Deleuze and Time (Robert W. Luzecky, Daniel W. Smith (Eds.) )
Deleuze and Time (Robert W. Luzecky, Daniel W. Smith (Eds.) )
Deleuze and Time (Robert W. Luzecky, Daniel W. Smith (Eds.) )
Deleuze Connections
‘It is not the elements or the sets which define the multiplicity. What
defines it is the AND, as something which has its place between the
elements or between the sets. AND, AND, A ND – stammering.’
Gilles Deleuze and Claire Parnet, Dialogues
General Editor
Ian Buchanan
Editorial Advisory Board
Keith Ansell-Pearson Gregg Lambert
Rosi Braidotti Adrian Parr
Claire Colebrook Paul Patton
Tom Conley Patricia Pisters
Titles Available in the Series
Ian Buchanan and Claire Colebrook (eds), Deleuze and Feminist Theory
Ian Buchanan and John Marks (eds), Deleuze and Literature
Mark Bonta and John Protevi (eds), Deleuze and Geophilosophy
Ian Buchanan and Marcel Swiboda (eds), Deleuze and Music
Ian Buchanan and Gregg Lambert (eds), Deleuze and Space
Martin Fuglsang and Bent Meier Sørensen (eds), Deleuze and the Social
Ian Buchanan and Adrian Parr (eds), Deleuze and the Contemporary World
Constantin V. Boundas (ed.), Deleuze and Philosophy
Ian Buchanan and Nicholas Thoburn (eds), Deleuze and Politics
Chrysanthi Nigianni and Merl Storr (eds), Deleuze and Queer Theory
Jeffrey A. Bell and Claire Colebrook (eds), Deleuze and History
Laura Cull (ed.), Deleuze and Performance
Mark Poster and David Savat (eds), Deleuze and New Technology
Simone Bignall and Paul Patton (eds), Deleuze and the Postcolonial
Stephen Zepke and Simon O’Sullivan (eds), Deleuze and Contemporary Art
Laura Guillaume and Joe Hughes (eds), Deleuze and the Body
Daniel W. Smith and Nathan Jun (eds), Deleuze and Ethics
Frida Beckman (ed.), Deleuze and Sex
David Martin-Jones and William Brown (eds), Deleuze and Film
Laurent de Sutter and Kyle McGee (eds), Deleuze and Law
Arun Saldanha and Jason Michael Adams (eds), Deleuze and Race
Rebecca Coleman and Jessica Ringrose (eds), Deleuze and Research Methodologies
Inna Semetsky and Diana Masny (eds), Deleuze and Education
Hélène Frichot and Stephen Loo (eds), Deleuze and Architecture
Betti Marenko and Jamie Brassett (eds), Deleuze and Design
Hélène Frichot, Catharina Gabrielsson and Jonathan Metzger (eds), Deleuze and the
City
Colin Gardner and Patricia MacCormack (eds), Deleuze and the Animal
Markus P.J.Bohlmann and Anna Hickey-Moody (eds), Deleuze and Children
Chantelle Gray van Heerden and Aragorn Eloff (eds), Deleuze and Anarchism
Michael James Bennett and Tano S. Posteraro (eds), Deleuze and Evolutionary Theory
Rick Dolphijn and Rosi Braidotti (eds), Deleuze and Guattari and Fascism
Anindya Sekhar Purakayastha and Saswat Samay Das (eds), Deleuze and Guattari and
Terror
Robert W. Luzecky and Daniel W. Smith (eds), Deleuze and Time
A CIP record for this book is available from the British Library
The right of Robert W. Luzecky and Daniel W. Smith to be identified as the editors
of this work has been asserted in accordance with the Copyright, Designs and
Patents Act 1988, and the Copyright and Related Rights Regulations 2003 (SI No.
2498).
Contents
Robert W. Luzecky
In a text on the relation between the music of Pierre Boulez and the
literature of Marcel Proust, Deleuze observes that the nameless narrator
of Proust’s expansive masterpiece was a person haunted by time (2007:
297). Indeed, the same might be said of Deleuze himself. Temporality is
a near constant theme from Deleuze’s earliest publications (on Hume, as
well as a scintillatingly brief review of Simondon) to his final publication
(‘Immanence: A Life’). Much like Bergson did with his unique concept of
duration, Deleuze continually added further nuances to his philosophy
of time. Temporality is a theme to which Deleuze continually returned
throughout the twenty-five monographs that were published during his
lifetime, in countless seminars and interviews, as well as in the texts
co-authored with Félix Guattari – the two Capitalism and Schizophrenia
volumes, the book on Kafka and What is Philosophy?
The ambit of Deleuze’s philosophy could scarcely be more expansive.
In the Foreword to Éric Alliez’s Capital Times: Tales from the Conquest
of Time, Deleuze explicitly affirms Plotinus’ claim that time is involved
in the movements of the universe’s soul (1996: xii). A few lines later –
through oblique reference to Fitzgerald, Iberall, the Stoics, Nietzsche,
Kant and S hakespeare – Deleuze further characterises these movements
as aberrant, in the sense that they are akin to the decoupling of a door
flying off its hinges; time is a cosmic dice throw that affirms the actu-
alisation of possibilities. In his two Cinema texts, as well as his other
works on Bergson’s philosophy, Deleuze suggests that temporal move-
ments involve the ongoing creation of virtual and actual modes of being.
(Here, one might also observe a subtle modification of Étienne Souriau’s
aesthetics.) The sheer number of texts that Deleuze published also hints
at a further aspect of his philosophy of time: it is non-reducible to the
thought of one key fi gure – to encounter Deleuze’s concept of time is to
participate with a plurality of thinkers. Though there are certainly some
2 Robert W. Luzecky
in key texts. Daniel W. Smith observes that Deleuze developed his theory
of time primarily in two moments of his career: first, in the books pub-
lished in 1968 and 1969, Difference and Repetition and The Logic of
Sense, and then, sixteen years later, in his 1985 book The Time-Image,
the second volume of his work on cinema. There is, of course, a develop-
ment in Deleuze’s thinking about time from one period to the other, and
his later work makes a claim that was only hinted at in Difference and
Repetition, namely, that a revolution in our philosophical conception
of time took place with Kant. This is the point where Smith’s analysis
begins. In antiquity, the concept of time was subordinated to the concept
of movement. In Kant, time is liberated from movement and assumes an
autonomy and independence of its own. Smith traces out the history of
this revolution and shows how in Kant time becomes a pure and empty
form, which is marked by the three syntheses of habit, memory and the
new. Smith’s chapter presents a perspicacious overview of Deleuze’s
entire theory of time.
If the swerve of elementary particles is an aspect of the emergence of
time, then perhaps it should also be observed that Deleuze seemed to
never tire of suggesting that aspects of the creation of time enjoy expres-
sion through reference to Nietzsche’s concepts of the eternal return and
the will to power. In some of the most beautiful passages of Nietzsche
and Philosophy and Difference and Repetition, Deleuze suggests that
the eternal return and implicated will to power may be characterised
as a dice throw that yields the creation of the new. In his fascinating
chapter on Deleuze’s reading of Nietzsche, James Mollison observes
that Deleuze tends to identify the will to power as a metaphysical selec-
tion. Perhaps no phrase in all of Nietzsche’s philosophy has endured so
much – s ometimes d eliberate – m
isinterpretation as ‘the will to power’.
Erroneous early interpretations suggested that the will to power may
admit of psychological interpretations – as though it were merely an
aspect of the personality of a psycho-social entity. Though Deleuze tends
to characterise the creation of the new as an affirmation of an emergent
circumstance, Mollison elegantly observes that, for both Nietzsche and
Deleuze, this characterisation is not an expression of a dubious anthro-
pomorphisation of philosophical concepts. (In this sense, the will to
power is more akin to Spinoza’s concept of conatus than it is to any
psychological drive.) Mollison further specifies that the eternal return
is an actualisation of a singularity – i.e., a point of inflection – which
involves aspects of evaluation and selection. He concludes by suggesting
that Deleuze conceived of temporality as the eternal actualisation of
difference.
4 Robert W. Luzecky
References
Deleuze, G. (1996), ‘Foreword’, in Éric Alliez, Capital Times: Tales from the
Conquest of Time, trans. Georges Van Den Abeele, Minneapolis: University of
Minnesota Press.
Deleuze, G. (2003), Kant’s Critical Philosophy: The Doctrine of the Faculties, trans.
Hugh Tomlinson and Barbara Habberjam, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota
Press.
Deleuze, G. (2007), ‘Occupy without Counting: Boulez, Proust, and Time’, in Two
Regimes of Madness: Texts and interviews 1975–1995, ed. David Lapoujade,
trans. Ames Hodges and Mike Taormina, South Pasadena: Semiotext[e].
Deleuze, G. and F. Guattari (1987), A Thousand Plateaus: Capitalism and
Schizophrenia, trans. Brian Massumi, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Simondon, G. (2020), Individuation in Light of Notions of Form and Information,
trans. Taylor Adkins, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
PART I
CONCEPTS OF TIME
Chapter 1
Time is Real: Deleuze and Guattari, from
Chaos to Complexity
Dorothea E. Olkowski
Creation?
Philosophy, as defined by Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari, is ‘the
art of forming, inventing, and fabricating concepts’ (1994: 4).1 More
specifically, it is ‘the discipline that involves creating concepts’, because
concepts are not ready-made, and even though they are incorporeal,
what we usually refer to as intellectual or mental, there is no heaven
of concepts; they must be created (1994: 5, 21). There are creators;
creators are not persons but personae, a force of ideas that provide a sig-
nature, a name like Descartes or Kant that is a cluster or assemblage of
concepts, and every concept is a multiplicity as there is no concept with
only one component. Every concept has some sort of history as well as
a becoming; it undergoes evolution, and so is both absolute with respect
to the problem it addresses but also relative to its components, as well
as infinite in its survol, its reach, but finite with respect to its Leibnizian
indiscernibility (Deleuze and Guattari 1994: 15–21). Although many
things can be said about this designation, what I wish to draw attention
to here is the problem of the creation of concepts. What does it mean to
say that the creation of concepts is possible? How can we justify even
the possibility of creation, not merely as a linguistic phenomenon but as
a reality, even if an incorporeal one?
The reason creation rises to the level of a problem has to do both with
Deleuze and Guattari’s own philosophy and with the mathematical and
scientific framework, which their philosophy must confront in utilising
the tools offered by the mathematics and cosmology upon which they are
reliant. Beginning with a schematic history of philo-scientific accounts
of the universe, and not simply of nature, western philosophy of science
was formalised by Plato’s (fourth century BC) and Ptolemy’s (100 AD)
models of the universe, both grounded in the idea of heavenly bodies
12 Dorothea E. Olkowski
moving in perfect circular motion guided by either Plato’s ‘pilot’ (in The
Statesman) or Ptolemy’s Aristotelean god’s realm of heavenly perfection
in which nothing that is true undergoes change. Much later (1687) there
is Newton’s similarly eternal and cyclical universe (inherited by Albert
Einstein) in which any event, no matter how improbable, must occur
an infinite number of times (Smolin 1999: 143–4). As the physicist Lee
Smolin sums this up: ‘[i]n a world of atoms governed by deterministic
laws, chance alone plays the role of the pilot who returns the universe
from time to time to an ordered state that makes life possible’ (144), but
only as an improbable fluctuation in an otherwise dying universe.
The point of this selective account is to take note that from Plato to
Einstein, physics posits a world governed by deterministic laws and
improbable events, and fails to describe a world in which things –
corporeal and incorporeal – arise and evolve; that is, the creation of
something new does not seem possible. This problem is further exac-
erbated by the nineteenth- century theory of thermodynamics which
postulates the law of entropy, which states that the disorder of systems
in the direction of equilibrium must always increase (Smolin 1999: 147).
The law of increasing entropy predicts the eventual heat death of the
universe because collections of atoms are more likely to arrive at a dis-
ordered state of equilibrium than an organised, creative configuration.
Together, the Newtonian worldview along with thermodynamics give us
a sad picture of reality as both deterministic and dead.
Deleuze famously critiques the Platonic view of the universe, directly
addressing the argument of The Statesman. The Statesman, the shepherd
of men, is well founded, but below him lie the auxiliaries and slaves,
and the evil power of simulacra and counterfeits (Deleuze 1990: 255–6).
The motivation for such divisions is, as Deleuze argues, ‘to distinguish
essence from appearance, intelligible from sensible, Idea from image,
original from copy and model from simulacrum’ (256). Plato’s goal,
according to Deleuze, is to distinguish good from bad copies: to dis-
tinguish well-founded copies, internally and spiritually balanced and
endowed with resemblance to the Idea, from simulacra engulfed in dis-
similarity, underhandedly failing to pass through the Idea and internally
unbalanced. It is of consequence in this model that at the top of the
hierarchy there is a knower who possesses knowledge of the unchang-
ing and eternal Idea. Below this is the possibility of right opinion, not
knowledge of the eternal but a good copy. Lowest is the imitator who
has access only to simulation due to their inability to master the eternal
and unchanging Idea or even right opinion. The imitator advocates for a
distortion that evades the equal, the Same and the Ideal, sinking into an
Time is Real 13
unlimited becoming that challenges the authority of the knower and the
known (Deleuze 1990: 258).
In the Platonic eternality, Justice is just and so the Same; the copy is
at least the Similar. Although Plato introduces this model, it is Aristotle
who codifies it through the division into genus and species, which delim-
ited and specified the role of representation and made it easier for
Christianity to celebrate the infinitely great of the genus of Being and the
infinitely small of species – all in God’s domain – to the exclusion of the
eccentric and the divergent (Deleuze 1990: 259).
Nietzsche’s attack on Platonism was supposed to have reversed it,
abolishing the eternal world of essences as well as its impoverished
bastard – the world of appearances. But Deleuze is not entirely satis-
fied with Nietzsche’s effort, which remains all too abstract, failing to
uncover Plato’s motivation. Thus the true overturning of this eternalist
model requires affirming the rights of simulacra to deny the claims to
truth of the original eternal Idea and its copy and assert the ‘triumph of
the false pretender’ (Deleuze 1990: 262). The resemblance of the similar
to the Same is abandoned for the sake of internalised difference, and the
identity of the Same is differentiated into the ‘identity’ that is the Being
of the Different, so that what is, is only as difference. As even Nietzsche
noted, under every formerly eternal foundation, there exists a more
profound subsoil, another cave, another subterranean world (Deleuze
1990: 263; Nietzsche, Beyond Good and Evil, sect. 289).
It might now seem to be the case that Deleuze has profoundly freed
his thought from the eternal and the inevitable or deterministic, but
we have yet to deal with the Newtonian version of the universe. The
question is what to make of Newtonian laws and absolute space and
time if simulation is now understood as the process of disguising, where
behind any mask is another and another, because, as Deleuze notes,
‘[s]imulation understood in this way is inseparable from eternal return’
(1990: 263). Wise to the implications of this, Deleuze quickly revises the
meaning of eternal return. It is not, he claims, the eternal return of the
Same, but the power of affirming chaos, an affirmation whose meaning
it is not a simple matter to discern. For Plato, chaos was defined in rela-
tion to order or laws; it is the ‘rebellious matter’ to be subjugated by the
Demiurge (Deleuze 1994: 68). Chaos can be currently defined in physics
as ‘a deterministic mechanism that generates the appearance of random-
ness’ and is sensitive to initial conditions (Casti 1994: 103). For Deleuze,
chaos is defined as ‘virtual chaos’, where virtuality is the ‘potential’
through which states of affairs take effect (Deleuze and Guattari 1994:
153). The task ahead is to connect this view of chaos from both early
14 Dorothea E. Olkowski
and late Deleuze texts to a new cosmology, one that is not situated in
relation to a timeless deterministic universe.
Time is Real
‘Time is real.’ When I spoke these words to an astrophysicist at a
seminar on cosmic and human time, h e – a long with several members
of the audience, which included a number of physicists – may have
thought, ‘no it’s not, time is only a psychological phenomenon’. This
is because, for the astrophysicist, time is an illusion, and temporal flow
and its somewhat recently revealed consequence – complexity – indicate
the existence of nothing more than a temporary fluctuation arising from
some special initial conditions in our region of an otherwise determinis-
tic universe governed by the time-reversible laws of classical mechanics.
This is what is called the Newtonian paradigm. Its conditions are that
the space under consideration – configuration space – is timeless, and
solving a specific set of equations gives the entire future of the system, a
system that exists in the present because the laws governing the system
are also timeless (Smolin 2014: 139). The effect of this paradigm is
that ‘time is inessential and can be removed from the description of
the world’, and the initial conditions of the universe determine the
future down to the smallest detail (167–8). And crucially, the laws of
Newtonian physics can be reversed. The initial conditions follow the
laws to a final configuration. Starting from that configuration, the laws
can be run in the opposite direction back to the initial conditions, so
that if it were possible to make ‘[f]ilmed motions of the whole solar
system’, then run them backward, the result would be an orbit allowed
by Newton’s laws that is indistinguishable from its forward motions
(111).2
This leaves us with the dispiriting notion that our sense of time as real
is nothing more than an illusion, that the real universe is timeless, and
that the so-called history of the universe is merely a system of causal
events in a block universe (Smolin 2014: 150–1). The concept of the
block universe allows for the treatment of time as a dimension of space,
a fourth dimension since ‘[a]n event taking place at a moment of time is
represented as a point in spacetime, and the history of a particle is traced
by a curve in spacetime called its worldline’ (151). In this geometricised
version of the universe, photons are represented as moving at 45 degree
angles, and other particles – b ecause they move more slowly than the
speed of light – are represented at steeper angles. Hermann Minkowski
devised this representation, the light cone, sometime between 1907 and
Time is Real 15
conditions (Casti 1994: 103). He begins his account with chaos, with
the appearance of randomness, which is to say, a less well-organised
sensibility knowing nothing about theories of matter or spirit, or reality
or ideality, and from this he articulates how such images may lose their
vitality.
All these images act and react upon one another in all their elementary
parts according to constant laws which I call laws of nature, and,; as a
perfect knowledge of these laws would probably allow us to calculate
and to foresee what will happen in each of these images, the future of the
images must be contained in their present and will add to them nothing
new. (Bergson 1988: 17)
If these images exist in a block universe and are the effect of reciprocal
actions and passions following deterministic laws of nature, then even if
they are initially apparently chaotic they should become highly o rdered
– even homogeneous – and this system would operate deterministically.
But evolution and creation call for intuition, and intuition falls within
duration, that which differs from matter but more profoundly differs
first from itself. Thus intuition’s third and possibly most significant
characteristic, Deleuze notes, is that it is the method that seeks differ-
ence, differences in nature or kind and articulations of the real (2004:
26). ‘Space breaks down into undifferentiated matter and differentiated
duration, and duration is differentiated into contraction and expansion’
(26–7); thus quality and quantity, instinct and intelligence, vital and
geometric order, metaphysics and science, are dualities that are tenden-
cies not opposites or contradictories. Duration is the change in nature,
quality, heterogeneity, and crucially, difference from itself, and intuition
takes advantage of this to return, to seek difference between two tenden-
cies, and so to reflect on its own images.
There is a fourth characteristic. Given that space is differentiated into
matter and duration, and duration is differentiated into contraction
and expansion, the method of intuition rediscovers the simple; that
is, what persists as a convergence of probabilities (Deleuze 2004: 27).
Deleuze points to the élan vital, the virtual chaos and its actualisation,
the prolongation of the past into the present, but Bergson does not
merely remain within biology, he also points to the universe that endures
because duration is not merely cognitive or psychological (28). ‘The
more we study the nature of time, the more we shall comprehend that
duration means invention, the creation of forms, the continual elabora-
tion of the absolutely new. The systems marked off by science endure
only because they are bound up inseparably with the rest of the universe’
20 Dorothea E. Olkowski
(Bergson 1983: 11), and only insofar as those systems are reintegrated
back into the ‘Whole’ – like our sun, which radiates heat and light into
the universe, and along this ‘very tenuous’ thread transmits, even to the
smallest particle of our world, the duration immanent to the whole of
the universe (10–11).
Deleuze affirms this Bergsonian method with the confirmation that
the reality of time is the affirmation of actualisation, the invention of
the virtual on any scale insofar as the virtual is the whole (2004: 30).
This is what makes it possible, in Bergson’s thought, for matter to be
the most relaxed degree of duration even as it returns and contracts
as differentiation into the past that is present and the past-present that
creates the temporally new and so creatively endures bound up with the
universe (31).
ast . . . I am trying the hypothesis that it [continuity] is real . . . If this
p
is real, the past is really known to the present . . . Then we must have an
immediate consciousness of the p ast . . . by four units, by eight units, by
sixteen units, etc. . . . Now, this is only true if the series be continuous.
Here, then, it seems to me, we have positive and tremendously strong
reason[s] for believing that time really is continuous. (CP 1.167, 1.168,
1.169)
For Peirce’s conception, just as for Bergson’s duration, continuity
arises from feeling, a present feeling immediately present in conscious-
ness as well as present memory and present suggestion, continuous
with one another. Peirce claims that according to this reasoning, space,
quality and other things, even all things, might be continuous, since,
after all, Peirce’s continuum is merely a discontinuous series with ‘addi-
tional possibilities’, and the best hypothesis is the one that ‘leaves open
the greatest field of possibilities’ (CP 1.170). And just as relevant is the
argument that when a portion of the mind acts on any other, it must be
immediately present to it, for all things ‘swim in continua’ (CP 1.171).
Real continuity arises from feeling or quality but it is a generality, a
general, because it is an absence of distinction of individuals and leaves
room for possible variables that cannot be exhausted by any multitude
of existents (CP 5.103, 5.431; Zalamea 2010: 10). This structure is
formalised in Peirce’s semiotics and his argument for the character of
continuity, wherein parts and wholes are regularised. But also, and
perhaps unexpectedly, it has to do with evolution, that is, diversifica-
tion, the passage from the unorganised to the organised, from what we
have called chaos to complexity, which Peirce refers to as an increase in
variety (CP 1.174).9 Can we say that this is crucial for an open system?
As Peirce argues, ‘were things simpler, was variety less in the original
nebula from which the solar system is supposed to have grown than it
is now when the land and sea swarms with animal and vegetable forms
. . .?’ (CP 1.174).
This view of nature and the universe, this theory, this idea of continu-
ity and evolution on all scales was and continues to be strongly opposed
by the scientific ‘algebraical apparatus of mechanical law’, which has
been asserted to be the one and only, the ‘very idea of law’, because laws
are absolute and cannot grow (CP 1.174, 1.175). The problem with this
view is that it makes the laws of nature blind and inexplicable; how can
we possibly explain the universe, the formation of its galaxies, planets,
stars and life itself on the basis of a single chance, a single role of the
dice? Whereas if continuity and the evolution of laws are real, there is
no reason not to think that the universe has undergone ‘a continuous
22 Dorothea E. Olkowski
Notes
1. Some of the material in this essay appeared initially in my book Deleuze,
Bergson, Merleau-Ponty: The Logic and Pragmatics of Creation, Affective Life,
and Perception (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2021).
2. Newtonian mechanics, quantum mechanics and Einstein’s Special and General
Relativity are all time-reversible (see Smolin 2014: 112).
3. Smolin shows that the block universe depends on the relativity of simultaneity.
4. The statement is that of Rudolf Clausius and is cited in Atkins 1984: 25.
5. See Schneider and Sagan 2005: 26. ‘An example of a closed system is a chemical
reaction in a closed flask where excess heat from the reaction is permitted to
move outside the flask into the surroundings.’
6. See Schneider and Sagan 2005: 28. ‘A change in one variable may lead near-
linearly to a change in another variable; or it may trigger unpredictable changes
that cannot be modeled with relatively simple mathematical equations.’
7. These accusations continue to the present day.
8. References for Peirce are to The Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce,
abbreviated to CP followed by volume and page number.
9. Peirce attributes this idea to the advocate of evolutionary theory, Herbert
Spencer.
10. Deleuze does not appear to follow Peirce into the ‘logic of vagueness’, bypass-
ing excluding the law of the excluded middle in favour of the concept of virtual-
ity.
References
Atkins, P. W. (1984), The Second Law: Energy, Chaos, and Form, San Francisco:
W. H. Freeman and Co.
Bergson, H. (1946), The Creative Mind, trans. Mabelle L. Andison, New York:
Citadel Press.
Bergson, H. (1983), Creative Evolution, trans. Arthur Mitchell, Lanham, MD:
University Press of America.
Bergson, H. (1988), Matter and Memory, trans. Nancy Margaret Paul and W. Scott
Palmer, New York: Zone Books.
Canales, J. (2015), The Physicist and the Philosopher: Einstein, Bergson, and the
Debate that Changed Our Understanding of Time, Princeton: Princeton University
Press.
Casti, J. (1994), Complexification: Explaining a Paradoxical World through the
Science of Surprise, New York: Harper Collins.
Cortês, M. and L. Smolin (2018), ‘Reversing the Irreversible: From Limit Cycles to
Emergent Time Symmetry’, Phys. Rev. D 97, 026004.
Deleuze, G. (1994), Difference and Repetition, trans. Paul Patton, New York:
Columbia University Press.
Deleuze, G. (2004), Desert Islands and Other Texts, 1953–1974, ed. David
Lapoujade, trans. Michael Taormina, Los Angeles, Semiotext(e).
Deleuze, G. and F. Guattari (1994), What Is Philosophy?, trans. Hugh Tomlinson
and Graham Burchell, New York: Columbia University Press.
Peirce, C. S. (1931–35, 1958), The Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, ed.
Charles Hartshorne, Paul Weiss and Arthur Burks, Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
Peirce, C. S. (1976), New Elements of Mathematics, The Hague: Mouton.
26 Dorothea E. Olkowski
Thomas Nail
We talk about the movement of time but does time move, or does
movement occur in time? This is a fundamental question in the philoso-
phy of time that philosophers and physicists are still trying to answer.
Interestingly, one of the most original and shockingly contemporary
answers to this question was given by the first-century Roman poet
Lucretius almost two millennia ago. Lucretius believed that nature was
composed of continually moving matter whose spontaneous swerving
occurs in ‘no determinate time and space’ (incerto tempore, incertisque
loci). Some ancient philosophers and scientists believed that time was
linear, others that it was cyclical. Virtually no one thought it was ‘inde-
terminate’. So, unfortunately, Lucretius’ theory of time sounded so
strange that it was either ignored or misinterpreted as a reference to the
soul’s freedom.
It was not until the French philosopher Gilles Deleuze returned to this
idea in his 1969 book, Logique du sens, that Lucretius’ theory of time’s
‘swerve’ was taken seriously. In the appendix of his book, Deleuze was
the first to argue that Lucretius had put forward an indeterminate (non-
linear and non-chronological) theory of time. Deleuze argued that the
swerve of falling atoms in Lucretius’ philosophy was not the result of a
determinate collision with other atoms but was caused by a vital force or
conatus immanent to them. This was a brilliant and vital insight but also
a strange one. Lucretius was a materialist, not a vitalist, and never used
the word conatus to describe the swerve of matter. Therefore, it is hard
to reconcile Deleuze’s conatus theory of the temporality of the swerve
with Lucretius’ text. It is even harder to reconcile Deleuze’s ‘static’ view
of time in Difference and Repetition with Lucretius’ kinetic materialism.
Deleuze explicitly subordinates movement to time: ‘The [third] synthesis
is necessarily static, since time is no longer subordinated to movement;
time is the most radical form of change, but the form of change does not
28 Thomas Nail
The consequence of this for the monads as well as for the atoms would
therefore be – s ince they are in constant m
otion – t hat neither monads nor
atoms exist, but rather disappear in the straight line: for the solidity of the
The Movement of Time 29
atom does not even enter into the picture, insofar as it is only considered
as something falling in a straight line. (Marx 2006: 111; emphasis added)
Marx uses dialectics to completely sublate the atom’s discreteness into
its fall, swerve and movement. Deleuze was likely the first to pick up
on this idea’s wild originality and run with it. In The Logic of Sense he
does not credit Marx explicitly, but in Nietzsche and Philosophy he does
provide a short note saying that this was where he got the idea (Deleuze
1983: 6–7).
1. Lucretius does not use the word ‘atom’ and never says it is
discrete
Deleuze, like virtually every other commentator, talks about ‘atoms’ in
Lucretius. Still, Lucretius never used the Greek word atomos, nor did
he use the Latin word atomus, which Cicero created later to talk about
atoms. Instead, Lucretius multiplied his terms for matter, complicating
any unified concept of matter in his work.
Furthermore, in all his terms for matter, Lucretius never says that
matter is discrete or that it is particle-like. This makes the following
claim by Deleuze not quite textually accurate:
The sensible object is endowed with sensible parts, but there is a minimum
sensible which represents the smallest part of the object; similarly, the atom
is endowed with parts that are thought, but there is a minimum thought
which represents the smallest part of the atom . . . the indivisible atom is
formed of thought minima. (Deleuze 1990: 268)
There is absolutely zero textual evidence in De Rerum Natura (The
Nature of Things) to suggest that Lucretius thought that atoms have
‘parts’. Firstly, this is because Lucretius does not use the word atom or
an equivalent. Second, even if this were the definition of an atom for
Epicurus, it would not necessarily be true for Lucretius. Deleuze does
not offer any source citation or translation to support this claim either.
32 Thomas Nail
Lucretius indeed believes that one cannot see corpora or bodily matters
with the eye because they are processes, not objects. However, this does
not mean that matter is thought. Deleuze offers no textual support from
De Rerum Natura for this claim because there is none. Instead, he cites
Epicurus as saying that ‘the atom moves “as swiftly as thought”’ (1990:
269). He then extrapolates this to mean that the atom’s reality is in
thought. If Marx mixed ancient materialism with Hegel, Deleuze mixed
it with Spinoza. Deleuze had some creative insights but also made some
wildly non-textual claims. ‘In agreement with the nature of the atom,
this minimum of continuous time refers to the apprehension of thought’
(269). Deleuze tries to make matter simultaneously thought. Although
this position is consistent with Spinoza, Deleuze does not directly credit
him here. We may want to adopt this Spinozist interpretation for other
reasons, but it is not something Lucretius said. It is inconsistent with
Lucretius’ philosophy because there are no atoms, no parts, and cer-
tainly no thought-atoms. My worry about this claim is that it heads
in an idealist direction and threatens to transform Lucretius’ radical
materialism into an idealism or panpsychism (see Nail 2018b, 2018c,
2020; Nail et al. 2019).
Only force can be related to another force. (As Marx says when he inter-
prets atomism, ‘Atoms are their own unique objects and can relate only
to themselves’ – Marx, The Difference Between the Democritean and
Epicurean Philosophy of Nature. But the question is; can the basic notion
of atom accommodate the essential relation which is attempted to it? The
concept only becomes coherent if one thinks of force instead of atom. For
the notion of atom cannot in itself contain the difference necessary for the
affirmation of such a relation, difference in and according to the essence.
Thus atomism would be a mask for an incipient dynamism. (Deleuze 1983:
6–7)
34 Thomas Nail
refer as past nature. The whole thing is continually different from itself
– but tending regionally toward energetic dissipation (Bergson 1988: 47,
197; 2007: 46, 155).
In my reading, Lucretius was right about the primacy of movement
over time. Deleuze got very close but ended up inserting the ideas of
conatus, vitality, power and force. He even claims that this dynamic
time is ‘necessarily static, since time is no longer subordinated to move-
ment’ (1994: 89). The form of change does not change, and so Deleuze
calls it a ‘static genesis’ in The Logic of Sense. Deleuze’s idea that time
is formal and static sounds much more like the strobe-like ‘occasions’
or ‘Cambridge changes’ of Alfred North Whitehead than like Bergson
or Lucretius.3 According to Whitehead, change is only ‘the difference
between actual occasions comprised in some determined event’, and
thus it is ‘impossible to attribute “change” to any actual entity’ (1978:
73, 59). ‘Thus an actual entity never moves: It is where it is and what it
is’ (Whitehead 2014: 73). For Whitehead, change and motion relate to
a succession of actual entities and are constituted only by the differences
among them. Every entity is ‘what it is’, and it ‘becomes’ as the whole
of reality enters a succession of different states, but technically nothing
ever changes or moves.
