children: Note
that in a broader sense, the term language acquisition refers to the learning of
any language including the learning of languages by adults.
While some theories use the terms language acquisition and language
development interchangeably others use the term language acquisition to mean
the learning of a particular rule, lexical item or grammatical item and language
development to mean the use of that rule, lexical item or grammatical item in an
increasingly wide range of linguistic and social situations (Crystal 1992: 6).
The term language acquisition device (LAD), one of Noam Chomsky‟s coinage,
refers to an infant‟s innate predisposition to acquire linguistic structure (Crystal
1992: 6). The postulation of LAD is opposed to the view that language
acquisition is a mere process of imitation – learning or a reflex of cognitive
development (Crystal, ibiden), Hartmann and Stork (1972: 125) explain LAD as a
follows:
input [L A D] output”
“L A D” is like a processor.
E/LAL112 62
Crystal (193: 234) has made the following comment on LAD:
Hartmann and Stork (1972): 124) distinguish six sages in the child language
development, as follows:
E/LAL112 63
(a) to balance means “to speak quickly in a way that is difficult to
understand or sound silly” (Longman Dictionary of contemporary
English (LDCE 1995: 77); the word is used here to emphasize the fact
that a 3 – 9 months the child produces a lot of sounds of which are
meaningless;
(b) lallation is the production of more or less articulated sounds by the child
in such a way that the child tends to combine repeated syllable – like
combinations of sounds such as lalala, tatata, etc;
(c) imitation is used here to emphasize the fact that the child strives and
manages to imitate not only the individual sounds but also sounds
produced by adults. The kind of speech produced by the child during this
period is called holophrastic speech, a holophrastic speech being a speech
in which single words express complex ideas which are normally
expressed by more words especially full sentences (McNeil 1970);
(d) Jargon literally means “technical words and expressions that are used
mainly by people who belong to the same professional group and are
difficult to understand” (e.g. “documents full off legal jargon”) (LDCE
195: 757); here the term jargon is simply used metaphorically to
emphasize that the child is able to produce (two-word) utterances but these
utterances are difficult to understand. During this period, the child tends to
produce two-word utterances which correspond in the child speech to the
full sentence from which some words have been omitted; for this reason,
this kind of speech is termed telegraphic speech (McNeil 1970). During
the “Jargon” or telegraphic” period, the words used by the child fall into
two classes (McNeil 1970), namely the PIVOT CLASS and the OPEN
CLASS. Pivot is a small number of words which are frequently used
while open-class words are in a greater number and are infrequently used.
Furthermore, pivot always appear with open words while open words may
appear alone, a situation which is visualized as follows (up = pivot class
word
P + 0
0 + P
0 + P
(e) talking: at the age of 2 years, the child has gone beyond telegraphic
speech and that speech it produces is closer to the adult language; hence
the choice of the term „talking‟ used to characterize this period;
(f) While the word loquacity literally means linking to talk a lot or too much,
the term is used here not only to mean that the child likes to talk a lot or
E/LAL112 64
too much but also to mean that the child has mastered the language almost
completely.
The best known theories of languages acquisition are the imitation theory, the
innateness theory and the cognitive theory.
Imitation
(b) Innateness
(c) Cognition
4. CONCLUSION
A lot is known on the stages in the chronological development of child language.
For instance, all studies have shown that, as a general rule, by the age 4 years the
child in all languages has almost completely acquired a speech comparable to
adult speech. However, many questions are still unanswered. One of such
questions is what happens in the child‟s brain.
E/LAL112 65
On the three theories of language acquisition discussed in this lecture, it is to be
noted that no theory can explain alone all aspects of language acquisition:
imitation, innateness of the ability to learn human languages, cognitive
development and, indeed, other factors all play a role in child language
acquisition.
REFERENCES
McNeil, D (1970) The Acquisition of Language. New York, Evanston and London:
Harper and Row, Publishers.
