HLI102 Crop-3
HLI102 Crop-3
HLI102 Crop-3
Brenda Dvoskin*
In a world of fundamental disagreements about how social media companies should govern speech, it is
striking that nearly everyone agrees that online speech governance should be based on human rights. The
human rights project for content moderation proposes that social media platforms align their own internal
speech policies with international human rights law. It seeks, I argue, a system of expert governance: one in
which a corporate technocracy applies a set of exogenous principles imagined as objective and global.
Ultimately, this governance model shifts power to experts under the illusion of empowering the people.
To support these claims, this Article unveils the intellectual work that scholars, U.N. bodies, and the
Facebook Oversight Board are doing to portray international human rights law as an objective synthesis of
the global public interest. The Article analyzes how they have recreated several dimensions of international
law. A salient example is their new reading of the U.N. Guiding Principles on Business and Human
Rights. According to a recent interpretation, companies are expected to align their content policies with
international law. But this interpretation widely diverges from the text and the original meaning of the
instrument. The Article also examines other tools the project uses such as creating boundaries between local
facts and normative work and framing normative questions as technical challenges. Overall, the Article
provides a deep dive into the toolkit that scholars, advocates, and the Facebook Oversight Board have
developed to date to pursue a system of expert governance of online speech.
Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 86 R
I. The International Human Rights Law Project for
Online Speech Governance. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 91 R
II. Justifying the IHRL Project . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 97 R
A. The Rationales . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 98 R
1. A New Interpretation of the U.N.
Guiding Principles . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 98 R
2. Because social media companies are like states, but they
are not like states. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 105 R
3. Because IHRL is consented to by all states, but state
consent does not matter. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 108 R
4. Because IHRL constrains corporate power, but its
indeterminacy is a feature . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 109 R
* Postdoctoral fellow, Georgetown University Law Center; Doctoral candidate, Harvard Law School;
Affiliate, Berkman Klein Center for Internet & Society. I am deeply thankful for insightful comments
from Dunstan Allison-Hope, Chinamyi Arun, Nicole Bassoff, Yochai Benkler, Elettra Bietti, Alejandro
Chehtman, Evelyn Douek, Noah Feldman, Sheila Jasanoff, Gerald Neuman, Peter Stern, Thomas Streinz,
Gali Racabi, Malcolm Rogge, and Yiran Zhang. I am also grateful to the participants at the Critical
Exploration of Human Rights Conference at the University College Dublin Center for Human Rights,
the Ideas Lunch at the Information Society Project at Yale Law School, the 2022 Global Meeting on Law
and Society, and the Science, Technology and Society Circle at the Harvard Kennedy School. Thank you
to Gabriella Papper, Deniz Aktaş, Sophia Poole, and Sara Raza for their work editing this piece. The
Article reflects developments and decisions through August 2022.
\\jciprod01\productn\H\HLI\64-1\HLI102.txt unknown Seq: 2 16-FEB-23 15:34
Introduction
ments. One strand of the reasoning noted that international law protects
deeply offensive speech, suggesting that depictions of Zwarte Piet might be
protected. However, the Board determined that the international human
rights question turned on whether featuring blackface caused “objective
harm” or “subjective offense.” The Board enumerated the many experts who
had verified that content featuring blackface is discriminatory, reinforces
harmful stereotypes, can impact individuals’ self-esteem, and can contribute
to an environment of intimidation.5 Experts’ reports were considered evi-
dence of “objective harm.”6
This Article aims to explain why the Board as well as many scholars and
advocates find that IHRL is a promising framework to make decisions re-
garding the governance of online speech. It dissects the argumentative
mazes they must navigate to justify both that nonstate actors should imple-
ment international law and that the rules they propose to moderate online
content are objective applications of that framework.
Over the last decade, scholars have often compared social media compa-
nies to states due to the control they exercise over the public sphere.7 It is
therefore unsurprising that many proposals to deal with corporate power
take inspiration from state institutions.8 In that vein, what I call the IHRL
project for content moderation proposes that social media platforms align
their own internal rules to govern speech with IHRL. In other words, the
IHRL project posits that companies should adopt the international legal
framework to protect individuals’ rights to freedom of expression from state
interference in order to protect individuals from corporate power.9
Intuitively, IHRL is an attractive framework for corporate actors to gov-
ern speech on social media. It is global like social media platforms and it
offers well-respected standards to guide content moderation in these quasi-
public spaces.10 The IHRL project proposes to address the democratic defi-
cits of corporate online speech governance not by suggesting a more par-
ticipatory institutional structure, but by offering a set of global substantive
rules that purport to reflect the public interest, the common good, or glob-
ally shared values.11 Indeed, blurring the lines between states and corpora-
tions could lead to seeing users as political subjects with an interest in
participating in the making of policy. Instead, the IHRL project proposes
that experts implement IHRL as an already available formulation of social
interests.
The project has gained more attention and traction since David Kaye pro-
posed it in 2018 during his tenure as U.N. Special Rapporteur.12 He recom-
mended that large social media platforms adopt IHRL as their own default
rules to moderate content.13 Also in 2018, Mark Zuckerberg announced that
Facebook would create an overseeing body composed of independent experts
to review some of Facebook’s content decisions and to make recommenda-
tions on how the company could improve its content governance.14 From
2021 to the present, the Board has applied the IHRL framework to its deci-
sions. The Board has been the main executor of the IHRL project to date.15
IHRL does not assure a panacea, but it makes appealing promises. Its
main purpose is to put the public interest front and center of online speech
governance. Kaye asserts: “[i]t’s time to put individual and democratic
rights at the center of corporate content moderation.”16 The project chal-
lenges the idea that no global set of rules to regulate speech exists. In his
2018 report, Kaye stated, “[t]he founder of Facebook recently expressed his
hope for a process in which the company ‘could more accurately reflect the
values of the community in different places.’ That process, and the relevant
standards, can be found in human rights law.”17 Thus, the IHRL project
10. See Sejal Parmar, Facebook’s Oversight Board: A Meaningful Turn Toward International Human Rights
Standards?, Just Security (May 20, 2020), https://www.justsecurity.org/70234/facebooks-oversight-
board-a-meaningful-turn-towards-international-human-rights-standards/ [https://perma.cc/LTW4-
E6HS].
11. David Kaye, Speech Police: The Global Struggle to Govern the Internet 18 (2019).
12. SR Report 2018, supra note 9. See Rebecca MacKinnon, Consent of the Networked: The R
Worldwide Struggle for Internet Freedom (2012) (pioneering the importance of human rights in
the context of social media).
13. SR Report 2018, supra note 9. See Evelyn Douek, U.N. Special Rapporteur’s Latest Report on Online R
Content Regulation Calls for ‘Human Rights by Default’, Lawfare (June 6, 2018), https://
www.lawfareblog.com/un-special-rapporteurs-latest-report-online-content-regulation-calls-human-
rights-default [https://perma.cc/X3HT-5CDA].
14. Mark Zuckerberg, A Blueprint for Content Governance and Enforcement, Facebook (Nov. 15, 2018),
https://m.facebook.com/notes/mark-zuckerberg/a-blueprint-for-content-governance-and-enforcement/
10156443129621634/ [https://perma.cc/KD2H-7CWU].
15. Announcing the Oversight Board’s first case decisions, Oversight Bd. (Jan. 2021), https://over-
sightboard.com/news/165523235084273-announcing-the-oversight-board-s-first-case-decisions/ [https:/
/perma.cc/JRG9-BBZ7].
16. Kaye, supra note 11, at 18. R
17. SR Report 2018, supra note 9, ¶ 41 (internal footnotes omitted). R
\\jciprod01\productn\H\HLI\64-1\HLI102.txt unknown Seq: 5 16-FEB-23 15:34
claims that it can provide a basis to moderate content that already reflects
the global public interest.18
By positing that we already know what rules reflect the global public
interest, the IHRL project vests legitimacy on new “new governors”: human
rights experts.19 The Board’s members or companies’ in-house human rights
directors—those who know these universal rules—can implement these
rules on social media. The experts’ democratic credentials would proceed not
from democratic politics but from the fact that they deduce their decisions
from IHRL.
I call this project a system of expert governance. Its legitimacy comes
from assuring the public that IHRL is an objective account of the public
interest or global values, capable of producing rules and decisions that also
reflect those values. Objectivity in this context means the opposite of indi-
vidual policy preferences. It is also the opposite of politics. I do not imply
that human rights themselves are not a political commitment. The IHRL
project’s claim to objectivity stems from portraying that commitment as
universal and pre-existing to the decisionmaking moment. Thus, the system
is objective because it is supposed not to favor anyone’s specific standpoint.
As Sheila Jasanoff, a pioneer in the field of Science and Technology Stud-
ies, says, objectivity takes hard work.20 Performing as objective governors
(judges often play this role) requires construing principles as being already
available and agreed on, as well as framing decisions as reasonable deriva-
tions from them. In the case about Black Pete, the Board had to present
IHRL as the framework it was compelled to rely on and to claim that it
deduced its decision from that framework, even though the Board acknowl-
edged that the exact opposite conclusion was also possible.
The main purpose of this Article is to make that work visible. It offers an
analysis of the tools that scholars, advocates, and the Board have developed
to build that claim to objectivity. By examining how objectivity is per-
formed, this Article makes four contributions.
First, it unveils the intellectual work that has gone into presenting IHRL
as a global set of rules appropriate for governing speech online. Sometimes
the effort toward objectivity is explicit. Like in the Black Pete decision,
experts might explain the work they are doing to construe the principles
that allegedly bind them and the parameters for diverging from them. Most
often, the work is done in the dark.21 This should be unsurprising to legal
worse. In a vibrant democracy, usurpation should have to be accomplished in the dark.” (internal citations
omitted; emphasis added). I am grateful to Libby Adler for highlighting this quote.
22. See Noah Feldman, Written Statement to the Presidential Commission of the Supreme Court of the United
States Hearing on “The Contemporary Debate over Supreme Court Reform: Origins and Perspectives”, The White
House (June 30, 2021), https://www.whitehouse.gov/wp-content/uploads/2021/06/Feldman-Presiden-
tial-Commission-6-25-21.pdf [https://perma.cc/4V6A-RSXU].