In this matter, there is this, too, that I want you to understand, that when
the first bodies are moving straight downward through the void by their
own weight, at times completely undetermined and in undetermined places
they swerve a little from their course, but only so much as you could call a
change of motion.
Indeterminate
Conclusion
At the turn of the eighteenth century, the philosophy of ‘forces’ faced
a brutal empiricist critique from Hume and others. Empiricists deemed
forces metaphysical entities with no reality. However, it was not until
nearly the end of the eighteenth century that Immanuel Kant began
to replace the metaphysics of force with a new ontologically primary
descriptor: time.
At least since Aristotle, time had been considered ontologically sub-
ordinate to motion and other terms. It was not until Kant that one
of the most historically derivative ontological categories, time, became
the most primary. After Kant, almost every nineteenth- and twentieth-
century ontologist took up the ontological primacy of time.
Modern ontology became increasingly critical of the idea that space,
eternity and force were ontologically foundational categories. Time,
however, remained mostly immune to the same critiques. Time became
the new name for b eing – u
shering in an age of generalised chronophilia.
With only a few exceptions, almost all modern ontologies of the eight-
eenth through twentieth centuries, in one way or another, accept the
reality and foundational nature of time. Everything occurs in time, but
time itself was not created by or derived from anything else.
This chapter’s thesis is that time, like space, eternity and force, is a
fundamentally kinetic process. Time is derived from motion in at least
three ways.
First, by definition, time is a division between three tenses: past, present
and future; before, during, after. Without such a division, it does not
make sense to use the word time without confusion. Time, as a divided
and differential phenomenon, presupposes that which it divides, namely
the flow and swerve of motion. If temporal division were fundamental,
being would already be divided, and movement would be reduced to a
mere juxtaposition of vacuum-sealed fragments, as Whitehead and the
occasionalists describe. Nothing would secure or allow for transition
between divided points. It would be a ‘static genesis’. Time, in my view,
is therefore derivative of movement. I have tried to show the origins of
this idea in Lucretius’ theory of the swerve and the simulacra. Motion is
how metastable moments emerge and pass.
Second, contemporary accelerationist cosmology confirms the deriva-
tive nature of time. Before the existence of the known universe, most
physicists postulate a rapid unfolding of matter (as quantum fields)
moving (exploding) o utward – in a stochastic process of differentiation
and combination. All forms of current division and discreteness come
42 Thomas Nail
Notes
1. This can be seen in several essays in Ellenzweig and Zammito 2017.
2. For a wonderful chapter arguing that time is only matter in motion see Righini
Bonelli 1973.
3. For a more detailed account of the difference between my process philosophy and
Bergson’s, Whitehead’s and Deleuze’s, see Nail 2018b, chapter three.
4. My reading of the swerve differs from Althusser’s since it is relational and not
random or ‘aleatory’, as Althusser calls it (2006: 163).
5. Plotinus has an interesting theory of the soul as more like a movement than a
thing, but for him, the soul is not material and certainly doesn’t swerve.
6. Dan Smith elaborates on the characteristics of simulacra excellently in Smith
2012: 12–16. See also Deleuze’s account in The Logic of Sense (1990: 257–67)
and Difference and Repetition (1994: 69).
7. This is what Susskind calls ‘black hole complementarity’ (2008: 237).
References
Althusser, L. (2006), Philosophy of the Encounter: Later Writings, 1978–1987,
London: Verso.
Bergson, H. (1988), Matter and Memory, trans. Nancy Margaret Paul and W. Scott
Palmer, New York: Zone Books.
Bergson, H. (2007), The Creative Mind: An Introduction to Metaphysics, New
York: Dover Publications.
Deleuze, G. (1983), Nietzsche and Philosophy, trans. Hugh Tomlinson, New York:
Columbia University Press.
Deleuze, G. (1990), The Logic of Sense, trans. Mark Lester with Charles Stivale,
New York: Columbia University Press.
Deleuze, G. (1994), Difference and Repetition, trans. Paul Patton, New York:
Columbia University Press.
Ellenzweig, S. and J. H. Zammito, eds. (2017), The New Politics of Materialism:
History, Philosophy, Science, London: Routledge.
44 Thomas Nail
Lucretius (2003), On the Nature of Things (De Rerum Natura), trans. Walter
Englert, Newburyport, MA: Focus.
Marx, K. (2006), The First Writings of Karl Marx, ed. Paul M. Schafer, New York:
Ig Publishing.
Nail, T. (2018a), Lucretius I: An Ontology of Motion, Edinburgh: Edinburgh
University Press.
Nail, T. (2018b), Being and Motion, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Nail, T. (2018c), ‘The Ontology of Motion’, Qui Parle: Critical Humanities and
Social Sciences 27 (1): 47–76.
Nail, T. (2020), Lucretius II: An Ethics of Motion, Edinburgh: Edinburgh University
Press.
Nail, T., C. N. Gamble and J. S. Hanan, ‘What is New Materialism?’, Angelaki:
Journal of the Theoretical Humanities, 24 (6): 111–34.
Righini Bonelli, Maria Luisa (1973), ‘Time and Motion: Reflections on the Non-
existence of Time’, trans. Thomas B. Settle, in Joseph Needham, Mikuláš Teich
and Robert M. Young, eds., Changing Perspectives in the History of Science:
Essays in Honour of Joseph Needham, London: Heinemann Educational.
Rovelli, C. (1998), ‘“Incerto Tempore, Incertisque Loci”: Can We Compute the
Exact Time at Which a Quantum Measurement Happens?’, Foundations of
Physics, 28 (1031–43).
Rovelli, C. (2018), The Order of Time, London: Penguin.
Siegel, E. (2019), ‘What Is The Smallest Possible Distance In The Universe?’, Forbes
Magazine, 26 June.
Smith, D. W. (2012), Essays on Deleuze, Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.
Spencer, J. M. (2014), ‘Left Atomism: Marx, Badiou, and Althusser on the Greek
Atomists’, Theory & Event 17 (3).
Susskind, L. (2008), The Black Hole War: My Battle with Stephen Hawking to
Make the World Safe for Quantum Mechanics, New York: Back Bay Books.
Whitehead, A. N. (1978), Concept of Nature, Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Whitehead, A. N. (2014), Process and Reality, New York: Free Press.
Chapter 3
The Pure and Empty Form of Time:
Deleuze’s Theory of Temporality
Daniel W. Smith
relations), and one part does not contain another part; what contains
parts is always a whole, even if this whole is itself a part in relation
to another whole. Intensive quantity, by contrast, is a zero–unit rela-
tion. What distinguishes two intensive quantities is the variable distance
through which one comprehends their distance from zero intensity,
although these distances are non- decomposable. The distance of 40
degrees from zero is ‘greater’ than the distance of 30 degrees from zero,
but neither of these distances is divisible into parts (though the function
of thermometers is to convert intensive qualities into extensive units)
(see Knowles Middleton 1966). If time is the measure of movement,
then time becomes something different when it measures intensive move-
ments rather than extensive movements.
Plotinus’ analysis of the soul, Deleuze argues, was modelled on the
concept of intensive quantity, and his greatness was to have incorporated
the intensive movements of the soul into his vision of the movement of
the ‘One’, with its emanative processes of procession and conversion.
Plotinus’ dialectic proceeds in terms of a series of powers, beginning with
the One, and proceeding through thought, the soul, nature, phenomena
and so on (Plotinus 1991: 213–32). Intensive movement is an ordination
of non-decomposable distances, that is, an ideal fall (French: chute,
‘decrease’ or ‘drop’) that marks the relation of a series of powers to
zero.5 Time emerges as the measure of intensive movement in two ways.
Eternity (aeon) designates the fact that all ‘powers’ are each internal to
the other insofar as they are ‘One’. The ‘now’ (nun) is a privileged point
in the internal movement of the soul that is intrinsically distinguishable
from other points thorough their differing degrees of power, dividing
into a pure past and a pure future, while nonetheless remaining united in
the One. This act of distinction is thus at the same time a synthesis, and
Deleuze argues that the Neo-Platonists were the first to see that time is
inseparable from an act of synthesis.6
What one sees in both Plato and Plotinus, then, is the formation of
an originary time that serves as a measure for movement, whether it
is derived from the extensive movements of the cosmos (Plato) or the
intensive movements of the soul (Plotinus). In both cases, the result
was a hierarchisation of movements depending on their proximity to or
distance from the eternal, an originary time marked by privileged posi-
tions in the cosmos or privileged moments in the soul. The discovery of
this invariant was itself the discovery of the true, since truth required a
universally commensurable time and space over which it could govern.
One should note that the common distinction between ‘objective’ and
‘subjective’ time does not mark a break with the ancient subordination
48 Daniel W. Smith
of time to movement. Objective ‘clock time’ (or physical time) and the
subjective experience of ‘time consciousness’ both measure movement,
the sole difference being the type of movement. Objective movement
measures the extensive movement of objects in the cosmos, whereas
subjective movement measures the intensive passage from one state to
another, even though the extensive object and the intensive state are only
artificial ‘snapshots’ or ‘cuts’ extracted from the transition or passage of
time.7 Moreover, it is clear that modernity no less than antiquity still
subordinates time to movement: the International System of Units (SI)
defines a second in terms of the motion of a caesium atom (Crease 2011:
252, 264). In physics, special relativity had its roots in the problem of
the synchronisation of clocks, and if ‘time moves more slowly’ for an
object moving faster than another object, it is because the clocks on
each object are measuring different movements.8 In this sense, special
relativity remained tied to the ancient conception of time and might
even be said to have completed it.9 Despite these practical exigencies,
the fundamental issue in the theory of time is not the distinction between
objective and subjective time but rather the relation between time and
movement.
sensation that fills time has an intensive quantity) (Deleuze 1994: 38).
Permanence, finally, is the rule of what endures for all times (substance),
which constitutes the ground of both successions and simultaneities. Put
summarily, succession is the rule of what is in different times; simultane-
ity is the rule of what is at the same time; and permanence is the rule
of what is for all times. As an individual, for instance, I exist in time as
something permanent that has simultaneous states and that successively
passes from one state to another.
Yet succession, simultaneity and permanence are all modes or rela-
tions of time; they are not time itself. When Kant defines time as the
immutable form of what changes, he tells us repeatedly that ‘time cannot
by itself be perceived’.26 Because I exist in time, I am eaten away and
worn down by a time that I cannot perceive. Time is ‘no less capable of
dissolving and destroying individuals than of constituting them tempo-
rarily’ (Deleuze 1994: 38). In a sense, the form of time dis-integrates: it
devours succession, it devours simultaneity, and it devours permanence.
From the viewpoint of succession, time is a straight line which the parts
of time are unmade at the moment they are made (elles se défont à mesure
qu’elles se font). From the viewpoint of simultaneity, time is an instant
that, in terms of content, is emptied out at moment it is being filled (un
instant qui se vide à mesure qu’il se remplit). From the viewpoint of per-
manence, time decomposes an enduring substance into something that is
ceaselessly undoing and emptying itself (ne cesse pas de se défaire et de
se vider).27 Proust would later write, ‘Time, which is usually not visible,
in order to become so seeks out bodies and, wherever it finds them, seizes
upon them in order to project its magic lantern on them’, quartering the
features of an aging face according to its ‘distorting perspective’ (Proust
1993: 342, 344; translation modified; cited in Deleuze 2000: 18, 160).
The only way to extract ourselves from the disintegrating power of
time is through the power of synthesis. As Kant shows in the first
Transcendental Deduction, synthesis is a triple o peration – apprehension,
reproduction and r ecognition – that is carried out by the activity of the
‘I think’ or consciousness (1929: 129–38, A98–110). Since every sensa-
tion that appears in time is a manifold and has a multiplicity of parts,
consciousness must synthesise these parts in an act of apprehension; it
must also reproduce or remember preceding parts when the following
ones appear if a synthesis is to take place; and this sensible complex of
parts can only be recognised if it is related to the form of the object (the
‘object = x’, which is the objective correlate of the ‘I think’). Synthesis is
an activity – o
r in Kant’s language, a s pontaneity – that is exercised by
the mind on both the parts and the content of time.
54 Daniel W. Smith
But what Kant’s analysis makes clear is that the new status of time
introduces into the individual a profound ‘fracture’ (fêlure) – a scission
between the disintegrative and synthetic aspects of time that Deleuze
summarises in a second poetic formula taken from Rimbaud: ‘I is
another’ (Rimbaud 1975: 101, 103).28 On the one hand, my existence is
that of ‘a passive, receptive, phenomenal subject appearing within time’,
a time that is being undone at the moment it is constituted (Deleuze
1994: 86). On the other hand, the unity of my experience in time
depends on the active and spontaneous temporal syntheses carried out
by the a priori categories of the transcendental ‘I think’. For Deleuze,
this fracture between the passive self (intuitions in time) and the active
self (the categories of the understanding) marks ‘a precise moment in
Kantianism, a furtive and explosive moment that is not even continued
by Kant, much less by the post-Kantians’ (58). Whereas Kant himself,
as well as post-Kantians such as Fichte and Hegel, would tend to focus
primarily on the ‘I think’ and the ‘transcendental unity of apperception’,
Deleuze’s analyses will attempt to penetrate the passive self and the pure
form of time.29 In other words, Deleuze will ultimately carry the Kantian
revolution in a different direction than Kant himself.
Consider a moment in the unfolding of the universe, that is, a snapshot that
exists independently of any consciousness. Then we shall try conjointly to
56 Daniel W. Smith
summon another moment brought as close as possible to the first, and thus
have a minimum of time enter into the world without allowing the faintest
glimmer of memory to go with this. We shall see that this is impossible.
Without an elementary memory that connects the two moments, there will
be only one or the other, consequently a single instant, no before and after,
no succession, no time. (Bergson 1965: 48)
In other words, for the modalities of time to appear, there must be a third
thing that retains a ‘first’ determination when the ‘second’ determination
appears – in other words, that synthesises the two determinations. In
Difference and Repetition, Deleuze will outline three different syntheses
of time, and it is this first synthesis that constitutes the foundation of
time under the modality of succession.
the absolutely new’ (1911: 13). The absolutely new entails what Anti-
Oedipus calls ‘a rupture with causality’ (Deleuze and Guattari 1983:
377–8). If effects pre-exist in their causes, then causal processes can only
give rise to things that are new in number, but not new in k ind – the
future is already contained in the past. The third synthesis, by contrast,
requires a break with the past, since it concerns the conditions for the
production of genuine novelty (Bergson) or creativity (Whitehead). The
third synthesis constitutes a ‘pure’ future that breaks with its grounding
in the past and its foundation in habit: Nietzsche’s untimely or Butler’s
erewhon (Deleuze 1994: xx–xxi, 285).
Compared to the concise analysis of the second synthesis provided
in the third chapter of Difference and Repetition, the discussion of the
third synthesis can seem somewhat disjointed and unfocused, moving
from Descartes and Kant to Hölderlin’s analysis of Greek tragedy to
Nietzsche’s concept of the eternal return. But in fact it is the entirety
of Deleuze’s oeuvre that constitutes an analysis of the third synthesis.
In Difference and Repetition, for instance, Deleuze argues that we need
to replace the possible–real opposition with the virtual–actual couple
in order to account for the form of time. In the possible, everything is
already given, and the possible simply has existence added to it when
it is ‘realised’: the real resembles the possible and does not produce
the new. But the virtual is constituted by difference, and in becoming
‘actualised’ it differentiates itself: the actual differs from the virtual, and
the actualisation of the virtual is the production of difference (Deleuze
1994: 211–12). What Deleuze calls simulacra are ‘excessive systems’ in
which the different is linked to the different in order to produce the dif-
ferent (115). Similarly, A Thousand Plateaus is an analysis of manifolds
or multiplicities, and Deleuze argues that it is the relation between
manifolds that is an act of becoming that creates the new.44
Although Deleuze’s entire philosophy can be seen as an exploration of
the third synthesis of time, it is nonetheless worth examining the quite
different presentations of the third synthesis that appear in Difference
and Repetition and The Time-Image (the latter book does not in fact
utilise the term ‘synthesis’).
the beginning and end ‘rhyme’ with each other, atoning for injustice,
whereas Sophocles is the first tragedian to un-curve time in an aberrant
movement in which the beginning and the end no longer rhyme but
unravel in a straight line: Oedipus’ long wandering is the incessant
march of a slow death. But it is Shakespeare’s Hamlet who is the first
hero that truly needed the pure form of time in order to act: the action
(avenging his father) marks a ‘caesura’ within the form of time between
a before and an after that is productive of something new. The before
appears in the form of an act that is ‘too big’ for Hamlet, and he remains
in a past disconnected from the present (second synthesis); the caesura is
the moment of metamorphosis, where Hamlet finally becomes capable
of the act and equal to it (first synthesis); but the after (third synthesis)
is revealed to be the production of something new that destroys both
the condition (the past) and the agent (the present): Hamlet must die.46
Yet Deleuze, following Blanchot, notes that death has two aspects:
the first is the disappearance of the person, but the second is ‘the state
of free differences when they are no longer subject to the form imposed
on them by an I or an ego’ (1994: 113). The latter ‘death’ is the object
of the third synthesis: a domain of singularities and events that are
both pre-individual and impersonal, and thus and irreducible to the self
(Deleuze 1990: 177).47 Life, in this sense, is coextensive with death: life
is traversed by ‘states of free differences’ that destabilise the organisation
of the organism as well as the identity of the self, while at the same time
producing a new self and a new body (Deleuze 1994: 113; Somers-Hall
2013: 95–6). This ‘death of the self’ is the correlate to the ‘death of
God’. If the order of God can be defined in terms of the identity of God
as the ultimate foundation, the identity of the world as the ambient
environment, the identity of the person as a well-founded agent and the
identity of bodies as the base, then the third synthesis entails the death
of god, the destruction of the world, the dissolution of the self and the
dis-integration of the b
ody – but always in terms of a new self (affects
and percepts), a new body (intensities and becomings) and ultimately the
creation of a new world, a chaosmos (singularities and events) (Deleuze
1990: 292).48
Difference and Repetition presents Nietzsche’s concept of the eternal
return as the highest expression of the third synthesis, but Deleuze inter-
prets the eternal return not as a return of the same but as the repetition
of the different.49 Zarathustra went through a transformation similar
to that of Hamlet. In the before, Zarathustra is incapable of an act, the
death of god (‘The Convalescent’); in the during – or the caesura – he
becomes equal to the act (‘On Involuntary Bliss’), though he feels the
62 Daniel W. Smith
hour has not yet come and still conceives of the eternal return as a
return of the Same; but in the after, which would have been presented
in the unwritten part of Thus Spoke Zarathustra, Zarathustra must
die, because ultimately the eternal return only allows the return of dif-
ferences, and mercilessly eliminates the identity of the hero (the second
sense of death) (Deleuze 1994: 298–9).50 In the third synthesis, the form
of time is characterised by a totality that is divided into a series (before,
caesura, after) that produces a pure order that is constitutive of the new.
The eternal return, Deleuze writes, ‘is present in every metamorphosis
. . . It is related to a world of differences implicated one in the other, to a
complicated, properly chaotic world without identity’ (1994: 57).
truth of the truthful person, or with the form of the true. If one makes
these modifications in the concept of the truth itself, one could say that
philosophy, science and art, as powers of the false, are nothing other than
enterprises in the creation of truth within the pure form of time.61
This is only a brief overview of the three syntheses that constitute the
pure and empty form of time.62 When time is freed from its subordina-
tion to movement, its a priori determinations of time are fixed or held,
as though in a photo or freeze-frame. The first synthesis provides the
foundation of time in the passing present, while the second synthesis
provides its ground in the pure past. In the third synthesis, however,
the ground is superseded by a groundlessness, a sans-fond, a universal
un-grounding in which the freeze-frame begins to move once more.
The extreme formality of the form of time, in other words, is there to
produce the formless, that is, the new, difference-in-itself. The system of
the future is ‘the deployment and explication of the multiple, of the dif-
ferent, and of the fortuitous’, it concerns ‘excessive systems’ (simulacra)
that link the different with the different (Deleuze 1994: 115). But this is
where time forms a circle again, for the third synthesis affects a world
that has rid itself of the condition and the agent, a chaos – even if these
singularities are taken up by the first two syntheses, and the singular is
rendered regular and ordinary. ‘This is how the story of time ends: by
undoing its too well centred natural or physical circle and forming a
straight line which then, led by its own length, reconstitutes an eternally
decentred circle’ (115).
Notes
1. Aristotle, Physics, Book 4, Chapter 11, 219b5–8: ‘time is the number of move-
ment in respect of before and after’.
2. See Leibniz, Letter to Arnauld, 30 April 1687, where Leibniz faults the ancients
for substituting a concept of ‘metempsychosis’ for a ‘metaschematism’ [metem-
psychosis pro metaschematismis].
3. One of the classic analyses of intensive quantities is the ‘Anticipations of
Perception’ section of Kant’s first critique, which recapitulates a long tradition.
See Kant 1929: 201–8, B207–18. Deleuze takes up the distinction in chapter
four of Difference and Repetition, ‘The Asymmetrical Synthesis of the Sensible’
(1994: 222–61).
4. See Duhem 1954: 112. ‘Diderot used to ask jokingly how many snowballs
would be required to heat an oven.’ Deleuze refers to this anecdote in his
seminar of 20 March 1984. Deleuze’s seminars can be accessed at ‘The Deleuze
Seminars’ project, deleuze.cla.purdue.edu.
5. On the notion of an ideal fall, see Plotinus 1991: 236. ‘Nature, asked why it
brings forth its works, might answer (if it cared to listen and to speak): . . .
“Whatever comes into being is my vision, seen in my silence, the vision that
belongs to my character who, sprung from vision, am vision-loving and create
The Pure Form of Time 67
vision by the vision-seeing faculty in me. The mathematicians from their vision
draw their figures: but I draw nothing: I gaze and the figures of the material
world take being as if they fell from my contemplation”’ (emphasis added). The
rejection of ‘drawing’ marks Plotinus’ distance from Plato’s dialectic, since the
latter entails a ‘real’ fall of the intelligible into the sensible.
6. Deleuze discusses the Platonic and Neo- Platonic conceptions of time in a
remarkable series of seminars from 7 February 1984 to 27 March 1984, which
include analyses that have no correlate in Deleuze’s published texts.
7. See Bergson 1965: 6. ‘If we go looking in time for features like those of space
[or movement] . . . we shall not have pushed on to time itself.’
8. See Gallison 2004, chapter 5, ‘Einstein’s Clocks’. Einstein’s work in the Swiss
patent office put him in a position ‘to seize clock coordination as the principled
starting point of relativity’ (260).
9. Rovelli suggests that, in physics, it was general relativity that finally brought
about ‘the destruction of the notion of time’ as a measure of movement in
favour of pure change or pure ‘events’ (2018: 96–7).
10. Deleuze suggests that the entirety of Aristotle’s c orpus – metaphysics, physics,
ethics and so on – c ould be read from the viewpoint of aberrant movements; see
the seminar lecture of 28 February 1984.
11. For a helpful discussion, see Paul Krause, ‘The Fall of the Soul from Plotinus to
Augustine’, online at Voegelin View (voegelinview.com/the-fall-of-soul-from-
plotinus-to-augustine).
12. On Chinese conceptions of time, see Hui 2016: 210–11, and his references to
the works of Marcel Granet and François Jullien.
13. In Catholic missals, the term ‘ordinary time’ (tempus per annum) refers to
the part of the liturgical year that falls outside the two primary seasons of
Christmastide and Eastertide, with their respective preparatory seasons of
Advent and Lent.
14. Newton noted his own inversion of the movement/time relation: ‘Absolute,
true, and mathematical time, of itself, and from its own nature, flows equably
without relation to anything external, and by another name is called duration:
relative, apparent, and common time, is some sensible and external (whether
accurate or unequable) measure of duration by the means of motion, which is
commonly used instead of true time; such as an hour, a day, a month, a year’
(1934: 6; 77 in the original Motte translation).
15. See Weber 2002, as well as Deleuze’s seminar of 27 March 1984.
16. Deleuze, seminar of 7 February 1984.
17. Book Two of Being and Time recapitulates, in temporal terms, the analysis of
‘everydayness’ provided in Book One.
18. Deleuze elucidates these themes in his seminars of 17 April 1984 and 4 May
1984.
19. Deleuze’s most complete analysis of Kant’s contribution to the theory of time
can be found in his seminar of 17 April 1984, to which the following analysis is
indebted.
20. Shakespeare, Hamlet, Act 1, Scene 5.
21. For instance, the Gospel of Luke famously dates the beginning of the preaching
of John the Baptist by contextualising it in a nexus of reigning officials in civil
and religious institutions: ‘In the fifteenth year of the reign of Tiberius Caesar,
Pontius Pilate being governor of Judaea, and Herod being tetrarch of Galilee,
and his brother Philip tetrarch of Ituraea and of the region of Trachonitis, and
Lysanias the tetrarch of Abilene, Annas and Caiaphas being the high priests,
the word of God came unto John the son of Zacharias in the wilderness’ (Luke
3:1–2). In the ‘Christian’ calendar, time begins with the reign of Christ.
68 Daniel W. Smith
22. See Kosmin 2018. There were no ‘end times’ until the constitution of an ordi-
nary linear time in the Seleucid empire (312 to 63 BCE), and Kosmin shows that
apocalyptic eschatologies – such as the biblical Book of Daniel (c. 165 BCE),
which was fiercely anti-Seleucid – c an be seen as subversive attempts to contest
the imperial institution of ordinary time.
23. Kant 1929: 76, A32/B48: ‘The concept of motion, as alteration of place, is pos-
sible only through and in the representation of time.’
24. See Kant 1929: 214, A183/B226: ‘If we ascribe succession to time itself, we
must think yet another time, in which the sequence would be possible . . .
Without the permanent there is therefore no time-relation.’
25. See, for instance, Leibniz 1956: 15. ‘I hold it [space] to be an order of coexist-
ences, as time is an order of successions.’
26. See Kant 1929: ‘Time cannot by itself be perceived’ (213, A182/B225); ‘time
cannot be perceived in itself’ (214, A183/B226; 219, A189/B233).
27. These three formulations of the disintegrating power of time appear in Deleuze’s
seminar of 14 April 1984.
28. Letter to Georges Izambard, 13 May 1871, letter to Paul Demeny, 15 May
1871.
29. Nonetheless, even Kant recognises that ‘I cannot determine my existence as that
of a self-active being; all that I can do is to represent to myself the spontaneity
of my thought’ (1929: 169, B158n). In other words, I can never truly recognise
the spontaneity of thinking as my own: the passive self ‘represents the activity
of thought to itself rather than enacting it, it experiences its effect rather than
initiating it’ (Deleuze 1994: 86). For a penetrating commentary, see Kerslake
2005.
30. Bernard Stiegler, in his three-volume Technics and Time – especially in the third
volume, Cinematic Time and the Question of Malaise – already went beyond
Heidegger’s analysis by rightly arguing that the temporal activity of schematisa-
tion, which Kant labelled a ‘mystery’, should be located in the ‘tertiary reten-
tions’ of technics (the externalisation of memory) (see e.g., Stiegler 2011: 56–7).
31. For an analysis of the role of the formless in the third critique, see Smith 2012:
222–34, esp. 228–30.
32. We are here summarising Deleuze’s important reading of Kant’s Critique of
Judgment in his 1963 article ‘The Idea of Genesis in Kant’s Aesthetics’ (trans.
Daniel W. Smith, in Angelaki, 5 (3), 2000, 57–70), which is an elaboration of
themes developed in Kant’s Critical Philosophy, published in the same year. See,
for example: ‘The theme of a presentation of Ideas in sensible nature is, in Kant,
a fundamental theme. There are several modes of presentation . . .’ (Deleuze
1984: 66).
33. For an analysis of how Deleuze transformed Kant’s theory of Ideas, see Smith
2012: 106–21.
34. In Difference and Repetition, the concept of the ‘white nothingness’ plays a
similar role and is characterised by what Deleuze calls ‘the rule of discontinuity
or instantaneity in repetition’: ‘one instance does not appear unless the other
has disappeared’ (1994: 28, 70).
35. ‘We place consciousness at the heart of things for the very reason that we credit
them with a time that endures’ (Bergson 1965: 49).
36. Though Leibniz held that the temporal synthesis of a body only lasts for a
‘moment’, he developed a theological theory of ‘traduction’ to account for the
propagation of minds. See Mercer 2004: e.g., 163, 223. The quote, from a letter
to Oldenburg, is cited in Mercer 2004: 164.
37. Deleuze would later speak of his affection for these analyses of fatigue and con-
templation in Difference and Repetition. See Deleuze 2006: 65.
The Pure Form of Time 69
38. Augustine, Confessions, 14.17. See also Deleuze 1989: 100. Husserl knew
Augustine well, and given his focus on the thickness of the present, Deleuze
characterised Husserl as a ‘theologian’, a kind of ‘church father’. See Deleuze,
seminar of 27 March 1984.
39. See Bergson 1920: 109–51. ‘Our actual existence duplicates itself all along
with a virtual existence, a mirror-image. Every moment of our life presents two
aspects, it is actual and virtual, perception on the one side and memory on the
other’ (135). See also Deleuze 1989: 79.
40. For an analysis of Bergson’s claim that ‘the whole is the open’, see Smith 2012:
256–67.
41. On the role of the ‘field of coexistence’ in Capitalism and Schizophrenia, see
Smith 2018: 232.
42. For an analysis of the components of the third synthesis as presented in
Difference and Repetition, see Voss 2013.
43. For the first sense, see Deleuze 1994: 88: ‘the pure form of time or the third
synthesis’. For the second sense, see 299: ‘What, however, is the content of this
third time, this formlessness at the end of the form of time?’ The phrase ‘form
of time’ appears only three times in The Time-Image (1989: 130, 273, 274), and
each seems to be used in the second sense.
44. See Deleuze and Guattari 1987: plateau 10, ‘1730: Becoming-Intense, Becoming-
Animal, Becoming-Imperceptible . . .’.
45. Deleuze cites Jean Beaufret’s influential commentary, ‘Hölderlin and Sophocles’,
in Hölderlin, Remarques sur Oedipe (Paris: Union Générale d’Éditions, 10/18,
1965), which analyses Hölderlin’s relation to Kant.
46. For analyses of Deleuze’s use of Hamlet, see Somers-Hall 2011 and Plotnitsky
2015.
47. See Deleuze 1994: 6 on what lies beyond the laws of nature.
48. For an elaboration of these themes, see Smith 2012: 189–221.
49. See James Mollison’s chapter in this volume.
50. The titles refer to the relevant sections in Thus Spoke Zarathustra (Nietzsche
1954): ‘The Convalescent’, III.13, 327–33; ‘On Involuntary Bliss’, III.3,
272–5.
51. To my knowledge, the phrase ‘power of the false’ appears once in both Difference
and Repetition (1994: 128) and The Logic of Sense (1990: 263), but never in
either Anti-Oedipus or A Thousand Plateaus. It is only in The Time-Image that
Deleuze develops the theme of the power of the false in detail.
52. The term ‘non-chronological time’ appears throughout The Time-Image, usually
with regard to the second synthesis (Deleuze 1989: 99), but in certain cases also
with regard to the third (129, 181).
