Kennedy 1987
Kennedy 1987
Kennedy 1987
Frankfurt School*
Ellen Kennedy
"Karl Marx may have discovered profit, but I discovered/>o/#tca/ profit." Carl
Schmitt's only half-joking remark plays with a persistent problem for political
theory since Hegel — the often perplexing similarity of ideological positions on
the left and the right. German intellectual history in this century presents an
unusually complicated example of such "convergence" in the reception of
Schmitt's work by the Frankfurt School.
The controversy surrounding Schmitt is not so much about the quality and
depth of his work as about its political consequences. An uncomfortable ques-
tion for intellectual history in general, die case of Schmitt is most problematic
for the German left. In contrast to their Italian comrades, who borrow
unabashedly from him, die German left mentions Schmitt's name gingerly if at
all.1 According to a view of Schmitt that began to take shape widi his defense of
die Preussenschlag2 in 1932 and froze into place widi his Nazi collaboration after
37
38 ELLEN KENNEDY
1933, Schmitt played the role in German history first as defender of reaction
and theorist of authoritarianism, then as Kronjurist of the totalitarian state. Con-
sequently, his popularity with writers on the other side of Weimar's political
spectrum has largely been forgotten. Despite Habermas' puzzlement at "the
powerful influence of Carl Schmitt even on the left,"3 the contemporary influ-
ence of Schmitt's anti-liberalism is obscured by his reputation as a "fascist"
thinker.
But the lineages of Schmitt's influence are not so straightforward. Haber-
mas' attention to Schmitt and Schmitt's influence on an earlier generation of
the Frankfurt School produces a more complicated picture. A reception of
Schmitt's diought can be traced in the work of Habermas and Walter Benjamin
and Otto Kirchheimer before him. However, none of these shared Schmitt's
political goals or values. A common aversion to liberalism and skepticism
about liberal democracy drew mem and omers to Schmitt's political and legal
theory, but this does not say much about the character of the reception or its
consequences, especially where the divergence of values is so apparent. How-
ever, if attention is shifted away from the principal values which distinguish
Schmitt from the Frankfurt School, another perspective opens up. Although
the editors of a recent English collection find the origins of Critical Theory in "a
series of ideas which emerged in Germany during the 1920s and 1930s," the
vast literature on the Frankfurt School has scarcely attempted to trace its semin-
al ideas beyond Adorno and Horkheimer. 4 Lack of attention to Weimar de-
bates concerning the state and politics is a glaring omission in the extensive de-
bate on the origins of Critical Theory. Misunderstandings of that theory itself
has been the result.
The following discussion addresses both these issues: the reception of
Schmitt's ideas by Frankfurt School theorists such as Benjamin, Kirchheimer,
and Habermas, and Schmitt's attitude toward liberal institutions. Second, it
will attempt to dissolve a paradox about Schmitt's reception that prevents ana-
ing that the Reich had no right to remove the Prussian government but was entitled to
appoint a Reich commissioner for Prussia.
3. Jurgen Habermas, "Psychischer Thermidor und die Wiedergeburt der re-
bellischen Subjektivitat," Habermas, Philosophisch-politische Profile (Suhrkamp Verlag:
Frankfurt a.M., 1984), p. 334.
4. David Held and John B. Thompson, Habermas: Critical Debates (Macmillan Pub-
lishers, London: 1982), p. 2. The best work on Schmitt and the German left has been
produced by Volker Neumann and Alfons Sdllner. See Volker Neumann: "Ver-
fassungstheorien politischer Antipoden: Otto Kirchheimer und Carl Schmitt," Kritische
Justiz (1981), no. 14, pp. 235-254; "Kompromiss oder Entscheidung?: Zur Rezeption
der Theorie Carl Schmitts in den Weimarer Arbeiten Franz L. Neumanns," Joachim
Perels, ed., Recht, Demokratie und Kapitalismus: Aktualitdt und Probleme der Theorie Franz L
Neumanns (Nomos Verlagsgesellschaft, 1984), pp. 65-78; "Carl Schmitt und die Linke,"
Die Zeit, no. 28 (July 8,1983), p. 32. See Alfons Sollner, "Leftist Students of the Conserva-
tive Revolution: Neumann, Kirchheimer and Marcuse," in Telos 61 (Fall 1984), pp. 55-
70. See also Wolfgang Jager, Offentlichkeit und Parlamentarismus: Eine Kritik an Jurgen
Habermas (Verlag W. Kohlhammer: Stuttgart, 1973).
SCHMITTANDTHEFRANKFURTSCHOOL 39
5. On this tradition see Fritz Stern, The Politics ofCultural Despair: A Study in the Rise of
German Ideology (Doubleday: New York, 1961).
6. Carl Schmitt (pseud., Johannes Negelius, Mox Doctor), Schattenrisse (Ski-
macheten Verlag: Berlin, 1918); Theodor Daubler's "Nordlicht": Drei Studien uber die Elemente,
den Geist und die Aktualitdt des Werkes (Georg Muller Verlag: Munich, 1916); "Die
Buribunken," Summa 4,1918, pp. 89-106. References in this paragraph to Adam Muller
and "occasio" are from Schmitt, Politische Romantik (Duncker & Humblot: Berlin, 1982),
especially pp. 22-26 and 115-152. Cf. Schmitt, The Crisis ofParliamentary Democracy (1923)'
Trans, by Ellen Kennedy, (The MIT Press: Cambridge, Mass: 1985), p. 46 and 33-50. '
7. Carl Schmitt, Political Theology: Four Chapters on the Concept of Sovereignty (1922),
Trans, by George Schwab, (The MIT Press: Cambridge, Mass., 1985).
40 ELLEN KENNEDY
the state in reading Kautsky's Terrorism and Communism (1919), and in the context
of the Marxist debate that ensued. But Schmitt's Diktatur, although subtided,
"From the Beginnings of the Modern Idea of Sovereignty to the Proletarian
Class Struggle," ends with die beginnings of the proletarian class struggle.8
This class struggle posed the most immediate challenge to die liberal state; its
theorists had developed die most powerful critique of bourgeois dieories of law
and dictatorship. They argued diat dictatorship need not contradia democracy
and diat a Marxist dictatorship destroys bodi die bourgeoisie and liberalism.
Schmitt concluded diat liberalism contradicts democracy because, unlike the
Leninist dieory of democracy, liberal democracy denies diat dictatorship can
be a means to an end and a legitimate form of die state. Schmitt argued further
that liberal ideas and institutions form neidier a practical nor a principled limi-
tation on a nation's democratic power to decide its constitution. There was evi-
dence in die contemporary history of Germany and Europe generally diat
democratic constitutions were not necessarily liberal, but it was only after die
1917 October Revolution that Schmitt defined a constitution as a "collective
decision about die kind and form of political unity." Lenin's claim that die dic-
tatorship of die proletariat is true democracy helped shape die notion of a con-
tradiction between liberalism and democracy that is crucial to Schmitt's analy-
sis of parliamentarism. In The Crisis of Parliamentary Democracy Schmitt argued
diat Marx had transformed the bourgeiosie from a symbol of literary spite into
a fact of world-historical significance.9 The dictatorship of die proletariat could
decide; die liberal bourgeoisie could not.10
Schmitt's starting point — law and the state — incorporated a transcendental
intention. Legal positivism had ignored the "ultimate quesitions" of political
audiority: state power and legitimacy. The modern crisis of legitimacy began
with Descartes. Widi die collapse of die old metaphysic centered on a tran-
scendent God, a dualism appeared in modern philosophy between external
and internal, being and feeling, nature and spirit, subject and object, etc.,
which had far-reaching consequences for political life. Widiout a transcendent
God, the critical question in political philosophy became "who would take His
8. Carl Schmitt, Die Diktatur: Von den Anfangen des modemen Souverdnitdtsgedankens bis
turnproletarischen Klassenkampf (Duncker & Humblot: Berlin, 1978).