REVISION QUESTIONS
E/LAL112 66
UNIT SEVEN
LANGUAGE HANDCAP
0. General
Language handicap is any systematic deficiency in the way people speak,
listen, read, write or sign that interferes with their ability to communicate with
their peers (Crystal 1993: 264). In medicine, the term pathology of language
may be used to refer to diseases which cause language handicaps.
The term language handicap may be used in a broad sense and in a narrow sense.
In the broad sense, it refers to any type of handicap (including cases where you
cannot express yourself properly in a foreign or second language simply because
you haven‟t mastered it due to lack of adequate exposure). In the narrower sense,
it refers only to those cases where handicap is due to malfunctioning of the body.
1. STATISTICS
Because handicap exists in a continuum from mild to severe, it is very difficult to
obtain accurate estimates of its prevalence (= the number of cases in a population
at any one time) or incidence (= the number of new cases within a particular
period) (Crystal 1993: 264). Crystal (1993: 264) reports that
E/LAL112 67
these, there is no doubt that the causes of the linguistic handicap lies in a person‟s
abnormal physical condition.
However, in the majority of cases, it is not possible to find a clear organic cause
given the present state of medical knowledge. Thousands of children have a
delayed language development, and in most of them there is nothing in their
medical history that can account for the problem. There are many thousands of
stutterers whose handicap, likewise, cannot be explained in any simple physical
way. And a large number of people develop problems in the use of their voice
that has no physical explanation. In such instances, we can search for
„functional‟ causes in a person‟s psychological, social, or linguistic background.
Assessment of language handicap must also allow for the fact that many
conditions have multiple causes. For example the level of language achievement
reached by a deaf child cannot e explained solely with reference to the child‟s
degree of hearing loss: many other factors contribute – such as the kind and
amount of exposure to spoken or signed language. Or again, an adult‟s voice
disorder might begin as hoarseness arising out of a straight forward disease, such
as laryngitis; but anxiety over the continued use of the voice (if the person is a
singer, for example) might promote the development of excessive strain while
talking; with the result that the hoarseness continues long after the disease has
disappeared. Similar combinations of organic and functional causative factors
underline most if not all language handicaps.
NOTES
1. aphasia = partial or complete loss of the ability to use spoken language as a result
of maldevelopment, disease or injury to the brain (Hartmann and Stork 1972: 16)
2. vocal folds or vocal cords = the two lip-like membranes of folds which vibrate in
the larynx to produce voice.
3. Larynx = the upper end of the trachea (= windpipe), which is a frame of cartilage
containing the two vocal folds.
E/LAL112 68
3. CLASSIFYING LANGUAGE HANDICAPS
(a) aphasia or dysphasia = partial or complete inability to use spoken language due
to maldevelopment, disease or injury to the brain (Hartmann and Stork: 16);
4. DEAFNESS
About 1 in 1,000 children have a hearing loss that is present at birth, or acquired soon
after, caused by pathology of the inner ear and its relationship to the auditory nerve.
Maternal rubella (German measles), meningitis, and several other diseases are known to
be causative factors. Many more children have a haring loss that they acquire in the
preschool or early school period, because of pathology of the middle ear, several-ear
problems get better without intervention; but other recur, become chronic, and do not
respond well to treatment. In such chronic cases, and in all cases of inner-ear deafness,
there can be serious consequences for the development of speech comprehension and
production.
Many adults – perhaps as many as a third of the population over 60 years of age have an
acquired heaving loss, which can noticeably affect their ability to comprehend and speak
(the latter, because they are unable to use hearing to monitor what they are saying).
Regular exposure to loud noise (at work, in discos, etc.) is a common cause. However,
E/LAL112 69
because language has been acquired before the onset of the deafness, these disorders are
usually less serious.
TYPES OF DEAFNESS
There is no single, simple phenomenon of „deafness‟ but a wide range of kinds and
degree of hearing impairment. The loss may affect only one ear (umilateral) or both ears
(bilateral). At one extreme, there may be a slight inability to hear a few low-intensity
frequencies, which interferes only occasionally with normal communication; at the other
extreme, a person may have no detectable response to any frequency, no matter how
intense the sound. The latter is uncommon: most deaf people have some degree of
„residual‟ hearing.