23. See Evelyn Aswad, The Future of Freedom of Expression Online, 17 Duke L. & Tech. Rev. 26, 34
(2018); David Kaye (Special Rapporteur on the Promotion and Protection of the Right to Freedom of
Opinion and Expression), Mandate of the Special Rapporteur on the Promotion and Protection of the Right to
Freedom of Opinion and Expression, 1, 2 U.N. Doc. OL OTH 24/2019 (May 1, 2019); Facebook Oversight
Board: Recommendations for human rights-focused oversight, Article 19 (Mar. 27, 2019), https://
www.article19.org/resources/facebook-oversight-board-recommendations-for-human-rights-focused-over-
sight/ [https://perma.cc/399N-JUVV] (“While Facebook is not legally bound by international human
rights laws, the UN Guiding Principles on Business and Human Rights set out responsibilities that
companies like Facebook have to respect human rights. This means ensuring that their Terms of Service
and Community Standards are fully in line with human rights laws”).
24. See infra Section II.A.1.
25. See Jeremy Waldron, The Core of the Case against Judicial Review, 115 Yale L.J. 1346 (2006); Mark
Tushnet, Following the Rules Laid down: A Critique of Interpretivism and Neutral Principles, 96 Harv. L. Rev.
781 (1983).
\\jciprod01\productn\H\HLI\64-1\HLI102.txt unknown Seq: 7 16-FEB-23 15:34
26. See Brenda Dvoskin, Representation without Elections: Civil Society Participation as a Remedy for the
Democratic Deficits of Online Speech Governance, 67 Vill. L. Rev. 447 (2022) (exploring the distributional
consequences of corporate adoption of administrative law principles for public participation).
27. Protecting the Open Internet: Regulatory Principles for Policy Makers, Twitter, https://cdn.cms-twdig-
italassets.com/content/dam/about-twitter/en/our-priorities/open-internet.pdf [https://perma.cc/5QJW-
27QG].
28. Monika Bickert, Online Content Regulation: Charting a Way Forward, Facebook, https://about.fb.
com/wp-content/uploads/2020/02/Charting-A-Way-Forward_Online-Content-Regulation-White-Paper-
1.pdf [https://perma.cc/NHB7-9GJL].
29. See, e.g., Defending and Respecting the Rights of People Using Our Service, Twitter, https://
help.twitter.com/en/rules-and-policies/defending-and-respecting-our-users-voice [https://perma.cc/
2RYJ-T44D]; Jack Dorsey (@jack), Twitter (Aug. 10, 2018, 9:58 AM), https://twitter.com/jack/status/
1027962500438843397 [https://perma.cc/VZA3-7E43]; Miranda Sissons, Our Commitment to Human
\\jciprod01\productn\H\HLI\64-1\HLI102.txt unknown Seq: 8 16-FEB-23 15:34
33. Rikke Frank Jørgensen, What Platforms Mean When They Talk About Human Rights, 9 Pol’y &
Internet 280 (2017) (showing how companies present themselves as public spaces). See also Amy
Kapczynski, The Right to Medicines in an Age of Neoliberalism, 10 Human. J. 79, 85 (2019) (describing the
polycentric uses of the term “human rights.”).
34. U.N. Hum. Rts. Comm., General Comment No. 34, Article 19: freedoms of opinion and expression, ¶
24, U.N. Doc. CCPR/C/GC/34 (Sept. 12, 2011) (hereinafter “General Comment 34”); David Kaye (Spe-
cial Rapporteur on the Promotion and Protection of the Right to Freedom of Opinion and Expression),
Rep. of the Special Rapporteur on the Promotion and Prot. of the Right to Freedom of Op. and Expression, ¶ 12,
U.N. Doc. A/71/373 (Sept. 6, 2016) (hereinafter “SR Report 2016”).
35. General Comment 34, supra note 34, ¶ 25. R
36. International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights, art. 19, 999 U.N.T.S. 171, 178 (entered
into force Mar. 23, 1976) (hereinafter “ICCPR”).
37. General Comment 34, supra note 34, ¶ 34. R
38. See Douek, supra note 30, at 41-50 (providing an overview of how international law can improve R
online speech governance).
39. See, e.g., Sander, supra note 30, at 988. R
40. See, e.g., Molly K. Land, Regulating Private Harms Online: Content Regulation Under Human Rights
Law, in Human Rights in the Age of Platforms 285, 288 (Rikke Frank Jørgensen ed., 2019).
\\jciprod01\productn\H\HLI\64-1\HLI102.txt unknown Seq: 10 16-FEB-23 15:34
41. Jacob Mchangama et al., A Framework of First Reference: Decoding a Human Rights Approach to Content
Moderation in the Era of “Platformization”, The Future of Free Speech (2021), https://futurefrees-
peech.com/wp-content/uploads/2021/11/Report_A-framework-of-first-reference.pdf [https://perma.cc/
BVP8-MJNQ].
42. Douek, supra note 30, at 49. R
43. See Social Media Councils: Consultation Paper, Article 19, (2019), https://www.article19.org/wp-
content/uploads/2019/06/A19-SMC-Consultation-paper-2019-v05.pdf [https://perma.cc/P6WD-28ZM]
(surveying competing proposals to align content moderation with international human rights law).
44. See, e.g., Aswad, supra note 23; Sander, supra note 30, at 969 (“Arguably the biggest challenge, R
however, resides in the translation of general human rights principles into particular rules, processes and procedures
tailored to the platform moderation context.”) (emphasis in original); id. at 971 (“[T]ranslation from the State
to the corporate context of platform moderation is likely to pose a number of challenges in practice.”)
(emphasis added).
45. See infra Section III.B.
46. David Kaye, A New Constitution for Content Moderation, Medium (June 25, 2019), https://
onezero.medium.com/a-new-constitution-for-content-moderation-6249af611bdf [https://perma.cc/2FSR-
VZ9U].
47. See, e.g., Aswad, supra note 23, at 44; infra Section III.B. (discussing the role of regional and U.N. R
instruments in the IHRL project).
48. See Aswad, supra note 23, 35. R
\\jciprod01\productn\H\HLI\64-1\HLI102.txt unknown Seq: 11 16-FEB-23 15:34
49. Douek, supra note 30, at 64 (expressing concern that platforms might “clothe themselves in the R
language of IHRL and accrue legitimacy dividends merely for meeting bare minimum transparency and
justification requirements.”).
50. Meet the Board, Oversight Bd., https://www.oversightboard.com/meet-the-board/ [https://
perma.cc/EE8T-AKY6]; Evelyn Douek, What Kind of Board Have You Given Us?, Chicago L. Rev. Blog
(May 11, 2020), https://lawreviewblog.uchicago.edu/2020/05/11/fb-oversight-board-edouek/ [https://
perma.cc/Y5NF-87DS] (analyzing the structure of the Board, its founding documents, and its initial
members).
51. See generally Aziza Ahmed, Medical Evidence and Expertise in Abortion Jurisprudence, 41 Am. J.L. &
Med. 85 (2015) (exploring how medical evidence and expertise are portrayed as neutral and objective in
the context of abortion access); Michael Klarman, From Jim Crow to Civil Rights: The Supreme
Court and the Struggle for Racial Equality (2005) (analyzing how judges reconstruct the law to
reconcile their understanding of what is legally required with their moral views).
52. Sheila Jasanoff, Subjects of Reason: Good, Markets and Competing Imaginaries of Global Governance, 4
London Rev. Int’l. L. 361, 363 (2016).
\\jciprod01\productn\H\HLI\64-1\HLI102.txt unknown Seq: 12 16-FEB-23 15:34
53. Jasanoff, supra note 20, at 313 (describing a mode of building objectivity in regulatory science R
that she describes as a view from nowhere).
54. Id. at 315.
55. Id.
56. See infra Section II.A.
57. Daniel Walters, The Administrative Agon: A Democratic Theory for a Conflictual Regulatory State, 132
Yale L.J. (forthcoming 2022) (discussing the democratic foundations of the administrative state and
arguing that what constitutes the common good is permanently contested).
58. Id.
59. See Nikolas Bowie, Comment, Antidemocracy, 135 Harv. L. Rev. 160, 160 (2021) (defining de-
mocracy as the situation in which “everyone in the community, or demos, [may] share in exercising
power, or kratos”).
60. SR Report 2018, supra note 9, at para. 54. R
61. Aswad, supra note 23, at 57. R
\\jciprod01\productn\H\HLI\64-1\HLI102.txt unknown Seq: 13 16-FEB-23 15:34
synonymous with the public interest.66 The attractive features of the frame-
work are easy to see: its claim to universality and the high esteem in many
circles. Thus, it could be useful to guide the private governance of speech on
platforms that also intend to be global and have a great need for a legitimate
set of rules to conduct their businesses.
On a closer look, however, it is not obvious that a framework designed for
states would be appropriate for corporate actors. Accordingly, proponents of
the IHRL project hint at various justifications for their proposal as well as
modifications that they consider necessary to adjust the framework for the
corporate environment. Examining these rationales serves two purposes. On
the one hand, this section shows how the justifications most commonly of-
fered share the quest for objective and apolitical principles to function as the
foundations of speech governance. On the other hand, although these ratio-
nales are offered as objective reasons to use IHRL as the framework for con-
tent moderation, this section challenges their objectivity. It argues that
these justifications are often internally inconsistent or depart widely from
established principles of international law. In addition, I argue that the pro-
posed adjustments to IHRL are closer to the construction of a new system of
rules than to an exercise of translation.67 As a consequence, even if IHRL
were a universal framework with democratic buy-in, it is unclear that the
IHRL project for content moderation would preserve those credentials.
I explore here five common rationales for asking social media companies
to implement IHRL in their content policies: the UNGPs, a functional anal-
ogy between social media companies and states, the wide ratification of cer-
tain human rights conventions, the capacity of IHRL to rein in corporate
power, and the fact that IHRL reflects globally shared values.
A. The Rationales
Perhaps the most common justification for the IHRL project is the
UNGPs. John Ruggie developed these principles during his tenure as the
U.N. Secretary-General’s Special Representative for Business and Human
Rights. The instrument provides standards to guide the conduct of states
and business enterprises. The UNGPs set the expectation that companies
66. See Douek, supra note 30, at 40 (“there has been almost no strong dissent from the proposition R
that IHRL should be adopted by companies as the basis for their rules”); Griffin, supra note 30, (describ- R
ing human rights as “the rarely-questioned moral yardstick against which all platform practices and state
regulation are measured”). Forceful opposing views to international human rights law as representative of
the public interest do exist in the broader literature outside of the specific debates about content modera-
tion. See, e.g., Samuel Moyn, The Last Utopia: Human Rights in History (2010); David Ken-
nedy, The Dark Sides of Virtue: Reassessing International Humanitarianism (2005).