53. Deleuze, seminar of 29 November 1983, p. 7: ‘The problem of contingent
futures is the confrontation of the concept of truth with the form of time.’ Jules
Vuillemin, who taught at the Collège de France, wrote an important book on
the Master Argument entitled The Necessity of Contingency, which Deleuze
relies on.
54. For analyses of the Master Argument, see Vuillemin 1996 and Schuhl 1960.
Vuillemin presents Epictetus’ summary of the argument: ‘It is contradictory
to hold any two of the following propositions together with the third: “Every
true proposition about the past is necessary. The impossible does not logically
follow from the possible. What neither is presently true nor will be so is pos-
sible”’ (1996: 3). For Deleuze’s discussion, see the seminars of 8, 22 and 29
November 1983, as well as Deleuze 1989: 130–1.
55. See Deleuze, seminar of 29 November 1983, as well as Deleuze 1989: 130.
56. Aristotle, for instance, was a partisan of a solution which said that what is
70 Daniel W. Smith
References
Aveni, A. (1989), Empires of Time: Calendars, Clocks, and Cultures, New York:
Basic Books.
Bergson, H. (1911), Creative Evolution, trans. Arthur Mitchell, New York: Henry
Holt.
Bergson, H. (1920), Mind-Energy, trans. H. Wildon Carr, London: Macmillan.
Bergson, H. (1965), Duration and Simultaneity, trans. Leon Jacobson, Indianapolis:
Bobbs-Merrill.
Crease, R. P. (2011), World in the Balance: The Historic Quest for an Absolute
System of Measurement, New York: Norton.
Deleuze, G. (1984), Kant’s Critical Philosophy: The Doctrine of the Faculties, trans.
Hugh Tomlinson and Barbara Habberjam, London: Athlone Press.
Deleuze, G. (1988), Bergsonism, trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Barbara Habberjam,
New York: Zone Books.
Deleuze, G. (1989), Cinema 2: The Time-Image, trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Robert
Galeta, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Deleuze, G. (1990), The Logic of Sense, trans. Mark Lester with Charles Stivale,
New York: Columbia University Press.
Deleuze, G. (1994), Difference and Repetition, trans. Paul Patton, New York:
Columbia University Press.
Deleuze, G. (1997), Essays Critical and Clinical, trans. Daniel W. Smith and Michael
A. Greco, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Deleuze, G. (2000), Proust and Signs, trans. Richard Howard, Minneapolis:
University of Minnesota Press.
Deleuze, G. (2006), Two Regimes of Madness: Texts and Interviews, 1975–1995,
trans. Ames Hodges and Mike Taormina, New York: Semiotext(e).
The Pure Form of Time 71
Rovelli, C. (2018), The Order of Time, trans. Erica Segre and Simon Carnell, New
York: Riverhead Books.
Schuhl, P.-M. (1960), Le Dominateur et les possibles, Paris: Presses universitaires
de France.
Serres, M. (1994), Atlas, Paris: Julliard.
Serres, M. (2000), The Birth of Physics, trans. Jack Hawkes, Manchester: Clinamen.
Smith, D. W. (2012), Essays on Deleuze, Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.
Smith, D. W. (2018), ‘7000 B.C.: Apparatus of Capture’, in A Thousand Plateaus
and Philosophy, ed. Henry Somers-Hall, Jeffrey A. Bell and James Williams,
Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.
Smith, D. W. (2019), ‘The Pure Form of Time and the Powers of the False: Deleuze
on Time and Temporality’, Tijdschrift voor Filosofie, 81: 29–51
Somers-Hall, H. (2011), ‘Time Out of Joint: Hamlet and the Pure Form of Time’,
Deleuze Studies 5 (Supplement): 56–76.
Somers-Hall, H. (2013), Deleuze’s Difference and Repetition, Edinburgh: Edinburgh
University Press.
Stiegler, B. (2011), Cinematic Time and the Question of Malaise, trans. Stephen
Barker, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Voss, D. (2013), ‘Deleuze’s Third Synthesis of Time’, Deleuze Studies 7 (2): 194–
216.
Vuillemin, J. (1996), Necessity of Contingency: The Master Argument, Stanford:
Center for the Study of Language and Information Publications.
Weber, M. (2002), The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism, and Other
Writings, London: Penguin.
Williams, J. (2011), Gilles Deleuze’s Philosophy of Time: A Critical Introduction
and Guide, Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.
PART II
HISTORY OF TIME
Chapter 4
Gilles Deleuze’s Interpretation of the
Eternal Return: From Nietzsche and
Philosophy to Difference and Repetition
James Mollison
again and innumerable times again; and there will be nothing new in
it’ (GS 341).2 Notwithstanding the myriad controversies surrounding
this idea, its central point seems obvious enough: each detail of our lives
will repeat, endlessly and identically. Yet, in Nietzsche and Philosophy,
Deleuze takes the eternal return to express the priority of becoming over
being and to function as a selective ethical and ontological principle that
eliminates all negativity. The claim that the eternal return eliminates
all negativity is especially contentious among Nietzsche scholars. Some
argue that a selective approach to ontology violates the doctrine’s ethical
aspiration of motivating an unconditional affirmation of existence.3
Others argue that the elimination of negativity and reactive forces also
eradicates affirmation and active forces.4 And still others argue that the
attempt to purge negativity and reactivity is ethically and politically dan-
gerous.5 While it is tempting to dismiss such arguments as hermeneutic
concerns for which Deleuze has little patience, his claim that his reading
of Nietzsche occurs within the history of philosophy suggests that
things are not so simple. Nor are these concerns confined to Nietzsche
and Philosophy. In the first work Deleuze authors in his own name,
Difference and Repetition, the eternal return occupies a privileged place
in Deleuze’s theory of time, functioning as a transcendental synthesis
of the future. Little wonder, then, that Deleuze is uncharacteristically
defensive over his reading of the eternal return (1994: 297–302) – as his
reading claims that the eternal return, which seemed to guarantee the
past’s endless and identical reappearance, is really a cypher for unbri-
dled novelty. To Nietzsche scholars, the image of philosophical buggery
could hardly seem more appropriate.
In this chapter, I examine Deleuze’s interpretation of the eternal return
and advance two claims about it. First, I suggest that much of the con-
troversy surrounding Nietzsche and Philosophy’s appeal to the eternal
return as a principle of selective ontology can be mitigated by attending
to Deleuze’s novel reading of the will to power as an evaluative typol-
ogy that produces individuals’ ontological commitments. The eternal
return enacts an ontological selection, for Deleuze, by transforming the
evaluative qualities of the will. Motivating this point takes some time,
but it also sets the stage for the second claim advanced here – namely,
that Deleuze’s interpretation of the eternal return undergoes a significant
shift in Difference and Repetition. In particular, I suggest that whereas
Nietzsche and Philosophy hesitates over the metaphysical status of the
eternal return, Difference and Repetition pursues an overtly metaphysi-
cal use of this idea as a principle of transcendental empiricism.6 As a
result, the eternal return ceases to denote the present’s internal differ-
Deleuze’s Interpretation of the Eternal Return 77
An evaluative typology
Deleuze describes Nietzsche and Philosophy by stating that ‘this book
sets out, primarily, to analyse what Nietzsche calls becoming’ (1983:
xii). It is thus unsurprising that he takes Nietzsche’s world to consist of
forces rather than beings.7 Forces, for Deleuze, are essentially relational
and plural (6). They are also necessarily unequal, such that whenever
two forces relate, one is quantitatively superior. Deleuze analyses these
quantitative disparities in terms of relations of ‘command’ and ‘obe-
dience’, though he hastens to add that such quantitative differences
produce qualitative differences, which he analyses in terms of ‘activity’
and ‘reactivity’ (40–3). Since Deleuze maintains that any relation among
forces produces a b ody – w hether chemical, biological, social or politi-
cal – Nietzsche and Philosophy examines all phenomena by treating the
active and reactive forces comprising them.
Deleuze distils Nietzsche’s tendency to analyse allegedly primitive
and simple concepts as products of dynamic principles down to a single
concept – force. He also distils Nietzsche’s tendency to explain diver-
gences among individuals’ outlooks in terms of qualitative differences
in their constitutions down to a single qualitative d istinction – a ctive/
reactive. But the active/reactive distinction cannot completely reduce
to forces’ quantitative differences. If it did, Deleuze could not explain
Nietzsche’s view that reactive forces can triumph over active forces
while remaining reactive. Slave morality is exemplary in this regard.
Nietzsche says of slave morality that ‘its action is, from the ground up,
reaction’ (GM I.10). And while slave morality defeats master moral-
ity and shapes humanity today, it remains reactive (BGE 202; GM
I.11–12). How does this occur? Nietzsche tells us that slave morality
overthrows master morality by positing ‘an indifferent substratum that
is free to express its strength – or not to’. After likening this to mislead-
ing expressions such as ‘lightning strikes’ or ‘force moves’, which add
an explanatorily otiose substratum behind activity, Nietzsche concludes:
78 James Mollison
Images of thought
Nietzsche regularly explains individuals’ perspectives in terms of their
values – v alues which trace to psycho-physiological and socio-historical
forces. For Deleuze, this explanatory strategy is emphatically non-
reductive. Forces themselves carry evaluations, which emerge from
still more fundamental, evaluative qualities of the will. Unflinching
commitment to the view that values extend beyond the psychologi-
cal domain reverberates in Deleuze’s comparisons of Nietzsche with
80 James Mollison
This life as you now live it and have lived it you will have to live once again
and innumerable times again; and there will be nothing new in it, but every
pain and every joy and every thought and sigh and everything unspeakably
small or great in your life must return to you in the same succession and
sequence . . . (GS 341)
will, will it in such a way that you also will its eternal return’ (1983: 68).
This imperative eliminates all half-hearted willing. ‘Laziness, stupid-
ity, baseness, cowardice or spitefulness that would will its own eternal
return would no longer be the same laziness, stupidity, etc.’, because
the practical thought of the eternal return pushes reactive forces to their
limit. Although this practical use of the eternal return ‘makes willing
something whole’, ‘makes willing a creation’, Deleuze thinks that this
is insufficient to overcome nihilism (69). Nietzsche describes the eternal
return as ‘the most extreme form of nihilism’ (WP 55) because reactive
forces can pass its practical test. This casts further doubt on hypothetical
readings of the eternal return, as the thought of life’s identical replica-
tion fails to transform the Last Man content with a reactive life. Deleuze
infers from this that the eternal return must carry out a second selection,
one that ‘involves the most obscure parts of Nietzsche’s philosophy and
forms an almost esoteric element on the doctrine of the eternal return’
(1983: 69).
This second selection is ontological. Whereas the first selection con-
cerns reactive forces, the second submits the will to nothingness to the
eternal return. This leads the will to nothingness to break its alliance
with reactive forces. As Deleuze puts the point, ‘only the eternal return
can complete nihilism because it makes negation a negation of reactive
forces’ (1983: 70). He illustrates this transition by distinguishing the
Last Man from the Man who actively destroys himself (69–70; 174). But
the details of this transmutation remain obscure. Inasmuch as the eternal
return forecloses the possibility of any life other than this, perhaps
it compels any evaluation which opposes life to confront its internal
contradiction, its use of life’s creative powers to negate life itself. On
this suggestion, the eternal return forces the ascetic who denies life in
favour of heaven to either abandon asceticism or to affirm asceticism as
an active negation of life. Likewise, the eternal return forces those who
pursue truth in opposition to life to either question the value of truth or
to affirm the will to truth as an active negation of life. Generalising the
point: if one attempts to affirm the practical thought of the eternal return
under the sway of nihilism, negation is pushed to break its alliance
with reactive forces and to actively pursue the destruction of reactive
forces themselves. Unfortunately, though, I suspect that such an expla-
nation of the eternal return’s selective ontology remains all-too-human.
Throughout Nietzsche and Philosophy, Deleuze insists that the will to
power must not be confined to psychology – both because human psy-
chology is categorically reactive (21, 34, 41, 64, 167–9) and because the
will produces forces more basic than individuals’ psychological outlooks
Deleuze’s Interpretation of the Eternal Return 85
Selective ontology
Despite my suspicion that the eternal return’s selective ontology cannot
reduce to individuals’ reflection on its practical application, I’d like to
ask whether the eternal return’s ethical selection might yield a selec-
tive ontology. An affirmative answer to this question would amount
to a general defence of Deleuze’s reading, as scholars typically accept
his claim that the eternal return functions as an ethical principle but
resist his further claim about selective ontology.21 Examining Deleuze’s
notion of selective ontology from this vantage also allows the distinct-
ness of Difference and Repetition’s interpretation of the eternal return
to emerge in sharper relief.
The suggestion that the eternal return’s ethical application could
produce a selective ontology might seem ill formed. If ontology describes
unalterable features of reality, and if the eternal return’s ethical selection
results from a psychological transformation, then one might think that
the eternal return’s ethical application cannot affect ontology, which is
more fundamental than psychology.22 However, at least in Nietzsche
and Philosophy, Deleuze denies that ontology and metaphysics describe
the ground floor of reality. ‘According to Nietzsche the philosophy of
the will must replace the old metaphysics: it destroys and supersedes
it’ (1983: 84; see also 35). Consistent with Nietzsche’s explanations
of individuals’ ontological commitments in terms of their psychologi-
cal constitutions, Deleuze maintains that the will to power’s qualities
produce our image of thought, including our ontological categories,
such that ‘metaphysics and the theory of knowledge themselves belong
to typology’ (145). Deleuze does not shrink before the consequences of
this intrepid claim. He takes Nietzsche to replace the Platonic question
of essence (what is [x]?) with questions of sense and value (who wills
86 James Mollison
the will to power’s qualities are not univocal. Granted, from the perspec-
tive of a negative will, the eternal return is a kind of auto-destruction.
To the extent that negative values define our human condition, affirming
the eternal return is therefore difficult indeed.26 But from an affirmative
vantage, the eternal return does not require the elimination of negation
or reactive forces; for, affirmation does not oppose negation or reaction.
This affirmative perspective on the eternal return is reflected in Deleuze’s
descriptions of t ransmutation – n ot as a sacrifice, b
ut – a s revealing that
negation depends on affirmation. The eternal return ‘makes negation a
power of affirming’ (86), so that ‘negation ceases to be an autonomous
power’ (191; see also 176–9). Similarly, reactive forces unilaterally
depend on active forces (41). And insofar as Deleuze maintains that
bodies in which active forces prevail are fundamentally active (86), there
is a sense in which reactive forces need not be eliminated but only subor-
dinated to active forces. Affirming the eternal return does not eliminate
negation and reaction in some physical sense. Rather, it reveals that
negation and reactivity depend on affirmation and activity. This is why
the eternal return produces a double affirmation (186). Selective ontol-
ogy does not select some phenomena as opposed to others; it affirms the
affirmative wills and active forces that subtend all phenomena. Negation
and reaction also rely on the affirmative powers of the f alse – t he fiction
of a will which does not create, or the fiction of forces separated from
their expression, for example. The eternal return asks whether we can
affirm such falsification to push the powers of the false still further.
Insofar as the practical thought of the eternal return forecloses the
possibility of any life other than this, it compels individuals either to
abandon life-negating values or to affirm these values as an active nega-
tion of the world. The ascetic deprived of the promise of heaven must
either abandon asceticism or affirm asceticism as an active negation of
life; the claimant of knowledge must either abandon their subordina-
tion of life to truth or affirm the will to truth as an active negation of
becoming. Either response to the eternal return produces an ontological
transformation. If the life-negating value of truth is replaced with the
life-affirming value of artistic creation, our conceptualisation of the
world becomes an artistic selection that contributes to the world’s crea-
tivity. But if negative values are actively affirmed, instead of replaced, a
profound conversion still unfolds. The ascetic who actively negates life
is not the same as the ascetic who merely reacts to forces beyond their
power. For, the active ascetic ceases to disavow the will’s creativity and
acknowledges that their will evaluates life but finds it wanting. Neither
response to the practical thought of the eternal r eturn – the replacement
88 James Mollison
Transcendental empiricism
If the foregoing, sympathetic reconstruction provides a general defence
of Deleuze’s account of selective ontology, it does so by exploiting
the puzzling position occupied by the will to power and the eternal
return in Nietzsche and Philosophy. Insofar as Deleuze insists that these
concepts are not confined to psychology but describe becoming, meta-
physical interpretations of both notions seem invited. Yet Nietzsche and
Philosophy’s discussions of metaphysics primarily aim at showing that
metaphysics in general expresses a negative will to power. For Deleuze,
‘
Nietzsche . . . makes nihilism the presupposition of all metaphysics
rather than a particular metaphysics: there is no metaphysics which
does not judge and depreciate life in the name of a supra-sensible world’
(1983: 34; see also 195). But this only makes the status of affirma-
tive wills and the return of becoming more perplexing. Are these not
metaphysical? Sometimes, Deleuze seems to permit the possibility of an
affirmative metaphysics – as when he claims that ‘Nietzsche . . . develops
a philosophy which must . . . replace the old metaphysics’ (145, see also
84). Still, Nietzsche and Philosophy seems to vacillate before this pos-
sibility, leaving us with an odd picture on which the phenomenal world
is produced by non-anthropomorphic evaluations, which are affirmed
non-anthropomorphically in the process of returning – and without any
of this being metaphysical. If Deleuze wavers before the possibility of
an affirmative metaphysics in Nietzsche and Philosophy, he overcomes
this hesitation in Difference and Repetition by developing his method of
transcendental empiricism.
Deleuze’s Interpretation of the Eternal Return 89
of difference and its repetition’, and that ‘the thought of the eternal
return [as a selection of affirmative wills] goes beyond all the laws of
our knowledge’ (1983: 49, 108). While these cryptic claims foreshadow
Difference and Repetition, they cry out for elaboration inasmuch as
Nietzsche and Philosophy vacillates before the questions of what a non-
anthropomorphic affirmation of the eternal return might entail and of
how such an affirmation could be non-metaphysical. Difference and
Repetition overcomes this hesitation. There, the eternal return ‘is the
only Same which can be said of this world and which excludes any
prior identity therein’, because the eternal return is a transcendental
affirmation of difference itself. Insofar as the eternal return, as a double
affirmation and a repetition of difference, marks the emergence of
understanding from the given, Deleuze claims that ‘repetition in the
eternal return is the highest thought’ (1994: 243). Just as Difference and
Repetition dispenses with the will to power’s negative qualities to focus
on its affirmative aspect, Deleuze also dispenses almost entirely with the
cosmological and psychological uses of the eternal return in favour of a
transcendental use of the idea as an affirmation of difference. The eternal
return ceases to describe a psychological transformation that induces
a selective approach to ontology and becomes a properly ontological
selection, one which ensures that only extreme intensive differences
emerge in the understanding.
As the repetition of difference, the eternal return also marks the
passive, temporal synthesis of the future. Deleuze is forthright about the
speculative character of this portion of his interpretation of Nietzsche.
He maintains that ‘the Nietzschean doctrine of eternal return was never
stated but reserved for a future work’, and that ‘Nietzsche gave no
exposition of the eternal return’ because ‘Thus Spoke Zarathustra is
unfinished’ (1994: 92, 297). While this gives Deleuze some reason to
speculate about Nietzsche’s ultimate formulation of the eternal return,
such speculation is distinct from ‘buggery’. Far from intentionally sub-
verting Nietzsche’s thought, Deleuze attempts to formulate what the
eternal return would have become were it not for Nietzsche’s collapse.
Deleuze takes his conjectures on this score to be warranted by the way
that the eternal return presupposes an absence of identity – the death of
God and the dissolution of the Self. If what returns is difference, then
sameness and identity only emerge as simulacra (126), ‘as secondary
powers’ of difference (301). Strictly speaking, then, ‘the eternal return
affects only the new’, since what repeats is always different (90). This
view of the eternal return as a transcendental synthesis of difference
entails a radical rethinking of time. While Nietzsche and Philosophy
Deleuze’s Interpretation of the Eternal Return 93
Conclusion
Deleuze’s interpretation of the eternal return develops at the threshold
of the traditional demands of the history of philosophy. Attending to
Nietzsche’s views that evaluations subtend even the most banal descrip-
tions of the world and that becoming exceeds all knowledge leads Deleuze
to push the will to power’s evaluative qualities and the eternal return’s
94 James Mollison
Notes
1. Selected portions of this chapter are adapted from Mollison (forthcoming).
2. Citations from Nietzsche use abbreviations listed in the references. Arabic
numerals refer to section numbers. Roman numerals to major divisions within
works.
3. See Schrift 1995: 139 n.32; and D’Iorio 2011.
4. See Ansell-Pearson 1994: 114–16; Ward 2010: 106–10; and Woodward 2013:
134–7.
5. See Hallward 2006: 149–52; Malabou 2010; and Woodward 2013: 140–3.
6. This shift is concealed by the tendency to interchangeably cite Nietzsche and
Philosophy and Difference and Repetition when examining Deleuze’s reading
of the eternal return. For examples, see Hallward 2006; Malabou 2010; Ward
2010; and, to a lesser extent, Woodward 2013. My developmental approach
to this topic also distinguishes my discussion from those that only appraise
Deleuze’s interpretation as a reading of Nietzsche (e.g., Ansell-Pearson 1994;
Malabou 2010; Ward 2010; D’Iorio 2011; and Woodward 2013) and those
that grant Deleuze’s interpretation to examine the use he makes of it (e.g.,
Williams 2011; and Voss 2013).
7. Deleuze’s choice to draw from Nietzsche’s Nachlass merits emphasising here.
For while Nietzsche’s publications provide some support for the claim that the
Deleuze’s Interpretation of the Eternal Return 95
world is comprised of forces (e.g., BGE 12, 17; GM I.13), his notebooks provide
drastically more support for it. The concept of force (Kraft) is used to analyse
the world in general (WP 1064, 1062, 638, 1066), organic life (WP 641, 650,
647, 689, 702–3), human life (WP 686, 490, 660, 704), phenomenology and
psychology (WP 664, 668, 568), value judgements (WP 260, 667, 781, 931,
386, 863, 576), social phenomena (WP 750, 762, 786, 784) and aesthetic activi-
ties (WP 852, 842, 809, 812, 815).
8. D’Iorio criticises Deleuze’s interpretation of the will to power as entailing ‘a
form of dualism which Nietzsche’s monistic philosophy strives to eliminate’
(2011: 3). The portion of D’Iorio’s argument concerning the legitimacy of the
French translation of Nietzsche’s notes that Deleuze uses is well-taken (see
Montinari 1996). However, D’Iorio’s accusation of dualism is complicated by
Deleuze’s analysis of the will to power as a plastic, empirical principle.
9. For examples, see Kaufmann 1956: 152–80; and Reginster 2006: 103–48.
10. For example, see Clark 1990: 205–44.
11. For example, see Richardson 1996.
12. For example, see Schacht 1985: 212–34.
13. On this aspect of Deleuze’s reading, see Norman 2000.
14. On Nietzsche and Philosophy’s relation to Kant, see Marsden 1998.
15. This gloss is supported by Kant’s description of his critical project as a ‘ripened
power of judgement, which will no longer be put off with illusory knowledge,
and which demands that reason . . . institute a court of justice, [to] secure its
rightful claims while dismissing all its groundless pretensions’ (1998: Axi–xii).
16. For examples, see Kaufmann 1956: 274–86; Heidegger 1991; Loeb 2010; and
D’Iorio 2011.
17. For examples, see Nehamas 1985: 141–69; Clark 1990: 245–86; and Reginster
2006: 201–27.
18. A similar argument motivates Deleuze’s claim that the eternal return affirms
chance (1983: 25–9).
19. D’Iorio argues that Deleuze’s claim that difference eternally returns ‘relies on
one fragment by Nietzsche, and one fragment only’ (2011: 1). The fragment
in question results from Geneviève Bianquis’ decision to combine two notes
from Nietzsche’s Nachlass and thereby obscure the fact that these notes criticise
Johannes Gustav Vogt’s rendering of the eternal return (D’Iorio 2011: 1–3; see
also Woodward 2013: 128–9). D’Iorio is right to challenge Bianquis’ rendering
of these texts (see Montinari 1996), but I think he overstates his case against
Deleuze. Nietzsche rejects ancient formulations of the eternal return as a cycli-
cal hypothesis, insists on the priority of becoming over being, and argues that
metaphysical notions of identity abstract from reality’s complexity. Deleuze’s
claim that difference returns largely derives from the cumulative force that these
themes exert on our understanding of the eternal return. Though, as we will see,
Deleuze becomes more forthright about the speculative nature of his interpreta-
tion by the time of Difference and Repetition, where the return of difference is
emphasised over the return of becoming.
20. This point bears a striking affinity with Deleuze’s reading of Bergson – although,
whereas Deleuze takes Bergson to claim that the present and past are contem-
poraneous (Deleuze 1988: 58–9), he takes Nietzsche to claim that the present,
past and future are coeval. While Deleuze suggests that this point follows from
Nietzsche’s analysis of temporal cycles’ extreme states, Borradori (1999) argues
that Deleuze’s earlier essay, ‘Bergson’s Conception of Difference’, operates
throughout much of Nietzsche and Philosophy. So, Deleuze may be perverting
Nietzsche somewhat here.
21. For examples, see Ansell- Pearson 1994: 113–16; Schrift 1995: 139 n.32;
96 James Mollison
Malabou 2010; Ward 2010: 106–7; D’Iorio 2011; and Woodward 2013:
128–44. At the risk of seeming facile, I will not reconstruct and rebut specific
objections raised against Deleuze’s notion of selective ontology. Isolating any
one objection strikes me as overly ad hoc and reconstructing all of the rel-
evant arguments would take considerable time. Still, I think a broad defence of
Deleuze’s reading can be offered, at least insofar as one accepts that the eternal
return carries ethical implications.
22. Ward seems to have something like this in mind when he accuses Deleuze of
‘conflating two different notions of selection’. The first selection, according
to Ward, operates ‘purely as a thought, as something which forces us to think
about existence in a particular way’, whereas the second selection operates as ‘a
universal, cosmological process’ (Ward 2010: 106).
23. For objections of this sort, see Schrift 1995: 139 n.32; Ward 2010: 106–10;
D’Iorio 2011; and Woodward 2013: 134–7.
24. For examples, see Ansell-Pearson 1994: 114–16; and Ward 2010: 106–8.
25. For examples, see Hallward 2006: 149–52; Malabou 2010: 25; and Woodward
2013: 134–7, 140–3.
26. While Ward argues that Deleuze’s selective ontology makes the eternal return
‘something blandly cheering and optimistic’ (2010: 106), I think this downplays
Deleuze’s insistence that humanity is categorically reactive. The elimination of
the ego, for example, is neither comforting nor easily accomplished.
27. On Difference and Repetition’s relation to Kant, see Lord 2012.
28. For a detailed treatment of these syntheses, see Williams 2011.
29. On the relation between truth and the empty form of time, see Smith 2013.
References
Nietzsche’s Works
BGE Beyond Good and Evil, trans. Judith Norman, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2002.
D Daybreak, trans. R. J. Hollingdale, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1997.
GM On the Genealogy of Morality, trans. Maudemarie Clark and Alan J. Swensen,
Indianapolis: Hackett, 1998.
GS The Gay Science, trans. Josefine Naukhoff and Adrian Del Caro, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2001.
TI Twilight of the Idols, trans. Judith Norman, Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 2005.
WP The Will to Power, trans. Walter Kaufmann and R. J. Hollingdale, New York:
Vintage, 1968.
Other Sources
Ansell-Pearson, K. (1994), An Introduction to Nietzsche as a Political Thinker,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Borradori, G. (1999), ‘On the Presence of Bergson in Deleuze’s Nietzsche’,
Philosophy Today, 43: 140–5.
Clark, M. (1990), Nietzsche on Truth and Philosophy, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Deleuze, G. (1983), Nietzsche and Philosophy, trans. Hugh Tomlinson, New York:
Columbia University Press.
Deleuze, G. (1988), Bergsonism, trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Barbara Habberjam,
New York: Zone Books.
Deleuze’s Interpretation of the Eternal Return 97
Deleuze, G. (1994), Difference and Repetition, trans. Paul Patton, New York:
Columbia University Press.
Deleuze, G. (1995), Negotiations 1972–1990, trans. Martin Joughin, New York:
Columbia University Press.
Deleuze, G. and C. Parnet (2007), Dialogues II, trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Barbara
Habberjam, New York: Columbia University Press.
D’Iorio, P. (2011), ‘The Eternal Return: Genesis and Interpretation’, trans. Frank
Chouraqui, The Agonist, IV (1): 1–43.
Hallward, P. (2006), Out of this World: Deleuze and the Philosophy of Creation,
New York: Verso.
Heidegger, M. (1991), Nietzsche, trans. David Farrell Krell, New York: Harper
Collins.
Kant, I. (1998), Critique of Pure Reason, trans. and ed. Paul Guyer and Allen Wood,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Kaufmann, W. (1956), Nietzsche: Philosopher, Psychologist, Antichrist, New York:
Meridian.
Loeb, P. (2010), The Death of Nietzsche’s Zarathustra, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Lord, B. (2012), ‘Deleuze and Kant’, in The Cambridge Companion to Deleuze,
ed. Daniel W. Smith and Henry Somers-Hall, Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Malabou, C. (2010), ‘The Eternal Return and the Phantom of Difference’, trans.
Arne De Boever, Parrhesia, 10: 21–9.
Marsden, J. (1998), ‘Critical Incorporation: Nietzsche and Deleuze’, Journal of
Nietzsche Studies, 16: 33–48.
Mollison, J. (forthcoming), ‘Deleuze’s Nietzschean Mutations: From the Will to
Power and the Overman to Desiring-Production and Nomadism’, Deleuze and
Guattari Studies.
Montinari, M. (1996), ‘La volunté de puissance’ N’existe Pas, Paris: Éditions de
l’éclat.
Nehamas, A. (1985), Nietzsche: Life as Literature, Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
Norman, J. (2000), ‘Nietzsche contra Contra: Difference and Opposition’,
Continental Philosophy Review, 33: 189–206.
Reginster, B. (2006), The Affirmation of Life: Nietzsche on Overcoming Nihilism,
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Richardson, J. (1996), Nietzsche’s System, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Schacht, R. (1985), Nietzsche, Boston: Routledge.
Schrift, A. (1995), Nietzsche’s French Legacy, New York: Routledge.
Smith, D. W. (2013), ‘Temporality and Truth’, Deleuze Studies, 7 (3): 377–89.
Voss, D. (2013), ‘Deleuze’s Third Synthesis of Time’, Deleuze Studies, 7 (2): 194–
216.
Ward, J. (2010), ‘Revisiting Nietzsche et la Philosophie’, Angelaki, 15 (2): 101–14.
Williams, J. (2011), Gilles Deleuze’s Philosophy of Time: A Critical Introduction
and Guide, Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.
Woodward, A. (2013), ‘Deleuze, Nietzsche, and the Overcoming of Nihilism’,
Continental Philosophy Review, 46: 115–47.
Chapter 5
Time and the Untimely: Deleuze, Foucault
and the Production of the New
Strand Sheldahl-Thomason
ntimely – that is to say, acting counter to our time and thereby acting
U
on our time and, let us hope, for the benefit of a time to come (Nietzsche
1997: 60)
Time is the most radical form of change, but the form of change does not
change. (Deleuze 1994: 89)
Once defined, a form is simultaneously too old and too new, too strange
and too familiar, not to be instantly rejected . . . (Foucault 1998: 167)
course, is not empty, but the content of history, namely dated events in
a relation of succession, or systems of relations between ordinal points
that are expressed as events, eras and epochs, becomes for Deleuze and
Guattari something like the pure past (the second synthesis of time)
that eternal return ungrounds and reorders. In keeping with Deleuze’s
totalising theory of time, all historical events coexist in a system that
becoming criss-crosses. Just as eternal return affects the whole of time,
so does it affect the whole of history, so that history itself is continuously
undergoing change. What Deleuze’s philosophy of time and Deleuze and
Guattari’s philosophy of history reject is homogeneous continuity. They
preserve totality and universality.