The main classification of hearing loss is abased on where the interference lies in the
auditory pathway. Conductive deafness arises when there is interference with the
transmission of sound to the inner ear, as when the middle ear becomes inflamed (otitis
media) or the ear drum or ossicles are affected by disease or trauma. Sensorineural
deafness arises when the source of interference lies within the inner ear, or along the
auditory nerve to the brain.
Other forms of hearing impairment have been identified, such as tinnitus – a range of
noise in the ear (singing, hissing, presating, etc.) that can occur in acute, delibilitating
form. Around 2 million people have this problem, to some degree, in the USA.
NOTES
2. The kind of body language used by deaf people is called sign language (often
abbreviated to SL). There exist several SLs. E.g. American sign language (ASL
or AMESLAM), British sign language (BSL), etc.
E/LAL112 70
REFERENCES
REVISION QUESTIONS
2. What must one say on the prevalence and incidence of language handicap. Before
answering the question, define the terms prevalence and incidence in this
context.
E/LAL112 71
UNIT EIGHT
A language expresses a person‟s individual identify and social identify and there are
many ways in which it does so. This lecture will examine only the following: physical
identify, psychological identify, geographical identity and social identity.
There is little in the anatomy of the human vocal tract to account for the linguistic
differences between people and groups. The proportions of the various vocal
organs seem to be very similar in all human beings. Individual variations do exist
but there is no evidence to suggest that anatomical variations have an effect on the
ability of a person to learn or use speech. Furthermore, despite the superficial
differences, it has generally been concluded that vocal tracts the world over are
sufficiently similar that we can regard them as variants of a single, universal type.
That there must be some kind of relationship between physical condition and
language is plain from the way language can be affected in cases of physical
handicap. Several disorders of constitutional origin have a direct effect on a
person‟s ability to use language, variously affecting the ability to comprehend and
produce speech, read, and write.
The relationship between age and language can be demonstrated by the fact that
no one would have much difficulty identifying a baby, a young child, a teenager,
a middle-aged person, or a very old person from a tape recording.
E/LAL112 72
1.4 Sex
Phonetic differences (i.e. differences in pronunciation) e.g. voice pitch, are the
most obvious measures of sexual identity; but languages provide many instances
of males and females learning different styles of speech – as in Japanese, Thai;
Carib, Chukohi, and Yana. Pronunciation, grammar, vocabulary, and context of
use can all be affected. In English, the situation is less clear: there are no
grammatical forms, lexical items, or patterns of pronunciation that are used
exclusively by one sex, but there are several differences in frequency. For
example, among the words and phrases that women are supposed to use more
often are such emotive adjectives as super and lovely, exclamations such as
Goodness me and Oh dear, and intensifiers such as so or such (e.g. It was so
busy). This use of intensifiers have been noted in several languages, including
German, French, and Russian.
More important are the strategies adopted by the two sexes in cross-sex
conversation. Women have been found to ask more questions, make more use of
positive and encouraging „noises‟ (such as man), use a wider intonational range
and a more marked rhythmical stress, and make greater use of the pronouns you
and we. By contrast, men are much more likely to interrupt, to dispute what has
been said, to ignore or respond poorly to what has been said, to introduce more
new topics into the conversation, and to make more declarations of fact or
opinion.
Comment
E/LAL112 73
3. GEOGRAPHICAL IDENTITY
The language or language variety someone uses point to the geographical origin
of the speaker. However, this is true only statistically. Thus a Bemba speaker
speaking Aushi is likely to have grown up in “Aushland” in Luapula province.
Similarly, someone speaking American English is likely to be American or have
spent a long time in the USA or Anglophone Canada.