67. See Sander, supra note 30, at 969, 971 (describing the IHRL project as a translation exercise). R
\\jciprod01\productn\H\HLI\64-1\HLI102.txt unknown Seq: 15 16-FEB-23 15:34
will respect human rights wherever they conduct their operations.68 On that
basis, scholars interpret the UNGPs as calling on social media companies to
align their policies with IHRL.69 In that vein, the Board states in every
decision that it applies international law per the UNGPs.70 But the origins
of the UNGPs show that this recent interpretation contradicts the history of
the instrument as well as its drafter’s understanding of its meaning, and it is
hard to find support for this recent interpretation in the text of the
UNGPs.71
To be sure, the UNGPs do provide guidelines that would help reduce the
harm caused by online speech. According to these principles, companies
should assess how their products impact people’s human rights in the differ-
ent markets where they operate.72 Companies should take measures to stop
any contribution to human rights violations.73 This responsibility means
that companies ought to take action regarding speech that international law
prohibits.
The UNGPs, however, do not set the expectation that companies will
align their content policies with IHRL. The UNGPs set the expectation that
companies will respect human rights, but international law does not cur-
rently recognize a human right to speak on privately owned media without
being subject to the medium’s editorial policies. Neither does it establish a
corresponding duty for media owners to host all speech that international
law protects.74 To the contrary, as Molly Land says, “users seek these plat-
forms precisely because of the choices the companies make about the infor-
68. U.N. Special Representative of the Secretary-General, Guiding Principles on Business and Human
Rights: Implementing the United Nations “Protect, Respect and Remedy” Framework, Principles 11-24, U.N.
Doc. A/HRC/17/31 (Mar. 21, 2011).
69. See, e.g., Stefania Di Stefano, The Facebook Oversight Board and the UN Guiding Principles on Business
and Human Rights: A Missed Opportunity for Alignment?, in Human Rights Responsibilities in the
Digital Age 93 (Jonathan Andrew & Frédéric Bernard eds., 2021).
70. The Facebook Oversight Board has applied human rights standards per the UNGPs in all of its
decisions. Since Facebook’s adoption of its corporate human rights, the Facebook Oversight Board has
also referenced this document as a basis for the application of international standards. See Case decision
2021-003-FB-UA, Oversight Bd., (Apr. 29, 2021), https://oversightboard.com/decision/FB-
H6OZKDS3/ [https://perma.cc/VV4K-NMRH]; see also Corporate Human Rights Policy, Meta, https://
about.fb.com/wp-content/uploads/2021/03/Facebooks-Corporate-Human-Rights-Policy.pdf [https://
perma.cc/8FBK-XFUG] (“We are committed to respecting human rights as set out in the United Na-
tions Guiding Principles on Business and Human Rights.”).
71. Coincidentally, a recent report submitted by the U.N. High Commissioner for Human Rights to
the Human Rights Council addressing the application of the UNGPs to the technology sector does not
indicate that social media should align their content moderation policies to international human rights
law. See OHCHR, The Practical Application of the Guiding Principles on Business and Human Rights to the
Activities of Technology Companies, U.N. Doc. A/HRC/50/56 (Apr. 21, 2022).
72. U.N. Special Representative of the Secretary-General, supra note 68, Principle 13. R
73. Id., Principle 11. See also Allison-Hope et al., A Human Rights-Based Approach to Content Governance,
BSR (Mar. 2, 2021), https://www.bsr.org/en/our-insights/blog-view/beyond-user-realdonaldtrump-
human-rights-based-approach-content-governance [https://perma.cc/LGC9-ELD8].
74. See Matthias C. Kettemann & Anna Sophia Tiedeke, Back up: can users sue platforms to reinstate
deleted content?, 9 Internet Pol’y Rev. 1 (2020) (showing that even in Germany, where courts have
pioneered the development of intermediaries’ duties to host certain types of content, platforms are al-
lowed to exclude lawful expressions).
\\jciprod01\productn\H\HLI\64-1\HLI102.txt unknown Seq: 16 16-FEB-23 15:34
Human Rights approved the norms in August 2003, but the Human Rights
Council (then Commission) refused to endorse them.85
In that context, the Human Rights Council created John Ruggie’s man-
date in 2005. The original mandate of the Special Representative of the
Secretary-General for Business and Human Rights was to “identify and clar-
ify standards of corporate responsibility and accountability” for businesses
concerning human rights and to elaborate the role of states in effectively
regulating corporations.86 Ruggie “saw no reason to replicate the debate”
that had bogged down the U.N. Draft Norms.87 Thus, he introduced some
modifications to the previous framework to gain support from states and
corporations.88
In Ruggie’s vision, the U.N. Draft Norms “had serious foundational
flaws, such as intermingling state and corporate obligations while providing
no boundaries for the latter.”89 Accordingly, in the UNGPs, he distin-
guished states’ obligations from corporations’ responsibilities. Unlike the
U.N. Draft Norms, which would have imposed legal obligations on corpora-
tions, the UNGPs set expectations that enterprises should meet voluntarily.
However, the distinction was not merely that states were bound by interna-
tional law and businesses should follow it voluntarily. Instead, Ruggie intro-
duced a substantive distinction between the content of states’ duties and
businesses’ responsibilities.90
According to Ruggie’s framework, companies should look at international
treaties not as a source of rules that apply to them but as an enumeration of
recognized rights.91 Thanks to this differentiation, even states that had not
ratified core U.N. human rights treaties endorsed the UNGPs. Notably,
China and the United States ratified them even though China has not rati-
fied the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights, and the
United States has not ratified the International Covenant on Economic, So-
cial and Cultural Rights.92
Corporations’ main responsibility is to “avoid infringing on the human
rights of others and should address adverse human rights impacts with
which they are involved.”93 Some emblematic cases help to clarify the com-
85. Comm’n on Hum. Rts., Report on the Sixtieth Session, ¶41, U.N. Doc. E/CN.4/2004/L.73/Rev.1
(2004).
86. Office of the High Comm’r for Hum. Rts., Secretary-General to appoint a special representative on the
issue of human rights and transnational corporations and other business enterprises, U.N. Doc E/CN.4/RES/2005/
69 (Apr. 20, 2005).
87. Ruggie, supra note 82, at 65. R
88. Id.
89. John Gerard Ruggie, The Social Construction of the UN Guiding Principles on Business and Human
Rights, in Research Handbook on Human Rights and Business 63, 71 (Surya Deva & David
Birchall eds., 2020).
90. Ruggie, supra note 84, at 81-127. R
91. Ruggie, supra note 89, at 71. R
92. Ruggie, supra note 82, at 65. R
93. U.N. Special Representative of the Secretary-General, supra note 68, Principle 11. R
\\jciprod01\productn\H\HLI\64-1\HLI102.txt unknown Seq: 18 16-FEB-23 15:34
94. Jennifer Burns & Debora Spar, Hitting the Wall: Nike and International Labor Practices, Case 9-700-
047, Harv. Bus. School Case Collection (2002).
95. Id.
96. Sydney Schanberg, Six Cents an Hour, Life (Mar. 28, 1996).
97. Id.
98. See Ruggie, supra note 84, at 3-6, 17, 69. R
99. Human Rights Council, Report of the independent international fact-finding mission on Myanmar, ¶ 74,
U.N. Doc. A/HRC/39/64 (Sept. 12, 2018).
100. Id.
101. See, e.g., Benesch, infra note 127. R
\\jciprod01\productn\H\HLI\64-1\HLI102.txt unknown Seq: 19 16-FEB-23 15:34
their platforms.102 This is the approach adopted by the U.N. Draft Norms,
which the Human Rights Council rejected and from which the UNGPs
explicitly diverged.103
At the same time, this new interpretation of the UNGPs alters the inter-
play between states’ duties and corporate responsibilities. Arguing that
every content moderation decision implies an IHRL issue means that states
have a corresponding duty to regulate each instance of content modera-
tion.104 The IHRL project’s interpretation of the UNGPs creates a human
right to freedom of expression on social media platforms vis-à-vis the owners
of such platforms.105 If individuals have that right, states have a correspond-
ing duty to protect it.106 However, there is little support, if any, for the idea
that states have a duty to protect the exercise of all IHRL-protected expres-
sion on private platforms.107 Indeed, no state requires companies to host all
speech that international law protects.108 The IHRL project for content
moderation asks from corporations what international law does not require
states to protect.
Another innovation refers to the different levels of responsibility between
large and small firms. According to the UNGPs, all firms are expected to
respect all internationally recognized rights.109 Does that mean that all com-
panies, including the New York Times or the Mandarin Oriental Hotel
Group,110 need to follow Article 19 of the ICCPR when deciding what
speech they will host? This interpretation of the UNGPs would be absurd
and hard to reconcile with the independence of the media and the protection
of their editorial freedom.111 In response, IHRL advocates sometimes rely on
Principle 14 of the UNGPs to distinguish among the responsibilities of
prominent social media companies and other business enterprises.
Principle 14 of the UNGPs establishes that the corporate responsibility to
respect human rights applies to all enterprises. However, the means through
102. See, e.g., Aswad, supra note 23; Parmar, supra note 10; Side-stepping rights: Regulating speech by R
contract, Article 19 (2018), https://www.article19.org/wp-content/uploads/2018/06/Regulating-speech-
by-contract-WEB.pdf [https://perma.cc/ZB6R-LCLB] (hereinafter (“Side-stepping rights”).
103. See supra n. 57-68 and accompanying text. R
104. See Land, supra note 40, at 292 (making a similar point stating that “it cannot be the case that R
every content moderation decision made by every digital platform should be subject to human rights
scrutiny.”).
105. See supra Section II.A.1.
106. U.N. Special Representative of the Secretary-General, supra note 68, Principle 1. R
107. See, e.g., Balkin, infra note 169, at 2025 (explaining why the best alternative to the current R
autocracy is not imposing the duty to carry all lawful speech).
108. See Daphne Keller, Who Do You Sue? State and Platform Hybrid Power Over Online Speech, 1902
Hoover Inst. Aegis Paper Series, 12 (2019) (surveying laws that impose the legal duty on platforms to
host speech, none of which includes the duty to host all lawful speech).