9. Schmitt, Parliamentary Democracy, op. cit., pp. 51-64.
10. Ball had argued that the relation of Schmitt's Political Romanticism to his Political
Theology can be compared to the relation between Kant's Critique ofPure Reason and his Cri-
tique ofPractical Reason. Not only is Political Theology expressly tied to the conclusions of Po-
litical Romanticism, it is also concerned with the concept of sovereignty. The relation be-
tween the two volumes can be seen in their concentration on the meaning of decision:
the romantic chooses not to decide on issues but rather to make a philosophy of the irra-
tional out of indecision. Cf. Hugo Ball, "Carl Schmitt's PolitischeTheologie," originally
published in Hochland 21, 1924, pp. 261-286; now reprinted in Jacob Taubes, ed., Der
Furst dieser Welt: Carl Schmitt und die Folgen (Wilhelm Fink/Ferdinand Schoningh Verlag:
Munich, 1983), p. 104. See also Ellen Kennedy, "Political Expressionism: The Meta-
physical and Theological Origins of Carl Schmitt's The Concept of the Political," inj. Reed
ed., Oxford German Studies (Oxford University Press: Oxford, 1987).
SCHMITTAND THE FRANKFURT SCHOOL 41
place as the highest and most certain reality and thus serve as a point of
legitimation in historical reality?" In Schmitt's view there were only two candi-
dates — either the "community" or "history." In modern political philosophy
these were the ultimate sources of progressive or conservative legitimacy."
The importance of "decision" in Schmitt's work stems from this problem.
"Decision" is the means to close the gap opened up by modern philosophy be-
tween idea and reality. His definition of sovereignty in Political Theology ("Sover-
eign is he who decides on the state of exception"12) generates a practical criteri-
on. Sovereignty rests not on a monopoly of force — here Schmitt's view differs
from Hobbes' — but on the sovereign's "monopoly of decision"; sovereign de-
cisions mediate between right and power and implement justice. The dilemma
of modern jurisprudence in Schmitt's thinking is a result of its place between
theology and technology; the tension can only be resolved by a concrete sci-
ence. So understood, jurisprudence holds the door open to transcendent truth
which alone can give meaning to history.13
Schmitt's cultural critique is the source of his negative critique of modern so-
ciety and politics; his philosophical intention is the source of his positive con-
ception of the state in terms of a theory of truth. Two distinctive features of
Schmitt's account of the Weimar Republic have remained formal parts of a dis-
tinctive German critique of liberalism. First, he constructed a "classical" model
of liberal institutions and then measured dieir contemporary counterparts
against it. This method was used in his book on parliamentarism and in his
constitutional theory, Verfassungslehre (1928). The Crisis ofParliamentary Democracy
shows this most clearly. After oudining the scope of liberal theory and defining
parliamentary government in terms of die principles of discussion, publicity
and the public sphere, he concludes mat parliament as an existing institution is
in decline and its principles no longer credible. He makes a similar argument in
Legalitat und Legitimitdt (1932), the difference being Schmitt's explicit conclusion
diat the decay of liberal institutions from dieir own principles destroys their
claim to legitimacy.14
A second feature of Schmitt's argument distinguishes it from both German
legal thought and Marxist critiques of liberalism. German legal meory ignored
politics or (in Schmitt's view) incorporated political values into a supposedly
neutral jurisprudence, whereas he tried to make constitutional law and juris-
prudence aware of the political reality in which and widi which they operated.15
Marxists offered a social critique but no meory of the state. Marx dealt widi die
political origin of law and the class origin of die state, but did not try to develop
11. Schmitt, Political Romanticism, op.tit.,p. 103.
12. Schmitt, Political Theology, op.tit.,pp. 5f.
13. Ibid., chap. 1. Cf also Carl Schmitt, "Die Lage der europaischen Rechts-
wissenschaft," in VerfassungsrecktlicheAufsdtzeausdenJahren 1924-1954. Materialien zu einer
Verfassungslehre (Duncker & Humblot: Berlin, 1958), pp. 386-429.
14. Carl Schmitt, Legalitat und Legitimitdt (Duncker & Humblot: Munich & Leipzig,
1932).
15. Cf. Schmitt, 1927 Foreword to Die Diktatur, op.tit.,pp. ix-x.
42 ELLEN KENNEDY
a science of law and politics that analyzed the liberal state under the complicat-
ed conditions of 20th century capitalism. European Marxists attempting to de-
velop a Marxist theory of die state in the 1920s, when a communist movement
actually held state power in Russia, became increasingly conscious of this gap in
radical theory.16
Schmitt's work analyzed die contradictions in liberal democracy — the starting
point of every radical challenge to representative democracy and liberal political
instructions since the French Revolution — in terms of a theory of die state.
Schmitt agreed that liberalism destroys democracy and democracy destroys
liberalism. His development of diis position into a theory of die state and liberal
institutions captured the attention of some in the Frankfurt School, who trans-
lated it into leftist political terms. The core of Schmitt's argument can be summa-
rized as follows: (1) The bourgeosie is frivolous and indecisive. It follows diat (a)
liberal democracy is a bourgeois political form dependent on compromise, (b)
compromise widiin diat system is tactically or explicitly redefined as "phoney" or
"formal," (c) liberal constitutions are "indecisive" political arrangements which
never substantially resolve the material claims of equality. (2) Democracy, "die
identity of die rulers and the ruled," challenges die legitimacy of liberal govern-
ment (majority rule, parliamentary discussion, and the public order). (3) Liberal
democracy is inseparable from die institutions of die bourgeois constitutional
state, die functional and normative guarantor of liberal society. The making of law
(parliament), as well as its interpretation and administration (die courts and state
bureaucracy), further divide die democratic ideal and liberal reality. They diereby
contradict democratic legitimacy dirough die "neutralization" and "forma-
lization" of politics. (4) Legality and legitimacy are not identical, as liberal dieory
maintains, but two distinct and even contradictory concepts. In addition to legal
and procedural sources of legitimacy diere are at least three odiers: ratione materiae
(the material claims of justice); ratione supremitatis (plebiscitary legitimacy); and
ratione necessitous (administrative orders in times of emergency or exception).
16. Cf. Max Adler, Die Staatsauffassung des Marxismus: Ein Beitrag zur Unterscheidung von
sozwlogischer und juristischer Methode (1922), reprinted by Wissenschaftliche Buchge-
sellschaft (Darmstadt: 1964). For a long discussion of Schmitt's Die Diktatur, whose main
categories (commissariat and sovereign dictatorship) are positively appropriated, see
pp. 193 ff.