4.0 General
In addition to the questions „who are you?‟ and „where are you from?‟, which
have been addressed from a linguistic viewpoint, there is also „what are you, in
the eyes of the society to which you belong?‟ It is a complex and multi-faceted
question, to which there is no easy answer. People acquire varying status as they
participate in social structure; they belong to many social groups; and they
perform a large variety of social roles. This section, therefore, has to be
extremely selective.
One does not need to be a sociolinguist to sense that the way people talk has
something to do with their social position or level of education. Everyone has
developed a sense of values that make some accents seem „posh‟ and others „low‟,
some features of vocabulary and grammar „refined‟ and others „uneducated‟.
Example 1 castes
Castes are social divisions based solely on birth which totally restricts a person‟s
way of life – for example, allowing certain kinds of job, or certain marriage
partners. The best-known system is that of Hindu society of India, which has four
main divisions, and many subdivisions – though in recent years, the caste barriers
have less rigidly enforced. The Brahmins (priest) constitute the highest class;
below them, in descending order, are the Kshatriyas (warriors), Vaisyas (farmers
and merchants), and Sundras (servants). The so-called „untouchables‟, whose
contact with the other castes is highly restricted are the lowest level of the Sudra
caste.
Linguistic correlates of caste can be found at all levels of structure. For example,
in Tamil, there are several clear-cut distinctions between the phonology (= sound
patterns), and grammar of Brahmin and non-Brahmin speech. The former also
tends to use more loan words, and to preserve non-native patterns of
pronunciation.
E/LAL112 74
E.g
Brahmin Non-Brahmin
tungu „sheep‟ orangu
krafu „haircut‟ krappu
jinni „sugar‟ cini
vandundu „it came‟ vanducou
In the Republic of Burundi, age and sex combine with caste to constrain the
nature of linguistic interaction. Seniority (ubukuru) governs all behaviour.
There are clear caste divisions: Older people precede younger; and men precede
women. The order in which people speak is strictly governed by the seniority
principle. Males of highest rank must speak first, regardless of age. Females do
not speak at all, in the presence of outsiders, unless spoken to.
Upper-caste speakers seem never to raise their voices, or allow emotion to show.
In a group discussion, for the senior person to be silent implies disapproval. As
others must then also stay silent, any further proceedings are effectively negated.
To speak well is considered a mark of good breeding in men. From their tenth
year, boys in the upper castes are given formal speech training – how to use social
formulae, talk to superior and inferiors and make speeches for special occasions.
Upper-caste girls do not take part in public speaking, but they do develop
effective bargaining skills, for use behind the scenes. They are also trained to
listen with great are, so that they can accurately recount to the men of the family
what has been said by visitors.
E/LAL112 75
Linguistically, it was highly predictable with a relatively high proportion
of such features as pronouns, tag questions, and use of gestures and
intonation to convey meaning. Elaborated code, by contrast, was thought
to lack these features.
The correlation of elaborated code and restricted code with certain types
of social-class background and their role in educational settings (e.g.
whether children used to restricted code will succeed in schools where
elaborated code is the norm – and what should be done in such cases),
brought this theory considerable publicity and controversy, and the
distinction has since been reinterpreted in various ways.
Devices for conveying relative respect and social distance can be found in all
languages.
E/LAL112 76
REFERENCES
REVISION QUESTIONS
4. With examples, show that there is some relationship between language and social
stratification.
E/LAL112 77
UNIT NINE
LANGUAGE FUNCTIONS
The phrase language functions may be used to refer to either (a) the various uses of
human language in general or (b) the various uses of particular languages by a nation or a
community. I shall deal in turn with the two kinds of language functions. This lecture
will show that, in addition to the communicative function (undoubtedly the main
function), language has many other functions.
1.0 General
As Dell (1976: 83) points out, “It is of some interest to realize that the
same division appears to co-occur in the types of language use singled out
by the different branches of the human sciences. Linguistics and
philosophy tended to focus on the cognitive, sociology and social
psychology on the evaluative and psychology and literary criticism on the
affective.”