109. Ruggie, supra note 84, at 79. R
110. The Mandarin Oriental group is one of 35 hotel companies and hundreds of other companies
that have adopted a human rights policy and committed to respect human rights. See Companies, Bus. &
Hum. Rts. Res. Ctr., https://www.business-humanrights.org/en/companies/ [https://perma.cc/X68U-
9SWS] (tracking companies’ human rights policies).
111. See General Comment 34, supra note 34, ¶ 16. R
\\jciprod01\productn\H\HLI\64-1\HLI102.txt unknown Seq: 20 16-FEB-23 15:34
which enterprises meet that responsibility may vary according to their size,
sector, operational context, ownership, and structure.112 Some authors who
support the IHRL project indicate that this principle gives companies flexi-
bility in how they apply human rights norms to their operations.113 Accord-
ingly, Principle 14 could justify that smaller platforms with specific
purposes, more limited resources to moderate content, or specific targeted
audiences may depart from international guidance to regulate speech.
This distinction in the UNGPs was originally intended to recognize that
some firms have more extensive resources to assert influence. Opportunities
to exert more influence come with greater responsibility for protecting
human rights. Going back to the Nike example, a much smaller business
that outsourced part of its production may not have the resources to audit in
depth the whole supply chain it takes part in, or may not have the necessary
influence to bring about change. In the words of David Weissbrodt and
Muria Kruger, “[t]his nuanced approach does not lower the standards for
any business; it simply ensures that those with greater power and influence
will also have greater responsibilities.”114
Companies may devote different amounts of resources to their human
rights due diligence, but the content of the rights that companies must
respect is always the same.115 According to the interpretation advanced by
the IHRL project, however, large and small companies have widely different
substantive responsibilities. Large companies should adopt international law
as their own internal rules. In contrast, small companies may adopt rules
that directly contradict international standards for speech regulation.
Finally, a note on the project’s ambivalence between asking companies to
implement IHRL and calling on companies only to take inspiration from
IHRL.116 It could be that the UNGPs require that companies will imple-
ment international law, but not as if they were a state.117 Perhaps the
UNGPs do not set the expectation that companies follow IHRL, but do set
the expectation that companies ground their policies in human rights or use
human rights as “an overall framework for decision-making and ac-
tion[.]”118 For example, perhaps companies need to balance the right to free-
dom of expression and the right to equality, but the rule they reach as a
result of that balancing exercise might contradict international law as in the
Black Pete case. As I discuss in detail in the next subsection, it is unclear
why the new rule would be called IHRL. The value of labeling these new
standards as IHRL might reside in preserving the legitimacy credentials of
112. U.N. Special Representative of the Secretary-General, supra note 68, Principle 14. R
113. See, e.g., Benesch, infra note 127, at 95; Aswad, supra note 23, at 39. R
114. Weissbrodt & Kruger, supra note 80, at 911. See also Ruggie, supra note 84, at 101, 114. R
115. Id.
116. See supra Section I.
117. See, e.g., Land, supra note 40, at 305-306 (offering a thoughtful description of how private com- R
panies might follow Article 19 of the ICCPR in order to meet the expectations set by the UNGPs).
118. Allison-Hope et al., supra note 73. R
\\jciprod01\productn\H\HLI\64-1\HLI102.txt unknown Seq: 21 16-FEB-23 15:34
IHRL, even if the connection between the new rule and IHRL is thin at
best.
Ruggie’s interpretation of the UNGPs is not necessarily the best one. It
may be that IHRL advocates have created a new way of reading the princi-
ples that advances worthy policy objectives like expanding users’ rights to
freedom of expression vis-à-vis private actors. My aim is to show both the
urge to frame policy positions as mandated by legal documents as well as the
intensive intellectual work behind the purportedly objective principles
under which experts govern online speech.
2. Because social media companies are like states, but they are not like states
Scholars raise the concern that companies that control giant social media
platforms are displacing governments as the main speech regulators. In the
words of Richard Ashby Wilson and Molly Land:
Governments are no longer the primary regulators of speech.
Their regulatory capacity has been far outstripped by some of the
largest companies in the world . . ., which together regulate the
speech of 3.7 billion active social media users. . . . In a reversal of
the historic roles, private corporations have even become the de
facto regulators of government speech[.]119
Scholars conceptualize what giant platforms do as state functions. Nadine
Strossen states, “the Platforms wield censorial power of a magnitude that in
the past only governments have exercised.”120 Julie Cohen says, “[d]ominant
platforms’ role in the international legal order increasingly resembles that of
sovereign states.”121 Daphne Keller agrees, stating that, “platforms can take
on and replace traditional state functions, operating the modern equivalent
of the public square or the post office, without assuming state
responsibilities.”122
In most aspects, platforms are nothing like states. Platforms do not col-
lect taxes, manage prisons, hold elections, etc.123 The role of technology
companies is hardly unprecedented. Other highly concentrated media indus-
tries have controlled the public sphere in the past.124 However, the analogy
can be a useful rhetorical device to highlight the immense power platforms
wield over public discourse and collective affairs.
119. Richard Ashby Wilson & Molly Land, Hate Speech on Social Media: Content Moderation in Context,
52 Conn. L. Rev. 1, 5 (2021).
120. Nadine Strossen, United Nations Free Speech Standards as the Global Benchmark for Online Platforms’
Hate Speech Policies, 29 Mich. State Int’l L. Rev. 307, 324-5 (2021).
121. Julie Cohen, Law for the Platform Economy, 51 U.C. Davis L. Rev. 133, 199 (2017).
122. Keller, supra note 108, at 2-3. R
123. See Benesch, infra note 127 (highlighting the obvious but fundamental fact that “Facebook is not R
a country.”).
124. Paul Starr, The Creation of the Media: Political Origins of Modern Communica-
tions (2004).
\\jciprod01\productn\H\HLI\64-1\HLI102.txt unknown Seq: 22 16-FEB-23 15:34
The requirement of legality has also been partially eroded. This prong
demands that restrictions to freedom of expression are “provided by law.”130
That is, there must be a legal basis for restrictions. In other words, only
bodies authorized to make law may impose such limits.131 The legality
prong has also been interpreted to require that restrictions be subject to
public comment and that independent judicial officials oversee their
implementation.132
The Human Rights Committee has argued that the requirement refers
not only to the body authorizing the restriction but also to its clarity and
precision. A law must be formulated with sufficient accuracy so that indi-
viduals can regulate their conduct accordingly.133 This aspect of the require-
ment has been very generative for the IHRL project. In the context of
content moderation, the provision is understood to mean that moderation
practices must be clear and transparent.134
The first part of the legality requirement, which refers to the entity that
may restrict individuals’ freedom of expression, is impossible for companies,
as they exist today, to meet. Again, seeing companies as states could be a
first step towards imagining participatory institutions. Instead, the legality
part of the test has been narrowed down to the transparency requirement.
Both transformations risk leaving too little of IHRL standing. What is
left is a test that says that restrictions on speech should be necessary to
achieve a legitimate goal. Without any guidance about which aims are per-
missible or who should issue the restrictions, what is left is a common-sense
idea that rules should reasonably serve a reasonable purpose.
Overall, IHRL is thought of as a constraint on state power that can also
constrain corporate power. On closer examination, IHRL requires the exis-
tence of state institutions to function effectively. Corporations do not have
internal systems authorized to pass laws in the terms of Article 19 of the
ICCPR, nor do they have institutions capable of making decisions about
national security or the adequate balance between human rights. IHRL can-
not make up for the lack of these structures; it can only demand that when
these institutional actors are available, they must regulate speech in accor-
dance to Article 19 of the ICCPR and any other relevant provisions. The
130. ICCPR, supra note 36, art. 19(3). See also Gilad Abiri & Sebastián Guidi, From a Network to a R
Dilemma: The Legitimacy of Social Media, Stan. Tech. L. Rev. (forthcoming 2023) (manuscript at 32-3)
(available at https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=4230635) (making a similar point).
131. General Comment 34, supra note 34, ¶ 24; SR Report 2016, supra note 34, ¶ 12. R
132. SR Report 2016, supra note 34, ¶¶ 12, 13; SR Report 2018, supra note 9, ¶ 7; David Kaye R
(Special Rapporteur on the Promotion and Protection of the Right to Freedom of Opinion and Expres-
sion), Promotion and Prot. of the Right to Freedom of Op. and Expression, ¶ 6(a), U.N. Doc. A/74/486 (Oct.
2019) (hereinafter “SR Report 2019”).
133. General Comment 34, supra note 34, ¶ 25. R
134. See Sander, supra note 30, at 971; Benesch, supra note 127, at 103; Aswad, supra note 23, at 46. R
However, calls for transparency in content moderation are sound, long-standing, and widely accepted. It
is unclear whether the IHRL project has added any force or meaning to these calls. See, e.g., The Santa
Clara Principles, supra note 8. R
\\jciprod01\productn\H\HLI\64-1\HLI102.txt unknown Seq: 24 16-FEB-23 15:34
tension then lies in the fact that even if companies do what states ought to
do, corporations do not have the institutions that are critical pieces to oper-
ate the IHRL machinery.