17. Schmitt, Political Theology, op. tit., pp. 61 f.
SCHMITTAND THE FRANKFURT SCHOOL 43
the class character of parliamentary democracy the seeds of decay. Once liber-
alism triumphed in the representation of the people in parliament, those
classes which had been allied with the bourgeoisie against the monarchy would
in turn struggle against the domination of the bourgeoisie. Being essentially
apolitical, the bourgeoisie will be unable to respond to this challenge. It will dis-
cuss, while others decide against parliamentary democracy and liberalism.
Walter Benjamin came to similar conclusions earlier. In a youthful essay
"Das Leben der Studenten" (1915), he criticized the "banal philosophy of life"
in German universities as a contradiction of the spirit. His attack on bourgeois
life equates bourgeois values with the neutralization of danger, and hence of
the spiritual center of life, science and eros. He saw a student's few years of free-
dom before family and professional life begin — "this whole irrational period
of waiting for a position and marriage" — as a playful, pseudo-romantic waste
of time.18 It inculcates the same frivolous superficiality which Schmitt also saw
in liberalism.
After WWI and the German Revolution, Benjamin developed this critique of
bourgeois values into a critique of bourgeois institutions. In 1921 he published
a critique of violence ("Kritik der Gewalt"), meant as part of a larger study of
politics. Written under the influence of Sorel's Reflections on Violence (1912),
which Benjamin read at the urging of Ernst Bloch and Hugo Ball, he used an
emergency situation (here a revolutionary general strike) to reveal the essence
of politics.19 Benjamin's argument parallels Schmitt's argument in Political The-
ology. The exception (Ausnahme) is a possibility which exposes bom the essence
of politics and the ultimate structure of sovereignty. His critique of liberal
parliamentarism owes more to Erich Unger and Anatole France than to
Schmitt in its conception of compromise as corruption. But die agreement widi
Schmitt's views is nevertheless striking.20 Benjamin argued mat parliament had
forgotten the origins of its authority and lacked the sense of law-giving force
that it represents, and declined into a "pathetic spectacle" incapable of reach-
ing decisions worthy of its democratic power.21 The decay of mis ideal in the ac-
tual practice of parliamentary institutions had finally driven as many away from
liberal democracy as this ideal had drawn mem to it before WWI. Benjamin's
18. Walter Benjamin, "Das Leben der Studenten" in Gesammelte Schriften, eds. Rolf
Tiedemannand Hermann Schweppenhauser (Suhrkamp Verlag; Frankfurt a.M., 1974),
Vol. II/l, pp. 75-87.
19. Walter Benjamin, "Kritik der Gewalt," Gesammelte Schriften 11/1. op.tit.,pp. 179-
203. On Benjamin's friendship with Bloch and Ball, see Gershom Scholem, Walter
Benjamin: Die Geschichte einer Freundschaft (Suhrkamp Verlag: Frankfurt a.M., 1975), pp.
100 ff.
20. Erich Unger, Politik und Metaphysik (Verlag David: Berlin, 1921). Benjamin wrote
to Scholem that this was "The most important work on politics of this age." See Walter
Benjamin, Briefe, Gershom Scholem and Theodor Adorno, eds. (Suhrkamp Verlag:
Frankfurt a.M. 1966), p. 252. Benjamin seems to have known Anatole France's Le lys
rouge (1894) in Franziska Grafin zu Revendow's German translation, Die rote Lilie (1919),
cf. Benjamin's Gesammelte Schriften, op. tit., II/3, p. 946.
21. Benjamin, "Kritik der Gewalt," Gesammelte Schriften, op. tit., II/l, pp. 190-191.
44 ELLEN KENNEDY
essays, however, were not directly influenced by Schmitt. But Benjamin's The
Origin of German Tragic Drama (1928) contains a long passage dealing with
Schmitt's theory of sovereignty in Political Theology.
Benjamin expressed his indebtedness to Schmitt in a letter: "In the next few
days you will receive from die publishers a copy of my book, The Origin of German
Tragic Drama. Widi diese lines I want not only to announce it, but also to express
my pleasure mat I am able, at Mr. Albert Salomon's suggestion, to send it to
you. You will very quickly see how much the book's description of the 17 th cen-
tury theory of sovereignty owes to you. Perhaps I might be allowed to say in ad-
dition that I found confirmation for my research mediod in philosophy and the
history of an in the philosophy of state expressed in your later works, above all
Die Diktatur. If you are of the same mind after reading my book, die purpose of
my sending it will have been fulfilled."22
Benjamin continued to admire Schmitt's work long after he had turned away
from die mystical conservatism of the Youth Movement and after he had met
Bertolt Brecht. Benjamin's eclecticism drew not only on Schmitt, but among
others on Stefan George, Ludwig Klages and Johan Jakob Bachofen. For
Benjamin's literary executors, however, his admiration of Schmitt was (along
with his admiration for Brecht) problematic. Adorno edited out all references
to Schmitt when The Origin ofGerman Tragic Drama appeared in die first collection
The Critique of Majority Rule and ofthe Constitutional State: Neumann and Kirchheimer
Bodi Neumann and Kirchheimer took part in Schmitt's seminar on constitu-
tional law at the Handels-Hochschule in Berlin in 1930-31 during die period of
intense crisis in Weimar's parliamentary institutions. The reason for this crisis
was antagonistic pluralism, which repeatedly hindered the formation of stable
political coalitions. In particular, die divergences between die Social Democrats
and die German People's Party were too wide to provide a firm basis for die So-
cial Democratic government of Herman Miiller, which resigned on March 27,
1930. The following day, President Hindenburg appointed Heinrich Briining
chancellor and his cabinet proceeded to rule dirough die emergency provi-
sions of Article 48 of the Weimar Constitution. Since Briining's "emergency"
powers came direcdy from Hindenburg, his cabinet could remain in power
only so long as die President was prepared to support his policies, which he did
until die spring of 1932. From die beginning, however, Briining's cabinet had
no parliamentary basis in die Reichstag. The Social Democrats pursued a poli-
cy of toleration or passive acceptance aimed at preventing a successful combi-
nation of anti-democratic forces on die left and right (die Communist and Nazi
parties) which would have intensified die political and constitutional crisis dur-
ing deepening economic chaos. Schmitt's Berlin seminar focused on the ten-
sion between die Weimar Constitution's formal (legal and legislative) character-
istics and its substance (what Montesquieu called the "spirit" of die laws, or, in
Schmitt's terminology, die Constitution's principle of legitimacy). In die next
two years he published Der Hiiter der Verfassung (1931) and Legalitat und Legitimitat
(1932). Both built on die arguments of Schmitt's The Concept ofthe Political and the
Verfassungslehre, and on his analysis of specific provisions in die Weimar Consti-
tution, notably diose dealing widi presidential audiority, die dissolution of par-
liament and, most importandy, die character of "basic rights" and dieir rela-
tion to die rest of die Constitution. The work of Neumann and Kirchheimer
during diose years followed Schmitt's focus.