E/LAL112 78
The traditional three-function model outlined above has been found to be
unsatisfactory. One reason for this is that the three functions are in fact
three aspects of the same function, namely the informative, or
communicative, function of language. The three-way division is based on
the type of information conveyed by language and, therefore, implies that
language is only used to convey information, an implication which is
untrue, as evidenced in B. S. R. Jakobson‟s and M. A. K. Halliday‟s
Models (see Dell 17. 1976: 83 – 87).
What this means is that language functions depend on the communicative aspects focused
on by the speaker/writer. Note that in Jakobson‟s terminology above (a) Emotive,
Expressive and Affective are synonymous (i.e. they mean the same thing, they are
interchangeable terms) and so are (b) Referential, Cognitive and Denotative and (c)
Phatic and Interaction management, although this is not the case elsewhere.
2. Addresseer: to require somebody to convey out some action (cf. the use of
Vocatives C-Calling somebody) and imperatives)
4. Message: focusing on the message itself for enjoyment as in art and most of
literature: poetic function.
E/LAL112 79
“In a series of papers Halliday … explored the relationship between function and
use in child and adult language and proposed a theory of sociological semantics in
which he demonstrates the collapse of the seven functions of child language (pre-
school children that is) into three macrofunctions which serve adults. The child,
he argues, has seven language functions which correlate very closely, initially in
one-to-one way, with form e.g. a child wishing to ask for a sweet is likely to say
“I want …” rather than the multiple of utterances available to the adult … what
the child does with language tends to determine its structure. During the course
of maturation, Halliday suggests, the seven discrete functions of child language
are gradually replaced by a more highly coded and more abstract, but also
simpler, functional system. This system contains only three macrofunctions – the
ideational, the interactional and the textual – which to some degree supplement
and cut across the three traditional functions”.
This corresponds closely to the cognitive function (expression of facts) but also
includes the „expression of experience‟ as well as the emotional and affective
aspects of attitude, value, emotion and feeling. In short, the ideational function is
concerned with the expression of phenomena of the external world as well as
those of consciousness (Dell, op. cit. p. 85)
Hartmann and Stork (1972: 91) give us the following list of language functions.
E/LAL112 80
5. The Cognitive Function: to verbalize intellectual reasoning.
Note that the same language function can be referred to by different terms; for
example the appellative function is also known as the conative function (NB
„appeler‟ in French means „to call‟ and „conare‟ in Latin means „to try‟). Note
also that the important language functions are not mentioned by Hartman and
Stork (1972 on p. 91), namely the phatic function and the poetic function. The
phatic function is the use of language for social interaction, illustrated by, e.g. the
exchange of stereotyped phrases (e.g. greetings or someone saying „Bless you‟
when someone else has sheered violently; see Crystal, 1987: 10 – 13). The poetic
function is the use of language for pleasure, as in literature.
The main idea behind the speech Act theory is that whenever we say we always
do something: speech is action. There are three kinds of acts we perform
whenever we say something:
To use Austin‟s (1962: 121) such acts are performed in saying while
perlocutionary acts (see (c) below) are performed by saying. The intention
of a speaker/writer producing a given utterance is referred to as the
illocutionary force of that utterance. For instance, the illocutionary force
of the utterance, I promise to come tonight is promising.
As observed by Crystal (1991: 323), several categories of illocutionary act have been
proposed, VIZ.
- directives, when addressers try to get their addressees to do something, e.g. when
commanding or requesting;
E/LAL112 81
- declaratives, when an addresser brings about a state of affairs such as baptizing,
appointing, dismissing, resigning, etc;
Verbs such as say, request, promise, command used to perform illutionary acts are termed
performative verbs or performatives.