3. Because IHRL is consented to by all states, but state consent does not
matter
Nearly everyone seems to be well aware that no universal, or even local,
agreement on how to regulate speech exists. Even international law scholars
deeply question the universality of international law.135 However, when jus-
tifying the IHRL project, advocates remind us that IHRL is the only glob-
ally-adopted framework. As Evelyn Aswad says, “[c]ompanies need not
recreate the wheel in developing speech norms that have worldwide legiti-
macy if they base their content moderation policies on international human
rights standards.”136
In some accounts of the IHRL project, its claim to universality comes
from state consent, particularly the vast adoption of U.N. treaties.137 As
former ACLU president Nadine Strossen puts it, “almost every single coun-
try in the world is a party to the ICCPR and the ICERD.”138 Proponents of
the IHRL project also invoke the wide acceptance of the UNGPs as one of
the main reasons to acknowledge their legitimacy. Strossen and Aswad em-
phasize that the Human Rights Council endorsed the UNGPs
unanimously.139
From these statements, one could assume that states would be a good
source for identifying a community’s values or agreements. However, IHRL
advocates regard states with deep suspicion. When Aswad analyzes a propo-
sal to renegotiate and clarify some international treaties, she rejects that
possibility (for understandable reasons): “an international negotiation to
regulate speech on platforms, including content moderation, is undesirable
because it would no doubt be dominated by powerful countries with weak
records on freedom of expression that would seek to roll back international
speech protections.”140 Instead of opening up avenues for states to deliber-
ate, Aswad proposes that we rely on experts’ interpretations that emphasize
the interpretations of U.N. treaties that broaden protections for freedom of
expression.141
When IHRL advocates discuss the divergences between U.N. and re-
gional treaties, they disregard state consent as an essential factor in deter-
mining which rules should govern speech. Interestingly, they acknowledge
that all regional systems diverge to various extents from U.N. standards.142
If state consent were the source of IHRL’s universality, these conflicts of
norms should be read as an opportunity to determine which commitment
more accurately reflects the state’s intent, values, or norms. However, pro-
moters of the project often assert that companies should follow only U.N.
guidance. For example, Aswad states that “regional human rights instru-
ments (and monitoring bodies) are not international human rights instru-
ments (and monitoring bodies).”143 Global expectations, she explains, are
reflected in international instruments, not regional ones.144
If it is the wide ratification of international treaties that makes these
norms a reflection of global values, it is unclear why the ratification of con-
tradictory treaties would be dismissed as irrelevant. A way out of this ten-
sion is to see human rights’ universality as prior to state consent and not
dependent on it. The wide ratification of human rights would only confirm
their universal status, rather than constitute it. In that case, IHRL may be
universal because it reflects global ethical principles that align with the
public interest. The next two subsections discuss this alternative claim to
universality.
The IHRL project’s central promise is that it can align corporate govern-
ance with the public interest. However, IHRL is also justified as an appro-
priate framework because it does not mandate specific policies.
IHRL could put the public interest at the center of speech regulation if it
reflected clear ways of delimiting the scope of conflicting rights that are
either globally shared or ethically correct. In response to concerns that IHRL
is too vague or internally contradictory,145 some scholars argue that IHRL
provides precise enough standards on many valuable points. Evelyn Aswad
and organizations such as Article 19 have unpacked what IHRL demands
142. See, e.g., Evelyn Aswad & David Kaye, Convergence & Conflict: Reflections on Global and Regional
Human Rights Standards on Hate Speech, 20, Nw. J. Hum. Rts., 165 (2022).
143. Aswad, supra note 23, at 44. R
144. Id. See infra Section III.B. (addressing how IHRL advocates try to iron out this contradiction
between state consent as the source of the legitimacy of IHRL and IHRL’s indifference toward state
consent).
145. See generally Amal Clooney & Philippa Webb, The Right to Insult in International Law, 48 Colum.
Hum. Rts. L. Rev. 1 (2017); Douek, supra note 30, at 37; Brenda Dvoskin, Why International Human R
Rights Law Cannot Replace Content Moderation, Medium (Oct. 8, 2019), https://medium.com/berkman-
klein-center/why-international-human-rights-law-cannot-replace-content-moderation-d3fc8dd4344c
[https://perma.cc/S7AE-N3AT].
\\jciprod01\productn\H\HLI\64-1\HLI102.txt unknown Seq: 26 16-FEB-23 15:34
5. Because IHRL is a shared language and because IHRL is like the First
Amendment
IHRL is portrayed as “a shared language” or least a common denomina-
tor.157 It is thought to provide a baseline for (unidentified) actors to be in
conversation and reach more granular agreements with each other.
At the same time, U.S. scholars argue that calling on companies to adopt
U.N. standards is the most promising avenue to bring content moderation
closer to First Amendment doctrine.158 They believe this strategy is auspi-
cious because U.N. sources would be more readily accepted globally than
the First Amendment doctrine, even though the two share many vital
elements.159
Similarly, as previously discussed, when U.N. authoritative interpreta-
tions conflict with decisions originating from European bodies, proponents
of the IHRL project assert that U.N. solutions should prevail in the context
of content moderation.160 It is problematic to claim that a legal framework
is open-ended, and either reflects or invites the search of collective answers,
while arguing that U.N. solutions should always preempt regional or local
preferences.
154. SR Report 2019, supra note 132, ¶¶ 43, 48; Article 19, supra note 43, at 13. R
155. Sander, supra note 30, at 967-68. R
156. Blayne Haggart & Clara Iglesias Keller, Democratic legitimacy in global platform governance, 45
Telecomm. Pol’y 1, 11-12 (2021); David Kennedy, The International Human Rights Movement: Part of the
Problem?, 15 Harv. Hum. Rts. J. 101, 109 (2002).
157. Michael Ignatieff, Human Rights as Idolatry, in Tanner Lectures on Human Values 349
(2000) (articulating the value of human rights as a “shared vocabulary” in a broader context).
158. Strossen, supra note 120, at 333 (“Notwithstanding widespread assumptions about the excep- R
tionally speech-protective nature of U.S. free speech law, careful comparison of the U.N. approach to that
of the U.S. demonstrates that the two share more key elements than has generally been recognized.”).
159. Id.
160. See, e.g., Aswad, supra note 23, at 57. R
\\jciprod01\productn\H\HLI\64-1\HLI102.txt unknown Seq: 28 16-FEB-23 15:34
B. Objective Justifications
161. Aswad, supra note 141 (arguing that this participatory procedure should not be reopened to R
negotiate more granular rules applicable to social media platforms because the outcome could be less
protective of freedom of expression than the current interpretations made by U.N. agencies).
162. See supra Section I.D.
\\jciprod01\productn\H\HLI\64-1\HLI102.txt unknown Seq: 29 16-FEB-23 15:34
This section explores how decisionmakers, and especially the Board, navi-
gate conflicts of norms and areas of indeterminacy within international law
while preserving the project’s claim to objectivity. When IHRL does not
yield a specific outcome or experts are faced with multiple possible solu-
tions, experts invoke interpretative theories, technical facts, or other strate-
gies to conceal their policy choices. Decisions are justified as a logical
deduction from higher principles or as the necessary consequence of objec-
tive facts. This section looks at four tools that the IHRL project has so far
developed for expert governance, while paying close attention to the Board’s
first decisions.
analyzing platforms’ internal hate speech rules, the report finds that plat-
forms’ rules usually restrict speech that IHRL protects.166 According to the
report, companies do not offer robust speech protections for commercial rea-
sons. The authors hypothesize that these rules enable platforms to grow their
user base and accommodate advertisers’ interests.167 Overall, the report as-
sumes that there are two options: rules driven by business interests and rules
that align with IHRL. At no point does the report question the idea that
IHRL and the public interest are equivalent.
The comparison between conversations about platforms adopting First
Amendment doctrines and IHRL as a default illuminates how IHRL is dis-
cussed as undoubtedly good. Most scholars who support First Amendment
doctrine as a generally appropriate normative framework to govern speech
are resistant to asking companies to apply it as a default rule for content
moderation.168 Scholars acknowledge that if platforms hosted all First
Amendment–protected speech, platforms would be worse for almost all
users.169 However, similar concerns have not been raised by IHRL support-
ers, even though if social media were to allow all the speech that IHRL
protects, users and companies would also have to tolerate all types of unde-
sirable speech.170 IHRL has both a non-contestable character and a higher
level of indeterminacy that seems to incentivize people to accept it as a
framework and work out exceptions rather than rejecting the whole frame-
work because it does not perfectly track their normative preferences.
Because of its simultaneously undefined and uncontestable character,
human rights language can be invoked to justify a decision without many
further explanations. If someone proposes that platforms should adopt a cer-
tain policy because it aligns with the First Amendment, it is very likely that
other advocates will raise serious objections to that justification. If someone,
however, argues in favor of a rule because it follows human rights law, they
are unlikely to be challenged on the basis that their framework is inade-
quate, even if they still have to persuade others about the merits of the
specific rule.
171. Benesch, supra note 127, at 91; Sander, supra note 30, at 977. R
172. Douek, supra note 30. See also Dvoskin, supra note 145. R
173. SR Report 2019, supra note 132, ¶ 26 (referring to the U.N. level). R
174. Aswad, supra note 136, at 634, n.94. R
175. Org. of Islamic Cooperation, The Cairo Declaration on Human Rights in Islam, Annex to Res. No.
49/19-P, art. 22 (Aug. 5, 1990).
176. Victoria Nuland, Press Statement on the ASEAN Declaration on Human Rights, U.S. State Depart-
ment (Nov. 20, 2012), https://2009-2017.state.gov/r/pa/prs/ps/2012/11/200915.htm [https://perma.cc/
ZC2W-WNTC] (“While part of the ASEAN Declaration adopted November 18 tracks the [Universal
Declaration of Human Rights], we are deeply concerned that many of the ASEAN Declaration’s princi-
ples and articles could weaken and erode universal human rights and fundamental freedoms as contained
in the UDHR.”).
177. Aswad & Kaye, supra note 142. R
178. Antoine Buyse, Tacit Citing: The Scarcity of Judicial Dialogue between the Global and the Regional
Human Rights Mechanisms in Freedom of Expression Cases, in The United Nations and Freedom of
Expression and Information: Critical Perspectives 443 (Tarlach McGonagle & Yvonne Donders
eds., 2015) (describing these dynamics).
179. Int’l Law Comm’n, Fragmentation of International Law: Difficulties Arising from the Diversification
and Expansion of International Law, ¶¶ 165-71, U.N. Doc. A/CN.4/L.682 (Apr. 13, 2006).
\\jciprod01\productn\H\HLI\64-1\HLI102.txt unknown Seq: 32 16-FEB-23 15:34
180. Joana Harrington, The Democratic Challenge of Incorporation: International Human Rights Treaties and
National Constitutions, 38 Victoria U. Wellington L. Rev. 217 (2007).
181. See, e.g., Case decision 2022-003-IG-UA, Oversight Bd. (June 13, 2022), https://over-
sightboard.com/decision/IG-2PJ00L4T/ [https://perma.cc/CZD5-VMA4] (citing Communication 488/
1992, Toonen v. Australia, Human Rights Committee, 1992; Resolution 32/2, Human Rights Council,
2016; UN Special Rapporteur on freedom of opinion and expression, reports: A/HRC/38/35 (2018) and
A/74/486 (2019); UN High Commissioner for Human Rights, report: A/HRC/19/41 (2011)).