At least when it comes to time and history, Foucault’s Kantian inherit-
ance extends to his retention of the term a priori, and his philosophy
of history distinguishes between condition and conditioned. However,
Foucault makes the a priori historical, and his move to history amounts
to a rejection of transcendental philosophies of time. His analysis of
Kant’s Anthropology shows that the time of that work is a time of
dispersion that is no longer subjectively contained. Nonetheless, he
also argues that Kant never escapes the fundamental problem of tran-
scendental philosophy: that of seeking an illusory, originary ground of
finitude beyond or behind the field of experience. Foucault’s positive
philosophy of history emphasises the discontinuous. For Foucault, any
notion of universal history goes by the wayside along with the founding
subject. His discussion of the historical a priori and the archive shows
that discursive proliferation and transformation cannot be reduced to
a unified historical perspective. Foucault characterises his own work as
a history of the present, but the point of such a history is not to justify
or reify our forms of knowing. It is to reveal the groundlessness of
that which grounds our ways of knowing and living, and to spur us to
develop new ways of living that are not predicted or determined by the
present, that cannot be articulated on the grounds of the present but
rather transform those grounds. Foucault’s philosophy of history rejects
continuity, totality and universality.
Serious questions dog both thinkers. For Deleuze, the question
becomes, is the empty form of time itself immune to becoming? For
Foucault, the question is, can his philosophy of transformation remain
coherent without metaphysical intervention? Yet these questions are
unfair to both thinkers. Deleuze might respond: what sense does it
make to speak of the transformation of that which is empty? Foucault
might respond: why must I be consistent or coherent? Yet it may be that
Foucault’s refusal to engage in any attempt to trace a formal structure
Time and the Untimely 101
of time gives him the advantage when it comes to pushing us toward the
genuinely new. As admirable and thorough as Deleuze’s efforts to spell
out a system of multiple, irreducible syntheses of time are, his adapta-
tion of Kant’s empty form of time undermines his own contention that
‘form will never inspire anything but conformities’ (1994: 134).
It is the third synthesis of time that Deleuze identifies with the pure
and empty form of time. If the traces of the subordination of time to
movement remain from Plato even through to Deleuze’s second synthesis
of time, Deleuze’s third synthesis of time achieves the promise glimpsed
by Kant, but now freed of the Kantian baggage which takes synthesis
as the province of an active subject. According to James Williams, ‘the
third synthesis of time is . . . empty, in the sense of lacking cardinal
numbering, and pure, in the sense of lacking hierarchies associated
with numbering’ (2011: 88). On the Platonic conception of time, time
is measured according to the relation of points to the cardo, or the
joint, hinge or astronomical pole which would serve as a ground for
measurement, as in the measurement of revolutions of the earth. Even
with the pure past, content remains that gives shape to the past and the
present alike, and the passing present construes past events as cardinal
points. With the third synthesis of time, ‘Time itself unfolds . . . It ceases
to become cardinal and becomes ordinal, a pure order of time’ (Deleuze
1994: 88). It is Shakespeare who gives literary expression to the third
synthesis of time when Hamlet says, ‘time is out of joint [cardo]’. Out
of joint, time is purified of any relation to the notions of origin, copy
and succession that are associated with cardinal numbers. The third
synthesis of time is a pure ordering because it breaks the circle of time,
or introduces a caesura in time, and in so breaking the circle orders
time into a before and after, or a past and future. It is tempting to
think of this ordering as an ordinal numbering (1st, 2nd, 3rd . . .), but
that would not be correct because, temporally speaking, such ordinal
numbers are tied to cardinal points, as in the case of a line of kings. The
third synthesis of time is a pure ordering because it is devoid of empiri-
cal content. Deleuze remarks that ‘time is defined . . . by a formal and
empty order’ because it has ‘abjured its empirical content’ (89). If the
second synthesis of time grounds the ordering of events in the passing
present, the third synthesis ungrounds the ground of that ordering
and re-orders time as a whole. In other words, with the caesura, ‘the
whole of time is ordered, but it is ordered differently’ (Williams 2011:
91). This formal ordering of the third synthesis of time therefore leads
Williams to call it ‘a speculative claim about time . . . as condition for
the new’ (90). In order for the new to be genuinely new, as opposed
to more of the same (the next king), it must stand out as new. That is,
the new must be distinguished from the same-old. To be new the new
breaks the circle of time and marks the before the new as past and the
after the new as future. The caesura that accompanies the appearance
of the new, then, touches the whole of time. This is why Deleuze says
104 Strand Sheldahl-Thomason
that the pure and empty form of time ‘is defined . . . also by a totality’
(1994: 89).
Deleuze’s reference to the totality of time indicates that the caesura
of the new cannot be the effect of some kind of blow from the outside
of time. Accordingly, the last important ingredient of Deleuze’s tem-
poral recipe is something borrowed from Nietzsche: eternal return. In
Williams’s fine formulation, for Deleuze, eternal return is ‘defined by the
principle that only pure difference or difference in itself returns and never
the same’ (2011: 115). Deleuze is aware of the possibility of hearing
eternal return as circular, and he points out Zarathustra’s remark that
we simplify the eternal return by relying upon the circle as its image.
Yet the image of the circle is not entirely wrongheaded, so long as what
circles back in eternal return is not understood as contents, events,
identities or representations. Deleuze characterises time as an ‘excentric
circle’, or a circle that is freed of the cardo (1994: 91). What returns
in the eternal return is difference itself. In other words, the mistake
that Zarathustra identifies is that of taking eternal return to mean the
recurrence or recapitulation of a discrete passing present. When Deleuze
calls forth the eternal return, he means the return of precisely that which
differentiates passing presents. He therefore associates eternal return
with ungrounding:
The form of time is there only for the revelation of the formless in the
eternal return. The extreme formality is there only for excessive form-
lessness (Hölderlin’s Unförmliche). In this manner, the ground has been
superseded by a groundlessness, a universal ungrounding which turns upon
itself and causes only the yet-to-come to return. (Deleuze 1994: 91)
eternal form, but precisely the form of what is not eternal’ (2012: 133).
Deleuze’s adaptation of Nietzsche’s eternal return is transcendental
rather than transcendent, and it is here especially that the transcenden-
tal side of Deleuze’s transcendental empiricism becomes apparent. The
form of time is not separable from empirical contents but related to
the new as its transcendental condition. It is also wrong to think of the
caesura as ‘taking time’. For the cut in time to itself take time, or be tem-
porally measurable, would require another order of time, or a time of
time, according to which the cut-event could be measured. However, the
caesura does not work like this. Lampert provides a helpful summary of
Deleuze’s three syntheses of time that is illuminating here. He says, ‘Just
as the present is all of time in the sense of events in passage, and the past
is all of time in the sense of events on record, so the future is all of time
in the sense of events in play’ (2006: 55). It is the third synthesis of time
that returns all events to play, and in so doing it affects all events imme-
diately. In other words, all processes of becoming are themselves part of
a play that is not reducible to any particular move. Deleuze expresses
this when he says, ‘each event communicates with all others, and they
all form one and the same E vent . . . the Event for all events’ (1990: 64).
The eternal return is eternal in the sense that it does not change, and the
caesura by which it reorders time does so immediately as the play that
puts into play all events for (re)ordering.
The connection of Deleuze’s philosophy of time to Deleuze and
Guattari’s philosophy of history is not as straightforward as it may
seem. Deleuze and Guattari remain committed to a notion of universal
history, or the notion that all events can be subsumed under a unifying
interpretive framework, which is consistent with Deleuze’s totalising
temporal philosophy. For Hegel, contingency in history is subordinated
to the necessity of universal reason. Deleuze and Guattari distinguish
their notion of universal history from Hegel’s when they say: ‘universal
history is the history of contingencies, and not the history of necessity’
(1983: 140). According to Craig Lundy, Deleuze and Guattari’s universal
history is universal in the sense that ‘the present forms a heterogeneous
continuity with the past, and it is this continuity as a whole that continu-
ously undergoes change’ (2016: 73). Deleuze and Guattari see history
not only as a series of contingent events retrospectively posited by the
present, but as a totality of relations that are contingent everywhere all
the time. For Lundy, this ‘continual contingency’ is enough to reconcile
the appearance of the new with a history that is genuinely universal
(71). Yet a familiar problem arises again. If the connection between
the living present and the pure past devolves into one of representation
106 Strand Sheldahl-Thomason
torical sensibility that seeks unity in history. Foucault argues that reason
itself is articulated against the background of unreason. Ascendant
reason comes to isolate unreason within itself as madness, but it cannot
fully conquer this necessary, threatening double that unpredictably
erupts into history and contests the stability of its development. It is
transcendental philosophy and the philosophy of history that grows
out of it that Foucault has in mind when he says, ‘The plenitude of
history is only possible in the space . . . of all the words without lan-
guage that appear to anyone who lends an ear, as a dull sound from
beneath history, the obstinate murmur of a language talking to itself’
(2006: xxxi). His claim is that reason, with the communication and
recognition that accompany it, needs to define itself against what it is
not. Reasonable language therefore demarcates itself and excludes from
itself whatever is left over, which becomes not only not reason but not
even language. If time is reason’s form of determination, and history is
a condition of possibility of recognition, both time and history are also
secondary to the cut by which reason inaugurates itself as opposed to
unreason. Therefore Foucault says, ‘The necessity of madness through-
out the history of the West is linked to that decisive action that extracts
a significant language from the background noise and its continuous
monotony, a language which is transmitted and culminates in time; it
is, in short, linked to the possibility of history’ (xxxii). His history of
madness is the history of reason’s ongoing relation to that which it is
not. It is the history of reason’s attempt to engulf unreason by making it
an object of knowledge and fold it into the natural history of anthropos.
Madness is not unreason, or rather madness is unreason transformed
into a knowable, treatable pathology. For all that, unreason remains at
the limit of reason, and continues to contest rational history’s necessity
and inevitability. As Foucault says, ‘the experience of unreason, such as
is evident in Hölderlin, Nerval, and Nietzsche, always leads back to the
roots of time – unreason thereby becoming the untimely (contretemps)
within the world par excellence’ (363). Foucault’s History of Madness
can only be a history of madness, and not a history of unreason, because
unreason has no history. What a history of reason’s relation to unreason
can do is show, at least, that a particular human science, psychology, is
not a route to the elusive unity of the subject-object that is anthropos. At
most it shows the contingency and arbitrariness of the very rationality,
along with its time and history, that presents itself as necessary.
These achievements are chiefly negative, and they call for a recon-
sideration of history as it is practised. The question becomes, if hope
for the unity that reason’s time promises has to be given up, what
110 Strand Sheldahl-Thomason
There are in fact two levels of temporality at play here. On one level,
there is the temporality of the appearance of statements that contribute
to an epistemic formation. On another level, there is the temporality of
the rules that govern those statements. Not every statement inaugurates
a new historical a priori, but statements bend and distort the rules of
what may be said as they accumulate, until statements produced accord-
ing to one iteration of the historical a priori are no longer intelligible to
statements produced according to a different iteration. In fact, Foucault
refers to plural historical a prioris. What distinguishes his notion of
history from Hegelian universal history is both that there is no dialectic
in Foucault, only subtle transformations of relations between statements
that affect neighbouring relations, and that events are not all contained
in a single context susceptible to a unifying interpretive framework.
History in Foucault is not universal. There is not yet a third level of time
that would unite incommensurable historical a prioris.
Foucault’s discussion of the archive makes this last point plain. The
archive is the most general discursive feature that Foucault discusses in
The Archaeology of Knowledge. In that book, he spells out a certain
hierarchy of generality that extends from statements to discursive for-
mations to epistemes. The term episteme refers to the relations that give
rise to formal sciences. The archive is more general still because it is
that collected or sedimented background out of which any episteme can
emerge. Foucault describes the archive as ‘a complex volume, in which
heterogeneous regions are differentiated or deployed, in accordance with
specific rules or practices that cannot be superposed’ (2010: 128). The
materiality of the archive has often been noted, but it is more than a col-
lection of records. It is not something inert like the ‘library of all librar-
ies’, but a living system that is the invisible underside of those statements
that actually appear (130). Foucault distinguishes between the archive,
the corpus and language. The corpus is that inert collection of what has
been said. Language governs possible sentences that, while grammati-
cally correct, may not function as statements in a particular discourse.
The archive lies between the corpus and language as that which makes
what is said neither dead nor disconnected. Lynne Huffer character-
ises the archive as ‘the abstract and unseen operating system Foucault
describes . . . as an episteme’s condition of intelligibility’ (2020: 7). Yet
the archive is more like the computer code that flows into the mother-
board of words, powered by the electricity of language, on which the
operating system of the historical a priori runs to organise information.
It is that unsaid system of relations out of which the historical a priori
extracts rules that in turn make statements intelligible. Perhaps the best
112 Strand Sheldahl-Thomason
technological metaphor for how the historical a priori and the archive
work together is that of machine learning. As discourse proliferates and
statements build up an archive, the historical a priori refines its rules to
retain certain statements and exclude others. The archive thus allows
for discursive transformation and discontinuity, or the new, rather than
reducing all that is said to one grand discourse. Foucault says ‘it is that
which differentiates discourses in their multiple existence and specifies
them in their own duration’ (2010: 129).
The archive generates incommensurable historical a prioris, which in
turn give rise to overlapping discourses which nonetheless do not share
the same duration. Since archaeology displaces continuous history and
the subjectivity and philosophies of experience that undergird continu-
ous history, history as a general term no longer makes sense except as
‘a multiplicity of time spans that entangle and envelop one another’
(Foucault 1998: 430). In fact, Foucault suggests that the archive itself,
however general, is multiple. As a ground, the archive is something
like a floating foundation or a tectonic plate, which is to say it is itself
unstable and itself roiled by the transformations that it enables. From
the perspective of the present, the ground is shifting under our feet, as it
is always shifting, but such that, while we may be able to more or less
trace previous shifts, we cannot predict the specific character of shifts
that are happening now, just as nobody can predict when and where
an earthquake will happen or how powerful it will be. Hence Foucault
says: ‘it is not possible for us to describe our own archive, since it is from
within these rules that we speak’ (2010: 130). The rules that allow us
to speak as we do are being rewritten as we speak, and because we are
speaking. As diagnostician of the present, the archaeologist will study
the archive in its close proximity to us and isolate those rules that mark
us in our difference from what we can no longer say.
Deleuze characterises Foucault’s discontinuous history as a Markov
process, a random process in which only the current state of a system in
flux can be used to assign the probability of what the next state will be
(Deleuze 1988: 86). This is an apt characterisation, and it points to the
difference between Deleuze and Foucault concerning time and history.
Markov processes do not have a memory, so while on the one hand it
might be said that the discontinuities that archaeology identifies order
time into a before and after, or that the archive is like the event for all
events, it is on the other hand true that the archive is not a totality,
and that once-active relations can become inert, forgotten or put out
of play as the archive transforms. One of Foucault’s main purposes in
writing The Archaeology of Knowledge was to show how sciences both
Time and the Untimely 113
Notes
1. For two nice synopses of the relationship between Deleuze and Foucault, see
Nicolae Morar, Thomas Nail and Daniel W. Smith, ‘Introduction: Between
Deleuze and Foucault’, and François Dose, ‘Deleuze and Foucault: A Philosophical
Friendship’, in Morar et al. (eds) 2016.
2. This well-known quote from Discipline and Punish is a translation of the French
l’histoire du présent. Foucault sometimes seems to conflate actualité and présent,
as when he says in a 1981 interview that one task of philosophy is to ‘s’interroger
sur ce que nous sommes dans notre présent et dans notre actualité’ (Berten 1988:
10). However, Deleuze and Guattari interpret him as differentiating between
présent and actualité in L’archeologie du Savoir, as when he says, ‘L’analyse de
l’archive comporte donc une région privilégiée: à la fois proche de nous, mais
différente de notre actualité, c’est la bordure du temps qui entoure notre present’
(Foucault 1969: 172). On the basis of this passage Deleuze and Guattari claim
that actualité corresponds to Nietzsche’s untimely while présent refers to what
we are, and therefore what we are in the process of no longer being.
References
Bell, J. A. and C. Colebrook, eds. (2009), Deleuze and History, Edinburgh:
Edinburgh University Press.
Berten, A. (1988), ‘Entretien avec Michel Foucault’, Les cahiers du GRIF, 37–38:
8–20.
Deleuze, G. (1983), Nietzsche and Philosophy, trans. Hugh Tomlinson, New York:
Columbia University Press.
Deleuze, G. (1988), Foucault, trans. Sean Hand, Minneapolis: University of
Minnesota Press.
Deleuze, G. (1990), The Logic of Sense, trans. Mark Lester and Charles Stivale, New
York: Columbia University Press.
Deleuze, G. (1994), Difference and Repetition, trans. Paul Patton, New York:
Columbia University Press.
Deleuze, G. (1995), Negotiations: 1972–1990, trans. Martin Joughin, New York:
Columbia University Press.
Time and the Untimely 115
Deleuze, G. and C. Parnet (2007), Dialogues II, trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Barbara
Habberjam, New York: Columbia University Press.
Deleuze, G. and F. Guattari (1983), Anti-Oedipus, trans. Robert Hurley, Mark
Seem and Helen R. Lane, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota.
Deleuze, G. and F. Guattari (1994), What Is Philosophy?, trans. Hugh Tomlinson
and Graham Burchell, New York: Columbia University Press.
Foucault, M. (1969), L’Archéologie du savoir, Paris: Gallimard.
Foucault, M. (1994), The Order of Things: An Archaeology of the Human Sciences,
New York: Vintage Books.
Foucault, M. (1995), Discipline and Punish, trans. Alan Sheridan, New York:
Vintage Books.
Foucault, M. (1998), Aesthetics, Method, and Epistemology: The Essential Works
of Michel Foucault, 1954–1984, trans. Robert Hurley and others, New York: The
New Press.
Foucault, M. (2006), History of Madness, trans. Jonathan Murphy and Jean Khalfa,
New York: Routledge.
Foucault, M. (2008), Introduction to Kant’s Anthropology, trans. Roberto Nigro
and Kate Briggs, Los Angeles: Semiotext(e).
Foucault, M. (2010), The Archaeology of Knowledge, trans. A. M. Sheridan Smith,
New York: Vintage Books.
Huffer, L. (2020), Foucault’s Strange Eros, New York: Columbia University Press.
Lampert, J. (2006), Deleuze and Guattari’s Philosophy of History, New York:
Continuum.
Lundy, C. (2016), ‘The Necessity and Contingency of Universal History: Deleuze
and Guattari contra Hegel’, Journal of the Philosophy of History, 10: 51–75.
Morar, N., T. Nail and D. W. Smith, eds. (2016), Between Deleuze and Foucault,
Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.
Nietzsche, F. (1997), Untimely Meditations, trans. R. J. Hollingdale, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Smith, D. W. (2012), Essays on Deleuze, Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.
Thompson, K. (2016), ‘From the Historical A Priori to the Dispositif: Foucault,
the Phenomenological Legacy, and the Problem of Transcendental Genesis’,
Continental Philosophy Review, 49: 41–54.
Williams, J. (2011), Gilles Deleuze’s Philosophy of Time: A Critical Introduction
and Guide, Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.
Chapter 6
Kant, Merleau-Ponty, Deleuze and the
Constitution of Experience
Henry Somers-Hall
We must make this notion of the world, which guides the whole transcen-
dental deduction of Kant, though Kant does not tell us its provenance,
more explicit. ‘If a world is to be possible’, he says sometimes, as if he
were thinking before the origin of the world, as if he were assisting at
its genesis and could pose its a priori conditions. In fact, as Kant himself
said profoundly, we can only think the world because we have already
experienced it; it is through this experience that we have the idea of being,
and it is through this experience that the words ‘rational’ and ‘real’ receive
a meaning simultaneously. (Merleau-Ponty 1964: 16)
Kant, Merleau-Ponty, Deleuze 117
Now, there are a number of key claims in this passage that will be
central to both Deleuze and Merleau-Ponty’s readings of Kant. First, we
can note that Merleau-Ponty makes a distinction here between think-
ing and experience. As we shall see, this distinction introduces two
different ways of understanding what it is for something to have a
determination, and has affinities with Deleuze’s own distinction between
representation and intensity. Second, Merleau-Ponty here implies that
Kant presupposes experience, but that he does not provide a proper
analysis of it. In Deleuze too, we shall find that for every synthesis Kant
proposes, Deleuze will argue that there is a passive synthesis that makes
it possible. Third, Kant illicitly assumes that the kind of determination
that we find in thinking or representation is prior to the genesis of the
world, and is responsible for it. Once again, this will be disputed by both
Deleuze and Merleau-Ponty, and here we can find an unlikely parallel
between Deleuze’s claim of a continuing ‘psychologism’ (1994: 135) in
the second edition of the Critique of Pure Reason and Merleau-Ponty’s
claim that Kant mischaracterises experience as ‘mutilated thought’
(1968: 35) in the Critique. For Deleuze, psychologism relates to a model
of the subject already overrun by representation, and Merleau-Ponty’s
mutilated thought is one that similarly understands experience from the
point of view of the categories of judgement.
I want to begin by looking at Kant’s account of synthesis in the first
Critique. We will focus on the transcendental deduction, but the aim
will be to look at what Kant takes synthesis to be. We will then explore
how this ties in to his account of determination as he sets it out in
the transcendental ideal, since it is this account that Deleuze takes up
explicitly. Following that, we will turn to Deleuze and Merleau-Ponty’s
accounts of synthesis. I will argue that Merleau-Ponty’s influence on
Deleuze’s account of synthesis is significant, despite the paucity of
explicit references to Merleau-Ponty in most of Deleuze’s work. We
will see how Deleuze’s account of determination as a lightning flash
can be understood in both Deleuzian and Merleau- Pontian terms.
Having seen how Deleuze and Merleau-Ponty’s accounts of determina-
tion differ from Kant’s, we will then explore how this difference in
determination leads both philosophers to a radically different notion of
synthesis.
Kant argues that ‘[i]t is one and the same spontaneity, which in the
one case, under the title of imagination, and in the other case, under
the title of understanding, brings combination into the manifold of
intuition’ (1929: B162n). The situation is more complicated in the A
deduction, though Longuenesse suggests that the imagination should
be taken in the A deduction simply as a non-reflective operation of
synthesis according to rules provided by the understanding, in contrast
to the reflective operation of the understanding proper.3 Regardless of
Kant, Merleau-Ponty, Deleuze 121
Kant combines this with a further claim that, for transcendental logic,
one of the opposed predicates must be understood as primary, and one
has to be understood as a limitation of it through the introduction of a
negation:
If, therefore, reason employs in the complete determination of things a tran-
scendental substrate that contains, as it were, the whole store of material
from which all possible predicates of things must be taken, this substrate
cannot be anything else than the idea of an omnitudo realitatis. All true
negations are nothing but limitations – a title which would be inapplicable,
were they not thus based up on the unlimited, that is, upon ‘the All’. (Kant
1929: A575–6/B603–4)
Now, we can note that for Kant this notion of complete determination
is a transcendental idea, which means that we need to assume it in order
for reason to investigate the world (if we do not assume that objects
are completely determined, then the law of excluded middle would not
hold, since it would be possible for an object to not have a particular
determination or its negation), but that its truth goes beyond the limits
of possible experience. As such, we can see that Kant’s account of the
synthesis of experience draws together two claims here. First that at
122 Henry Somers-Hall
Difference is the state in which one can speak of determination as such. The
difference ‘between’ two things is only empirical, and the corresponding
determinations are only extrinsic. However, instead of something distin-
guished from something else, imagine something which distinguishes itself
– and yet that from which it distinguishes itself does not distinguish itself
from it. Lightning, for example, distinguishes itself from the black sky but
must also trail it behind, as though it were distinguishing itself from that
which does not distinguish itself from it. It is as if the ground rose to the
surface, without ceasing to be ground. There is cruelty, even monstrosity,
on both sides of this struggle against an elusive adversary, in which the
distinguished opposes something which cannot distinguish itself from it but
continues to espouse that which divorces it. Difference is this state in which
determination takes the form of unilateral distinction. We must therefore
say that difference is made, or makes itself, as in the expression ‘make the
difference’. (Deleuze 1994: 28)
applied to the universe and not to phenomena’ (2012: 50). Here too, we
have the assumption that our basic categories of understanding involve
an extensive view of the world, and rely on judgement and conceptual
determination. What are the basic characteristics of the sedentary model,
or the model of objective thought?
First, we can note that both objective thought and the sedentary
distribution deal with the existence of a field of ‘ready-made things’
(Merleau-Ponty 2012: 99). As Deleuze similarly puts it, ‘extensity does
not account for the individuations which occur within it’ (1994: 229).
In effect, for Kant, synthesis involves taking elements that already exist,
and synthesising them into unities. This allows us to see the world as ‘an
invariable system of relations to which every existing thing is subjected if
it is to be k
nown . . . like a crystal cube, where all possible presentations
can be conceived by its law of construction and that allows its hidden
sides to be seen in its present construction’ (Merleau-Ponty 2012: 342).
Second, the world for Kant is understood as composed of representa-
tions that themselves are all fully determinate. We have seen this already
in Kant’s notion of determination outlined above. There is thus a sym-
metry, or, as Kant argues in the Analogies, a reciprocity, between the
elements that make up the world around us. As Merleau-Ponty notes,
this model rests on an idea of temporality as a series of instantaneous
‘now’s, in which ‘every “elsewhere” is given as another here’ (2012:
348) such that everything can in principle be given at once as determi-
nate in perfect simultaneity.
Third, such a synthesis presupposes the notion of a self as the source
of the synthetic activity that relates together the representations. Kant
notes that even when the self isn’t clearly represented, it is still present in
our synthesis of the world:
Fourth, and following from all of the claims we have looked at so far,
ultimately synthesis takes as its model the synthesis of judgement, with
its concomitant claims to subsumptive relations between determinate
Kant, Merleau-Ponty, Deleuze 125
distinguishing itself from that which does not distinguish itself from
it’ (1994: 28). What would it mean for determination not to operate
reciprocally? Deleuze’s alternative to the sedimentary distribution is
the nomadic distribution. He describes this a situation where ‘there is
no longer a division of that which is distributed but rather a division
among those who distribute themselves in an open s pace – a space which
is unlimited, or at least without precise limits’ (36). We can see that this
also gives an account of synthesis, but not of the synthesis of a field of
elements by a subject, but rather of a field that synthesises itself. Rather
than diversity, which Deleuze associates with extensity, the nomadic
distribution instead operates in terms of difference. ‘Difference is not
diversity. Diversity is given, but difference is that by which the given is
given, that by which the given is given as diverse’ (222). Deleuze’s claim
is that this field of difference gives rise to the kinds of extensive proper-
ties that Kant talks about in terms of intensity.
Deleuze takes as his model here embryogenesis, with the egg as a
qualitatively indeterminate field that determines the development of the
embryo within it. Deleuze argues that the development of an embryo is a
process whereby determinate features emerge from an apparently homo-
geneous field. We can see the egg as a field that appears homogeneous,
but which is composed of gradients of intensities. The embryo develops
through an unfolding through velocities and distances that are governed
by these gradients. In effect, therefore, the egg is for Deleuze a field of
forces that determines the transformations of the embryo as it develops.
Now, Deleuze argues that ‘the world is an egg’ (1994: 251), thereby sug-
gesting that these processes can be generalised to everything that exists:
Here too, however, the positive element lies less in the elements of the given
symmetry than in those which are missing. An intensity forming a wave
of variation throughout the protoplasm distributes its difference along the
axes and from one pole to another. The region of maximal activity is the
first to come into play, exercising a dominant influence on the development
of the corresponding parts at a lower rate: the individual in the egg is a
genuine descent, going from the highest to the lowest and affirming the
differences which comprise it and in which it falls. (Deleuze 1994: 250)
We can note a number of key features that emerge from this account
of the embryo. First, the space of the embryo cannot be understood
as a simple extensive space. Rather, the development of the embryo
takes place through processes of folding the structure of space itself:
‘Embryology shows that the division of an egg into parts is secondary
in relation to more significant morphogenetic movements: the augmen-
Kant, Merleau-Ponty, Deleuze 127
the visual field is not easy to describe, but it is certainly neither black nor
grey. (Merleau-Ponty 2012: 6)
Asymmetrical Synthesis
Merleau-Ponty is not mentioned in the long bibliography at the end of
Difference and Repetition, and is barely mentioned within the text itself.
Nonetheless, we find that Deleuze’s account of the three syntheses in
chapter five of Difference and Repetition makes clear the importance
of Merleau-Ponty’s work for Deleuze. Here, the concern is with space
rather than time, but ‘we should not be surprised that the pure spatial
syntheses repeat the temporal syntheses previously specified’ (Deleuze
1994: 230). In the syntheses of time, we begin with the structure of
habit and discover that habit could only be understood in terms of an
ontologically prior field of memory. Here, Deleuze begins with three
oppositions: ‘up and down, the right and the left, and the figure and the
ground’ (229, translation modified).10 Each of these oppositions is dealt
with in detail by Merleau-Ponty in relation to his discussion of extensity,
and in each case he argues that the opposition can only be properly
understood if we assume that our relation to space is perspectival. As
such, we can see here Deleuze recognising Merleau-Ponty as a precursor,
implicitly arguing that Merleau-Ponty’s discussion of perspective can be
understood as an analysis of intensity in another element.
So how do these asymmetrical syntheses differ from the symmetrical
synthesis of Kant’s philosophy? Let us return to the six characteristics
of the symmetrical synthesis, and see how they compare to those of the
asymmetrical synthesis.
First, as we saw, the symmetrical synthesis involves a combination
of ready-made representations. Now, Kant’s account is constitutive of
experience, in that the transcendental unity of apperception is outside
of time. As such, it is a synthesis of constitution from nowhere in that
it precedes space and time, and it operates in terms of ready-made ele-
ments. For Deleuze, synthesis operates between two levels, and is a con-
tinuous process of communication between these two levels: ‘In reality,
the individual can only be contemporaneous with its individuation, and
individuation, contemporaneous with the principle: the principle must
be truly genetic, and not simply a principle of reflection. Also, the indi-
vidual is not just a result, but an environment of individuation’ (Deleuze
2004: 86). This process of movement between intensity and extensity is
precisely what constituted the qualities taken up by representation, not
as states, but rather themselves as processes of difference. For Merleau-
Ponty too, we saw that through the process of attention we did not
simply have the illumination of the world, but rather the constitution
of properties. Just as for Deleuze synthesis is a continual process of
Kant, Merleau-Ponty, Deleuze 131
Conclusion
I want to conclude this chapter by considering two questions. First, why
does Kant fall into the errors that he does? And second, how do we dis-
tinguish Merleau-Ponty and Deleuze? The response to the first question
is that it is by understanding time in terms of moments that we fall into
error, and that so long as we understand synthesis to operate in relation
to judgement, we cannot help but fall into this error. Time cannot be
reconstituted once it has been broken up into discrete atomic elements.