It is important to note that certain linguistic constructions generally directly reflect its
illocutionary force, i.e. its communicative purpose. For instance, commands and requests
are typically made using imperatives (e.g. come; give me that book). When this is the
case, the illocutionary act is called a direct speech act, as opposed to an indirect speech
act, which is an illocutionary act not performed by the usual (i.e. expected) linguistic
construction. Thus, the utterance I‟ m feeling hungry may be used as a request for some
food. The (illocutionary) force of an indirect speech act depends on the context of
communication, a major concept in pragmatics (= the study of the use of language (= the
study of the use of language in context);
Consider now the case where only the President of Republic can appoint ministers but
someone who is not the President of Republic says to you: “I appoint you as minister of
Defense”. Such an appointment is invalid because the one who appointed you is not the
appointing authority. The criteria which have to be satisfied in order for a speech act to
be successful are known as felicity conditions (Crystal 1991: 323).
(---) the Whorfian hypothesis (---) states that our conceptual categorisation of the
world is determined (wholly or partial) by the structure of our language. In its
strong from, the hypothesis is not accepted by most linguists.
The Whorf Hypothesis (or Whorfian Hypothesis) named after the American linguist
Benjamin Lee Whorf (1897 – 1941) was actually initially developed by Edward Sapir
(1884 – 1939) of who he once was a student, but it was Whorf who “argued (the
E/LAL112 82
hypothesis) most widely and vividly” (Dale 1976: 237). Comparing the European
languages to which he collectively referred to as Sandard Average European (SAE),
because they are all quite similar, “to the American Indian languages, which are radically
different from SAE and often from another” (Dale 1976: 237 – 8), he came up with the
following two hypothesis which form together the Whorf Hypothesis (or Whorfian
Hypothesis, or Sapir – Whorf Hypothesis:
(a) Linguistic Determinism: all higher levels of thinking are dependent on language,
that is, our first language determines our thinking; and
Note that (b) is a consequence of (a). Based on several experiments, most linguists,
appointed out by Crystal (see above), reject the Whorf hypothesis in its strong form.
Concerning the functions of literature, and art in general there have been two opposing
views. One view holds that the prime function of literature, and art in general, is
entertainment, or pleasure. Wellek and Warren (1982: 36) pointed out that some scholars
regard catharsis as the main function of literature, and art in general. Catharsis is a Greek
word which means “purification‟ or „relief‟. Te believe that literature, or art in general,
has a cathartic function is to believe that literature, or art in general, relieves writers and
readers from the pressure of emotions: “to express emotions is to get free of them”
(Wellek and Warren 1982: 36). However, as pointed out by Wellek and Warren 1982:
36), one can object that some literary works actually arouse emotions.
The doctrine of Art for Art‟s Sake is the strongest view against the utilitarian
conceptions of literature and art in general. This doctrine holds, in effect, that art should
perform one and only one function: the expression of beauty (whatever this means).
Nowadays, most writers and artists believe that, in addition to expressing „beauty‟,
literature and art should serve some practical purpose. In the words of the Latin poet
Horace, this position means that art is both “dulce” (a Latin word meaning
„pleasant/mild‟) and “utile” („useful‟).
Besides the general functions of human language, there are functions that are performed
by particular languages in particular state of/and contexts of communication. One
example is the case of the use of a language as a national official language English in
Zambia) or as a Regional Official Language (ROL). Another example is the exclusive
use of a language in church services. These and other uses of language in society will be
discussed in another lecture.
E/LAL112 83
3. CONCLUSION
In addition to the communicative function, which is the main function, human language
has many other functions. However, there is no agreed upon or exhaustive list of
language functions and scholars do not always agree on certain proposals.
REFERENCES
Dale, P. S. (1976) Language Development Structure and Function New York etc: Holt,
Rinehart and Winston.
E/LAL112 84
REVISION QUESTIONS
E/LAL112 85
UNIT TEN
LANGUAGE AND COMMUNICATION
1. Types of Human Communication
Human communication is verbal or/and non-verbal. Communication is said to be verbal
if it is done through the medium of an articulated language, i.e. using speech sounds (=
sounds produced by the so-called organs of speech). Communication is said to be verbal
even if speech sounds are written.
Gunther (1968), as cited by Keltner (1970: 106) gives the following examples of non-
verbal communication.