Franz Neumann came to Berlin in 1928 — die year Schmitt left Bonn for a
new post at die Handels-Hochschule — and was active from die very beginning
in a legal practice specializing in labor legislation. His ties to Social-Democratic
trade-union lawyers (among diem Otto Kahn-Freund, Ernst Fraenkel and
Goetz Briefs) were close, and he continued to pursue the academic and practi-
cal-political interests he had developed as Hugo Sinzheimer's assistant in
Frankfurt (1923-27). In Berlin he shared an office widi Fraenkel and lectured at
die Hochschule for Politik, an institution founded after WWI on die model of
die London School of Economics and die Ecole Normale in Paris. Neumann
still found time to take part in Schmitt's seminar, where he gave a paper during
die winter semester 1930 on "Public and Private Law in Labor Law." Neu-
mann's participation in Schmitt's seminar afforded him die opportunity, as
Sollner has remarked, to study "die agony of die Weimer Republic at its critical
point, die conjunction of die labor movement and democracy."25
Neumann's analysis applied Schmitt's concepts to die specific problems of
labor law and, more broadly, to die political crisis of democracy in Germany.
This is particularly dear in two articles he published during 1930-31 — exacdy
during die period when he took part in Schmitt's Berlin seminar — "The Social
Significance of Basic Rights in die Weimar Constitution" and "Concerning die
Presuppositions and die Concept of Law in an Economic Constitution"26 Util-
izing Schmitt's dieory of institutions and legal dogmatics, Neumann studied
economic democracy in his analysis of the place of trade unions in die Weimar
constitutional system: Koalitionsfreiheit und Reichsverfassung: Die Stellungder Gewerk-
schaften im Verfassungssystem, (1932). His basic question was whedier "freedom"
in die liberal-capitalist sense could be joined widi economic democracy.
Neumann held diat trade unions in late Weimar were committed to democ-
ratizing economic institutions (public and private), thus achieving a more equal
distribution of goods and social power, while preserving private property
25. Alfons Sollner, "Franz L. Neumann: Skizzen zu einer intellektuellen und
politischen Biographie," in Franz L. Neumann, Wirtschaft, Staat und Demokratie: Aufsatze
1930-1954, Alfons Sollner, ed. (Suhrkamp Verlag: Frankfurt a.M., 1978), p. 11. Informa-
tion on Neumann's participation in Schmitt's Berlin seminar is taken from an
unpublished letter from Neumann to Schmitt dated November 21,1930 (Carl Schmitt,
Nachlass, Hauptstaatsarchiv, Diisseldorf, RW265-339).
26. Both articles originally appeared in Die Arbeit and are reprinted in Neumann,
Wirtschaft, Staat und Demokratie, op. cit., pp. 57-75 and 76-102.
SCHMITTAND THE FRANKFURT SCHOOL 47
27. Letter from Neumann to Schmitt (2 September 1932), published in Rainer Erd,
ed.. Reform und Resignation: Gesprache iiber Franz L Neumann (Suhrkamp Verlag: Frankfurt
a.M., 1985), p. 79.
28. Sollner, "Left Students of the Conservative Revolution," op. cit.
29. John Herz and Erich Hula, "Otto Kirchheimer: An Introduction to his Life and
48 ELLEN KENNEDY
bound expropriation to the common good in its second; and declared property
a "duty" in its third section.) For both, Weimar pluralism was a concrete exam-
ple of the Constitution's "indecision," the result of an historical compromise at
the Weimar National Assembly. Although they agreed that property rights
were a crucial constitutional-political problem for the Republic, they differed
on how to interpret the Constitution's intention.34 For Kirchheimer, the legal
institution of private property contradicted the notion of "social constraint";
for Schmitt, Art. 153 left this question open. Neumann tried to reconcile both
claims in his concept of economic democracy. However, all agreed that the
contemporary controversy was over the limits of state intervention. For Schmitt
the definition of property rights "has the practical purpose of determining a
measure of protection against the legislator."35 For Kirchheimer, it was a dis-
pute about the limits of appropriation and the indecision of the Weimar Con-
stitution concerning how far the state would go in creating socialist equality.
Schmitt and Kirchheimer drew similar conclusions regarding the legitimacy
of the core institutions of liberal government. Without a substantial equality of
its citizens, which would in turn make shared values possible, democratic deci-
sions lose their legitimacy. In his dissertation, Kirchheimer asked: "How is gov-
ernment possible at all under such conditions?"; "who decides on the wielders
of power?" The liberal answer — majority rule — failed because majority rule
also requires justification in the absence of commonly shared values.36 In a sys-
tem of liberal pluralism, majority rule means the suppression of socially and po-
litically weaker members of the economy. Commenting on Kirchheimer's
"Weimar — and What Then?," Schmitt argued that the rights and duties
specified in the constitution's second half were the product of a "shallow formal
compromise," of "the constitution's agnosticism." For Kirchheimer, it was "a
constitution without a decision." It did not resolve but postponed the basic
conflict between "Western capitalism and Eastern Communism. The indeci-
sive status quo of the second part of the constitution was preserved by the insti-
tutional structure of the first part."
Schmitt, Neumann and Kirchheimer agreed on the fundamental "indeci-
sion" of the Weimar Constitution with respect to the conflict of capital and la-
bor. Each developed, however, distinctive interpretations of that conflict. While
Schmitt saw its resolution as a precondition for the survival of the Republic,
unlike Neumann and Kirchheimer, he rejected socialist and communist solu-
tions. Schmitt focused on the specifically political and constitutional dimensions
34. Cf. Schmitt, "Freiheitsrechte und institutionelle Garantien" (1931), in Ver-
fassungsrechtliche Aufsdtze, op. tit., pp. 140-173; and Kirchheimer, "Reichsgericht und
Enteignung: Reichsverfassungswidrigkeitdes preusischen Fluchdiniengesetzes" (1930),
in Von der Weimarer Republik, op. tit., pp. 77-90.
35. Schmitt, Ibid, p. 161.
36. Kirchheimer, "Zur Staatslehre des Sozialismus und Bolschewismus," Von der
Weimarer Republik, op. cit., p p . 34-35. Cf. Schmitt, Parliamentary Democracy, op. tit., p p . 13-
14. See also Schmitt's reply to Richard Thoma (in the Foreword to Parliamentary Democra-
cy) in which formal democracy is contrasted with a substantial democratic order.
50 ELLENKENNEDY
of the crisis and developed the legal theory Kirchheimer found so useful.
Kirchheimer's polemical position celebrated the constitution's apparent fail-
ure. As a good Marxist, he saw the crisis of capitalism in terms of a developing rev-
olutionary situation: the collapse of liberal democracy would serve, at the very
least, the interests of the working class. The elimination of liberal institutions
was a precondition for true democracy. Neumann was more skeptical of such
ideologies. As he saw it, the "central task of a socialist state theory [was] to devel-
op the positive social content of the second part of the Weimar Constitution."
Thus Neumann writes "When Kirchheimer's tide asks 'Weimar — And What
Then?,' the answer can only be: First of all Weimar."37
Kirchheimer agreed with Schmitt that liberal democracy and the bourgeois
constitutional state were essentially neutral and pluralist. The dilemma of the
constitutional state resulted from liberalism's inadequate concept of the politi-
cal. Once die bourgeoisie won their rights from the crown and the aristocracy,
die idea of the rule of law had been neutralized. Also implied in this transfor-
mation was a neutralization of die political through law and the "legalization" of
social relations.38 Both Schmitt and Kirchheimer rejected the liberal identification
of legitimacy widi legality. For Kirchheimer, the legality of the constitutional state
did not provide it with a legitimate claim to audiority, because it was still an instru-
ment of class interest. For Schmitt, the liberal state was direatened by its own
pluralism: it could not distinguish between political competitors by its own cri-
terion of legitimacy; dius, it accepted all of them according to the legal "rules of
die game" and was left undefended by its own neutrality. The legitimacy of die
constitution eroded from within, because its decisions were formal.39
Kirchheimer saw two alternatives to Weimar's "legal machinery." The first
was die Social Democrat's course of political reform. Schmitt had argued that
parliamentarism was a system of rational balance which rejected force as "die
37. Neumann, "Die soziale Bedeutung der Grundrechte in der Weimarer Ver-
fassung," in Wirtschaft, Staat und Demokratie, op. tit., p. 75.