‘It thinks it can comprehend our natal bond with the world only by
undoing it in order to remake it, only by constituting it, by fabricating
it’ (Merleau-Ponty 1968: 32). The ultimate implication of this for both
Deleuze and Merleau-Ponty is that traditional accounts of synthesis
are unable to explain our experience within time without recourse to
paradox. Merleau-Ponty puts the point as follows:
Kant, Merleau-Ponty, Deleuze 133
Notes
1. For both, transcendental illusion is a key methodological discovery that is
not taken far enough by Kant himself. Merleau-Ponty explicitly takes Kant’s
account of the antinomies into his own methodology, noting that ‘One of
Kant’s discoveries, whose consequences we have not yet fully grasped, is that
all our experience of the world is throughout a tissue of concepts which lead
to irreducible contradictions if we attempt to take them in an absolute sense or
transfer them into pure being, and that they nevertheless found the structure
of all our phenomena, of everything which is for us. It would take too long
to show (and besides it is well known) that Kantian philosophy itself failed
to utilise this principle fully and that both its investigation of experience and
its critique of dogmatism remained incomplete’ (1964: 18–19). Deleuze takes
134 Henry Somers-Hall
References
Allison, H. (2004), Kant’s Transcendental Idealism: An Interpretation and Defense,
New Haven: Yale University Press.
Ansell-Pearson, K. (2001) Philosophy and the Adventure of the Virtual, London:
Routledge.
Deleuze, G. (1978), ‘Cours Vincennes: Synthesis and Time’, trans. Melissa
McMahon, at <https://www.webdeleuze.com/textes/66>.
Deleuze, G. (1990), The Logic of Sense, trans. Mark Lester with Charles Stivale,
London: Athlone Press.
Deleuze, G. (1994), Difference and Repetition, trans. Paul Patton, New York:
Columbia University Press.
Deleuze, G. (1998), ‘To Have Done with Judgment’, in Essays Critical and Clinical,
trans. Daniel W. Smith and Michael A. Greco, London: Verso.
Deleuze, G. (2004), ‘On Gilbert Simondon’, in Desert Islands and Other Texts 1953–
1974, ed. David Lapoujade, trans. Mike Taormina, Los Angeles: Semiotext(e).
Kant, I. (1929), Critique of Pure Reason, trans. Norman Kemp Smith, London:
Macmillan.
Longuenesse, B. (2001), Kant and the Capacity to Judge: Sensibility and Discursivity
in the Transcendental Analytic of the Critique of Pure Reason, trans. Charles T.
Wolf, Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Merleau- Ponty, M. (1964), ‘The Primacy of Perception’, in The Primacy of
Perception, ed. James M. Edie, Evanston: Northwestern University Press.
Merleau-Ponty, M. (1968), The Visible and the Invisible, ed. Claude Lefort, trans.
Alphonso Lingis, Evanston: Northwestern University Press.
Merleau-Ponty, M. (2012), The Phenomenology of Perception, trans. Donald A.
Landes, Abingdon: Routledge.
Somers-Hall, H. (2011), ‘Time Out of Joint: Hamlet and the Pure Form of Time’,
Deleuze Studies, 5 (supplement): 56–76.
Somers- Hall, H. (2012), Deleuze’s Difference and Repetition: An Edinburgh
Philosophical Guide, Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.
Somers- Hall, H. (2019), ‘Merleau- Ponty’s Reading of Kant’s Transcendental
Idealism’, The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 57 (1): 103–31.
Williams, J. (2004), Deleuze’s Difference and Repetition: A Critical Introduction
and Guide, Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.
Chapter 7
Disjoint and Multiply: Deleuze and Negri
on Time
Peter Trnka
The joint, cardo, is what ensures the subordination of time to those prop-
erly cardinal points through which pass the periodic movements which it
measures . . . By contrast, time out of joint means demented time or time
outside the curve which gave it a god, liberated from its overly simple
circular figure, freed from the events which made up its content, its relation
to movement overturned; in short, time presenting itself as an empty and
pure form. Time itself u nfolds . . . instead of things unfolding within it . . .
It ceases to be cardinal and becomes ordinal, a pure order of time. (Deleuze
1994: 88; emphasis added)
Preamble
In the spirit of Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari’s collaboration, or dein-
dividuated authorial coupling ‘between you and me’, we speak together
(or not at all) as a fused reader-writer becoming-couple; a reader reading
written signs of some writer(s) is the minimal threshold or condition.
In the imperative mode: disjoint, multiply, time or times, that is. An
imperative, however, of exhortation, not command. We speak together,
for the displacement and disjointing of unitary imposed time, that is,
work time.
Presuming for now, at least at the limit (and the limit is, as we shall
see below, the measure of the gradient or scissor angle between formal
and real subsumption), more and more, all time is work time, as if all
digital clocks had hidden punches. Work time is the marching time of
‘one-two-three-four-one-two-three-four’: regular, automatic, endlessly
repetitive, instituting fast grooves to follow-fill. So on and so on and so
on and so on.
Dis-joint, de-couple, dis-place. Favour, instead, multiplication. Love
multiplies. Add and add and then take adding to the next power. Increase
Disjoint and Multiply 137
and fold over the increases to increase faster and at different scales.
Release the folds of plural times, bloom a hundred flowers, explicate a
thousand plateaus or levels.
Practice over theory, action over representation, knowing full well
that as we use the technology or machine of language, the name of the
thing tends to insist it is done and finished, pushing any dynamic tenden-
cies, flows and fluxes of time to the margins, peripheries, and dumping
lots of error.1
As if time does not infect all things. As if names as fixed identities
do not always fail. As if we had some continued interest in thingifying,
reifying, fetishising, idolising.
The practical mode is the futural mode of what is to be done: what is
to be made, to-come to-be. Revolutionary communism2 is futural and in
the infinitive: live to multiply futures. At times these futures are exclu-
sively micropolitical, molecular, micro-futures (a shared glance across a
room), but there are also rarer molar shifts, revolutions in fundamental
modes of being. Futures, of course, come with things, whole worlds of
things in each and every new time.
Our method is to read Deleuze, his work alone and in collaboration
with Guattari, through his friend and comrade Negri. This serves the
purpose of a clear political line, to Marx that is. We begin, then, in
the next section, with Negri’s reading of Marx, and of Marx’s theory
of time. The third section features Deleuze’s thought of time, in his
singularly authored works and with Guattari in A Thousand Plateaus
(oddly, for philosophy, many authorial couples in these territories:
Marx-Engels, Deleuze-Guattari and Negri-Hardt). Section four on the
time-image is something like an example of a collective phenomeno-
logical constitution of new machines and new experiences of time. The
differences between Deleuze and Negri on time appear to centre on
their differential appraisals of Spinoza’s thought of time, duration and
eternity, which we will tease out at some length in section five, with the
help of Spinoza scholars Samuel Alexander, H. F. Hallett and David
Savan.
When Negri speaks of a ‘communist idea of time’, and specifies that
‘[r]evolution is born from the pathways of a constitutive phenomenol-
ogy of temporality’ (2003: 21), he is putting the politics of time, its
production, control, circulation, distribution and exchange, at the heart
of liberation struggles. Time is not money. Time is living labour. Time
is life.
Translate academic vocabularies and grammatologies. Believe that you
can do something to change the fucked-up world. Update the eleventh
138 Peter Trnka
The synchronic rules are modified within the framework of the diachronic
transition. (Negri 2003: 42)
the ontological composition of the events that expresses itself as power and
imagines itself as reality to-come. (Negri 2003: 157)
The expression of power is at one and the same time an act of imagina-
tion: an imagining, in the full concrete desiring aching sense; imagining,
wanting, demanding and making what is to-come. Imagination is here
Hume’s constructive power, as affirmed in the mad, fabulous sense of
Deleuze’s Empiricism and Subjectivity (see Trnka 1997). Such a positive
and absolutely free imagination is far from the tamed Kantian faculty.
As constructive, in Negri’s terminology, constitutive power, imagination
is an ontological force; it is real and makes things real. Subjectivity has
real forms and real effects.
Unitary command time and the multitudes of liberated times are
opposed and co-implicated; Negri claims that ‘[w]ith these two refer-
ences (to Marx and Deleuze) before us, we find ourselves introduced
to the full experience of the power of the Kairos’ (2003: 158). What
is Kairos? It is ‘the power to observe the fullness of temporality at the
moment it opens itself onto the void of being, and of seizing this opening
as innovation. The common name is situated in the passage (Kairos)
from fullness to the void: it is a common and imaginative act of produc-
tion’ (158). It is not a decision, in some Schmittian-Hobbesian possessive
individualist nominalist ontology, but a collective historical work of the
multitudes of intellectual and manual workers, in the broadest sense of
those subjectivities who think, feel and move. The common name, such
as, for example, ‘communism’, ‘democracy’, ‘freedom’, ‘is not only the
sign of the singular existent in the instant that links the act of naming to
the thing named, nor is it solely the seeking of multiplicity in surveying
over the edge of time. Situated within the power of the production of
being, it is also the construction of the telos of generation’ (158), the
tendency of the striving and work of the collective: ‘It is this production,
that is to say this generation, which we call praxis’ (158). Praxis is col-
lective goal-oriented practical activity. Praxis makes what is to come.
What was to come and did, of course, has constituted us and our
situations, tools and weapons. To the draw of the future over the push
of the past Negri ‘give[s] the name of “to-come” . . . the horizon of
experimentation of the adequation of the name and the thing, and to
the imaginative perspective that – in realizing itself – presents itself as
new being’ (2003: 163). This is a perspective in accord with ordinary
experience:
The everyday sense of life confirms the definition of that ‘which is coming’
as to-come, rather than as future. It is . . . in the struggle for the free
142 Peter Trnka
appropriation of the present that life opens itself to the to-come, and desire
perceives – a gainst the empty and homogeneous time in which all is equal
(including, and in particular, the future) – the creative power of praxis.
(Negri 2003: 163)7
It just has, it is just about to, but it is not now. ‘The infinitely divisible
event is always both at once’, Deleuze writes. ‘It is eternally that which
has just happened and that which is about to happen, but never that
which is happening’ (1990: 8). The vein of paradox, which Deleuze
affirms positively, is appropriate to the attempt to think time.
The logic of the time of the event is posited in a counter-actualised
Stoic ontology of sense, filled with bits of Bergsonian durée. Events are
typically out of reach, on stage, separated from the limit of one’s powers,
out of bounds, spectacularised, as in Hollywood. Desiring8 to become
an actor of one’s own events, ‘the actor delimits the original, disengages
from it an abstract line, and keeps from the event only its contour and its
splendor, becoming thereby the actor of one’s own events – a counter-
actualization’ (Deleuze 1990: 150).9 As I’ve shown elsewhere (Trnka
2001: 56), Deleuze’s ‘ultimate sense of counter- actualization’ brings
together the time of the infinitive with the construction of a concept and
the notion of an event, such that an individual involved would ‘grasp
the event actualized within her as another individual grafted onto her’
144 Peter Trnka
Time-Image Paradigm
A paradigm of the historically dynamic constitution of a machinic
assemblage of subjectivity, one that allows us to imagine time as never
before: cinema, and, more specifically, its later ‘time- image’ (which
Deleuze distinguishes in historical and formal ways from the original
‘movement-image’). Procedure led to a course of machines, producing
generations of subjectivities and multiplications of times. In the second
volume of his Cinema: The Time-Image, the machinic assemblage con-
cerns the future to come:
The French school never lost its taste for clockwork automata and clock-
making characters, but also confronted machines with moving parts, like
the American or Soviet schools. The man-machine assemblage varies from
case to case, but always with the intention of posing the question of the
future. (Deleuze 1989: 263)
For the time-image to be born . . . t he actual image must enter into relation
with its own virtual image as such; from the outset pure description must
divide in two, ‘repeat itself, take itself up again, fork, contradict itself’.
An image which is double-sided, mutual, both actual and virtual, must be
constituted. (Deleuze 1989: 273)
The image has two sides or faces at one and the same time:
We are no longer in the situation of a relationship between the actual image
and other virtual images, recollections, or dreams, which thus become
actual in turn: this is still a mode of linkage. We are in the situation of an
actual image and its own virtual image, to the extent that there is no longer
any linkage of the real with the imaginary, but indiscernibility of the two, a
perpetual exchange. (Deleuze 1989: 273)
The two are one and yet differ in a perpetual relay of exchange. At the late
capitalist postmodern moment of spectacularised society, we affirm the
pre-eminence of imagination and the early affirmation of time and social
constitution in David Hume: ‘Repetition changes nothing in the object
repeated, but does change something in the mind which contemplates
it. Hume’s famous thesis takes us to the heart of a problem’ (Deleuze
1994: 70). So Deleuze situates in relation to Hume his own work on
repetition in Difference and Repetition. Deleuze glosses Hume’s thesis as
follows: ‘Time is constituted only in the originary synthesis which oper-
ates on the repetition of instants. This synthesis contracts the successive
independent instants into one another, thereby constituting the lived, or
living, present’ (70).
Imaginative constructive habit à la Hume is the basic psychic machine,
the free productive agency which gives birth to memory and reason:
The passive synthesis of habit [first] in turn refers to . . . [a] more profound
passive synthesis of memory: Habitus and Mnemosyne, the alliance of the
sky and the ground. Habit is the originary synthesis of time, which consti-
tutes the life of the passing present; Memory is the fundamental synthesis of
time which constitutes the being of the past (that which causes the present
to pass). (Deleuze 1994: 79–80)11
Hence the subject’s creation in and of time, by way of the capacity of
synthesis, of holding things together.
The time-image extends our account of Deleuze’s theory and practice
of temporal constitution, and also exemplifies an emergent quality, a
new experience and collective constitution of time that is cinema.12
Temenuga Trifonova begins her ‘A Nonhuman Eye: Deleuze on Cinema’
by linking Deleuze to the Sartre of Imagination and The Psychology of
Imagination and characterising their joint venture (with Bergson) as one
148 Peter Trnka
Let us take our bearings from the Ethics itself at two points, a random
couple from Spinoza’s admittedly few explicitly positive mentions of
time in the work. Consider, first, this temporal qualification of the
nature of individuals, from IIIP8: ‘The conatus with which each single
thing endeavors to persist in its own being does not involve finite time,
but indefinite time’ (Spinoza 1982: 110). And consider this with the
later claim, at VP29, wherein Spinoza is developing his understanding
of the most virtuous form of conatus or striving, i.e., the drive to know
and love God or Nature: ‘Whatever the mind understands under a form
of eternity it does not understand from the fact that it conceives the
present actual existence of the body, but from the fact that it conceives
the essence of the body under a form of eternity’ (218). The Proof is
expansive on the relation between time as measure, the felt experience
of duration, and the eternal point of view:
In so far as the mind conceives the present existence of its body, to that
extent it conceives a duration that can be determined by time, and only to
that extent does it have the power to conceive things in relation to t ime . . .
But eternity cannot be explicated through d uration . . . T
herefore to that
extent the mind does not have the power to conceive things under a form of
eternity. But since it is the nature of reason to conceive things under a form
of eternity . . ., and since it belongs to the nature of mind, too, to conceive
of the essence of the body under a form of eternity . . . and since there
belongs to the essence of mind nothing but these two ways of conceiving
. . ., it follows that this power to conceive things under a form of eternity
pertains to the mind only in so far as it conceives the essence of the body
under a form of eternity. (Spinoza 1982: 218)
We will not explicate the full sense of this passage but only note the
differentiation between measurable and hence unreal time, on the one
side, and real duration, on the other; and, second, the possibility, as
well as the limitation and warning concerning, the movement from
duration to eternity. Alexander’s critical dismissal of Spinoza on time is
precociously quick. ‘Time has been slipped’, he alleges, ‘into Extension
out of the undefined activity of God’ (1939: 359). He continues on
to explain that while we contemporaries ‘might be tempted to say
that extension includes not only extension in space but duration in
time’ and that such a supposition would ‘solve Spinoza’s problem’,
yet ‘there is no word of it in Spinoza and could not be’. It is our
contention that there indeed could be and was. Alexander makes the
implausible assumption that Spinoza simply misconceives motion: ‘The
truth appears to be that Spinoza could pass so easily from extension
to motion because motion was conceived as it were statically’ (359).
Disjoint and Multiply 151
Perfection and the expression of the totality are seen as productive and
differentiating, not representative or copying. Hallett is clear on the
real qualitative felt character of duration in distinction from time as
measure: ‘Spinoza’s theory of joy . . . m
ust be taken as his recognition
that the finite mind perceives duration, not as separated puncta, but as
quality. Pure externality belongs only to time and measure, and these
are unreal’ (1930: 59). Duration, in distinction, is process; it is qualita-
tive, not quantitative; ‘and the essence of existence, even of enduring
existence, is that very qualitative growth through which we escape the
“absolute relativity” of mere time (and the self-contradictory phrase
exactly describes the logical vice of both time and measure)’ (59). Hallett
argues that Bergson’s ‘intensive quantity, i.e., a quality’ (59), is not a
refutation of Spinoza but ‘a partial and inadequate Spinozism; for it is
not, strictly speaking, the past as past that permeates the present, but
only the past as the given, and therefore as our main source of creative
essence’ (60). What is creative production?
The creativity of duration is one with the determination of the temporal
occurrence of individual things and minds, and this again with the produc-
tion by the eternal whole of its own finite expressions or partial content.
It is the nature of the whole so to express itself and, in expressing, to
constitute itself; and since ‘matter was not lacking to him for the creation
of everything from the highest down to the lowest degree of perfection’
[Ethics I, Appendix], the expressions are of every degree of completeness,
and cannot but appear, therefore, to the finite expressions themselves as
incomplete and successive, i.e., as involving limited duration. The creativity
of duration is thus but a finite extract of real creativity, which is eternal and
constitutive. (Hallett 1930: 61)
And if that is not clear enough, the footnote spells it out: ‘All existence
is, in a sense, miraculous: that is the significance of the term “creation”;
but there is nothing in “emergent qualities” more demanding of natural
piety than in the constitution of Space-Time itself. My thesis is that
Space-Time and its so called “emergent” qualities should never have
been divorced’ (Hallett 1930: 61).
The new, emergent, positive quality is a part of the whole, expressive
and expressed, and as such, eternal in its formal essence:
positive quality is caught up into eternity, while its externality and limita-
tion, its negativity, is lost . . . J oy is the realizing of perfection in its degrees,
its temporal achieving; acquiescentia is the realization of a perfection already
achieved; blessedness is the realization of perfection and its eternal achieve-
ment; it is the ideal limit of both desire and joy as they constitute a being for
whom transformation involves no succession. (Hallett 1930: 61–2)13
Disjoint and Multiply 153
For Hallett, as for Negri and, as we shall see shortly, David Savan also,
the distinction between Natura naturans and Natura naturata is real
and explanatory of Spinoza’s doctrine of creation, implying ‘an eternal
act’: ‘Substance as Natura naturans, in expressing itself in the complete
modal system, Natura naturata, in the same eternal act recreates itself
with infinite degrees of perfection, and thereby creates the nature which
it expresses, and which expresses it’ (Hallett 1930: 206).14
Qualitative, intensive synthesis, that is the character, according to
Hallett, of the movement in and to eternity. ‘Time is the phenomenon of
eternity’, he claims, and ‘eternity the infinite existence that determines
and comprehends all existence in time, and partly expresses itself in the
duration of things. Eternity at once transcends and pervades its finite
expressions’ (1930: 228). Such an eternity is ‘full’ or ‘purely intensive’;
it is qualitatively transforming but not successive.
A similar corroborating reading may be found in David Savan’s
‘Spinoza on Duration, Time, and Eternity’, which he begins by noting
his major presupposition – which we have now secured in a way in
advance – that Spinoza identifies God with Natura naturans and that
this means ‘generative action’ as per Ethics I P29S, 4 Pref (Savan 1994:
4). The participation of the modes in eternity by way of qualitative
transformation in duration is a sempiternity, as Savan defines it:
The universe is an infinite individual. Like any mode, its existence does not
follow necessarily from its essence. It endures. Since there is no individual
mode external to it that could produce it or destroy it, it must endure always
without beginning or end. Its duration must be everlasting, perpetual, or
sempiternal. Yet Spinoza called the universe an infinite and eternal mode (E
IP21, 22, & Ep 64). (Savan 1994: 7)
Sempiternal comes from semper, meaning eternal duration. Savan’s goal
is ‘to show that it is Spinoza’s new conception of eternity that enables
him to distinguish the eternity of God, incompatible with sempiternity,
and the eternity of the infinite and sempiternal universe’ (7).
Nature is eternal and durational:
The identity of essence and existence . . . is simply the identity of the
unlimited causal power of nature with the infinite variety of its actual and
intelligible effects. Eternity is infinite actual existence, natura naturata, con-
ceived as the necessary display of an infinitely originative activity, natura
naturans. There is a divergence here between what is in fact the c ase – the
identity of nature’s power with nature’s actuality – and the conceived
distinction of antecedent from consequent. Eternity is a way of conceiving
the real unity of nature, dividing that unity conceptually into two – active
cause and necessary effect. (Savan 1994: 21)
154 Peter Trnka
Conclusion
The association of time with communism is consistent through much
of Negri’s work. In Marx Beyond Marx he identifies communism with
‘the negation of all measure’ (1991a: 33). Hardt and Negri in Empire
propose the following definition of time:
The new phenomenology of the multitude reveals labor as the fundamen-
tal creative activity that through cooperation goes beyond any obstacle
imposed on it and constantly re-creates the world. The activity of the
multitude constitutes time beyond measure. Time might thus be defined
as the immeasurability of the movement between a before and an after, an
immanent process of constitution. (Hardt and Negri 2000: 402)
And in the Spinoza book, Negri is clear and unequivocal concerning the
future-oriented character of Spinozism:
The anomaly of Spinoza’s thought with respect to his times is made . . .
a savage anomaly: savage because it is articulated in the density and the
multiplicity of affirmations that rise up out of the unlimited affability of the
infinite . . . When the paradox of the world and the open tension contained
in it between the positive infinity and the infinity of determinations is
developed in activity and is recognized in the constitutive process, the
pleasure of the world begins to become central, and the anomaly is made
savage: savage because it is connected to the inexhaustible multiplicity of
being, to its blossomings, which are as vast as they are agitated in flux.
(Negri 1991b: 222)
There is no concern for the subordination or impotence of the modes
on Negri’s view. He then goes on to link Spinozism to the philosophy
of the future:
The Spinozian problematic of spatial being, as spatial constitution, with
spatial production, coming to an end, is a proposal for the metaphysics
of time. Not of time as becoming, as the most recent Modern philosophy
would have it: because the Spinozian perspective excludes every object of
becoming outside of the determination of the constitution. Rather, it is
a proposal of metaphysics of time as constitution, the time that extends
beyond the actuality of being, the being that constructs and selects its
future. A philosophy of the future. (Negri 1991b: 199)
Disjoint and Multiply 155
For Negri, Spinoza does a better job than Nietzsche for the future, and
perhaps Spinoza may also do better than Nietzsche and Bergson on time,
duration and eternity. Doing better in thinking time, duration and eter-
nity by way of the imaginative-selection-and-construction-of-new-being:
the inscription of power in being opens being toward the future. The
essential tension wants existence. The cumulative process that constructs
the world wants a further time, a future. The composition of the subject
acquits the past only to make it tend toward the future. Being is temporal
tension. If difference forms the future, then here the future ontologically
founds d ifference . . . A continuous transition toward always greater perfec-
tion. Being produces itself . . . Being is greater tension toward the future as
its present density grows to a higher level. The future is not a procession
of acts but a dislocation worked by the infinite mass of intensive being: a
linear, spatial displacement. Time is being. Time is the being of the t otality
. . . Being that is dislocated from one point to the next in space, in its infin-
ity, in its totality, accomplishes a passage in the order of perfection, that
is, in its construction. Not in relation to any other, but only in relation to
itself. Therefore, it is liberation, emancipation, transition. Time is ontology.
Constitution internal to production, and also internal to freedom. (Negri
1991b: 228)
For Negri, Spinoza plays a more crucial role than even the thinker of
immanence and univocity in Deleuze. Negri’s Spinoza is the philosopher
of the future and of the radical democratic communist constitution of
future times, by putting immanence and univocity within a constructive,
constitutive, dynamic totality, or growing universe. Repetition and dif-
ference, tension, extension and intensification are its basic patterns of
operation.
What times are to come? Better: what times will subjects be able
to enjoy? Let us return to the time-image. The time-image expresses
a new collective experience and constitution of time, and as such, a
transformation of subjectivity (by a new human-machine assemblage).
This transformation is a liberation: subjectivity expresses itself more and
more in pure time. The coincidence of actual and virtual image in the
time-image forms its self-reference. The cinematic time-image allows us
to live more in the future. The future works on us more by way of the
time-image. We are more and more creatures of time.
Notes
1. Class struggle, and hence much of the form of history, is in part a contest over
apparatuses of thought, including fluency and literacy in various languages
and machines of expression and dissemination; we develop a brief example of
156 Peter Trnka
able force of its own, divisible without remainder, into the forces acting upon it’
(1994: 6). Savan maps time as measure, duration and eternity onto McTaggart’s
A, B and C series, which Negri (2003) appears to play with or, rather, deter-
ritorialise in his A, B, W and Y series.
14. Hallett is clear on expressionism in Spinoza: ‘The “creation” which is accepted
by Spinoza is thus not an action or set of actions initiated in time through
which what was previously non-existent came into being. God is not the causa
transiens of the world but its causa immanens, and creation is the infinite self-
manifestation of a being whose essence is to express himself. Creation is eternal.
And the distinction in the Real between that which is created and that which is
incarnate is the same as that within an “expression” between the expression of
the expressed, and the expressed expression’ (1930: 209).
References
Alexander, S. (1939), ‘Spinoza and Time’, in Philosophical and Literary Pieces,
London: Macmillan.
Deleuze, G. (1985), Cinema 2: L’Image-Temps, Paris: Les Éditions de Minuit.
Deleuze, G. (1989), Cinema 2: The Time-Image, trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Robert
Galeta, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Deleuze, G. (1990), The Logic of Sense, trans. Mark Lester with Charles Stivale,
New York: Columbia University Press.
Deleuze, G. (1992), Expressionism in Philosophy: Spinoza, trans. Martin Joughin,
New York: Zone Books.
Deleuze, G. (1994), Difference and Repetition, trans. Paul Patton, New York:
Columbia University Press.
Deleuze, G. and F. Guattari (1987), A Thousand Plateaus: Capitalism and
Schizophrenia II, trans. Brian Massumi, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota
Press.
Hallett, H. F. (1930), Aeternitas: A Spinozistic Study, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Hardt, M. and A. Negri (2000), Empire, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press.
Hunter, G., ed. (1994), Spinoza: The Enduring Questions, Toronto: University of
Toronto Press.
Lyotard, J-F. (1993), Libidinal Economy, trans. Iain Hamilton Grant, Bloomington:
Indiana University Press.
McTaggart, J. (1927), The Nature of Existence, Volume II, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Massumi, B. (1987), ‘Foreword’ to Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari, A Thousand
Plateaus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia II, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota
Press.
Negri, A. (1991a), Marx Beyond Marx: Lessons on the Grundrisse, trans. Harry
Cleaver, Michael Ryan and Maurizio Viano, New York: Autonomedia/Pluto.
Negri, A. (1991b), The Savage Anomaly: The Power of Spinoza’s Metaphysics and
Politics, trans. Michael Hardt, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Negri, A. (1999), Insurgencies: Constituent Power and the Modern State,
Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Negri, A. (2003), Time for Revolution, trans. Matteo Mandarini, New York:
Continuum.
Negri, A. and M. Hardt (2000), Empire, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Piercey, R. (1996), ‘The Spinoza-Intoxicated Man: Deleuze on Expression’, Man
and World, 29: 269–81.
158 Peter Trnka
EXPRESSIONS OF TIME
Chapter 8
Kill Metaphor: Kafka’s Becoming-Animal
and the Deterritorialisation of Language
as a Rejection of Stasis
Charlene Elsby
Part of the fault rests in our concept of r eference – t hat is, the concept
of reference as a relation between two discrete entities, a word and a
thing, one of which symbolises the other. (This definition, which I in
no way endorse, renders all language symbolic, and only emboldens
the sophists.4) Pervasive not only in the interpretation of literature but
also in its creation is this insidious habit of always having present to
mind some significance outside of the work itself – this tendency to not
only produce or consume text but also to kill it, to assign it a meaning
outside of the text itself, to set the text aside in favour of this meaning,
and then proceed without it, the text becoming incidental to the external
significance, the stripping of all that is concrete from the story in favour
of some abstraction, which the history of western philosophy tells us is
superior to all concretions, the concrete being something of which we
must rid ourselves in order to access the idea of the text in the pure realm
of ideas, the eternal forms. Assigning metaphor to a text is practising for
death. The process fixes the text amongst the known, rendering it static.
The pigs are capitalists capitalism is bad the pigs are only there to
make a point, to act as a tool, a means or a metaphor, and altogether
incidental to the grander idea concerning the ideal political system.5
But since Nietzsche, the redemption of the body in philosophy has
become central to both Deleuzian and phenomenological thought. And
according to phenomenological conceptions of literature, the body of
the work is its materiality, the graphic elements of the text and their
phonetic formations, prior to and undergirding the stratum of ideal
meaning units by which we assign static meanings to terms. By refusing
to render Kafka’s text symbolic, these philosophers allow the body of
the work to stay alive. It is anima and animal. ‘Becoming-animal’, for
Deleuze, is not a metaphor; he is using the term in accordance with its
definition.
The human concept of literature, on the other hand, is its death. It’s
the rationalisation of what is specifically expressed in a non-rational
form (the literary work of art), to its detriment. While I’m sure it’s not
what Kafka meant when he said that his literary works were failures, if
only all literary works could be such failures.6
By failure here, I mean the existential dichotomy of attempting to
overcome the subjective in favour of the objective and always being
forced back into the subjective.7 (It is worthwhile to note that Deleuze
was not a fan of the idea that there existed any kind of pure cogito that
does or does not persist. All ‘subjective’ means here is ‘perspectival’, in
the sense of a zero point of orientation unique to an individual human.)
I conceive of the literary work of art as active within the realm of
Kill Metaphor 163
Thus, the art (modern art in this sense) that Kafka tried to introduce is
effectively no longer an art that proposes to ‘express’ (a meaning), to
‘represent’ (a thing, a being), or to ‘imitate’ (a nature). It is rather a method
(of writing) – of picking up, even of stealing: of ‘double stealing’ as Deleuze
sometimes says, which is both ‘stealing’ and ‘stealing away’ – that consists
in propelling the most diverse contents on the basis of (nonsignifying)
ruptures and intertwinings of the most heterogeneous orders of signs and
powers. (Bensmaïa 1986: xvii).
We’re agreed about imitators, then. Now, tell me this about a painter. Do
you think he tries in each case to imitate the thing itself in nature or the
works of craftsmen?
The works of craftsmen.
As they are or as they appear? You must be clear about that. How do
you mean?
Like this. If you look at a bed from the side or the front or from any-
where else is it a different bed each time? Or does it only appear different,
without being at all different?
And is that also the case with other things?
That’s the way it is – it appears different without being so.
Then consider this very point: What does painting do in each case? Does
it imitate that which is as it is, or does it imitate that which appears as it
appears? Is it an imitation of appearances or of truth?
Of appearances. (Plato 1997b: 1202)
that just because these arguments are bad ones, does not mean that all
arguments are bad, and proceeds on a path to soothe his listeners’ fear
of death through another method (storytelling). It is not beyond the
possible inferences one might make to argue that if every argument Plato
has Socrates present in favour of the soul’s immortality is in fact a bad
argument, then perhaps he did not mean to argue toward the conclusion
of those arguments at all.13
And that conclusion is immediately repugnant, for the conclusion to
be drawn from the ideas that the soul is immortal and that after death
it reunites with the forms with which it claims an affinity is that death
is good. This counter-intuitive conclusion is indeed what Socrates aims
to prove – in a dialogue in which he has been sentenced to death, as a
penalty.