182. Aswad, supra note 23, at 44. R
183. See Int’l Law Comm’n, supra note 179, ¶ 26. R
184. Id.
185. Id., ¶ 324.
186. Int’l Law Comm’n, supra note 179, ¶ 410. R
187. U.N. Charter art. 103.
188. Int’l Law Comm’n, supra note 179, ¶ 16. R
\\jciprod01\productn\H\HLI\64-1\HLI102.txt unknown Seq: 33 16-FEB-23 15:34
Most relevant to the problem of regional and universal treaties is the tool
of lex specialis.189 This technique prioritizes the most specific rule when two
legal provisions are applicable and no clear hierarchical relationship exists
between them. The closer connection to the particular context may more
adequately reflect the interests and consent of the parties involved.190 How-
ever, this technique did not make it into the Vienna Convention on the Law
of Treaties from 1960, which identifies other methods for treaty interpreta-
tion.191 Some authors dismiss this technique as irrelevant or impractical.192
In any case, using lex specialis as a plausible tool to put global and regional
rules in relation to each other is incompatible with the general rule that
IHRL advocates propose (i.e., that U.N. norms always take priority).
Because international law has not traditionally dictated that U.N. norms
should be preferred to regional norms, proponents of the IHRL project have
focused on alternative interpretations of the relationship between human
rights treaties. For example, Aswad’s reply to Douek’s objection about in-
consistencies between regional and global treaties is that “[s]uch a concern
inappropriately conflates IHRL with separate bodies of law embodied in re-
gional human rights instruments.”193 Excluding regional human rights trea-
ties from international law is highly uncommon. Describing a norm as
“international” refers not to its global application, but to the source of legal
authority upon which the norm exists.194 That is, regional human rights
treaties are part of international law “because they have been recognized as
an international legal obligation through established international legal
process.”195
IHRL advocates also argue that “[r]egional human rights norms cannot,
in any event, be invoked to justify departure from international human
rights protections.”196 But this says nothing about the hierarchy of interna-
tional norms or which rules companies should use to govern speech. This
only says that a U.N. body would consider a state to be in violation of its
international duties even if its conduct is permissible under another interna-
tional norm. A regional tribunal could reach a similar conclusion if a state
adopted a rule that is compatible with a U.N. norm but incompatible with
its duties under a regional treaty.
It is common for IHRL advocates to argue that the U.N. system acts as a
floor or minimum of rights that companies must respect. Companies should
only apply regional norms when these norms expand rights. Along those
lines, Aswad argues that inconsistencies between international and regional
mechanisms do not render the U.N. human rights regime incoherent: “[i]t
simply means that the U.N. system provides more protections for speech
than the regional systems.”197 Discussing the idea of referencing regional
human rights treaties in the decisions of the Board, Co-Chair Catalina
Botero stated that the Board could apply regional treaties in the future if the
treaties expanded the level of protection of freedom of expression.198
Usually, the expansion of one right bears costs on other rights. For exam-
ple, in regulating prior restraint on speech, the American Convention on
Human Rights is more protective of speech than any other system.199 But
this protection of speech comes at the expense of less protection for other
rights such as privacy or safety.200 One can only see the Inter-American Con-
vention as expanding rights if one assumes that the right that ought to be
expanded is freedom of expression and not others.
In the context of the Board, this preference to expand freedom of expres-
sion over other rights has normative support. The Board’s Charter refers only
to “human rights norms that protect freedom of expression.”201 As a general
rule for how companies should adopt international human rights, however, a
normative basis is lacking. The principle is articulated in neutral terms
(“apply the rule that offers higher protection”) but it hides a clear normative
orientation (“always choose the most free-speech protective rule”).
Finally, IHRL advocates may find a basis for the preeminence of U.N.
treaties in the UNGPs. The UNGPs only refer to the International Bill of
Rights, which consists of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights, the
ICCPR, and the International Covenant on Economic, Social, and Cultural
Rights.202 Therefore, Aswad argues that companies ought to look exclusively
at global treaties. For example, she considers that Twitter’s statement about
looking at U.S. law and the European Convention on Human Rights “de-
parts from the UNGPs, which provide that companies should seek to align
their operations with IHRL rather than domestic laws (like the U.S. Bill of
Rights) or regional law (such as the European Human Rights
Convention).”203
As argued above, this is a new interpretation of the UNGPs.204 John Rug-
gie, the author of the UNGPs, believed companies should look at the Inter-
national Bill of Rights and the ILO’s Declaration on Fundamental Principles
and Rights at Work as an authoritative list of recognized rights.205 How-
ever, this did not mean that companies should follow the law stemming
from U.N. treaties and their authoritative interpretation. In addition, dis-
cussing the relationship between global and regional norms, Ruggie con-
cludes that “no homogenous hierarchical meta-system is realistically
available within the international legal order to resolve the problem of in-
compatible provisions among different bodies of law.”206
Looking at the efforts to build a coherent and uniform system of interna-
tional rights makes the work toward objectivity visible. A clear relationship
between global and regional norms creates the illusion that there is a system
of norms readily available to constrain corporate power. However, asking
companies to behave as if a coherent universal system of human rights ex-
isted gives corporations unprecedented powers. Corporations are put in
charge of deciding which rights should be prioritized when international
norms conflict, or how conflicts of norms between the European system of
human rights (or any other regional system) and the U.N. should be
adjudicated.
203. Aswad, supra note 23, at 44; see also Aswad & Kaye, supra note 142, at 56. R
204. See supra Section II.A.1.
205. Ruggie, supra note 84, at 19. R
206. Id. at 65.
207. See, e.g., Danielle Citron, Extremist Speech, Compelled Conformity, and Censorship Creep, 93 Notre
Dame L. Rev. 1035, 1063 (2018); Douek, supra note 13, at 66. R
208. See, e.g., Douek, supra note 30, at 56, 72. R
209. Danielle Citron, Cyber Civil Rights, 89 B.U.L. Rev. 61, 63 (2010).
\\jciprod01\productn\H\HLI\64-1\HLI102.txt unknown Seq: 36 16-FEB-23 15:34
ferently than states and international bodies do when they restrict speech
offline?
The Board has started to deal with this question. In some cases, it allowed
Facebook to adopt rules that, in its own view, directly contradict what
IHRL prescribes. Even in these cases, the Board justified these rules as an
appropriate implementation of human rights in part because online speech is
different from offline speech. A series of decisions evaluated Facebook’s ban
on a list of racial slurs210 and Case Decision 2021-002-FB-UA reviewed
Facebook’s prohibition on content depicting blackface.211
The Board had to justify why, in its view, a state would violate interna-
tional law if the state issued a ban on blackface or on racial slurs, but
Facebook was meeting its human rights responsibilities when issuing those
same bans. In the case about blackface, the Board hinted at four rationales:
U.N. experts and other authorities determined that blackface creates objec-
tive harm;212 Facebook has a human right responsibility to promote equal-
ity;213 it is hard to evaluate the intent of the speaker on social media;214 hate
speech, even when it does not have an intent to discriminate or to incite
violence, can create a discriminatory, harassing, and degrading
environment.215
Consider the last two rationales. One could challenge them on factual
terms. It might well be that racial slurs and people in blackface create a
discriminatory environment regardless of whether the expression is online or
off, and the intent of the speaker may always be hard to judge. It is also
unclear that these types of expressions when they take place at one’s univer-
sity, in the workplace, or other close social environment are less harmful
than when they occur on social media. But let us accept these distinctions
between online and offline speech. Perhaps digital racial slurs and people in
blackface create an even worse discriminatory environment because of their
reach and quantity. What should we make of that difference?
The Board gave three different answers. First, the general ban on black-
face that Facebook adopted is incompatible with international law.216 In the
Board’s words, “international human rights law would not allow a state to
impose a general prohibition on blackface through criminal or civil sanc-
tions, except under the conditions foreseen in ICCPR Article 20, para. 2 and
Article 19, para. 3.” In the Board’s view, the post discussed in this case
210. Case decision 2021-011-FB-UA, Oversight Bd. (Sept. 28, 2021), https://oversightboard.com/
decision/FB-TYE2766G/ [https://perma.cc/UE9F-FHP7]; Case decision 2020-003-FB-UA, Oversight
Bd. (Jan. 28, 2021), https://oversightboard.com/decision/FB-QBJDASCV/ [https://perma.cc/DC5H-
STWU].
211. See supra Introduction (discussing this decision).
212. Case decision 2021-002-FB-UA, supra note 1, at 16. R
213. Id.
214. Id.
215. Id.
216. Id. at 14.
\\jciprod01\productn\H\HLI\64-1\HLI102.txt unknown Seq: 37 16-FEB-23 15:34
“[w]ould fall within this category of protection from state restriction.” Sec-
ond, in this new medium, speech produces different consequences, and new
answers are possible.217 Third, the prohibition is compatible with interna-
tional law. The Board concluded that “Facebook followed international gui-
dance and met its human rights responsibilities in this case.”218
Notice the tension between asserting that states would breach interna-
tional law if they adopted this rule (that is, IHRL does prescribe what rules
are acceptable) and that the new medium creates a situation in which new
normative answers are possible (that is, IHRL does not prescribe what rules
are acceptable).
The Board had two options to avoid that tension. First, given the open
texture of IHRL, the Board could have argued that IHRL allows prohibi-
tions on blackface, at least in the online context.219 However, that would
have meant committing to the view that states can also issue these regula-
tions. What seems to animate the Board’s reasoning is the belief that states
and companies should actually govern speech differently. If that is the case,
the Board also had a second option. It could have stated that IHRL was not
the appropriate framework in this case because states and corporations are
different. However, that would have meant losing the legitimizing force of
IHRL.
Ultimately, the Board adopted a third choice: states and corporations
ought to regulate speech differently and both options are compatible with
IHRL. In order to preserve the claim to objectivity, the Board framed this
third option as determined by technical facts.
The strategy here was to transform an unanswered question into one that
can be answered with technical facts. The Board’s move was the following:
international law does not allow general bans on content depicting black-
face, but online speech is more harmful and harder (perhaps impossible) to
adjudicate on a case-by-case basis. The Board’s conclusion could have been
that IHRL provides no guidance to decide the case. Instead, the Board de-
cided that these technical facts make Facebook’s rule proportional and com-
patible with IHRL. Through these steps, the Board framed an open
normative question as a question about how to translate international law
principles in a new technical context, as if the technical context could deter-
mine the answer to the question. As a result, the Board did not appear to be
creating new human rights standards, but rather appeared to be an objective
translator.