38. Kirchheimer writes: "In all fields of endeavor things are turned into law; all factual
decisions involving actual power relations are avoided, whatever the issue: the dictatorial
powers of the Reich President, the settlement of labor disputes, or anything else. Every-
thing is juridically formalized and thereby neutralized. And now begins the epoch of the
bourgeois constitutional state — a state which consists exclusively in its laws" ("Zur
Staatslehre der Sozialismus und Bolschewismus," Von der Weimarer RepubUk, op. cit., p. 36).
Schmitt writes: "The bourgeois constitutional state is in general characterized by its basis in
the rights of the individual and the principle of the division of powers. Thus the freedom of
the individual is conceived as unlimited in principle .... Controls and controlling instances
are built in everywhere and juridically secured." "Der biirgerliche Rechtsstaat," in
Abendland, 7, 1928, pp. 201-203); "A state constitutes a constitutional state only if all its
activities without exception are considered as the sum of precisely-defined competencies"
(ibid. p. 131); "The completed ideal of the bourgeois constitutional state culminates in the
general legalization of the whole life of the state" (ibid. p. 133).
39. In addition to works already cited, see Kirchheimer, "Verfassungswirklichkeit
und politische Zukunftder Arbeiterklasse," in Der Klassenkampf, n. 3 (1929), pp. 455-459,
reprinted in Von der Weimarer Republik, op. tit., p. 69-76; see also Schmitt, "Die konkrete
Verfassungslage der Gegenwart" in Der Hitter der Verfassung, op. tit., pp. 71-131.
SCHMITTAND THE FRANKFURT SCHOOL 5/
way of beasts" (Locke) and affirmed the rule of law. The intellectual foundation
of the bourgeois constitutional state's neutrality was opposed, Schmitt argued,
by the irrational myths of the new anti-liberal movements: Fascism and Bolshe-
vism. Kirchheimer accepted Schmitt's analysis and, like his teacher, believed
that contemporary European politics proved how vulnerable liberalism was
because of its neutrality and indecision. "The political myth has the capacity to
bring about an extremely decisive grouping according to political values."40
Compared to political activism of this sort, Social-Democratic reformism could
only be a reflection of liberal neutrality. For the Social Democrats the Weimar
Constitution remained a book of possibilities among which they were unable to
decide, precisely because awareness of the alternatives made them incapable of
deciding for one of them, namely socialism.41
The second alternative was Bolshevism. Lenin ended "the view of the judici-
ary as an independent third force, as an arbiter above contending parties... In-
stead, Lenin's point of view restores the image of the substantive character of
law which in Europe, since the age of liberalism, has tended to disappear and
become totally dissolved into the legal mechanism of formal democracy. Wher-
ever a state exists, be its form intrinsically democratic or dictatorial, legal judge-
ments are rendered in the name of definite value concepts."42
The Soviet Union emerges in Kirchheimer's study as a state in Schmitt's
terms; his examination of Soviet foreign policy uses Schmitt's analysis of the lib-
eral character of the League of Nations. The appearance of the USSR on the in-
ternational scene is that of a lion among sheep. It acts politically by not recog-
nizing liberal neutrality; it understands the structure of peace after 1918 as a
truce between international material interests. Because the League mirrors lib-
eral neutrality, its dilemmas are the same as those of the liberal state. In the ab-
sence of the homogeneity of interests required for a decision, the USSR was
forced to reject both the majority principle in international practice and any
internationally-recognized court which would claim to render binding deci-
sions.43
Luthardt's observation that Kirchheimer developed Marx's Bonapartism
thesis to explain the Briining government is only partly correct.44 Schmitt had
40. Kirchheimer, "Zur Staatslehre des Sozialismus und Bolschewismus," in Von der
WeimarerRepublik, op.tit.,p. 43; Politics. Law and Social Change, op.tit.,p. 5. Cf. Schmitt, Par-
liamentary Democracy, op. tit., pp. 65 ff.
41. Kirchheimer, "Verfassungswirklichkeit und politische Zukunft der Arbeiter-
klasse," in Von der Weimarer Republik, op. tit., see especially the critique of the SPD in the
"Grosse Koalition" as evidence of the absence of "the will to reality" (p. 76).
42. Kirchheimer, "Zur Staatslehre des Sozialismus und Bolschewismus" in Von der
Weimarer Republik, op. tit., p. 47: Politics, Law and Social Change, op. tit., p. 13.
43. Ibid, Kirchheimer refers directly to Schmitt's Der Kemjrage des Volkerbundes,
(Dummler Verlag: Berlin, 1926) and notes that the clausida rebus sic stantibus "completely
dominates Soviet thinking on international law" (ibid. pp. 18 and 48 respectively).
44. Wolfgang Ludiardt, "Bemerkungen zu Otto Kirchheimers Arbeiten bis 1933,"
in Von der Weimarer Republik, op. at., pp. 7-31; see p. 24.
52 ELLENKENNEDY
built Marx's thesis into his own interpretation of liberalism. Kirchheimer fil-
tered Marx's thesis dirough Schmitt's theory of me state; his analysis of political
events in Germany shared Schmitt's scepticism about the bourgeois constitu-
tional state. Majority rule is "bourgeois dictatorship"; the search for a majority,
merely a crass game played out for 5196 of the votes in an election. Equality
before the law, thefirstprinciple of the constitutional state, is afictionand the
instrument of reaction. With only formal democracy the crisis during
Briining's administration could only deepen. The way out, Kirchheimer argued,
lay in a decision for socialist politics. That decision could not be taken by a neu-
tral third party, but would only result from the political in Schmitt's sense of the
concept. Only after Schmitt defended Papen's seizure of the Prussian govern-
ment on July 20, 1932, which replaced the Social Democratic (SPD) cabinet
with a commissarial executive acting in the name of the Reich, did Kirchheimer
criticize his teacher.45 As late as July 1932, both he and Schmitt were interpreting
Germany's growing crisis as legality vs. legitimacy in the state.46 Each offered,
however, a different political interpretation of the so-called "Preussenschlag."
For Kirchheimer, Papen's government and the months of emergency rule de-
stroyed the constitution's legitimacy by its destruction of governmental legality;
die appeal to presidential authority was invalid. Schmitt saw the persistence of
(defunct) parliamentary mediods, including majority rule and the "equal
chance" for all political competitors, as the main threat to Weimar's legitimate
constitutional order.