The aim of philosophy in the Phaedo is the pursuit of theoretical
knowledge, and this knowledge is precisely of universals. The philoso-
pher, by pursuing this sort of knowledge, escapes from the lesser world
of material instantiations (defined by their particularity) toward a realm
of pure form. While our world is characterised by particulars, subject to
temporality, the crux of the affinity argument for the soul’s immortal-
ity is to characterise immortality as significantly similar to a form’s
eternality – devoid of material, it carries on.14
But what of a negative timelessness?
It is possible, within the variables given in Plato’s dialogue, that we
are meant to notice the disanalogy between the soul’s immortality and
a form’s eternality. For one, the soul’s immortality is meant to com-
mence when time comes to an end. This is a distinct state of affairs in
comparison to the form’s eternality, as the forms were never subject to
time. Plato takes as an assumption that a soul exists in time while it is
instantiated and even has the capacity to be affected by things in the tem-
poral realm, characteristics which are not shared with the forms. If we
are meant to infer this distinction, it is reasonable to assume that death
is not good, that death is bad, and that in contradistinction to eternality,
a negative timelessness is also possible, and this is death.
We are motivated to keep the literary work of art alive only if death is
negative, if death is conceived not as eternality but as stasis – if we value
the anima and lament its destruction. A reversal of Plato, or perhaps
an argument in support of a secret Platonic argument in favour of the
lifeworld, Deleuze and Guattari’s concept of Kafka’s literature as animal
reignites an axiology where particularity, situatedness and motion are
favourable to stasis, universality and death. Perhaps the universal is
problematic after all.
166 Charlene Elsby
having only one instance, but a universal nonetheless, just to escape his
particularity.
These cases in fact open up an extremely interesting version of lin-
guistic reference as a sort of tenuous fixation. Conceived of as such, we
could avoid the death of language (and consequently, literary works)
by allowing their continuity in flux. But the term ‘tenuous fixation’ is
not even enough, for Deleuze, as it’s an attempt to describe something
novel by applying old terminology, resulting in contradiction. (For the
tenuousness of the fixation renders it unfixed, recognising that what is
tenuous is really not fixed at all.) Rather, the attempt to affix a term
to a referent in such a way as to kill them both has brought tension
to the history of the philosophy of language and metaphysics as well.
But most interestingly, the demise of the fixed nature of the relation
of signifier and signified occurs in Husserl’s grappling with Aristotle
in his analyses of linguistic signification, in Ingarden’s adaptation of
Husserl’s phenomenology to his analysis of the literary work of art, and
finally in Merleau-Ponty’s concept of expression, ultimately leading to
the collapse of the signifier and what is signified, which finally lays the
groundwork for Deleuze’s murder of the metaphor.
mean, rather than how they have a meaning. The intimating function of
expressions is their capacity to point toward something, ‘meaning’ in the
sense of an act, while the ‘content’ of the expression is something else;
it’s a meaning in the sense of a noun. As Husserl describes in the First
Investigation:
all expressions in communicative speech function as indications. They serve
the hearer as signs of the ‘thoughts’ of the speaker, i.e. of his sense-giving
inner experiences, as well as of the other inner experiences which are part
of his communicative intention. This function of verbal expressions we
shall call their intimating function. The content of such intimation consists
in the inner experiences intimated. (Husserl 2001: 189)
In the case of independently significant expressions, the content of the
expression is pointed toward by the intimating function of the expres-
sion. But in the case of syncategorematic terms, the intimating function
becomes internal to the expression, specifying the way in which the
terms should be conceived of as related, rather than indicating any
additional content. They mean but do not have a meaning. ‘And’ does
not signify a separately existing relation, the third thing in the expres-
sion ‘this and that’, where ‘this’, ‘that’ and ‘and’ specify three separate
entities, one of which is representative of a separately existing relation-
ship of conjunction. The ‘and’ is non-referential, or non-independently
significant. It intimates but does not have a content. It is there in order
to determine the way in which the conception of ‘this’ and ‘that’ are to
be concretised in relation to one another. ‘And’ is incomplete without
two things to conjoin.
The distinction between significant and insignificant terms, depend-
ently and independently significant words, is less prominently featured
in Roman Ingarden’s The Literary Work of Art as compared to his
analysis of the cognition of the literary work of art in The Cognition
of the Literary Work of Art. But he recognises that some phrases are
meant to convey atemporality while others are not. There is a continuing
tension in the work of Ingarden regarding the ‘ideal meaning units’ that
constitute the second stratum of a literary work of art.
That tension is precisely the ideality of the meaning units. Ingarden
conceives of the literary work of art as ontologically describable through
four strata:
(1) The material
(2) The ideal meaning units
(3) Schematised aspects
(4) Represented objectivities
170 Charlene Elsby
The base material of the literary work of art is its physical existence,
which includes not only the paper or material through which the text
survives, but also the marks on the page making up the letters that we
perceive as symbols. The ideal meaning units are the units of meaning
that these materialities invoke in us, which provide the conduit through
which we come to conceive the world of the book, its characters, hap-
penings and circumstances. The ideal meaning units are linguistic con-
structions of varying complexity, and the fact that they are of varying
complexity means that some meaning units are less obviously ‘ideal’
than others, where ‘ideal’ means their temporality has been abstracted
away.
For individual referential terms, ‘ideal’ may be applicable, as dis-
cussed above, when we are discussing abstract notions like ‘time’,
‘space’, ‘unity’ and other such concepts whose referents, we assume,
don’t die. Nevertheless, we recognise immediately that the concepts
to which these words refer do and have changed over the course of
humanity’s dealings with them. The problem is more evident when
Ingarden discusses more complex meaning units – phrases and sen-
tences. While ‘the blue frog’ may be conceived (by some) as a phrase
constituted of three independent (or dependent) meanings, the phrase
taken as a complex, as a combination, appears not nearly as necessary,
inevitable or worthy of universality as any term in particular. Sentences,
likewise, come and go. The more complex a linguistic meaning unit
becomes, the less it seems able to claim ideality. And finally, Ingarden
allows that the literary work of art, as a whole, is capable of life and
death. It is a thing that comes into being and which may eventually
die, as every copy is destroyed and every human memory of it erased.
Now it seems almost absurd that anything eternal should ever have
constituted it.
Which leads us to two possible conclusions: either a book is not
constituted of words, or those words are not ideal meaning units. The
latter conclusion seems more reasonable. What Deleuze ultimately aims
to achieve is the internalisation of the forms of language into its mate-
riality. Like an Aristotelian rejection of ideal Platonic forms that asserts
the ‘hereness’ of the eidos in the material entity, so Deleuze’s concept of
sense reintegrates meaning and phonetic material by eliminating ideality
from meaning, along with separability (contrary to a representational
model of language, the meaning of language isn’t separate from lan-
guage, but exists as an embodied eidos which, for Aristotle, is any
eidos).15 Smith correctly characterises Aristotelian hylomorphism in his
Essays on Deleuze:
Kill Metaphor 171
In brief, matter and form aren’t two separate things in some kind of
combat; they’re aspects and causes of a more primary unity (the thing),
separable only by abstraction.
Finally, in Merleau-Ponty, an analysis of language arises that allows
for its conception outside of pure reference. Relying heavily on Husserl
and, in particular, on the concept of the intimating function of expres-
sions, Merleau-Ponty’s concepts of speech and expression allow for a
living language better representative of the lifeworld in which it subsists.
Materiality, meaning, thought and language are all reconceived in
Merleau-Ponty, destroyer of dichotomies. The most obvious dichotomy
destruction in Phenomenology of Perception is that between the subject
and object, and it is not surprising that this dichotomy should also dis-
solve in a linguistic context. ‘Representation’, which Husserl defines at
least a dozen times in The Logical Investigations, is sidelined as nowhere
near the primary function of expression.16 Merleau-Ponty points out
that it is in fact not the case that a meaning is first conceived by a human
subject, converted to linguistic form, and then related to other nearby
subjects. Rather, expression itself generates meaning. It is meaning,
where meaning is conceived of in the sense of an act (as it is sometimes
for Husserl – see above) and not as the dead correlate of a word.17
Words mean in the same way that I do. And this is why the novels
of Kafka continue to mean after his death. It is simply wrong to think
that the book is nothing more than the recorded thoughts of a dead
man. It is a living thing that continues to mean in his absence, a sort of
quasi-subject with things to say, fully capable of meaning those things
on its own. It’s our concept of meaning that needs revision. Meaning is
not reference.
Conclusion
In Kafka: Toward A Minor Literature, Deleuze and Guattari assert
that the magic of Kafka’s literary works is nothing less than a deter-
ritorialisation of language and a becoming-animal of the literary work
(where these terms are almost synonymous). The becoming-animal of
the literary work applies specifically to Kafka, whose human characters
tend to become literally animal (e.g., Gregor Samsa’s metamorphosis);
while such transformations have been interpreted as symbolic, Deleuze
and Guattari reject their symbolic nature on the basis that it would be
174 Charlene Elsby
Notes
1. A despotic regime of significance, if you will, comparable to the malicious use
of semiotics by authoritarian psychoanalysts that Deleuze and Guattari discuss
Kill Metaphor 175
8. Compare Deleuze and Guattari’s genetic concept of language: ‘The act of
becoming is a capturing, a possession, a plus-value, but never a reproduction or
an imitation’ (1986: 14).
9. Husserl recognises the impossibility of ever perceiving a spatiotemporal object
in its entirety and designates the sides of it which are apparent to us at any
given time as ‘fulfilled’, while those that are not apparent are ‘unfulfilled’.
Unfulfilled aspects of any concrete entity may later be fulfilled and contribute
to an overall noema. He says in Ideas: ‘No perception of the physical thing is
definitively closed; there is always room for new perceptions, for determining
more precisely the indeterminatenesses, for fulfilling the unfulfilled. With every
progression the determinational content of the physical thing-noema, which
continually belongs to the same physical thing-X, is enriched. It is an eidetic
insight that each perception and multiplicity of perceptions is capable of being
amplified; the process is thus an endless one; accordingly, no intuitive seizing
upon the physical thing-essence can be so complete that a further perception
cannot noematically contribute something new to it’ (Husserl 1985: 358).
10. Deleuze and Guattari reference the statisticity of an image as memory early in
the Kafka book, in a discussion of Kafka’s use of images of people with bent
heads: ‘The memory is a family portrait or a vacation photo showing men with
bent heads, women with their necks circled by a ribbon. The memory blocks
desire, makes mere carbon copies of it, fixes it within strata, cuts it off from
all its connections. But what, then, can we hope for? It’s an impasse’ (1986:
4). In the diagram that follows, Deleuze and Guattari ascribe territoriality to
the image, on account of its being a blocked, oppressed or oppressing, or neu-
tralised desire. (Desire, as we know, is the catalyst of all motion.) It’s useful to
compare territoriality and deterritorialisation in Deleuze and Guattari to the
limited and unlimited in Pythagorean philosophy. Plato’s philosophy of forms
is a philosophy of the limited – a marking off of coherent concepts from the
maelstrom of all that is. In the Pythagorean list of dichotomies from Aristotle’s
Metaphysics 986a22, the limited has something in common with the odd, the
one, the right, the masculine, rest, the straight, light, good and the square, while
the unlimited would have something in common with the even, many, left, femi-
nine, motion, the crooked, darkness, evil and the oblong.
11. A more cautious interpretation would be that Plato meant to eliminate bad
artists, the ones who produced simulacra: ‘The Republic does not attack art or
poetry as such; it attempts to eliminate art that is simulacral or phantastic, and
not iconic or mimetic’ (Smith, 2012: 15).
12. According to Smith, Deleuze interprets Nietzsche as aiming at the inversion
of Platonism. In Deleuzian terms, this means specifically that the ‘inversion of
Platonism . . . implies an affirmation of the being of simulacra as such. The sim-
ulacrum must then be given its own concept and be defined in affirmative terms’
(Smith 2012: 12). I’ve no doubt this is what Nietzsche was doing; the question is
whether Plato meant any of what he wrote on the s ubject – i .e., if there is indeed
such a Plato to invert. Deleuze writes in Difference and Repetition: ‘The whole
of Platonism, by contrast, is dominated by the idea of drawing a distinction
between “the thing itself” and the simulacra . . . Overturning Platonism, then,
means denying the primacy of original over copy, of model over image; glorify-
ing the reign of simulacra and reflections’ (2004: 80).
13. For in-depth analyses of each of these arguments in turn, see Dorter 1982.
14. Socrates’ affinity argument starts at 78b in the Phaedo. Socrates gets Cebes to
agree that there is nothing left to say against the conclusion that ‘the soul is
most like the divine, deathless, intelligible, uniform, indissoluble, always the
same as itself, whereas the body is most like that which is human, mortal, mul-
Kill Metaphor 177
tiform, unintelligible, soluble and never consistently the same’ (Plato 1997a:
70).
15. Of course, Deleuze would never say it in those words, and this is not Aristotle’s
concept of language. I’m identifying an Aristotelian hylomorphism in Deleuze’s
concept of sense. As Smith phrases it: ‘The genesis of language must be found
at the relation between the intensive depth (noise) and the extensive surface
(sense)’ (2019: 59). I’d say, the genesis of language is the relation between an
unformed matter (sound) and the imposition of some organisation (form) that
renders it sensical and which primarily defines what it is (form as essence). That
is, language is expression more than it is phonemes.
16. Cf. Chapter 4 of Investigation 2 in Husserl’s Logical Investigations (Husserl
2001).
17. Deleuze picks up the concept of a living language as genesis in The Logic of
Sense, which Smith elucidates in a fashion reminiscent of Merleau-Ponty: ‘This
is the function of the surface organisation of sense: it separates sounds from
the body and begins to turn them into the elements of speech. The creation of
sense (out of non-signifying elements) is what allows the sounds coming out of
one’s mouth to participate fully in a shared linguistic world. But the converse is
also true. If a child comes to a language it cannot yet grasp as a language, but
only as a familial hum of voices, perhaps conversely it can grasp what adults
no longer grasp in their own language, namely the differential relations between
the formative elements of language’ (2019: 53). That is to say, in the language
of Merleau-Ponty’s phenomenology, that linguistic formations are habits that
have achieved automaticity – when people talk, we are directly aware of their
meaning, and do not (but might, if we choose) focus on the sounds which act
as media for meaning. We can confirm this experientially by noticing that when
we attempt to recall a conversation, we are more likely to remember what was
expressed rather than the individual words or actual sounds. In the Kafka book,
Deleuze and Guattari conceive of the production of a minor literature as imme-
diately operating within the realm of expression, rather than the expression
of a pre-existing content (the non-minor literatures that have come before). If
there’s a metaphor in Kafka, it’s tacked on to the text later, masquerading as the
‘content’ of yore. ‘A major, or established, literature follows a vector that goes
from content to expression. Since content is presented in a given form of the
content, one must find, discover, or see the form of expression that goes with it.
That which conceptualizes well expresses itself. But a minor, or revolutionary,
literature begins by expressing itself and doesn’t conceptualize until afterward
(“I do not see the word at all, I invent it”). Expression must break forms,
encourage ruptures and new sproutings’ (Deleuze and Guattari 1986: 28).
References
Bensmaïa, R. (1986), ‘The Kafka Effect’, in Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari,
Kafka: Toward a Minor Literature, trans. Dana Polan, Minneapolis: University
of Minnesota Press.
Deleuze, G. (2004), Difference and Repetition, trans. Paul Patton, New York:
Bloomsbury.
Deleuze, G. and F. Guattari (1986), Kafka: Toward a Minor Literature, trans. Dana
Polan, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Deleuze, G. and F. Guattari (1987), A Thousand Plateaus: Capitalism and
Schizophrenia II, trans. Brian Massumi, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota
Press.
178 Charlene Elsby
Robert W. Luzecky
the analyses of other art forms (Deleuze 1997a: 57). (Here, one cannot
help but think of the numerous phenomenological analyses of paintings
and literary works by Heidegger, Merleau-Ponty, Gadamer and their
followers.) Deleuze’s provocative observation that Husserl ‘never men-
tions cinema at all’ (56), though technically true, is not quite as scandal-
ous as one might think. Though Husserl doesn’t specifically mention
the moving images of film (i.e., cinematographic images), this shouldn’t
come as a terrible shock, if for no other reason than cinematic art was in
its infancy when Husserl was writing. The Lumière brothers are credited
with presenting the first series of documentary shorts to a paying audi-
ence on 28 December 1895 – L’arrivée d’un train en gare de La Ciotat,
Déjeuner de Bébé and L’arroseur arrosé. Georges Méliès founded the
first film studio and in-house film theatre in 1896. Méliès is also credited
with producing and showing the first single-reel narrative film – Le
Voyage dans la Lune – in 1902.3 During this period, Husserl was busy
starting his philosophical career at the University of Halle before being
uprooted to take residence in Göttingen. He published the first edition
of the Logical Investigations one year before Méliès entertained audi-
ences with the images of magical aliens dancing on the moon. In all
likelihood, Husserl was unaware of the evolution of the magic lantern
in France when he published his first major phenomenological text. It
should also be noted that Husserl does discuss the moving image (albeit
briefly) during this time (2005: 66, 584n3, 645, 646). Unfortunately, the
situation does not improve much with Sartre, who – though he mentions
going to the movies with his mother in The Words and briefly elaborates
on the nature of slow motion cinema in The Imaginary – refrains from
offering a systematic analysis of the art form (Sartre 1964: 119; 2004:
130).4 Deleuze also suggests that cinema suffers from a cursory treat-
ment by Merleau-Ponty (1997a: 57).5 Perhaps it is worth noting that
Roman Ingarden discusses film in a slightly more substantive way than
Merleau-Ponty. Unfortunately, Ingarden’s brief analyses of film h ave
– until quite recently – b
een unduly neglected by North American and
French phenomenologists (Ingarden 1973, 1989). Deleuze’s observation
that phenomenologists tend to treat the filmic art form in a manner
analogous to how a family might be inclined to treat a bastard cousin is
borne out (with some modification) by history.
Deleuze offers a further clue to the fraught relation between phenom-
enology and cinematic representation with his explicit suggestion that
cinema offers an alternative to the model of natural perception offered
by Husserlian phenomenology. In a lecture on the topic given during the
autumn of 1981, Deleuze starkly notes that ‘cinematic perception is not
Memories of Cinema 183
at the end Stanley Kubrick’s The Shining – a film that is vastly superior
to King’s derivative novel, because it explicitly correlates the physical
changes of the hotel to the mental states of Jack, Wendy and Danny,
as well as the memorial history of the Colorado Rocky Mountains,
i.e., the qualitative elements of various domains. Thomas Allen Nelson
elaborates on how, in Kubrick’s film, changes to the hotel’s spatiality
are directly correlated w ith – i.e., responses to, expressions of, doublings
of – the characters’ internal states (2000: 202–8). One cannot help but
think of the spatiotemporal discontinuities evident in some of the film’s
most memorable scenes: the elevator of blood that erupts when Jack,
Wendy or Danny feel rage or terror; the appearance of the bloated
corpse of a nude crone that greets Jack’s aberrant sexual desires in room
237; the ominous appearance of an ancient scrapbook next to Jack’s
typewriter as he struggles to recall the plot of his horribly repetitive
manuscript; the disquieting appearance of the twin girls (the Grady
twins) who promise to play with Danny ‘forever and ever’; the shifting
patterns on both the hallway carpet and the Native American murals
in the Colorado Lounge; the population and de-population of the Gold
Room; the alteration in lighting of the hotel bar when Jack gets a
glass of bourbon; the shifting spatial dimensions of the hedge maze; the
strange appearance of a room full of skeletons as Wendy is confronted
with memories of Jack’s abuse of her and Danny; the deeply disturbing
appearance of an entity dressed as a bear performing fellatio on a man
in 1920s formal attire as Wendy witnesses a temporally prior event in
the hotel (the 1921 New Year’s Eve party). All of these spatiotemporal
modifications (modifications to the hotel and its surrounding area) are
reflective of qualitative variations of various character’s mental states.
Each of them expresses a spatiotemporal translation of particulars (a
quantitative translation). All involve a fundamental qualitative transfor-
mation of the whole. These moments of horror have been adduced to
aptly illustrate the ontological modification suggested by Bergson’s third
thesis on the nature of space in relation to qualitative alteration.
Deleuze suggests that filmic duration does something more profound
than merely present photographic examples of differentiation through
photographic and aural means. In ‘Bergson’s Conception of Difference’,
he explicitly identifies duration as the internally differentiated process
that involves the capacity to ‘englobe’ (i.e., ontologically comprehend)
ontologically distinct entities (2002: 39). This suggests that the particular
filmic species of duration has the capacity to comprehend modifications
within entities which are ontologically discrete from filmed persons,
settings and other photographically represented states of affairs. The
192 Robert W. Luzecky
the memories of those who behold them – i.e., to ‘look back’ into the
minds and prior lived experiences of those who get transfixed by their
unblinking gaze.18 This observation echoes the suggestion that duration
modifies the qualitative aspects of the thought content of people who
participate in cinematic duration (through the concrete act of viewing
a film).
tion seems to enjoy only a diminished role, in the sense that it has been
supplanted by a creative function.20 One might balk at this suggestion,
with the observation that mimesis has been taken to be a crucial aspect
of art since Plato’s observation – in the Republic, 604e–605a – t hat it is
the artist’s job to produce ‘multicolored imitations’ of various tangible
and intangible aspects of reality (1997: 1209). It might further be noted
that Plato’s entire condemnation of bad artists presupposes the validity
of the metaphysical claim that there exists a true reality (which good art
putatively represents).21 Robbe-Grillet modifies this characterisation of
the function of art by radicalising the artist’s creative capacities. Though
it must be noted that theories of imitation do involve aspects of artistic
creation, in the sense that they tend to identify the artist as creating an
adequate description of a reality that is extrinsic to the work of art’s
reality, this is characterised as a secondary, dependent process. Robbe-
Grillet radicalises this creativity when he suggests that the work of art
is akin to an architectural ‘point’ of invention (i.e., a singular point, a
singularity, a point of inflection) (1965: 148). Bernard Cache carefully
observes that architecture involves two analytically discrete kinds of
singularities, extrinsic singularities and ‘points of inflection’ (or intrinsic
singularities). An extrinsic singularity is a hypothetical point with which
the tangent of the physical curve, were it conceived as an ideal curve,
would be perpendicular (it is the point of a hypothetical y-axis which
is involved in the specification of one part of the curve’s coordinates).
An intrinsic singularity is identified as a point along the curve that
‘designates a pure event of curvature’ (Cache 1995: 16). Intrinsic sin-
gularities are actualised (or at least illustrated) by the ogives that are so
often instantiated in the architecture of medieval European churches.
Architectural works, it might also be observed, are a particular species
of the general class of artwork. Here, it seems that Robbe-Grillet is
stipulating that the property of a p articular – in this case, the property
of having intrinsic singularities as elements of the particular’s formal
ontological content – m ay be generalised as the property of a class.
Given that the property of a class may gain expression in any particular
species or member that is comprehended by the class, this yields the sub-
stantive observation that films and novels (because they are also works
of art) involve intrinsic singularities. Robbe- Grillet further observes
that intrinsic singularities tend to gain artistic expression as diegetic
moments of radical upheaval, profound correction, or bifurcation into
non-compossible series of events. Robbe- Grillet explicitly notes that
his conceptualisation of artistic description is distinct from the mimetic
relation through direct reference to temporality when he observes that
196 Robert W. Luzecky
the types of temporal changes expressed in films need not correlate with
the temporality evidenced by the quantitative measurement of physical
(as opposed to artistically presented) clocks and calendars (1965: 151).
It should be observed that Robbe- Grillet’s suggestion implies a
subtle reformulation of Aristotle’s observation that art tends to involve
moments of great dramatic reversal. In Poetics, Aristotle suggests that
lyric poems tend to represent reality adequately, in the sense that they
involve περιπέτεια (reversals). Robbe-Grillet seems to suggest that these
moments of great reversal in the lives, fates and fortunes of the charac-
ters evidence a rupture from the mimetic order, in the sense that none
of these needs to be representative of any circumstance in the world.
These profound shifts involve an element of temporality, in the senses
that they occur within time, evidence a temporal duration and express a
moment in temporal continuum. This suggests that a direct expression
of time involves the illustration of these sorts of changes, characterised
as any of the properties (or attributes) of the relation that obtains among
entities in the artwork; thus it is discrete from the sorts of modification
that obtain as a property of the mimetic relation that might or might not
obtain between these and entities in the physical world. Stated again,
the direct expression of temporally saturated change is immanent to the
relation among fictive relata, which is different in kind and content from
the sort of changes that are involved (as attributes, immanent conditions
or emergent properties) in the relation that obtains among artistically
presented objects and their correlates in the universe populated by physi-
cal entities and psycho-social entities with physical attributes.
Deleuze observes that analogous disjunctions may be found in pure
optical and acoustic situations, which are constituted by ‘opsigns’ and
‘sonsigns’. In Cinema 1, he explains that these situations (and their
correlated signs) are filmic precursors to the direct presentation of time
(1997a: 210). Properly speaking, both opsigns and sonsigns are indica-
tive of a breakdown of the sensory-motor order (i.e., the sequence of
shots, montage) that tends to be identified with realist cinema. Each of
these discrete types of sign – though they may be, and often are, present
in the same shot, sequence or film – indicates a disjunction among any
of the photographically expressed entities relative to one another, as
well as any of the narrative, implied character arc, or thematic content
attributed to a film or its aspects. In these senses, opsigns and sonsigns
are intrinsic singularities that stand apart from (i.e., enjoy a disjunctive
relation with) other aspects of the film.22 Deleuze elucidates the natures
of these peculiar moments of filmic upheaval when he observes that
these sorts of purely optical and acoustic situations force any of the
Memories of Cinema 197
kind evoked by certain horror movies. Here one cannot help but think
of the virtual image clawing its way out of a television screen in David
Cronenberg’s Videodrome (1983), or the terrifying moments of mon-
sters materialising out of reflective surfaces in the trilogy of Japanese
Ring films (Nakata 1998, 1999; Tsuruta 2000). The terror elicited by
these scenes of the virtual being actualised as material is sufficient to
demonstrate the metaphysical truth of the complex distinction between
the virtual and actual.
The crystal-image involves a relation of the virtual memory and the
actual present. The tension of these is the content of time’s direct expres-
sion in cinema. Bergson suggests that the past emerges as a moment
of temporal bifurcation, a relation among the virtual and actual that
yields a division of the instant into ‘two jets exactly symmetrical, one
of which falls back toward the past, whilst the other springs forward
to the future’ (2012: 160). Deleuze explicitly characterises this relation
as the simultaneous creation of two discrete temporal modalities (the
memorial past and the fleeting present).28 The staggering implication is
that the past does not follow after the lived present – one’s memory of
an object obtains simultaneously with one’s perception of the object.
Proust beautifully illustrates this through reference to the lingering scent
of madeleines:
But let a noise or scent, once heard or once smelt, be heard or smelt again
in the present and at the same time in the past, real without being actual,
ideal without being abstract, and immediately the permanent and habitu-
ally concealed essence of things is liberated and our true self which s eemed
– perhaps for long years seemed – t o be dead but was not altogether dead,
is awakened and reanimated as it receives the celestial nourishment that is
brought to it. A minute freed from the order of time has re-created in us,
to feel it, the man freed from the order of time. And one can understand
that this man should have confidence in his joy, even if the simple taste of
a madeleine does not seem logically to contain within it the reasons for this
joy, one can understand the word ‘death’ should have no meaning for him;
situated outside time, why should he fear the future?
But this species of optical illusion, which placed beside me a moment of
the past that was incompatible with the present, could not last for long.
The images presented to us by the voluntary memory can, it is true, be
prolonged at will, for the voluntary memory requires no more exertion on
our part than the turning over of the pages in a picture book. (Proust 1982:
906)
hypothesis that a dependency relation obtains among the present and the
past; the past does not subsist from the present; the two (characterised as
any of past and present, virtual and actual, perceived object and content
of recollection) emerge in immanent relation to one another as ontologi-
cal correlates, each designating a discrete temporal modality. Perceptual
moments of quantifiably existent entities are co-created as virtual enti-
ties that obtain as existing qualities. Further, Deleuze carefully notes
that a crystalline-image never reaches a state of completion – it never
obtains as ‘altogether dead’ – in the sense that its process of producing
the virtual and actual never ceases. That is, the crystal involves an ‘indis-
cernible exchange [that] is always renewed and reproduced’ (1997b:
274). The suggestion here is that time is continually regained in the
ongoing process of generating the past and the present simultaneously.
This is a regeneration of discrete modes of time, in which each enjoys a
temporal difference from what was immediately prior as well as an onto-
logical difference from the other. In this sense, the attribute of finitude
cannot be predicated of time. Though the relation among the virtual
and the actual is stabilised in the form of a relation, this stability does
not imply any temporal, logical or ontological cessation. In the most
general sense, one cannot predicate an end to time – i.e., temporality
is an ongoing relation, a continuum of differentiation. Taken together,
these elucidations reveal that the direct-image of time involves four non-
competing aspects: (1) the fundamental indeterminacy of a singularity;
(2) virtuality and actuality, which enjoy a categorical distinction (as
is demonstrated by their non-reducible properties); (3) a simultaneous
creation of the past and present, each of which is characterised as a non-
reducible (non-subsistent, relatively autonomous) way of time’s being;
(4) its expression as an ongoing stable relation (i.e., a continuum) that is
akin to the process of a seed involved in a germination, in the sense that
it produces difference, in multiple senses.
Notes
1. Referring to Deleuze’s Essays Critical and Clinical and The Logic of Sense,
Williams observes that in these ‘concepts and artwork grow inwards and
explode outwards together, in a style with more rhythm, texture, complexity
of pace, and linguistic invention’ than is evident in either of Deleuze’s books on
Cinema (2011: 161).
2. With his suggestion that Deleuze seems to bear an affinity to various phenom-
enologists and explicitly phenomenological claims, Schrader is hardly a voice in
the wilderness. Particularly interesting recent studies advancing similar theses
include Somers-Hall 2019; Wambacq 2017; Lampert 2015; Bryant 2008; and
Shores 2014. It should be pointed out that most of these tend to focus on
ork – primarily Difference and Repetition – while leaving aside
Deleuze’s early w
Deleuze’s critiques of Husserl (and the Husserlian concept of ‘natural percep-
tion’) in The Logic of Sense, Cinema 1: The-Movement Image, and Cinema 2:
The Time-Image. François Zourabichvili suggests that when one takes Deleuze’s
characterisation of ‘becoming’ – particularly, the various cinematic becomings
that are evidenced by the changes in the way films are made, as well as the ways
cinematic narrative style has altered with the French New Wave – Deleuze’s
conceptual distance ‘from phenomenology and its heirs’ becomes apparent
(Zourabichvili 2012: 173).
3. Cook offers a lovely, condensed history of the art form, including its genesis
from the zoetrope (2016: 7–14).
4. Perhaps due to their brevity, Sartre’s observations have generated scant critical
analysis. Dana Polan is one of the few to have elaborated on Sartre’s ‘occa-
sional’ thought on cinema (Polan 1987).
Memories of Cinema 205
20. Robbe-Grillet writes: ‘Description once served to situate the chief contours of
a setting, then to cast light on some of its particularly revealing elements; it no
longer mentions anything except insignificant objects, or objects which it is con-
cerned to make so. It once claimed to reproduce a pre-existing reality; it now
asserts its creative function’ (1965: 144–7).
21. It would be difficult to overstate either the longevity or importance of Plato’s
identification of art as mimetic. Charles Sanders Peirce offers only a slight
modification of Plato’s suggestion with his observation that visual art tends to
represent ‘iconic signs’ of the real (1982: 53–4). John Hyman develops the epis-
temological aspects of Plato’s claim by insisting that one can only understand
the truth of a p ainting – i.e., understand its sense – through reference to the
immaterial or material objects that it represents (2009: 495–8). This is not to
say that Robbe-Grillet is a voice in the wilderness. Echoing John Ruskin, E. H.