Shaking hands
Your posture
Facial expressions
Your appearance
Voice tone
Hair style
Your clothes
The expression of your eyes
Your smile
How close you stand to others
How you listen
Your confidence
The way you move
The way you stand
How you touch other people
Gunther (1968) is quoted by Kelther (1978: 106) as making the following comment on
the above examples of non-verbal communication:
“The body talks, its message is how you really are, not how you think you are”.
There are four communicative behaviours, or language skills as they are called by
language teachers, namely: speaking, listening, writing, and reading. These are
associated with the addresser and the addressee as follows:
E/LAL112 86
SPEAKING _______________ LISTENING
WRITING _______________ READING
Note, however, that there are cases where the addresser and the addressee are the same
and one persons, as when somebody speaks to himself (it does happen) or when we write
notes and other things in our diary for our personal use.
On the four communicative behaviours, or language skills, Keltner (1970: 11) wrote:
Speaking, listening, reading and writing involve different functions of the body
and accomplish different objectives. From the very stages of his existence, after
he graduated from the use of signs, man has used speech and listening as his
principal meaning.
Keltner (ib) points out that although writing and printing have had a tremendous impact
on the recording of ideas, the key interaction that forms the basic of our society is still
spoken language or speech. He also reports (on p. 12) that Ralph Nichols and Leonard A.
Stevens (1957) have shown that the breakdown of the time spent in normal
communicative discourse by the average American is as follows:
The distinction we have made between verbal and non-verbal communication is based
on, the means of communication (in the sense of tube of code used). We can also
categorize human communication in terms of whether a person is communicating with
himself (just in case a person is both the addresser and the addressee) or a communicative
event involves at least two participants such that the addresser(s) and the addressee(s) are
different people. The latter case is known as interpersonal communication. The criterion
used here is the number of participants. In connection with the number of participants,
Hartmann and Stork (1972: 143 – 4) give the following terms:
(a) monologue: the linguistic activity of a single speaker, e.g.. in the form of a
speech or lectures or as internal speech;
(b) soliloquy: the activity of a single speaker when no to other person is present;
(d) multilogue or polylogue involves more than two contributing speakers, e.g. in a
group discussion or argument.
E/LAL112 87
A system is a whole in which there is a “part-to-part, part-to-whole
interrelationship and interdependence” (Sereno and Bodaken 1975: 278).
Writing on communication as a system, Sereno and Bodaken (op. Cit p.
10) had this to say:
“when a person tries to make sense out of the world (and people have a
deep psychological need to make sense out of the world), he has basically
two sources of information available to him: the elements he brings with
him-all his past, his attitudes, his personality – and those elements
presently existing in the external world – all other people, their words and
messages, their gestures, the surroundings. Perception is the individual‟s
blending of internal and external stimuli.
E/LAL112 88
(a) participant: addresser and addressee(s);
(b) message: what is said or written;
(c) channel: the physical means used by the addresser to transmit his message to the
addressee(s);
(d) code: symbols used (= language).
Note, however – and we have already pointed it out – that there are cases where the
addresser and the addressee are the same and one person, in which case there is only one
participant.
Hymes (1972) has proposed thirteen elements reduceable to the acronym SPEAKING:
Setting, Participants, Ends, Act sequence, Key, Instrumentalities, Norms and Gennes Bell
(1976: 79 - 81) explains these elements as follows:
3. End – divided into outcomes – results, intended and unintended – and goals
individual and general. For example, a lecture may e intended to e illuminating
and entertaining but in the event turn out to be vague and boring, while the
lecturer‟s goal may be engender interest in an aspect of sociolinguistics but that of
the audience to spend an hour in a warm comfortable atmosphere!
4. Act sequence - the form and content of the message: how and what is said; the
„topic‟. To continue the example of lecture, the form would be fifty minutes or so
of text analyseable by well-tried, and some less well-tried, techniques of
descriptive „linguistics,‟ while the content might be subjected to semantic
analysis of various kinds and an integrated description of the two attempted.