Sollner's analysis of Kirchheimer tries to show that a supposed contradiction
between democracy and die constitutional state reveals a fundamental differ-
ence between Schmitt and Kirchheimer. While Schmitt saw the presidential
dictatorship of 1932 as confirming his own "fundamental political assump-
tion," Kirchheimer looked for social and political relations which permitted
such a transformation. Their differences were "the different conceptions of
democracy which inform their respective analyses of the constitution." But
emphasis on Schmitt's and Kirchheimer's substantially different political
preferences confuse Sollner's argument and lead him to underestimate die
45. Kirchheimer, "Bermerkungen zu Carl Schmitts 'Legalita't und Legitimist"' in
Archivfiir Sozialwissenschaft und Sozialpolitik, n.68 (1932-33), pp. 457-487; reprinted in Von
der Weimarer Republik, op. cit., pp. 113-150. Kirchheimer accuses Schmitt of fostering con-
stitutional reaction. But the discussion is an odd mixture. He reads Schmitt as placing
too much emphasis on equality and freedom, and too much weight on the liberal no-
tion of freedom as freedom from the state, which presumably led Schmitt to underesti-
mate the social reality of individual freedom and its role in creating the popular will (p.
116). Kirchheimer also asserts that Schmitt's critique of formal democracy is a rejection
of democracy per se (p. 118). It is a curious turnabout, given Kirchheimer's own views
on democracy and particularly in light of his stress on the direct democratic and
plebiscitary elements in Schmitt's work (cf. Verfassungsreaktion, 1932 in Die Gesellschaft,
n. 9, 1932, pp. 415-427; translated into English as "Constitutional Reaction, 1932," in
Politics, Law and Social Change, op. cit., pp. 75-87.
46. Kirchheimer, "Legalitatund Legitimist," inDie Gesellschaft, n.9 (1932), pp. 8-26;
Schmitt, Legalitat und Legimitdt, op. cit.
SCHMITT ANDTHE FRANKFURTSCHOOL 5J
49. Karl Korsch, "Carl Schmitt, Der Hiiter der Verfassung," in Zeitschrift fiir
Sonalforschung, Vol. 1 (1932), pp. 204-205.
50. Hans Speier, "Carl Schmitt, Der Begriff des Politischen," Zeitschrift fur Sozial-
forschung, vol. 1 (1932), pp. 203-204. Both Speier's and Korsch's reviews appear under
the heading "Special Sociology," emphasizing the contemporary reading of Schmitt's
works as fundamental to the foundation of social research and a critical theory of state
and society.
51. Herbert Marcuse, "The Struggle Against Liberalism in the Totalitarian View of
the State," in Negations: Essays in Critical Theory, (Beacon Press: Boston, 1968). see also
Jtirgen Habermas. "Die Frankfurter Schule in New York," in Philosophisch-politische Profile,
(Suhrkamp Verlag, Frankfurt a.M., 1984).
52. Jay, The Dialectical Imagination, op. tit., pp. 121-122.
SCHMITTAND THE FRANKFURT SCHOOL 55
his assertion in The Concept of the Political that war is the ultimate political situa-
tion. As Marcuse read Schmitt: "Predominantly political conditions and rela-
tions are sanctioned here as existential, and within die political dimension it is
die relation to die enemy, or war, diat counts as die simply and absolutely exis-
tential relationship ('die folk and folk membership' have been added as a sec-
ond, equally existential relationship)." Totalitarian regimes put Schmitt's ideas
into practice.
In light of Schmitt's influence on Kirchheimer (and on Benjamin), Marcuse's
analysis was paradoxical. Precisely those aspects of Schmitt's work diat had
already entered into die Frankfurt School — die political analysis of law and die
bourgeois constitutional state, criticism of die 'positivistic' elements of liberal
democracy, the connection between direct democracy and social homogeneity,
and, above all, die criticism of parliamentarism — were now characterized as
"die best description of liberalism from die standpoint of totalitarian state dieo-
ry." In effect, Marcuse's article removed Schmitt as a positive source in die Frank-
furt School during die 1930s and 1940s. Schmitt's collaboration widi die Nazis
consolidated die effect of Marcuse's argument. From 1933 onward, Schmitt's
work stood under a virtual ban for German intellectuals on the left. But the
original paradox remained and is underscored by the Frankfurt School's devel-
opment of a critique of liberalism in diis period. In 1934 Marcuse had asserted
"die inner relationship between liberalist social dieory and die (apparendy so
antiliberal) totalitarian dieory of the state" is revealed in a "liberalist rationalism
mat ends in irrationalism."53 Horkheimer took up diemes from die critique of
liberalism in Weimar and expanded diem into a new perspective on rationalism
and irrationalism in bourgeois society; in so doing he discovered die common
origins of liberalism and totalitarianism.
Schmitt and Kirchheimer argued diat liberal neutralization and formal de-
mocracy did not eliminate political conflict but ultimately intensified it.
Horkheimer extended diis critique of liberalism in a collection of aphorisms he
wrote during die Weimar Republic and published pseudonymously during die
Third Reich: "The true bourgeois has die capacity to look at all diings objectively,
and in postwar Germany mat even extends to revolution. Once he begins to re-
flect objectively about it or, radier, its political preparation, it seems like any
other activity widiin die context of social reality and is judged accordingly."54
Horkheimer extended his critique of liberalism into a critique of its linguistic
foundations in a meditation on reason and self-preservation published private-
ly in 1942 in a book dedicated to die memory of Benjamin. Not only did he re-
ject die pluralism of liberal democracies as ideological, he began to set out die
critique of rationalism in technological society diat became one of die most im-
portant elements in radical diought in die late 1960s. Moreover, he finally ex-
53. Marcuse, "The Struggle Against Liberalism," op. at.
54. Max Horkheimer, Ddmmerung, originally published in 1934 under the pseudo-
nym Heinrich Regius. The edition used here is a photomechanical reproduction pub-
lished in 1968. Cf. the section tided "Nachdenken iiber die Revolution." p. 71.
56 ELLENKENNEDY
plained the Frankfurt School's preoccupation after 1933 with the connection
between liberalism and totalitarianism. The transformation of bourgeois socie-
ty into open dictatorship took place through "technological reason" — "in the
transformation of bourgeois rule the bourgeois continues, despite the fact that
the new order represents a leap into direct domination." 55
the substantialist sense. Schmitt pointed out the weaknesses of Thoma's theory
— it could neither expound the structure of democracy as an idea, nor explain
the sociological consequences of modern democratic systems.59 Such was pos-
sible, Schmitt argued, only if Rousseau's assertion that democracy is the identity
of the rulers and the ruled was used as an analytical and normative principle.
Habermas shares this objection to modern definitions of democracy. In
terms of die Weimar debate between substantialists and positivists, he opts for die
former. Against Thoma's interpretation, he argues widi Schmitt diat democracy
demands an identity of die rulers and die ruled.60 This conception of democracy
is not, of course, peculiar to Schmitt; but he did develop its mediodological
importance. Whereas "classical" liberalism enjoyed a genuinely democratic
element, as a constitutional form it was sociologically limited to a period of
bourgeois dominance. In die age of universal suffrage, institutions based on a
specific historical homogeneity of interests must slide into a series of increasingly
intense contradictions, die most important being diat between democratic le-
gitimacy and representative institutions in die liberal constitution. Habermas'
early work used diis insight to criticize "formal" democracy.