Gombrich observes that visual art tends to involve a creation of the ‘innocence
of the eye’ (1960: 296). One implication of Gombrich’s suggestion is that such
innocence might not pre-exist the viewer’s participation with the work of art.
This further suggests that art is non-mimetic, in the sense that it cannot resemble
(or copy) that which does not exist.
22. Deleuze continually modifies his concept of singularity. It seems each of the
books following The Logic of Sense – in which Deleuze first uses the term –
witnesses a further evolution of the nuanced nature of singularities. Though
Manuel DeLanda suggests that singularities may be characterised as ‘spaci-
otemporal dynamisms’ and ‘passive selves’, these attempts at definition seem
inadequate, in the sense that both of these are profoundly opaque, and perhaps
even involve definitional aspects that would confound any assertion of identity
(2002: 206–7). Steven Shaviro observes that Deleuze tends to identify singu-
larities as ‘acategorical’ entities, in the sense ‘that they cannot be categorized
in any terms broader than their own . . . they cannot be fitted into a hierarchy
of species and genera, of the particular and the general: just as they cannot be
derived as instances of any larger, more overarching and predetermining struc-
ture’ (2012: 89, n.11). Daniel W. Smith traces Deleuze’s concept of singularities
to a modification of Albert Lautman’s suggestion – in his Essay on the Notions
of Structure and Existence in Mathematics – that points on a geometric curve
may be distinguished from one another in terms of whether or not they are
involved in a change of direction in the curve: ordinary points do not radically
alter the direction of the curve; singular points (or singularities) are moments on
the curve at which the trajectory of the curve alters (2012: 302). Smith further
observes that Deleuze generalises the variability implied in Lautman’s strictly
mathematical definition, to suggest qualitative and affective components. It
should be noted that not all of these need be temporal, in the sense that some
have suggested that mathematical entities enjoy an a-temporal existence. Taken
together, these suggest that a singularity may by rigorously characterised as any
of a temporal or non-temporal moment of variation or difference (i.e., change).
It is conceivable that such moments could be visually or aurally represented in
film. This is plainly the case in films involving profound crisis, if it is granted
that these are not – and perhaps never aspired to be – copies, imitations or
duplications of a world marked by the striking appearance of continuity, banal-
ity or putative normalcy, all of which might be characteristics of a circumstance
bereft of profound variation. It might be further observed that all of these
apparent traits of normalcy could obtain as representations in film – the typical,
even quotidian, has often been the subject matter of some of the more fascinat-
ing films of the last hundred years of cinema; e.g., the films of Antonioni, but
this would not negate (or otherwise diminish) the possibility of singularities
208 Robert W. Luzecky
being present in these, as long as one acknowledges that the seemingly banal
may involve understated crises, which are – for all their subtlety – just as pro-
found as those expressed in the most bombastic Hollywood blockbuster.
23. Deleuze elaborates: ‘These are pure optical and sound situations, in which the
character does not know how to respond, abandoned spaces in which he ceases
to experience and act so that he enters into flight, goes on a trip, comes and
goes, vaguely indifferent to what happens to him, undecided as to what must be
done’ (1997b: 272).
24. Bergson writes: ‘Whenever we are trying to recover a recollection, to call up
some period of our history, we become conscious of an act sui generis by which
we detach ourselves from the present in order to replace ourselves, first, in the
past – a work of adjustment, something like the framing of a camera’ (1991:
133–4).
25. Bergson writes: ‘The more he analyses his experience, the more he will split into
two personages, one of which moves about on the stage while the other sits and
looks. On the one hand, he knows that he continues to be what he was, a self
who thinks and acts comfortably to what the situation requires, a self-inserted
into real life, and adapting itself to it by a free effort of the will; this is what his
perception of the present assures him. But the memory of this present, which is
equally there, makes him believe that he is repeating what has been said already,
seeing again what has been seen already, and so transforms him into an actor
reciting his part’ (2012: 169).
26. It is important to observe the limited scope of this analogy. The conceptual dif-
ferences between Deleuze’s and Aristotle’s respective philosophies of time are
substantive, as are the differences in their metaphysics. Daniel W. Smith (2001)
elaborates on the differences between Deleuze’s and Aristotle’s metaphysics.
27. Bergson writes: ‘The memory seems to be the perception of what the object in
the mirror is to the object in front of it. The object can be touched as well as
seen; acts upon us as well as we on it; it is pregnant with possible actions; it is
actual. The image is virtual, and though it resembles the object, it is incapable
of doing what the object does’ (2012: 165).
28. Deleuze observes: ‘What constitutes the crystal-image is the most fundamental
operation of time: since past is constituted not after the present that it was but
at the same time, it has to split itself in two at each moment as present and
past, which differ from each other in nature, or, what amounts to the same
thing, it has to split the present in two heterogeneous directions, one of which is
launched toward the future while the other falls into the past’ (1997b: 81).
References
Barthes, R. (1981), Camera Lucida: Reflections on Photography, trans. Richard
Howard, New York: Hill and Wang.
Bazin, A. (2005), What is Cinema? 1, trans. Hugh Gray, Berkeley: University of
California Press.
Benjamin, W. (2005), ‘Little History of Photography’, in Selected Writings 2, 1931–
1934, trans. Rodney Livingstone, ed. Michael W. Jennings, Howard Eiland and
Gary Smith, Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press.
Benjamin, W. (2006a), ‘On Some Motifs in Baudelaire’, in Selected Writings 4,
1938–1940, trans. Rodney Livingstone, ed. Michael W. Jennings, Howard Eiland
and Gary Smith, Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press.
Benjamin, W. (2006b), ‘Protocols of Drug Experiments (1–12)’, in On Hashish,
trans. Howard Eiland, Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press.
Memories of Cinema 209
and Other Texts, trans. Ames Hodges, ed. David Lapoujade, South Pasadena:
Semiotext(e), pp. 195–240.
Deleuze, G. and F. Guattari (1987), A Thousand Plateaus: Capitalism and
Schizophrenia II, trans. Brian Massumi, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota
Press.
Gombrich, E. H. (1960), Art and Illusion: A Study in the Psychology of Pictorial
Representation, London: Phaidon.
Guillemet, J. (2010), ‘“The ‘New Wave” of French Phenomenology and Cinema:
New Concepts for the Cinematic Experience’, New Review of Film and Television
Studies, 8 (1): 94–114.
Hansen, M. B. (2008), ‘Benjamin’s Aura’, Critical Inquiry, 34: 336–75.
Hill, R. (2012), The Interval: Relation and Becoming in Irigaray, Aristotle, and
Bergson, New York: Fordham University Press.
Husserl, E. (1931), Ideas, trans. W. R. Boyce Gibson, London: Allen and Unwin.
Husserl, E. (1965), Phenomenology and the Crisis of Philosophy, trans. Quentin
Lauer, New York: Harper and Row.
Husserl, E. (2005), Collected Works XI: Phantasy, Image, Consciousness, and
Memory (1898–1925), trans. John B. Brough, ed. Rudolf Bernet, Dordrecht:
Springer.
Hyman, J. (2009), ‘Realism’, in A Companion to Aesthetics, ed. Stephen Davies et
al., Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell.
Hyppolite, J. (2003), ‘Various Aspects of Memory in Bergson’, trans. Athena
V. Colman, Appendix II in Leonard Lawlor, The Challenge of Bergson:
Phenomenology, Ontology, Ethics, London: Continuum, pp. 112–27.
Ingarden, R. (1973), The Literary Work of Art, trans. George G. Grabowicz,
Evanston: Northwestern University Press.
Ingarden, R. (1989), Ontology of the Work of Art: The Musical Work, the Picture,
the Architectural Work, the Film, trans. Raymond Meyer, Athens: Ohio University
Press.
Jackson, S. (1959), The Haunting of Hill House, New York: Penguin.
King, S. (1977), The Shining, New York: Doubleday.
Kovács, A. B. (2007), Screening Modernism: European Art Cinema, 1950–1980,
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Lampert, J. (2015), ‘Deleuze’s “Power of Decision”, Kant’s = X and Husserl’s
Noema’, in At the Edges of Thought: Deleuze and Post-Kantian Philosophy,
ed. Craig Lundy and Daniela Voss, Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, pp.
272–92.
Lawlor, L. (2003), The Challenge of Bergson: Phenomenology, Ontology, Ethics,
London: Continuum.
Merleau-Ponty, M. (1962), Phenomenology of Perception, trans. Colin Smith, New
York: Routledge.
Merleau-Ponty, M. (1964), Signs, trans. R. C. McQeary, Evanston: Northwestern
University Press.
Mitscherling, J. (2010), Aesthetic Genesis: The Origin of Consciousness in the
Intentional Being of Nature, Toronto: University of America Press.
Nelson, T. A. (2000), Kubrick: Inside A Film Artist’s Maze, Bloomington: Indiana
University Press.
Peirce, C. S. (1982), The Writings of Charles S. Peirce: A Chronological Edition
2, ed. M. Fisch, C. Kloesel, E. Moore and N. Houser, Bloomington: Indiana
University Press.
Plato (1997), Republic, trans. G. M. A. Grube and C. D. C. Reeve, in Complete
Works, ed. John. M. Cooper, Indianapolis: Hackett.
Polan, D. (1987), ‘Sartre and Cinema’, Post-script, 7 (1): 66–88.
Memories of Cinema 211
Films
Michelangelo Antonioni (dir.), Red Desert, Rizolli, 1964.
Luis Buñuel (dir.), Un Chien Andalou, Les Grands Films, 1929.
Robert Clouse (dir.), Enter the Dragon, Warner Brothers and Concord Productions
Inc., 1973.
David Cronenberg (dir.), Videodrome, Universal, 1983.
Maya Deren and Alexander Hammid (dir.), Meshes of the Afternoon, 1943.
Stanley Kubrick (dir.), The Shining, The Producer Circle Company, 1980.
Paul McGuigan (dir.), The Hounds of Baskerville, BBC, 8 January 2012.
Hideo Nakata (dir.), Ring, Ringu/Rasen Production Committee, 1998.
Hideo Nakata (dir.), Ring 2, Asmik Ace Entertainment, 1999.
Stuart Rosenberg (dir.), Cool Hand Luke, Jalem Productions, 1967.
Roberto Rossellini (dir.), Europe ’ 51, Roberto Rossellini, Carlo Ponti, Dino De
Laurentiis, 1952.
Walter Ruttmann (dir.), Berlin: Die Sinfonie der Großstadt, Fox Europa, 1927
Martin Scorsese (dir.), Taxi Driver, Bill/Phillips Productions and Italo/Judeo
Productions, 1976.
212 Robert W. Luzecky
Vernon W. Cisney
A theory of cinema is not ‘about’ cinema, but about the concepts that
cinema gives rise to and which are themselves related to other concepts
corresponding to other practices, the practice of concepts in general having
no privilege over others. It is at the level of the interference of many prac-
tices that things happen, beings, images, concepts, all the kinds of events.
(Deleuze 1989: 280)
One of the most perplexing among the many innovative concepts in the
Cinema volumes is the ‘power of the false which replaces and super-
sedes the form of the true’ (Deleuze 1989: 131). This ‘power of the
false’, introduced as early in Deleuze’s work as 1962’s Nietzsche and
Philosophy (1983: 96, 185), is immediately connected to what, in the
Cinema volumes, Deleuze characterises as truth: ‘What the artist is, is
creator of truth, because truth is not to be achieved, formed, or repro-
duced; it has to be created. There is no other truth than the creation of
the New’ (1989: 146–7).
Overlooking for the moment the apparent tension in the fact that
Deleuze valorises the false as the supersession of the form of the true,
while also celebrating the creation of truth, there is an even more dan-
gerous obstacle afoot. For the notions that truth is in any way subject to
the force of time, such that it must be created, or that there is a power – a
positive power, no l ess – i nherent to the false, these notions are antitheti-
cal not only to banal, common-sense understandings (as when parents,
for instance, attempt to impress upon their children the obvious superi-
ority of truth to falsehood), but, more importantly, to the philosophical
tradition’s understandings of truth and falsehood. Speaking broadly, we
can say that truth is traditionally characterised in terms that are static,
atemporal and positive (in senses that are at once ontological, epistemic
and moral), while falsehood has been predominantly characterised as
an absence, a lack of truth or of reality. Thus, the task of this paper
will be to explore the connections between the power of the false and
the creation of truth. To do so, we must look at the reasons for which
Deleuze argues that ‘time has always put the notion of truth into crisis’
(1989: 130). We will characterise this crisis of truth in both Platonic and
Aristotelian senses. We will then look at the notion of incompossibility
that Deleuze adopts from Leibniz, whereby he offers a forking of incom-
possibilities as the basic ‘form’ of time, as a strategy for responding to
the notion of truth that is put into crisis – this is the sense of the ‘power
of the false’ that we will explore. Finally, we will see that this power of
the false, as Deleuze conceives it, makes possible the creation of truth, in
the form of ‘minor art’ that conduces to the invention of a people.
216 Vernon W. Cisney
Indeed, it isn’t even reasonable to say that there is such a thing as knowl-
edge, Cratylus, if all things are passing on and none remain. For if that
thing itself, knowledge, did not pass on from being knowledge, then knowl-
edge would always remain, and there would be such a thing as knowledge.
On the other hand, if the very form of knowledge passed on from being
knowledge, the instant it passed on into a different form than that of
knowledge, there would be no knowledge. And if it were always passing
on, there would always be no knowledge. Hence, on this account, no one
could know anything and nothing could be known either. But if there is
always that which knows and that which is known, if there are such things
as the beautiful, the good, and each one of the things that are, it doesn’t
Time, Truth and the Power of the False 217
so from all eternity, he was so always and freely. My father only granted
him the existence which his wisdom could not refuse to the world where
he is included: he made him pass from the region of the possible to that
of the actual beings’ (377). His nature is written into the larger script
of a world designed in its tiniest detail entirely by God, and not subject
to change once actualised. As Deleuze writes, while this might enable
Leibniz to deal with the problem of future contingents, ‘it in no way
guarantees the character of so-called voluntary events, or the freedom
of whoever wants to engage a naval battle, or of whoever does not want
to’ (1993: 69). This seems a most limited and unsatisfying notion of
possibility, as ‘possibility’ would seem to suggest an openness of eventu-
alities. On Leibniz’s understanding, that openness is foreclosed by God
from the moment he brings into existence this particular possible world
and not some other. The infinite worlds of infinite possibilities obtain
only in the abstract, only in the mind of God. Thus, while Deleuze finds
Leibniz’s resolution to be the most interesting, it is also ‘the strangest
and most convoluted’ (1989: 130).
(2) It presents a problematic notion of time as well, insofar as there
is no reason to think that there’s a smallest isolable ‘unit’ of time that
would be required in order to determine it to its limits and establish
the unbreakable links from one arrangement of predicates to the next.8
Indeed, one of the most significant analyses in Deleuze’s 1969 text,
The Logic of Sense, is the distinction, which Deleuze lifts from the
Stoics, between the conceptions of time as ‘Chronos’, where ‘only the
present exists in time’ (1990: 162), and ‘Aion’, where ‘Instead of a
present which absorbs the past and the future, a future and past divide
the present at every instant and subdivide it ad infinitum into past and
future, in both directions at once’ (164). The time of Chronos is not
unlike Husserl’s concept of the ‘living present’ (Husserl 1991: 56), the
experiential moment, pregnant with retention and protention, past and
future. But with the notion of Chronos, we can expand this progressively
further, such that surrounding each present one can imagine an even
greater present (pregnant with past and future), with the greatest present
being God’s eternally contentful present, as the ‘external envelope’ of
all human moments (Deleuze 1990: 162). As such, the imagistic model
of Chronos is the circle, whose radius marks the infinity of God.9 The
model of the Aion, on the other hand, is the straight line, run through
by the Instant, ever displaced, forking limitlessly into past and future.
Time, Truth and the Power of the False 223
Two paths meet here; no one has yet followed either to its end. This long
lane stretches back for an eternity. And the long lane out there, that is
another eternity. They contradict each other, these paths; they offend each
other face to face; and it is here at this gateway that they come together.
The name of the gateway is inscribed above: ‘Moment’. But whoever would
follow one of them, on and on, farther and f arther – d
o you believe, dwarf,
that these paths contradict each other eternally? (Nietzsche 1966: 157–8)
and Repetition, but hardly appears at all just one year later in The Logic
of Sense. There, the primary ontological distinction occupying Deleuze
is the contrast of ‘bodies with their tensions, physical qualities, actions
and passions, and the corresponding “states of affairs”’, and ‘incorpo-
real events which would play only on the surface, like a mist over the
prairie’ (1990: 4–5). But with the translation of the Aion into Cronos in
Cinema 2, the virtual returns:
of the false ‘replaces and supersedes the form of the true’ (1989: 131).
It is not, in other words, simply an affirmation of the false, because to
assert the false is to operate still under the form of the true – ‘it is true
that it is false’. As Dan Smith says, the false takes on a power when
‘it is freed from the model of truth: that is, when the false is no longer
presented as being true’ (2012: 139). Likewise, the power of the false
is ‘not error or doubt’ (Deleuze 1989: 133), both of which are again
conceived as deviations from the true. It is the power that unsettles
the very form of the true, and this power is ascribed when the form of
the true is challenged by the form of time, ‘the pure form of the Aion’
(Deleuze 1990: 180). The power of the false is the power of becoming,
and it is, therefore, synonymous with the very ‘powers of life’ itself
(Deleuze 1989: 135).
Conceiving time in this Aionic way elicits a shift in our understanding
of the notion of possibility, where the possibilities of multiple eventu-
alities are in fact the pregnancy of time with multiple in-compossibil-
ities; but contrary to Leibniz’s possible worlds, these incompossibles
coexist, virtually and, in a way, simultaneously, within the real world.
Argentinian author Jorge Luis Borges, in his famous ‘The Garden of
Forking Paths’, writes:
In all fictions, each time a man meets diverse alternatives, he chooses
one and eliminates the others; in the work of the virtually impossible-
to-disentangle Ts’ui Pen, the character chooses – simultaneously – all of
them. He creates, thereby, ‘several futures’, several times, which themselves
proliferate and fork. That is the explanation for the novel’s contradictions.
Fang, let us say, has a secret; a stranger knocks at his door; Fang decides
to kill him. Naturally, there are various possible outcomes – Fang can kill
the intruder, the intruder can kill Fang, they can both live, they can both be
killed, and so on. In Ts’ui Pen’s novel, all the outcomes in fact occur; each
is the starting point for further bifurcations. (Borges 1998: 125)
In Deleuze’s words, Borges’ response to Leibniz is that ‘the straight line
as force of time, as labyrinth of time, is also the line which forks and
keeps on forking, passing through incompossible presents, returning to
not-necessarily true pasts’ (1989: 131). Leibniz’s band-aid for the crisis
of truth is ripped off, revealing the bleeding wound of time itself.
For Deleuze, this realisation reaches the arts in the character of the
‘forger’, understood through the ‘power of the false’ which ‘poses
the simultaneity of incompossible presents, or the coexistence of not-
necessarily true pasts’ (1989: 131). Classical, ‘truthful’, narration
assumes a logically ordered world where the instants of time connect
in the same direct, sequential, linear way that governs Leibniz’s notion
226 Vernon W. Cisney
less grotesque for his relentless pursuit of truth. His concerns lie, not so
much with the question of justice (for it is very likely that the suspected
criminal is indeed culpable), but with exposing the corruption of his
nemesis, and to this pursuit he is willing to sacrifice everything, leaving
his wife in extreme danger in order to trap his villain. Vargas is the
‘truthful man’, who has ‘strange motives, as if he were hiding another
man in him, a revenge’ (Deleuze 1989: 137).
Welles’s power of the false culminates in his masterpiece, F for Fake
(1973), which explicitly examines the nature of art, authorship, authen-
ticity and forgery. Inspired by the Clifford Irving book, Fake, the film
focuses on famous art forger, Elmyr de Hory, who fraudulently sold to
museums and galleries over a thousand hand-painted forgeries in the
artistic styles of such famous artists as Picasso, Matisse and Renoir. F
for Fake is narrated by Welles himself, who acts as a host of what is
presented in the form of a documentary, which is to say, a cinematic
presentation of factual content. Indeed, the film opens with a promise
from Welles that everything to come for the next hour will be true. He
then addresses the case of Elmyr de Hory, and in particular, the fact
that de Hory was so tremendously successful in his career as a forger,
leading Welles to speculate on the question of whether perhaps the art
critics and dealers who were fooled by his forgeries, and, by extension,
the bourgeois world of modern art, are themselves frauds. If the forger
is capable of mimicking a style so as to fool the experts, are the ‘experts’
themselves not the greater frauds? Is the forger not an expert in his own
right? The film then concludes with a story about Oja Kodar, Welles’s
partner at the time. Kodar had purportedly been at the middle of a
controversy involving Pablo Picasso and a series of twenty-two Picasso
paintings with Kodar as their subject, paintings later revealed to be
forgeries, mimicries of Picasso’s style painted by Kodar’s grandfather.
Welles then admits that the entire Kodar segment was a lie, pointing out
that the promised hour of truth had long since passed: ‘What we profes-
sional liars hope to serve is truth; I’m afraid the pompous word for that
is “art”. Picasso himself said it: “art”, he said, “is a lie, a lie that makes
us realize the truth”’.
is no other truth than the creation of the New’ (1989: 146–7). On its
face, there are multiple ways that we might understand this passage. We
might interpret it in a shallow relativistic sense, characteristic of all the
worst interpretations of ‘postmodernism’, whatever that term means –
that is, we might say that what the passage entails is that there is no such
thing as truth, and so the only truth is the one that we, that is, human
beings, assert. This opens us not only to philosophical problems, but
more immediately and dangerously, it opens us as well to serious politi-
cal concerns, because the folks adjudicating in matters of ‘the truth’ are
almost always the ones in positions of power and privilege who use their
truth-creating powers in order to hang on to and to expand that power
and privilege. Indeed, in the aftermath of the 2016 US presidential elec-
tion, with the preponderance of ‘fake news’ and the repeated doubling-
down on demonstrably false claims (not the least of which culminated in
the storming of the United States Capitol building on 6 January 2021),
there were multiple attempts in the public sphere to blame the success of
Donald Trump on ‘postmodernism’, broadly construed as a widespread
absence of truth.14
But this is not what Deleuze’s passage says. Deleuze does not say
that there is no truth, but rather, that there is no truth other than the
creation of the New. Truth, in other words, is always created, even when
it is a truth of the natural world. If it is true that it is raining today, it
is because the forces of nature constituted the atmospheric conditions
in such a way that rain, in this particular location, resulted; the forces
of the natural world created that truth. Truth, in this sense, is always
created. As we saw with the Aionic structure of time, it is the return of
the different, the miraculous production of the New. The artist, Deleuze
says, is one who recognises this secret of nature, and who participates
in that creation of the New. But this creation is no less ‘true’ or no less
‘real’ than the creations of nature; its effects, likewise, are no less true.
As Anne Sauvagnargues writes, ‘Art is real; it produces real effects on the
plane of forces and not forms’ (2013: 19). And for Deleuze, this artistic
power is evident most saliently in what we might call, following Deleuze
and Guattari’s book on Kafka, minor art, the art of the minoritarian:
‘What is opposed to fiction is not the real; it is not the truth which is
always that of the masters or the colonizers; it is the story-telling func-
tion of the poor’ (Deleuze 1989: 150). Minor art is, first and foremost,
the artistic mode that sees, beyond the world as it is, the world as it
can be. Minor art strives to constitute ‘a people’ against the forces of
capital, servitude, oppression, exclusion and domination. It utilises the
power of the false in order to give to itself a new truth, a new mythos,
Time, Truth and the Power of the False 229
that has always been exploited by the powerful, as he sees within it the
only genuinely liberatory possibilities. As Deleuze claims, ‘it is the only
chance for art or for life’ (1989: 147).
Notes
1. See St. Matthew’s Gospel, chapter 18, verse 3.
2. It is also worth noting that almost the entirety of Williams’s book is dedicated
to the three syntheses of time in Difference and Repetition. The one chapter not
dedicated to Difference and Repetition is dedicated to The Logic of Sense. But
even there, Williams ultimately claims, ‘I will argue later that the two times [of
The Logic of Sense – Chronos and Aion] lead to the same six relations as the
three syntheses [of Difference and Repetition]’ (2011: 138).
3. For good measure, neither do I accept John Mullarkey’s criticisms of ‘Deleuze’s
essential dualism of the two [movement-images and time-images], born from
his non-Bergsonian dissociation of time from movement’ (2009: 101), or David
Bordwell’s characterisation of Deleuze’s ‘uncritical adherence to historiographic
tradition’ (1997: 117).
4. All DK references refer to the Diels-Kranz numbering system for Pre-Socratic
philosophy.
5. For a thorough account of this problem, see Øhrstrøm and Hasle 2015.
6. Admittedly, this is more my own extrapolation of the implications of Leibniz’s
understanding of possible worlds than it is a direct assertion about the nature
of time by Leibniz. In point of fact, Leibniz’s own reflections on time are ever
evolving and tremendously nuanced, and in many ways, as is well-known,
Leibniz’s relationalist view of time anticipates much of what would later become
the accepted physical understanding of time with Einstein’s theories of special
and general relativity in the early twentieth century. For instance, in the Leibniz-
Clarke correspondence, Leibniz claims that ‘instants, considered without the
things, are nothing at all and that they consist only in the successive order of
things’. See Leibniz 2000: 15. For an excellent account of Leibniz’s understand-
ing of time, see Futch 2008. However, for my purposes, even if time is merely
a ‘well-founded’ phenomenon, its ‘instants’ only isolable theoretically or in the
mind of God, if time is, as Leibniz says, an ‘order of successions’, a linear order
of precisely tuned cosmic arrangements, each of which is completely deter-
mined, the ‘instant’ is still there, even if only in abstraction.
7. It is not impossible in itself because it does not violate the law of contradiction.
8. There is much that can be said on this score. Broadly speaking, philosophical
views on time are typically broken into the two primary camps of absolut-
ism and relationalism. Absolutist views of time hold that time is, like space,
something of a container for events to occur in, with the container existing
independently of the events. There are ancient versions of temporal absolut-
ism, such as that of Plato, who, in the Timaeus, famously characterises time
as a ‘moving image of eternity’ (37d). This conception would be thoroughly
theologised in accordance with the doctrines of Christianity in the sixth century
CE by Boethius. Isaac Newton also famously argued for an absolute conception
of time, and it was Newton’s understanding that dominated scientific thinking
until Einstein in the early twentieth century. The most famous defenders of rela-
tionalist accounts of time are Aristotle and, as we saw above (note 6), Leibniz.
Relationalists hold that time cannot be conceived apart from the physical events
that it marks or measures. Aristotle, for instance, famously claims that ‘time
Time, Truth and the Power of the False 231
References
Achebe, C. (1998), Hopes and Impediments: Selected Essays, New York and
Toronto: Anchor Books.
Boethius (1973), Tractates; The Consolation of Philosophy, trans. H. F. Stewart,
E. K. Rand and S. J. Tester, Loeb Classical Library, vol. 74, Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press.
Bordwell, D. (1997), On the History of Film Style, Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
Borges, J. L. (1998) Collected Fictions, trans. Andrew Hurley, New York: Penguin.
Coope, U. (2005), Time for Aristotle: Physics IV.10–14, Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Cornford, F. M. (1935), Plato’s Theory of Knowledge, London: Routledge.
Deamer, D. (2009), ‘Cinema, Chronos/Cronos: Becoming an Accomplice to the
Impasse of History’, in Deleuze and History, ed. Jeffrey A. Bell and Claire
Colebrook, Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, pp. 161–87.
Deleuze, G. (1983), Nietzsche and Philosophy, trans. Hugh Tomlinson, Minneapolis:
University of Minnesota Press.
Deleuze, G. (1986), Cinema 1: The Movement-Image, trans. Hugh Tomlinson and
Barbara Habberjam, Minnesota: University of Minnesota Press.
Deleuze, G. (1989), Cinema 2: The Time-Image, trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Robert
Galeta, Minnesota: University of Minnesota Press.
Deleuze, G. (1990), The Logic of Sense, ed. Constantin Boundas, trans. Mark Lester
with Charles Stivale, New York: Columbia University Press.
Deleuze, G. (1993), The Fold: Leibniz and the Baroque, trans. Tom Conley,
Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Deleuze, G. (1994), Difference and Repetition, trans. Paul Patton, New York:
Columbia University Press.
Descartes, R. (1984), The Philosophical Writings of Descartes: Volume II, trans.
J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff and D. Murdoch, Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Descartes, R. (1985), The Philosophical Writings of Descartes: Volume I, trans.
J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff and D. Murdoch, Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Epictetus (1994), Discourses, in Discourses and Enchiridion, trans. Thomas
Wentworth Higgins, New York: Walter J. Black.
Futch, M. (2008), Leibniz’s Metaphysics of Time and Space, Berlin: Springer.
Time, Truth and the Power of the False 233
Charles J. Stivale
I’d like to tell you, [but] we won’t have time; we never have enough time.
I don’t know, I’ll never get finished if this continues. (Deleuze)1
these weekly encounters. For while the exchanges between Deleuze and
the participants offered openings for potential creation, such encounters
were menaced in terms of limitations to actual duration as well as
compression of space upon time.
Through access to the seminar recordings and transcripts from 1979 to
1987,4 I consider the numerous ways in which time and duration played
fundamental roles in Deleuze’s articulation of his ongoing research
within the pedagogical framework. Given this valuable research tool, I
choose to be guided in this study by the sessions themselves and the insti-
tutional contexts in which they are circumscribed to allow the practices
therein to suggest different facets of Deleuze’s strategies in relation to
time, and especially to remain open to unusual or surprising intersec-
tions that emerge from the seminar exchanges. While I acknowledge
the many perspectives developed on Deleuze’s philosophical conception
of time, by Deleuze himself in different contexts as well as in James
Williams’s masterful introduction to this topic (Williams 2011), I believe
that allowing this archive to speak its own lessons, as it were, provides
a unique opportunity for understanding Deleuze’s teaching more fully.
I first consider the space of the seminar, since the session recordings
convince me that the peculiarities of classroom space in the French
university system, as well as Deleuze’s own requirements, made the
‘spatial question’ a backdrop to any understanding of temporal issues.
Not just a man frequently out of time, Deleuze as an educator was
nearly always out of space. Video clips reveal Deleuze’s regular teaching
location consisting of him seated with students at his elbows, cassette
recorders arrayed around him, with room for his notes and texts.5 Why
did this esteemed professor put up with such conditions? The answer
is simple: Deleuze chose such cramped quarters rather than accept the
available solution, to schedule the seminar within a more spacious uni-
versity amphitheatre. Deleuze repeatedly opposed this option since, as
he put it, ‘What I would do would not work there’, and because ‘we
would need a microphone, so if someone wanted to say something,
they would have to come to the microphone, which puts everyone off.’
Whatever the inconveniences, then, the cramped seminar space allowed
236 Charles J. Stivale
direct exchanges with students, creating the ‘circus [quality] that amuses
me and tends to be more involved (profond)’ (‘P as in Professor’).