Labeling new norms designed for platform governance as IHRL is a clear
expression of the ideal of expert governance. Even if these new norms oppose
IHRL norms, preserving the human rights label helps to maintain IHRL’s
217. Id. at 16 (assessing the cumulative effects of speech on social media and the challenges of enforce-
ment at scale).
218. Id. at 14.
219. Thanks to Evelyn Douek for raising this point in a personal conversation.
\\jciprod01\productn\H\HLI\64-1\HLI102.txt unknown Seq: 38 16-FEB-23 15:34
220. Siva Vaidhyanathan, Antisocial Media: How Facebook Disconnects Us and Under-
mines Democracy 27 (2018).
221. Kennedy, supra note 156. R
222. See, e.g., Dina Shelton, The Promise of Regional Human Rights Systems, in The Future of Interna-
tional Human Rights 351, 356 (Burns H. Weston & Stephen P. Marks eds., 1999); Malcom Evans,
The Future(s) of Regional Courts on Human Rights, in Realizing Utopia 261 (Antonio Cassese ed., 2012).
223. Jack Goldsmith & Tim Wu, Who Controls the Internet? Illusions of a Borderless
World 150 (2006).
224. Int’l Law Comm’n, supra note 179, ¶ 206. R
225. See Stephen Humphreys, Theatre of the Rule of Law: Transnational Legal Inter-
vention in Theory and Practice (2010) (exploring how rule of law promotion programs reframe
political preferences as questions of expertise).
226. Naomi Appelman & Paddy Leerssen, On “Trusted” Flaggers, Yale-Wikimedia Initiative on
Intermediaries & Information (July 12, 2022), https://law.yale.edu/sites/default/files/area/center/isp/
documents/trustedflaggers_ispessayseries_jul2022.pdf [https://perma.cc/NWP4-UXE8]; Brenda Dvos-
kin, Social Media Platforms and Civil Society in Latin America: A View from the Nonprofit Organizations
(Centro de Estudios en Tecnologı́a y Sociedad, Working Paper No. 20, 2020).
\\jciprod01\productn\H\HLI\64-1\HLI102.txt unknown Seq: 39 16-FEB-23 15:34
227. See, e.g., EFHR welcomed into Trusted Partner Channel of Facebook, European Foundation of
Human Rights (Jan. 29, 2018), https://en.efhr.eu/2018/01/29/efhr-welcomed-trusted-partner-channel-
facebook/ [https://perma.cc/8M2Y-A4AU].
228. Dvoskin, supra note 226, at 8-9. R
229. See, e.g., Case decision 2021-010-FB-UA, Oversight Bd. (Sept. 27, 2021), https://over-
sightboard.com/decision/FB-E5M6QZGA/ [https://perma.cc/GCE6-75XA]; Case decision 2020-006-FB-
FBR, Oversight Bd. (Jan. 28, 2021), https://oversightboard.com/decision/FB-XWJQBU9A/ [https://
perma.cc/4K9L-K2GA].
230. Chinmayi Arun, Rebalancing Regulation of Speech: Hyper-Local Content on Global Web-Based Plat-
forms, Medium (Mar. 28, 2018), https://medium.com/berkman-klein-center/rebalancing-regulation-of-
speech-hyper-local-content-on-global-web-based-platforms-1-386d65d86e32 [https://perma.cc/XUD4-
3K9W] (stressing the importance of local contexts for platform governance).
231. See generally Evelyn Douek, Governing Online Speech: From “Posts-As-Trumps” to Proportionality and
Probability, 121 Colum. L. Rev. 759 (2021); New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U.S. 254 (1964)
(arguing, although not in these terms, that actual malice was the appropriate standard of review because
it avoids false positives, even if that means allowing some false negatives).
\\jciprod01\productn\H\HLI\64-1\HLI102.txt unknown Seq: 40 16-FEB-23 15:34
However, this is not the kind of local context that the Board considers
necessary to consider. For example, in Case Decision 2020-006-FB-FBR, the
Board analyzed Facebook’s removal of false information about COVID-19.232
The balance between free expression and public health in the context of the
COVID pandemic is a good example of where people and communities hold
different views. Platforms, accused of contributing to the spread of misinfor-
mation, have aggressively targeted public health misinformation at least
partially in response to the preferences of some segments of the public.233
In the post at issue, a user had stated (incorrectly) that a cure for COVID-
19 was available, that the drug was harmless, and complained that the
French authorities were not making the drug available in France.234
Facebook explained to the Board that, following the opinion of consulted
experts, it decided to take down all content stating that a cure for COVID-
19 is available because other users may believe it and may disregard precau-
tionary health guidance or may self-medicate as a consequence.235 The Board
disagreed that this was the right balance between freedom of expression and
public health. The user was questioning a governmental policy and calling
for a change.236 The Board reasoned that the protection of this kind of politi-
cal discourse was fundamental.237 In addition, the Board was not certain that
the post could contribute to imminent harm.238
In this case, the Board highlighted that the drugs referenced in the post
were not available in France without a prescription.239 It added that, “the
alleged cure has not been approved by the French authorities and thus it is
unclear why those reading the post would be inclined to disregard health
precautions for a cure they cannot access.”240 As in other decisions, the
Board was very interested in looking at the offline context of a post, but this
context was limited to facts that experts can explain and the Board can con-
sider when making its own normative choice.
252. U.N. Special Representative of the Secretary-General, supra note 68, Principle 17. R
253. Id.
254. See, e.g., Case decision 2021-011-FB-UA, supra note 210, at 10. R
255. See, e.g., Vanessa Pappas, Introducing TikTok Content Advisory Council, TikTok (Mar. 18, 2020),
https://newsroom.tiktok.com/en-us/introducing-the-tiktok-content-advisory-council [https://perma.cc/
DL34-C3M7]; Arjun Narayan Bettadopur, Introducing the TikTok Asia Pacific Safety Advisory Council,
TikTok (Sept. 22, 2020), https://newsroom.tiktok.com/en-sg/tiktok-apac-safety-advisory-council [https:/
/perma.cc/5DMU-YGNM]; Julie de Bailliencourt, Meet TikTok’s European Safety Advisory Council, TikTok
(Mar. 1, 2021), https://newsroom.tiktok.com/en-gb/tiktok-european-safety-advisory-council [https://
perma.cc/83VD-NNWU]; Introducing the Twitch Safety Advisory Council, Twitch (May 14, 2020), https://
blog.twitch.tv/en/2020/05/14/introducing-the-twitch-safety-advisory-council/ [https://perma.cc/YS3G-
YCAK]; Nick Pickles, Strengthening our Trust and Safety Council, Twitter (Dec. 13, 2019), https://
blog.twitter.com/en_us/topics/company/2019/strengthening-our-trust-and-safety-council.html [https://
perma.cc/ZB4M-T759]; Patricia Carter, Announcing the Twitter Trust & Safety Council, Twitter (Feb. 9,
2016), https://blog.twitter.com/en_us/a/2016/announcing-the-twitter-trust-safety-council.html [https://
perma.cc/UW3E-WSSS]; Stakeholder Engagement, Meta, https://www.facebook.com/communitys-
tandards/stakeholder_engagement [https://perma.cc/KL63-KP64].
256. See, e.g., Case decision 2020-006-FB-FBR, supra note 229, at 15 (acknowledging that the board’s R
recommendations to Facebook drew on public comments the board received).
\\jciprod01\productn\H\HLI\64-1\HLI102.txt unknown Seq: 43 16-FEB-23 15:34
civil society.257 The Board has valued Facebook’s efforts to engage civil
society.258
As discussed above, the UNGPs refer to companies’ responsibility to re-
spect human rights that international law recognizes.259 Accordingly, when
the UNGPs discuss human rights due diligence, they envision that compa-
nies will make an effort to audit the impact of their operations on human
rights.260 For example, under this framework, Facebook is expected to un-
derstand how its platforms are used in different countries. If it is the case, as
it has been in Myanmar, that the platform is a key tool in organizing crimes
against humanity, Facebook should be aware of this and take active steps to
prevent or remedy its involvement in human rights abuses.261
The Board’s interpretation goes well beyond that responsibility. When
Facebook engages civil society around the world to gather feedback on how
to amend its community guidelines, it proposes different potential rules and
hears advantages or concerns about each one of them.262 The kind of stake-
holder engagement that companies carry out and that the Board promotes
does not have the sole or even central purpose of identifying potential
human rights infringements. Rather, companies engage civil society to in-
corporate their preferences among multiple human-rights-respecting policy
options.263 The assumption is that all discussed alternatives respect human
rights.
Even if divergent from the text of the UNGPs, the Board’s interpretation
can be very useful. The main stated goal of the IHRL project is to align
private speech regulation with the interests of the people. This reading of
the human rights due diligence responsibility may strengthen companies’
consultation with the public during the policy development process. Along
those lines, in Case Decision 2020-006-FB-FBR concerning a post contain-
ing inaccurate information about COVID-19 treatments, the Board recom-
257. See, e.g., Case decision 2021-011-FB-UA, supra note 210, at 11 (citing a report elaborated by the R
NGO Media Monitoring Africa).
258. See, e.g., Case decision 2021-002-FB-UA, supra note 1, at 11. R
259. See supra Section II.A.1.
260. See Ruggie, supra note 84, at 99. R
261. See id. at 100 (describing the responsibilities of multinational corporations operating in countries
where they are at risk of becoming complicit in egregious human rights abuses).
262. See generally Matthias Kettemann & Wolfgang Schulz, Setting Rules for 2.7 Billion. A (First) Look
into Facebook’s Norm-Making System: Results of a Pilot Study (Hans-Bredow-Institut Working Paper, 2020)
(describing the steps in Facebook’s stakeholder engagement process).