In Student und Politik Habermas draws on Ernst Forsdioff s analysis of die de-
velopment of die liberal state into an agent of collective welfare (the satisfaction
of immediate needs); he incorporates Schmitt's argument diat die attendant
structural changes imply a decay of die principles of political organization
which Montesquieu identified as essential features of die constitutional state: 1)
die generality of norms; 2) individual rights; 3) die division of powers to protect
bodi. Forsdioff argued that die welfare state's social and economic functions in-
trude on Montesquieu's (and liberalism's) fundamental assumption diat state
and society are independent spheres. In a direct comment on Forsdioffs argu-
ment, which accepts its definition of liberalism's contemporary dilemma,
Habermas agrees diat, to die extent die state intervenes in society "caring, ad-
ministering, distributing" die first principle of die constitutional state cannot
be maintained.61 Laws aimed at concrete social groups (typical of social welfare
legislation) cannot be general; and even when diese are explicidy conceived as
59. Carl Schmitt, "Der Begriffder modernen Demokratie in seinem Verhaltnis zum
Staatsbegriff," in Archivfiir Sozialwissenschaft und Sozialpolitik (1924), no. 51, pp. 817-823.
60. Habermas, Student und Politik, op. tit., p. 31. Habermas refers here to the "ficti-
tious identification" of a current parliamentary majority with the popular will. His argu-
ment questions the legitimacy of parliamentary representation of the people's will and,
although negatively expressed, his view must logically assume a democratic identity that
is not 'fictitious' but 'true.' "The plebiscitary-democratic identity of a given parliamenta-
ry majority in government and in parliament is in truth a fictitious identification with the
popular will; it is essentially dependent on who controls the force and educational
means to create the popular will by manipulation or demonstration. The parties are the
instruments of will-formation, which is not in the hands of the people but in those who
control the party apparatus."
61. Habermas, Student und Politik, op,tit.,p. 35. Habermas' discussion ("Zur Alterna-
tive der autoritaren oder sozialen Demokratie") is based on Forsthoffs analysis in
Lehrbuchdes Venualtungsrechts (C.H. BeckVerlag: (Munich, 1955).
SCHMITT AND THE FRANKFURT SCHOOL 59
"orders," such interventions cause the boundaries between "laws" and "or-
ders" established in the dieory of the constitutional state to disappear. As state
and society become intertwined in this way, obligation to the rule of law is
weakened. Individual rights, negatively conceived in liberal theory as limita-
tions on political authority, are transformed into positive claims on the state.
The development erodes the guarantees for individual rights within the con-
stitutional state that Montesquieu assumed would follow from the division of
executive, legislative and judicial powers.
Habermas maintains that this change reveals the contradiction that has always
existed between democracy and the liberal state.62 While the bourgeois constitu-
tional state proclaims the idea of democracy and even institutionalizes it to
some extent, liberal democracy is in reality "a minority democracy on the ba-
sis of a social hierarchy."63 Only when it works as the self-determination of hu-
manity is democracy true democracy; as the product or technical means of a
governmental system, participation is not genuinely democratic. If democracy
and democratic government are taken seriously, the empirical-pragmatic con-
ception reveals itself empty. To understand democracy as the politics of rules
and institutions, rather than as a substantial value, merely repeats the unique
defect of liberalism's historical consciousness.
Habermas' "Schmittianism" here is transparent. As more social initiative
and responsibility accrues to the state, parliament ceases to be the representative
organ conceived in liberal theory and becomes instead an instrument in the new
constitutional system. The people and parliament have lost their purpose.64 The
agents of the new constitutional reality are political parties and organized interest
groups. These act via a new manipulative organization of public opinion to fur-
ther private goals at the cost of, or even by means of publicly declared goals.
Despite die constitutional principle of dieir division, die parties achieve a "real
unification of powers" and diis concert of powerful interests is concealed from
die forum of public discussion in parliament.65 Habermas implies diat such
combinations, even if legal, pose such a powerful contradiction to liberal princi-
ples and democratic substance that diey are illegitimate. Parliamentary politics
62. Habermas writes: "The bourgeois constitutional state assumes the identity of
bourgeois existence and the people. The contradiction: to proclaim the idea of democ-
racy, in a sense to institutionalize it, but in reality to operate a minority democracy on
the basis of a social hierarchy. This is unique to the bourgeois constitutional state (Stu-
dent und Politik, op.tit.,p. 18). This contradiction presumably characterizes participation
in such systems and is typical in parliamentary governments. Habermas takes his histor-
ical description of parliamentary representation and its political meaning from
Schmitt's Verfassungslehre [Student und Politik, op. tit., p. 16, n. 13).
63. Habermas, Student und Politik, op. tit., p. 18.
64. Ibid., p. 51. This assertion comes at the end of Habermas' discussion of the
changed reality of parliamentary democracy; the principles of the bourgeois constitu-
tional state are contradicted by their reality.
65. Habermas, Student und Politik, op. tit., p. 39: "In the party-state, parties establish
an actual unity of powers behind closed doors — a unity which is problematic in relation
to the constitutional principle."
60 ELLENKENNEDY
66. Habermas, Student und Politik, op. cit., pp. 26 ff. Commenting on Gerhard
Leibholz's theory of modern democracy, Habermas concludes: "In this way parliament
becomes a place where previously instructed party delegates meet in order to register
decisions already taken. Carl Schmitt had already noticed something of this sort in the
Weimar Republic." (in Parliamentary Democracy, op. cit.).
67. Habermas, Student und Politik, op. cit., p. S3.
68. Ibid., pp. 28 and 51.
69. Ibid., p. 31.
70. Jurgen Habermas, Struhturwandel der Offentlichkeit: Untersuchung zu einer Kategorie
der burgerlichen Gesellschaft, (Luchterhand Verlag: Darmstadt and Neuwied, 1962), p. 8.
SCHMITTAND THE FRANKFURT SCHOOL 61
does nothing of the sort today."71 For both Schmitt and Habermas, the classical
model of publicity originated in the eighteenth-century notion of an "enlight-
ened" public; its mature formulation can be found in Guizot's Historie des
origines du gouvemement representatif en France (1851). "Rule of public opinion"
(Habermas) or "principles of parliamentarism" (Schmitt) were, according to
Guizot, public discussion, publicity, and a free press. These assured that laws
passed were in accord with truth and the general good; they alone legitimated
die power of parliament.
According to Habermas, these actually worked until a certain point in the
nineteendi century. But with the emergence of "liberalism," bourgeois publicity
as trudi-producing gave way to "common-sense meliorism."72 This decline
was accompanied by economic changes which die constitutional state permitted
and stabilized. Student und Politik treats parliament as one of die contradictions of
die liberal state; Strukturwandel der Offentlichkeit describes how socio-economic
changes worked against die old publicity: culture and discussion were commer-
cialized and die free press became a capital investment. Widi universal suffrage,
diese changes produced a mass public of "cultural consumers" diat displaced
die cultural reason of a reading public. Ultimately, the principles of representative
government were hollowed out: publicity became public managment; die press,
part of a single manipulative system; die public itself, "passive customers."73
If Habermas' debt to Schmitt and his students is explicit in such early works
as Student und Politik and Strukturwandel der Offentlichkeit, it remains implicit in
Legitimation Crisis (1973) and his recent essays on politics in West Germany.