5. Key – the manner in which the message is conveyed, e.g. the lecture might be
delivered in a precise way or perhaps in a light-hearted way.
6. Instrumentalities: - these include both the channels employed and the forms of
speech, language, dialect, etc. To return yet again to the lecture, the channel
would be essentially spoken language, including the ancillary pseudo-and
paralinguistic resources suggested above and probably back-up use of the written
channels; handouts, notes on the blackboard and so on, while the form be the
lecture‟s own brand of English, possibly with shifts into other varieties, where the
E/LAL112 89
topic required examples from other dialects and even into other languages, where
appropriate quotations from the works of non-English speaking linguists were
incorporated into his notes.
7. Norms – both the interaction itself contains norms of behaviour on the part of the
participants and the interpretation of the communication can be similarly seen as
containing norms, in the sense of expectations, particularly on the part of the
receivers. In a lecture for example, the British lecturer and his audience usually
expect a monologue, free of interruptions, with questions left until the end,
although each group has considerable latitude in this respect and often the lecturer
will state at the beginning of a course, what rules he expects the interaction to
follow. Similarly, the audience will expect the cognitive meaning of the
utterances they hear to be those intended by the speaker. They will not, unless
they are accustomed to the lecturer‟s style, (i.e. key), expect remarks to be ironic
for example indeed one of a lecturer‟s greatest disappointments is that his most
humorous remarks fall flat, simply because the audience is not expecting them to
be anything other than serious.
8. Genres – categories which can be fairly clearly identified through the linguistic
forms they typically employ; the lecture is actually a good example of a particular
genre and, of course; the term has considerable history in literary studies.
The various elements of communication function as variables. For instance, our style in
speaking (choice of words, general behaviour during communication) depends, among
others, on whom we are speaking to (= addressee): our relationships with him, his age,
his sex, his cultural, religious back-ground, etc. similarly, our style depends, partly, on
the channel of communication (letter, telephone, telex, etc).
X Y
E/LAL112 90
Shortcoming of this model
This model omits the fact that a message does not only end in the
receiver‟s mind but always has an effect on the receiver who often gives
some kind of feedback.
(X Y)and (Y X)
What this means is that an addressee does not wait for the addresser to finish the sending
of this message for him to react. Rather his reaction (= feedback) begins at the very
moment when the addresser begins to send his message.
5. COMMUNICATIVE COMPETENCE
In linguistic theory, especially in generative grammar, the term competence is
usually used to refer to “the speaker‟s knowledge of their language, the system of
rules which they have mastered so that they are able to produce and understand an
infinite number of sentences, and to recognise grammatical mistakes and
ambiguities” (Crystal 1992: 66). This kind of competence may be referred to as
pure linguistic competence. However, to communicate effectively, such pure
linguistic competence is inadequate. What we need, to communicate effectively,
is known as communicative competence, defined as the speaker‟s ability to
produce and understand utterances which are appropriate to the context. In this
definition of communicative competence the two key words are „utterances‟ and
„context‟. We do not always produce sentences when we speak. For instance, a
greeting such as Good morning is not a sentence though it is accepted as a correct
E/LAL112 91
utterance. As for „context‟, this means that for one to communicate effectively,
he must take into account a number of variables, such as the social status of the
addressee, his sex, his age, his cultural background, etc. consider for example, the
following utterance: The door, If I meet you, at the Independence Stadium in
Lusaka and I say to do. The door, this utterance does not make any sense. But if
you enter my office and leave the door open and I say The door, this utterance is
now acceptable because it is interpreted as “close the door”. Also note that this
same utterance (The door) can mean either close the door or open the door,
depending on the context.
REFERENCES
Gunther, B. (1968) Sense relaxation: Below your mind. New York: Collier Books.
Nichols, R. G and L. A Stevens (1975) Are you listening? New York: McGraw-Hill
Book Company.
E/LAL112 92
REVISION QUESTIONS
E/LAL112 93