263. See, e.g., Standing Against Hate, Meta (Mar. 27, 2019), https://about.fb.com/news/2019/03/
standing-against-hate/ [https://perma.cc/BRV3-D9A7]; Monika Bickert, Enforcing Against Manipulated
Media, Meta (Jan. 6, 2020), https://about.fb.com/news/2020/01/enforcing-against-manipulated-media/
[https://perma.cc/C2YX-PB7U]; Vanessa Pappas, Combating Misinformation and Election Interference on
TikTok, TikTok (Aug. 5, 2020), https://newsroom.tiktok.com/en-us/combating-misinformation-and-
election-interference-on-tiktok [ https://perma.cc/6XJH-VDER]; Twitter Safety, Updating Our Rules
Against Hateful Conduct, Twitter (July 9, 2019), https://blog.twitter.com/en_us/topics/company/2019/
hatefulconductupdate.html [https://perma.cc/PE5X-WD4L]; Vijaya Gadde & Del Harvey, Creating New
Policies Together, Twitter (Sept. 25, 2018), https://blog.twitter.com/official/en_us/topics/company/2018/
Creating-new-policies-together.html [https://perma.cc/7EAB-DX6B].
\\jciprod01\productn\H\HLI\64-1\HLI102.txt unknown Seq: 44 16-FEB-23 15:34
ban, the Board did not reference this process. Instead, the Board decided
that the divergence was justified because many experts had found that
images depicting blackface are discriminatory and harmful. Among other
reasons discussed above, the Board relied on the fact that “[n]umerous
human rights mechanisms have found the portrayal of Zwarte Piet to be a
harmful stereotype.”270 But not any harmful stereotype would satisfy the
Board. The Board cited many reports and concluded that these expert find-
ings provided “sufficient evidence of objective harm to individual’s rights to
distinguish this rule from one that seeks to insulate people from subjective
offense.”271 This passage defines a boundary between objective knowledge
and subjective feelings. Here, objectivity comes not from the stakeholder
engagement process but from the human-rights experts’ findings.
Another example in the same direction comes from Case Decision 2021-
011-FB-UA concerning the use of a racial slur in South Africa.272 The Board
analyzed Facebook’s decision to delete a post that used a racial slur in the
context of discussing wealth and racial dynamics in South Africa. The Board
had already decided other cases dealing with bans of specific terms, always
finding that even though prohibiting the use of particular words would
breach IHRL if adopted by a state, Facebook’s ban was compatible with
IHRL.273
This case offers an additional glimpse of how the Board divides tasks
among U.N. experts and civil society organizations. On the one hand, the
Board stated that banning racial slurs is incompatible with IHRL. Still,
Facebook can adopt that ban because the “[U.N.] Special Rapporteur indi-
cates that entities engaged in content moderation like Facebook can regulate
such speech.”274 On the other hand, the Board stated that Facebook should
consult affected groups and human rights experts, as it did in this case, to
review its policies and update the list of banned slurs.275 The consultation in
this case contributed to Facebook’s understanding of the meaning of the
term in the context where it is used.276 In this sense, engagement with local
civil society is used mainly as an implementation mechanism to ensure the
correct understanding of racial slurs, while the rule-making process is kept
in the hands of a small group of experts.
277. See, e.g., Douek, supra note 30, at 63; Dvoskin, supra note 145. R
278. See Sheila Jasanoff, Designs in Nature: Science and Democracy in Europe and the
United States 152-55 (2005) (explaining and illustrating the idea of a communal viewpoint developed
from the top).
\\jciprod01\productn\H\HLI\64-1\HLI102.txt unknown Seq: 47 16-FEB-23 15:34
279. See Kennedy, supra note 156, at 108; Samuel Moyn, Humane: How the United States R
Abandoned Peace and Reinvented War (2021) (arguing that international humanitarian law di-
verts from pursuing more radical projects).
280. Sander, supra note 30, at 1005. R
281. See Ganesh Sitaraman, The Puzzling Absence of Economic Power in Constitutional Theory, 101 Cor-
nell L. Rev. 1445, 1500 (2016); Nico Krisch, The Pluralism of Global Administrative Law, 17 Eur. J.
Int’l. L. 247, 276 (2007).
282. Walters, supra note 57, at 56. R
283. Id. (emphasis in the original).
\\jciprod01\productn\H\HLI\64-1\HLI102.txt unknown Seq: 48 16-FEB-23 15:34
The IHRL project provides a framework for experts to present their deci-
sions as objective to the public and, in turn, gain the public’s acceptance.
This is a tempting offer. But resisting the comfort that legal language pro-
vides and coming to terms with one’s power can lead to decisions that are
more transparent, less likely to be framed as universal answers, and easier to
contest.
If newly empowered experts are too concerned with proving their objec-
tivity, they may miss a valuable opportunity for plural and experimental
governance. Indeed, the most interesting recommendations the Board has
made to date were not grounded in IHRL.289 Moving away from the IHRL
project may prompt experts to provide better justifications for their deci-
sions, involve more actors, and make space for more meaningful inclusion of
normative disagreements. Imagining how the Board could have reached its
decision in the case about Black Pete illustrates these points.
First, IHRL is highly praised for offering a framework to justify decisions
to the public.290 Likewise, one of the core purposes of the Board is to deliver
transparent and well-justified decisions.291 But in the Black Pete case, the
Board’s adoption of the IHRL project actually harmed the coherence and
clarity of its decision.
Throughout the Article, I have discussed how the Board dealt with tech-
nical facts,292 U.N. experts,293 and stakeholder engagement in the Black
Pete case.294 An additional point to consider is how the Board assigns corpo-
rate actors a fundamental role in the protection of human rights that, in the
Board’s view, is a role barred to states. In the Black Pete case, the Board
concluded that “international human rights law would not allow a state to
impose a general prohibition on blackface”295 and at the same time asserted
that “Facebook followed international guidance and met its human rights
responsibilities in this case.”296
289. See, e.g., Case decision 2021-009-FB-UA, Oversight Bd. (Sept. 14, 2021), https://
www.oversightboard.com/decision/FB-P93JPX02/ [https://perma.cc/NR3T-WM65] (recommending
Facebook “. . . conduct a thorough examination to determine whether Facebook’s content moderation in
Arabic and Hebrew, including its use of automation, have been applied without bias.”); Case decision
2020-004-IG-UA, Oversight Bd. (June 28, 2021), https://oversightboard.com/decision/IG-7THR3SI1/
[https://perma.cc/PNY8-B7HX] (recommending Facebook “[i]mplement an internal audit procedure to
continuously analyze a statistically representative sample of automated content removal decisions to re-
verse and learn from enforcement mistakes.”); Case decision 2021-006-IG-UA, supra note 265 (recom- R
mending Facebook open a public call for inputs on how to update its Dangerous Individuals and
Organizations policy).
290. Sander, supra note 30, at 967. R
291. Feldman, supra note 8, at 102. R
292. See supra Section III.C.
293. See supra Section IV.
294. Id.
295. Case decision 2021-002-FB-UA, supra note 1. R
296. Id.
\\jciprod01\productn\H\HLI\64-1\HLI102.txt unknown Seq: 50 16-FEB-23 15:34
The reasons why the Board thought that this was an appropriate rule for
Facebook to adopt were, again, that blackface produces objective harm, that
the real intent of the speaker on social media is hard to determine, that this
kind of speech can create a discriminatory, harassing, and degrading envi-
ronment, and that Facebook should promote equality.297 It is hard to under-
stand why Facebook would be expected to prevent the harms caused by this
kind of content under its human rights responsibility but a state would not
be allowed to take analogous steps under the same legal framework.
All of the circumstances that justified Facebook’s decision also apply to
state regulation. Instances of discriminatory speech, even if not intended to
cause harm, are pervasive in many contexts and create discriminatory envi-
ronments.298 If experts’ reports find that people in blackface create “objec-
tive” harm, then the harm is obviously independent of whether Facebook or
governments are the ones to address it. States have a greater responsibility
than Facebook to promote equality. Ultimately, the need to justify a rule
that diverges from IHRL as an adequate application of that framework
makes the decision more confusing, not more transparent.
Second, being transparent about what is driving the Board’s decisions
would enable more effective participation by the public. In the comments
received by the Board in this case, Professor Sejal Parmar from the Univer-
sity of Sheffield was the only commenter who provided an analysis of the
decision under IHRL, and particularly Articles 19 and 20 of the ICCPR.299
Her comment cites some of the same reports the Board referenced, although
she highlights that the reports do not call for a total ban on portraits of
Black Pete. Ultimately, the Board decided to diverge from IHRL. In this
case, telling the public that IHRL will determine the decision does not en-
hance the public conversation, as the project promises, but rather under-
mines it. Indeed, it becomes less clear to the public what reasons the Board
will consider to be weighty when making a decision.
The Board instead could have explained why Facebook’s rule aligned with
the Board’s normative approach. For example, the most important factor
driving the decision could have been the support that the prohibition had
among consulted stakeholders. If the Board acknowledges that this factor is
driving its decision, then the Board can openly set requirements that a con-
sultation process needs to meet in order to persuade the Board to give defer-
ence to the consultation’s findings.
Third, if the Board is successful in promoting IHRL as the correct moral
yardstick for content moderation, other companies might believe they need
297. Id.
298. See Chester Pierce, Psychiatric Problems of the Black Minority, in American Handbook of Psy-
chiatry 512 (Silvano Arieti ed., 1974) (coining the term “microaggressions” and studying their impact
on mental health).
299. Public Comment Appendix for Case decision 2021-002-FB-UA, Oversight Bd. (Apr. 13, 2021),
https://www.oversightboard.com/sr/decision/2021/002/public-comments [https://perma.cc/3GB5-
BD37].
\\jciprod01\productn\H\HLI\64-1\HLI102.txt unknown Seq: 51 16-FEB-23 15:34
to converge with the Board in their decisions. When the Board says that
Facebook is meeting its human rights responsibilities by adopting a general
ban on blackface, the Board makes it harder for other companies to adopt a
different rule. More fundamentally, the Board’s proposal for how to assign
roles in online speech governance greatly increases the power of corporate
actors (including the Board’s own power). In the Board’s interpretation, a
great objective harm exists to social equality that only companies (and the
Board) should remedy. Framing its decisions as the product of its members’
views would help the Board avoid this kind of general and universalizing
stance of what online speech governance should look like.
Finally, abandoning the ideal of objectivity would help the Board be more
explicit about its political commitments. As Walters says about administra-
tive agencies, there is a lot to gain from the Board admitting that its deci-
sions reflect some people’s preferences, not everyone’s.300 Instead of putting
an end to the debate, making normative preferences explicit calls for in-
stances for those with different preferences to contest the decision in the
future. In expert governance, the quest for objectivity is an obstacle for
meaningful participation. Ultimately, putting politics front and center may
more effectively facilitate the public conversation, transparency, and public
justifications that the IHRL project envisions.
Conclusion