Besides the difficulties just noted of Deleuze’s own making, the semi-
nars’ popularity resulted in regular overcrowding, and these space diffi-
culties were but one kind of limitation, or striation, that Deleuze endured
while teaching at Vincennes and then at Vincennes/St Denis.6 Deleuze
clearly dreamed of the teaching venue as a site of an ideal smooth space,
one unfettered by any limitations whatsoever for possibilities of creative
exchange. However, given his work with Félix Guattari on these con-
cepts, Deleuze understood fully that his work unfolded within a State
institution inevitably subject to striations, that is, numerous institutional
and particularly spatial constraints.7 Deleuze also recognised that within
these smooth–striated spatial distinctions, ‘they are mixed together the
whole time’ (TDS ATP V 1–061179), meaning that the ‘smooth’ ideal he
dreamt of necessarily existed only in striated form. In short, the spatial
backdrop emphasised here had unforeseen consequences for the time of
the seminar from one year to the next.
Before shifting to temporal aspects, I note another important detail
that emerges from comments that Deleuze made following the move to
the St Denis location, notably his attempt to find a classroom adequate
for his and his students’ needs. Among numerous classroom space
issues – for example, noises and interruptions from outside the room
– one detail, the security bars placed on the classroom windows, was
something that alarmed Deleuze constantly.8 Hence, this distinguished
scholar was forced to do his own footwork to find a better location,
an effort that seemingly came to fruition during the 17 January 1984
session (in the Cinema III seminar) when Deleuze returns after a mid-
session site visit to announce that henceforth the course would meet in a
larger room, ‘a palace where we will discover happiness’ (TDS Cinema
III 8–170184).
Of course, any teacher actively seeks to obtain or create the most
effective space for teaching and learning, but in Deleuze’s case, his
requirements meant limitations that he had to accept for several years
following his arrival at Vincennes/St Denis. While possibly reflecting
some peculiar professorial idiosyncrasies, Deleuze’s demands for a more
intimate space corresponded to his conception of using the classroom to
support the potentially creative ends of his pedagogical ideals.
Gilles Deleuze, A Man Out of Time 237
slid in each session was fragile, with frequent disturbances of the focus
required for him to create impulsions of inspiration. The impact of
Deleuze’s teaching ‘always [consisted of] something that was not des-
tined to be understood in its totality. A course is a kind of matter in
movement (matière en mouvement), . . . in which each person, each
group, or each student at the limit takes from it what suits him/her’ (‘P as
in Professor’). As he exhorted the participants at the start of the Cinema
IV seminar, ‘It hardly matters if you don’t understand yet; it will come,
there’s no need to hurry; first you listen, and then you understand much
later’ (TDS Cinema IV 1–301084). And in fact, following his retirement,
Deleuze expressed how much he owed to the audience in the seminars,
insisting that this process did not at all resemble ‘argument (discus-
sion)’ – ‘philosophy has absolutely nothing to do with arguing about
things’ – but rather consisted of attempting to understand ‘the problem
someone’s framing and how they’re framing it; [thus] all you should ever
do is explore it, play around with the terms, add something, relate it to
something else, never argue about it. [The seminar] was like an echo
chamber, a feedback loop, in which an idea reappeared after going, as it
were, through various filters’ (Deleuze 1990: 190–1; 1995: 139).12
Furthermore, while discussing distinctions between the modes of
time’s synthesis during the Cinema III seminar (TDS 16–170484),
Deleuze emphasises the importance of an ‘apprehension of the present’,
something that one can focalise (fixer), but that is also contingent on a
wide variability of presents between individuals. He offers the revealing
example of what occurs in his seminar:
I’m here teaching the course, you’re there listening; a third case, one of you
intervenes. When I arrive here, let’s say I have a two-hour long present,
but I mean, I have no impression of time passing. I’ve arrived focalized,
and my entire act of consciousness consists in focalizing this kind of time
period, a two-hour present, that is, these two hours are p resent . . . T
his is
why the two hours for me ultimately go so fast, whereas for you, they don’t
move fast enough at all except when this works sufficiently for you to come
into my present. At that point, you are living the same time as I do. (TDS
Cinema III 16–170484)
sessions in the Spinoza and Leibniz CDs was prepared by weeks of fairly
consistent development of the seminar’s ‘matter in movement’, thus
constituting these selected sessions as turning points of sorts for each
seminar’s development.
However, in each case, we glimpse how the ‘ideal game’ of a session
can go awry through temporal impediments, that is, how Deleuze’s
nearly one-pointed focus on achieving ‘inspiration’ (however fleeting)
collides with the other key facet of this process, namely, the advan-
tages he hoped to derive from extremely close proximity with seminar
participants. For, as he notes in his discussion on apprehending and
focalising the present, the participants’ apprehension tends to be briefer,
less focalised, and a participant who intervenes ‘has determined, at least
in a confused way, what he/she is going to say, why he/she wants to
intervene, the motives for intervening also determining a present, one
that is very different for others’ (TDS Cinema III 16–170484).
As regards these two presumably exemplary CD seminars, although
Deleuze intended the Spinoza session to be the last one so that he could
commence the seminar on Painting, different interventions following
his 70-minute presentation transform the subsequent 80 minutes into a
question-answer session, ultimately preventing Deleuze from returning
to the session’s main point.14 In contrast, while the 1987 Leibniz session
opens in progress on the BNF recording with a 9-minute presentation
by Richard Pinhas (omitted from the CD), Deleuze then reflects nearly
without interruption on the topics of individual choice and inclination,
and then the successive states as these relate to monads, to the soul’s
amplitude and clarity, and hence to freedom. In contrast to the previous
‘exemplary’ CD session, the participants intervene minimally, and yet
one indeed grasps Deleuze’s deep engagement with those around him,
occasionally directing remarks to different students, and clearly gaining
energy step by step as he develops these concepts at the centre of the
seminar’s focus.
Hence, the two sessions selected as sufficiently exemplary for produc-
tion as CDs by one of France’s most prestigious publishers offer dis-
tinctly different profiles in terms of Deleuze’s interaction with students:
one session is seemingly derailed by questions, the other kept steadily
on track by minimal overt student interventions. These polar differences
raise the implicit question of whether Deleuze was more inspired by
remaining open to questioning with the risk of dispersion of different
presents, or by the more subtle, implicit engagement of students quietly
following his every word and possibly focalising extensively within
his present.15 Still, both sessions constitute significant lessons that are
240 Charles J. Stivale
Impediments
One must settle in at the extreme point of one’s knowledge or one’s igno-
rance . . . [at] this very border between knowing and non-knowing: it’s
there that one must settle in to have something to say. (‘N as in Neurology’,
in Deleuze and Parnet 1997)
The conflict between two p oles – of the ‘ideal game’ in Deleuze’s semi-
nars, that is, sessions in which ‘inspiration’ arising from the ‘matter in
movement’ yielded a possible temporal synchronisation of ‘presents’, on
the one hand, and on the other, sessions in which, for many different
reasons, this was not the o utcome – c reated a developing tension across
the years, from one seminar to the next, especially in terms of the time
of the seminar. Deleuze’s belief in his approach of seeking ‘inspira-
tion’ through the seminar’s ‘echo chamber’ collided on occasion with
his frustrations regarding classroom practices, and he sought different
approaches to assuring student interventions, provided that these might
allow him to maintain his focus on the ‘matter’ at hand.
One notable expression of frustration linked to pedagogical consid-
erations occurred at the start of the second Cinema seminar in autumn
1982. While justifying his decision to continue the same topic as the
previous y ear – since he felt that by going too fast, he had ‘let certain
things escape’ in 1981–82 – Deleuze presents an acerbic judgement of
his own teaching activity, observing that ‘for ten years, I’ve been acting
like a clown! . . . It’s a show (spectacle), since the proof is right here:
. . . I speak facing half [an audience] of humans and half tape record-
ers’ (TDS Cinema II 1–021182). Hence, he ponders how to maximise
the course’s implied goal of a collaboration between listeners and the
speaker, that is, how to ‘obtain reactions – n ot objections, which are
always painful and intolerable’ – that is, assistance from the participants
which might result in ‘correct[ing] me, to extend things longer’. As he
admitted, ‘Believe me, this [process of going back over topics] is not
meant to speed things up.’
Gilles Deleuze, A Man Out of Time 241
occurred in circumstances other than solely with Comtesse, and yet curi-
ously, it can also help us to conceptualise Deleuze’s ultimate goal within
the time of the seminar.
subsist or inhere, . . . [that are] verbs, . . . not living presents, but infini-
tives: the unlimited Aion, the becoming that divides itself infinitely in
past and future and always eludes the present’ (1990/2015: 4–5/5). This
infinitive, ‘parler’/to speak, is especially fragile in the seminar, where
Deleuze’s aim is to insert himself into this fleeting interstice between
past-future and present, constantly attempting to create an ongoing
balancing act ‘to grasp [time] in two complementary though mutually
exclusive fashions . . . as the living present in bodies which act and are
acted upon [Chronos] . . . [and] as an entity infinitely divisible into past
and future [Aion], and into the incorporeal effects which result from
bodies, their actions and their passions’ (1990/2015: 5/5–6).
This insight corresponds to the ongoing struggle of sense- making
along a continuum that constituted Deleuze’s experimentation with
‘Deleuze-time’ in the seminars, aptly described as follows: ‘If the battle
is not an example of an event among others, but rather the Event in
its essence, it is no doubt because it is actualized in diverse manners
at once, and because each participant may grasp it at a different level
of actualization within its variable present’ (1990/2015: 100/103). It
is remarkable to glimpse this ‘Event in its essence’ through so many
sessions and across so many seminars and decades, from The Logic of
Sense into the Cinema seminars, with Deleuze developing this thought
from past to future, as Aion, and yet also in actualisations of Chronos.31
Just as smooth space in relation to striated space is a variable mixture of
both, the Aion–Chronos doublet is likewise conjoined yet distinct.
However, rather than considering this a limitation, say, of a pure
Aion, we can discern the event of Aion in its ongoing intersection with
Chronos. The tension between Aion and Chronos for Deleuze is his
recherche for the event as it plays out in contrast to variable actualisa-
tions within a time that inevitably in the classroom is frequently ‘out of
joint’. If Deleuze could do little about the striated space of his seminar
room (in some ways, by his own choice) as well as the educational
regime under which he worked, he attempted to parry these constraints
with the philosophical becomings toward Aion (or eternity) consisting of
‘this copresence of all the degrees of power of action (puissance)’ (TDS
Cinema III 15–270384).32 Yet, he was also fully aware that, just as one
can never reach an entirely smooth space, such movement toward Aion
could only be achieved momentarily, always in moments of extreme
fragility, ‘matter in movement’. As Deleuze suggested about listeners’
reactions within the ‘musical conception of a course’, a delayed effect is
always possible, even preferable, in grasping the ‘matter in movement’
within its ‘variable present’ (‘P as in Professor’).
248 Charles J. Stivale
Moreover, given that ‘the battle hovers over its own field, being neutral
in relation to all of its temporal actualizations . . . it is all the more ter-
rible. Never present but always yet to come and already passed, the
battle is graspable only by the will of anonymity which it itself inspires’
(Deleuze 1990/2015: 100/103). In light of the many steps along the
continuum traced above, I maintain that the extreme, inherent focus and
flow toward the ‘ideal’ end of the c ontinuum – that is, the in-between
of pedagogy and creation or ‘Deleuze-time’ at its extreme – tend toward
this neutrality, this hovering over its ‘field’, in relation to the temporal
actualisations within individual sessions. For the sessions where Deleuze
is most immersed, tending toward the extreme of ‘Deleuze-time’, are
simply those in which Deleuze is effaced and an anonymity of thought is
manifested, however difficult it is for listeners to glimpse this effacement.
The immersion into the event constitutes Deleuze’s ongoing recherche
for ‘counter-actualization’, a tending toward the Event that he described
in The Logic of Sense as ‘the actor’s or dancer’s simple, flat representa-
tion’ (1990/2015: 157/161).
This recherche becomes clearer precisely when such immersion is
impeded through the diverse actualisations traced previously. That is,
the impediments themselves, at varying degrees along the continuum,
confirm the possibility of the ‘ideal’ end of the continuum, clarifying
why, at certain moments, especially in his different comments, defensive
postures and extreme reactions, Deleuze had to take time out, to reset,
to regroup in his battle for immersion into the counter-actualisations of
‘Deleuze-time’ which had been thrown so terribly ‘out of joint’. For the
impediments that he most firmly rejected were those that he identified
unmistakably as ‘objections, which are always painful and intolerable’
(TDS Cinema II 1–021182), since they reveal the extent to which a
listener was not understanding and that waiting would be best: ‘what
someone doesn’t understand, there is the possibility that he’ll under-
stand it afterwards’ (‘P as in Professor’).33
Hence, given that for Deleuze the essential element in a course was ‘to
become alert at the right moment to grasp hold of what suits you, what
suits you personally’ (‘P as in Professor’), rather than posing objections,
Deleuze argued that the ‘[students’] task consists in speaking either
on the basis of [their] thoughts or of [their] feelings (sentiments), but
not [their] opinions (avis)’ (TDS Cinema II 1–021182). Although this
distinction might seem self-serving for Deleuze – ‘thought’ and ‘senti-
ments’ corresponding to comments with which Deleuze could agree,
‘opinions’ or ‘objections’ being quite the o pposite – this perspective at
least provides an alternative to the impression that Deleuze’s supposed
Gilles Deleuze, A Man Out of Time 249
Feeling/Intellect
I’m going fast, really fast as you notice, very fast, but I am speaking toward
your feeling (sentiment), not your intellect (intelligence). (TDS Cinema IV
26–120684)
(saut sur place) of the whole body which exchanges its organic will
for a spiritual will’ (149/153–4). And I believe we can see Deleuze’s
own recherche emerging when he says: ‘My misfortune is present in all
events, but also a splendor and a brightness which dry up misfortune and
which bring about that the event, once willed, is actualized on its most
contracted point, on the cutting edge of an operation’ (149/154).
This ‘cutting edge’ is the fine line that Deleuze pursued within each
seminar. Bousquet’s dictum corresponds to his recherche: ‘“Become the
man of your misfortunes; learn to embody their perfection and bril-
liance”’, to which Deleuze adds the forceful statement:
Nothing more can be said, and no more has ever been said: to become
worthy of what happens to us, and thus to will and release the event, to
become the offspring (le fils) of one’s own events, and thereby to be reborn,
to have one more birth, and to break with one’s carnal birth – to become
the offspring of one’s events and not of one’s actions (oeuvres), for the
action (l’oeuvre) is itself produced by the offspring of the event. (Deleuze
1990/2015: 149–50/154)
Each seminar and each session encompassed these dual facets, Deleuze
seeking on the one hand the ‘counter-actualisation’, however fleeting,
within ‘Deleuze-time’, which necessarily included the potential ‘actu-
alisations’ of ongoing exchanges with participants, and on the other
hand, to realise the event beyond one’s misfortune, beyond one’s battles,
beyond one’s wounds, and thereby to be worthy of what happens.
We can link this recherche in the seminars to Deleuze’s ongoing inquiry
into the ‘supreme subject’ of ‘what is philosophy?’, a focus with which
Deleuze introduced the Leibniz and the Baroque seminar with great hesi-
tation: ‘So, why this [seminar’s] subject [Leibniz]? I wanted to do “What
is philosophy?”, and then I couldn’t. It’s such a sacred subject . . . that I
didn’t dare to take it on. But this [seminar] is nearly an introduction to
“What is philosophy?”’ (TDS Leibniz & Baroque 1–281087). In fact,
Deleuze had already begun this seminar topic explicitly during Cinema
seminar IV when he indicated that he would undertake it ‘on the level of
an encounter of cinema and philosophy’ (TDS Cinema IV 1–301084).
Then, in that seminar’s final session, while speculating on possible topics
for 1985–86, he again suggested that while the ‘dream course’ would be
on ‘what is philosophy?’, another topic would be to link this to consid-
eration of both Blanchot and Foucault (TDS Cinema IV 26–180685).
Indeed, Deleuze would spend half a session on this subject (TDS Leibniz
& Baroque 15–280487), urging students to connect to philosophy by
grasping hold of what suited them personally.
252 Charles J. Stivale
In many ways, this statement hearkens back to ‘the sage’ who, like the
archer, ‘is closer to Zen’:
The sage waits for the event, that is to say, understands the pure event in
its eternal truth . . . as something eternally yet-to-come and always already
passed according to the line of the Aion. But, at the same time, the sage also
wills the embodiment and the actualization of the pure incorporeal event in
a state of affairs and in his or her own body and fl esh . . . and this applies to
the wound and to archery just as much as it applies to the stroll. (Deleuze
1990/2015: 146–7/150–1)
Notes
1. TDS Leibniz & Baroque 14–070487. See the seminar sessions at The Deleuze
Seminars database (deleuze.cla.purdue.edu) founded by Daniel W. Smith
(with research support from Purdue and the National Endowment for the
Humanities), with whom I serve as co-director as well as a principal transcriber
and translator. References to The Deleuze Seminars sessions follow this conven-
tion: TDS + seminar title (often abbreviated) + session number and date (day-
month-year).
2. See ‘P as in Professor’, in Deleuze and Parnet 1997. Cited hereafter in the text
as ‘P as in Professor’.
3. Deleuze often returned to this reference from ‘Hamlet’. See ‘On Four Poetic
Formulas That Might Summarize the Kantian Philosophy’, in Deleuze 1997:
27–35. See the phrase’s development also in the Kant seminar (March–April
1978) and in TDS Cinema III 5–131283 and Cinema III 12–280284.
4. See the digital archive of Deleuze’s seminars located at the Université de Paris
8, established in 1999 at the Bibliothèque Nationale de France (BNF), based
on recordings faithfully made by a Japanese student, Hidenobu Suzuki. The
archive of 273 cassettes of 180 separate lectures comprises 413 hours of record-
ings, accessible online from the BNF through the Gallica search engine (https://
gallica.bnf.fr). A detailed yet partial summary of the BNF holdings has been
published by Frederic Astier (2006).
5. See the two RAI 3-produced videos from the 1986–87 Leibniz seminar (TDS
Leibniz & Baroque 3–181186 and 20–030687) and also the YouTube clip from
the mid-1970s, clearly revealing Deleuze’s compressed spatial circumstances,
the professor barely able to pass through the crowd, pointing out that an inher-
ent danger existed for everyone present both for breathing and should a fire
break out (TDS ATP I 10–240276, an approximate date). In an earlier session
(see TDS ATP I 7–130176), a full-scale revolt broke out concerning the lack of
space. This clip’s translated title is ‘Molar and Molecular Multiplicities’; see
deleuze.cla.purdue.edu/node/230 for the YouTube video link, under the title
Deleuze su molteplicità molare e molteplicità molecolare.
6. In the late 1970s, the conservative government of Valéry Giscard d’Estaing
decided to destroy the Vincennes campus (deemed a hotbed of radical activ-
ity and drug trafficking) and to move the campus operation to St Denis, in
northeast Paris, starting in the autumn 1980 academic year. Hence, Hidenobu
Suzuki’s recordings correspond to the final year at Vincennes, then continue
for the entire seven years that Deleuze spent at Vincennes/St Denis. For discus-
sion of specific political issues on the Vincennes campus preceding this move,
see TDS ATP V 10–040380. On the political atmosphere at Vincennes during
Deleuze’s years there, see Dosse 2010: 347–57.
254 Charles J. Stivale
7. On these distinctions, see ‘Plateau 14. 1440, The Smooth and the Striated’, in
Deleuze and Guattari 1987.
8. Following the November–December 1986 demonstrations that created a four-
week hiatus in the Leibniz and the Baroque seminar, Deleuze vigorously encour-
ages the students to prepare a petition to have these bars removed (TDS Leibniz
& Baroque 4–161286).
9. For a remarkable overview of Deleuze’s vocalisations within his different ‘ora-
torial avatars’ (personnages oratoires) in the seminars, see Jaeglé 2005.
10. References to The Logic of Sense include pagination for both translation edi-
tions.
11. Private correspondence with author. For an example of these notes, see the
images in the French transcription of TDS Cinema III 18–150585.
12. Translation modified; as the translator Martin Joughin notes, ‘discuter [as well
as discussion] has in French a polemical resonance absent from “discuss”’
(Deleuze 1995: 200). For Deleuze’s extended explanation of why discuter
and discussions have no place in philosophy, see TDS Leibniz & Baroque
15–280487.
13. ‘Spinoza: immortalité et éternité’ (Immortality and Eternity) (Paris: Gallimard,
2001), ‘Leibniz: âme et damnation’ (Soul and Damnation) (Paris: Gallimard
2003) and ‘Gilles Deleuze Cinéma’ (Paris: Gallimard, 2006). I focus on the two
complete sessions (Spinoza and Leibniz) rather than the excerpts collected from
five different sessions (Cinéma). Both Parnet and Pinhas were long-standing par-
ticipants in Deleuze’s seminars. Parnet co-edited with Deleuze their exchanges
in Dialogues (Deleuze and Parnet 1987) and interviewed him in L’Abécédaire
de Gilles Deleuze (Deleuze and Parnet 1997). Pinhas is a musician who created,
with the Deleuze family’s permission, a still active website, WebDeleuze (web
deleuze.com) with transcriptions and translations of many seminar sessions
and including a range of resources and links for scholars interested in Deleuze’s
work. Claude Jaeglé’s (2005) overview of the seminars is based primarily on the
Spinoza and Leibniz CDs as well as L’Abécédaire.
14. As a result, the Spinoza seminar continued through the following session (on
24 March 1981) and only culminated after 54 minutes of additional questions
and answers on 31 March, following which the Painting seminar began.
15. Each session is temporally distinctive in being considerably edited for the CDs
in contrast to the BNF recordings. The Spinoza CD omits approximately 20
minutes of the recorded session, the Leibniz CD omits approximately an hour;
many of these omissions in each correspond precisely to interactions with par-
ticipants, apparently deemed ancillary by the producers.
16. Objections arose to Deleuze’s tendentious proposal to reduce the class size to
a smaller group limited to the space in which everyone could be comfortably
seated, in order to ‘return, review and perfect with me what we’ve already
done’. Unfortunately, after extensive discussion but without offering practical
details on how this reduction would work, Deleuze never attempted any of
these extreme measures, having vented frustration at the seemingly insoluble
situation.
17. Notably, during the final semester at Vincennes in 1980, with campus politics
upsetting the usual schedule, Deleuze devoted an entire session to assisting the
participants in developing concrete actions for non-violent direct protest (TDS
ATP V 10–040380); at the next session, continued unrest forced them to stop
after only 40 minutes (TDS ATP V 11–110380). See Dosse 2010, chapter 19,
for a contextual explanation of the Vincennes situation.
18. Besides student departures and arrivals, noise from sources in and outside the
building, including external students interrupting the class, the session I call ‘the
Gilles Deleuze, A Man Out of Time 255
day of the squeaky door’ reveals Deleuze first irritated by a repetitive screech,
then shifting toward dark humour (‘I’m going to bring a revolver next time’),
before finally linking the hallucinatory squeak to specific points in the lecture
(TDS Cinema I 19–180582).
19. See the videos linked to TDS ATP I-Deleuze at Paris 8, seminars to which
Guattari regularly contributed, and also TDS Foucault 23–130586. As for
Parnet, she is present (seated near Deleuze) in the RAI 3 video of TDS Leibniz
& Baroque 3–181186.
20. See, for example, Alliez’s contribution (on economic doctrine and mercantilism)
in TDS ATP V 7–290180, and also six years later (TDS Foucault 24–200586,
nearly entirely inaudible). Pinhas intervened occasionally on digital technology
and music, the end of one such intervention located at the start of TDS Leibniz
& Baroque 10–240287. I discuss Comtesse’s numerous interventions below.
21. For example, musicologist Pascale Criton (TDS Cinema IV 10–220185); direc-
tor and writer Raymonde Carasco (TDS Cinema IV 12–050285); film and video
artist Pascal Auger (TDS Cinema IV 20–300485); filmmaker Dominique Vaillant
(TDS Cinema IV 22–140585); a mathematician and colleague at Vincennes/St.
Denis (designated only as Marek, TDS Leibniz & Baroque 8–270187); musi-
cologists Pascale Criton and Vincent Walls in the final session (TDS Leibniz &
Baroque 20–020687).
22. Notably, Dominique Vaillant’s interview/intervention in May 1985 on dif-
ferent aspects of sound and soundtracks in films inspired Richard Pinhas’s
lengthy (and unanticipated) intervention, followed by another invited inter-
vener, Pascale Criton, who objected to Pinhas’s perspectives. Facing precisely
the kind of exchange he detested, Deleuze shifted between alternate postures,
on one hand defending Pinhas, but on the other hand seeking common ground,
finally responding to another student’s objections with a peculiar rationale: ‘She
[Vaillant] wasn’t speaking in her own name; she had accepted to answer some
questions that I asked her, fine. I wanted to have my technical session’ (TDS
Cinema IV 22–140585). Moreover, this exchange seems to confirm Parnet’s
views on the limits of the question–answer/interview procedure (Deleuze and
Parnet 1987: 20).
23. One remarkable exchange of this kind occurred during the Spinoza seminar.
Having introduced the theme of good and evil through Spinoza’s correspondence
with Willem van Blyenbergh (a harsh critic of Spinoza’s view), Deleuze faced a
forceful critique from one participant, whom Deleuze at one point described as
‘my Blyenbergh’, and yet he succeeded in responding to the student while gener-
ally remaining within the focal development (TDS Spinoza 6–130181).
24. However, after the student departed, Deleuze first apologised quite sincerely,
expressing his concern for this young woman’s ‘little burst of delirium’, admit-
ting that she had shown up at his home several days earlier, ‘in a state of crisis’,
and that he worried that she might do something extreme. At the start of the
following session, Deleuze allowed her to make a presentation which was not
preserved on any recordings (TDS Cinema IV 19–230485). On ‘les fous’ (the
crazies) as a phenomenon in the Vincennes seminars, see ‘D as in Desire’ in
Deleuze and Parnet 1997, and in terms of the politics of so-called marginaux
(marginals), see Deleuze and Parnet 1987: 138–40.
25. Comtesse completed a dissertation in 1974 with Deleuze. The principal
Comtesse interventions to which Deleuze responded affirmatively, including
extended presentations (noted here with *), are: TDS Leibniz 4–060580*; TDS
Spinoza 4–161280; TDS Spinoza 5–060181; TDS Spinoza 6–130181; in the
Spinoza seminar, sessions 7 through 11, and 13; TDS Painting 8–050681; in
Cinema I, sessions 4, 5, 18, 19, 20*; in Cinema II, sessions 5, 9, 10, 13*, 17,
256 Charles J. Stivale
19*; in Cinema IV, sessions 2, 3, 10, 12; in the Foucault seminar, sessions 10*,
17*, 26*; TDS Leibniz & Baroque 15–280487 and 18–190587. On Comtesse’s
seminar contributions, see also Dosse 2010: 356.
26. See above for Comtesse’s Foucault presentations; Guattari participated in TDS
Foucault 23–130586, Alliez in TDS Foucault 24–200586, the musicologist
(speaking on Boulez’s composition Pli selon pli) in TDS Foucault 25–270586.
27. See the last 5 minutes of the 4-hour, 20-minute-long video titled ‘Il Senso in
Meno II’ at TDS ATP I-Deleuze at Paris VIII (deleuze.cla.purdue.edu/node/230)
and on YouTube (under this title).
28. The interventions to which Deleuze objected most strongly occur in TDS
Spinoza 12–100381; TDS Painting 5–120581; TDS Cinema IV 7–181284; TDS
Cinema IV 16–190385; TDS Leibniz & Baroque 13–170387.
29. As regards the matter of textual evidence, a remarkable exchange occurs in the
Cinema II seminar (TDS Cinema II 19–030583) in which Deleuze challenges
Comtesse on a citation from Proust, based on one word that Comtesse attrib-
uted to Proust that seemed suspicious to Deleuze. Upon verification, I have
determined that Comtesse misquoted Proust’s novel, Jean Santeuil, and cer-
tainly was unable to provide the reference to Deleuze. Moreover, Deleuze’s ire
in the cited exchange arose no doubt from his having rebuked Comtesse several
weeks before, albeit more gently, on the same lack of sources in a discussion on
Élie Faure (TDS IV 3–131184).
30. Of course, Comtesse was not the only student able to upset Deleuze. An exem-
plary session in this regard occurs in seminar Cinema II. Despite being extremely
upset by a dual confrontation with Comtesse and one other student, Deleuze
was still able eventually to return to a focused development, quite pertinent
for this discussion, in which he encompassed two figures of time, one that is
understood as an aggregate of time and another that is time as the instant, the
interval, concluding the session with ‘next time, yes, we’ll see’, following which
a pause occurred, and, as if picked up by a hot microphone, Deleuze said to
someone nearby, ‘They were so nasty today . . .’ (TDS Cinema II 14–150383).
31. For example, see the discussion on the present, the instant and the interval in
TDS Cinema II 17–190483.
32. ‘Cette coprésence de tous les degrés de puissance appartient à l’éternité, c’est-
à-dire à l’Aiôn’, the copresence that Deleuze continues to explore in Cinema III
15. See also TDS Cinema III 14–200384 and Cinema III 16–170484, in which
Deleuze juxtaposes Aion to the instant and to the Greek term nûn, or mainten-
ant (now).
33. Deleuze continued: ‘The best students were those who asked questions the fol-
lowing week . . . they would pass me a little note from one week to the n ext – a
practice I appreciated.’
34. Among the most striking locutions in Deleuze’s sessions are the phrase ‘il faut
que vous sentiez . . .’ (you must sense/feel that . . .) this or that point or concept
under consideration, and the imperative ‘Sentez que . . .’ (Sense that . . .); also,
the complimentary, supportive phrase ‘Vous sentez que . . .’ (You get/sense/feel
that . . .), from which students could infer Deleuze’s confidence in their grasping
hold.
35. This example from Nietzsche occurs often in Deleuze; see especially Deleuze
1983: 106 and 201, n.31.
Gilles Deleuze, A Man Out of Time 257
References
Astier, F. (2006), Les cours enregistrés de Gilles Deleuze, 1979–1987, Mons:
Éditions Sils Maria.
Deleuze, G. (1983), Nietzsche and Philosophy, trans. Hugh Tomlinson, New York:
Columbia University Press.
Deleuze, G. (1990), Pourparlers, Paris: Minuit.
Deleuze, G. (1990/2015), The Logic of Sense, ed. Constantin V. Boundas, trans.
Mark Lester with Charles J. Stivale, New York: Columbia University Press/
London: Bloomsbury.
Deleuze, G. (1995), Negotiations, trans. Martin Joughin, New York: Columbia
University Press.
Deleuze, G. (1997), Essays Critical and Clinical, trans. Daniel W. Smith and Michael
A. Greco, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Deleuze, G. and C. Parnet (1987) Dialogues, New York: Columbia University Press.
Deleuze, G. and C. Parnet (1997), L’Abécédaire de Gilles Deleuze, dir. Pierre-André
Boutang, Paris: Éditions Montparnasse (DVD: Gilles Deleuze, From A to Z, trans.
Charles J. Stivale, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2012).
Deleuze, G. and F. Guattari (1987), A Thousand Plateaus, trans. Brian Massumi,
Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Dosse, F. (2010), Gilles Deleuze & Félix Guattari. Intersecting Lives, trans. Deborah
Glassman, New York: Columbia University Press.
Jaeglé, C. (2005), Portrait oratoire de Gilles Deleuze aux yeux jaunes, Paris: PUF.
Williams, J. (2011), Gilles Deleuze’s Philosophy of Time: A Critical Introduction
and Guide, Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.
Notes on Contributors
the strike during his work as president and chief negotiator for the
Canadian Union of Educational Workers Local 2. He has published
articles on Hume, Canguilhem, Derrida, Deleuze and others, as well a
cookbook and poetry. He is currently serving as editor-in-chief of Janus
Unbound: Journal of Critical Studies, launched in November 2021, and
of Codgito: Student Journal of Philosophy and Theory, launched in
spring 2022.
Index