Schmitt's arguments supply die dieoretical elements of Habermas' analysis of
die state in late capitalism. Legitimation problems result from die dilemma of
mass democracy presented in die earlier works: a structural change in publicity,
die key to democratic dieory in Habermas' system, now prevents public partici-
pation in die political system; it has transformed die citizen from die subject
71. Ibid., pp. 244-245. Habermas' description of parliament on these pages draws
on Schmitt's Parliamentary Democracy (cf. Habermas, Strukturwandel der Offentlichkeit, op. tit.,
p. 351, note 69). He repeats the comment (from Student und Politik, op. at., p. 14) that par-
liament has become a place where decisions already taken are merely registered. It is
clear here that Habermas' objection to this change in the function of parliamentary rep-
resentation is connected to his critique of the change in the public sphere as a whole:
"The new status of the representative is no longer characterized by general participation
in a reasoning public" (p. 242). The opposition between an earlier classic period (in
which the representative did play such a role) and present political reality is the crucial
aspect of Habermas' reception ofSchmitt (Strukturwandel der Offentlichkeit, op.tit.,pp. 113
ff., p. 322, n. 43, and p. 125. He quotes the same passage from Guizot that Schmitt uses
to define the function of publicity in parliamentarism, and the note on p. 322 indicates
that Habermas took this aspect of his argument from Schmitt (see Parliamentary Democra-
cy, note 5 on pp. 97 f.). Habermas' description of parliamentary reality (as opposed to its
principles) on p. 244 paraphrases Schmitt (cf. Parliamentary Democracy, op. tit., pp. 51 f.)
and refers to Ernst Friesenhahn, "Parlament und Regierung im modernen Staat,"
Veroffentlichungen der Vereinigung der Deutschen Staatsrechtslehrer (1958), no. 16.
72. Habermas, Strukturwandel der Offentlichkeit, op. tit., p. 160.
73. Ibid., pp. 202, 220 ff. and 233.
62 ELLEN KENNEDY
into an object of public opinion; the purported sovereign, the people, is actual-
ly powerless.74 The legitimation crisis arises from a contradiction between con-
stitutional principles and political reality, from the disintegration of traditional
bases of legitimacy at the moment when new legitimation demands arise. In the
liberal state, the fundamental cause of die legitimation crisis is metapolitical.
Habermas begins and ends his book on legitimation problems of late capi-
talism widi a question about "world-sustaining interpretative systems" based
on dieJudeo-Christian God. If diese now belong "irretrievably to die past," he
asks, "what fulfills the moral-practical task of constituting ego and group-iden-
tity?"75 As it was for Schmitt, diis question concerns the fundamental philo-
sophical problem of the post-Enlightenment and die ultimate intellectual basis
of die system of political audiority in die state and law. If die state and public
power cease to be understood as part of a meaningful order, as diey apparendy
have in die modem period, dien the demands and commands of die state must
appeal to an increasingly fragile basis of respect and consent. Habermas argues
that die modern legitimation crisis is a "motivation-deficit" or a gap between
what die state (and the economic and education systems) requires and what die
sociocultural system can provide.76 like Schmitt, he is doubtful whedier die in-
tellectual foundations of diis system are still credible sources of motivation.
There is nodiing exceptional in die notion diat democratic states require credi-
bility in die eyes of dieir citizens to maintain dieir claim to legitimacy. There is
nodiing new in die perception diat die decline of religious and metaphysical
justifications for die state's audiority poses a political problem. But Habermas,
like Schmitt, projects die criterion of legitimacy from a "classical" model into
contemporary political practice. The intellectual-historical foundations of legit-
imacy in die past have disappeared as real factors in pluralist society; die bour-
geois ideology of legitimacy through the citizen's obligation has become a mere
facade.77
At die beginning of die Weimar Republic, Schmitt's critique of parlia-
mentarism divided institutions and procedures from substance, while his ana-
lysis of die Weimar constitution similarly divided its formal from its substantial
aspects — legality and legitimacy were not identical but separate and even con-
tradictory principles. In the context of parliamentary paralysis after September
1930, he developed a dieory of sovereignty detached from die liberal ideology
of parliamentarism and located Weimar's "democratic sovereignty" in die of-
74. Ibid., pp. 276 and 358, n. 129. While the text relies implicitly on Schmitt's defini-
tion of classical parliamentarism, the note rejects Schmitt's "model of an administrative
state, whose technical conditions of functioning contradict the possibility of democrati-
zation" and criticizes Helmut Schelsky's development of this model in post-war Ger-
man sociology.
75. Habermas, Legitimation Crisis, translated by Thomas McCarthy, (Heinemann,
London: 1976), p. 120.
76. Ibid. Cf. Schmitt, Political Theology and "Das Zeitalter der Neutralisierungen und
Entpolitisierungen" in Der Begriffdes Politischen (1963), op. at., pp. 79-95.
77. Habermas, Legitimation Crisis, op. tit., pp. 79 and 89 ff.
SCHMITTANDTHE FRANKFURTSCHOOL 63
Conclusion
In every reception of Schmitt's ideas discussed here, there is a gap between
the political values and goals espoused and the formal argument advanced on
their behalf. In none, however, is the gap so wide as in Habermas' work. None
of the others can be considered so "liberal," nor did they devote so much intel-
lectual effort to the construction of a system of rational and discursive social re-
lations. Thus, the parallels between Habermas' argument and Schmitt's own
are all the more paradoxical. Given Habermas' structural and textual reliance
on Schmitt, and the serious differences between them on political values, does
the use of Schmitt's formal argument against liberalism affect the normative
choices available in Habermas' system of thought?
If we take only two precursors to Habermas in the tradition of Critical Theo-
ry discussed here — Benjamin and Kirchheimer — it is relatively easy to show
that the formal elements of anti-liberalism and, in Kirchheimer's case, a sophis-
ticated political and legal theory, steered them away from liberal democracy
and tended to blind both to the Weimar Republic's developmental possibilities
in the direction of a more socially just society. By identifying the core institu-
tions of liberal government in Germany with a closed system of bourgeois in-
terests and dius as contradictions of democracy, Kirchheimer underestimated
their potential. The concepts he adopted from Schmitt strengthened his case
against the Republic. But his classical Marxist perspectives led him to reject the
Republic's imperfect democracy in favor of an ideally homogeneous society
and direct democracy.
Eschewing Kirchheimer's emphasis on the material identity of class, Haber-
mas proposes something quite different — agreement on principles of ethical
conduct arrived at through rational and peaceful discussion. He also intends a
different political outcome than Schmitt: the realization of democracy as an
educative process in which citizens participate as free, equal, self-determining
and sovereign entities; a democratic discourse that "recovers" those rational
80. Ibid., p. 90.
SCHMITTAND THE FRANKFURT SCHOOL 65
83. Lukes, "Of Gods and Demons," in Habermas: Critical Debates, op. cit. This point is
also made by Agnes Heller from a different perspective ("Habermas and Marxism," in
Habermas: Critical Debates, op. cit., p p . 21-41).
84. Jiirgen Fijalkowski, Die Wendung zum Filhrerstaat: Ideologische Komponenten in der
politischen Philosophie Carl Schmitts, (Westdeutscher Verlag: Cologne, 1958), p. 4.
85. Ibid. Also in "Ziviler U n g e h o r s a m " in Die Neue Uniibersichtlichkeit, op. cit., where
reference is made to the appeal by "the lawyers of authoritarian legalism" to Schmitt's
theory.
86. See Claus Offe and Bernd Guggenberger, eds., An den Grenzen der Mehr-
heitsdemokratie: Politik und Soziologie der Mehrheitsregel (Westdeutscher Verlag: Opladen,
1984).