35 Berkeley Tech LJ
35 Berkeley Tech LJ
Citations:
Please note: citations are provided as a general guideline. Users should consult their preferred
citation format's style manual for proper citation formatting.
-- Your use of this HeinOnline PDF indicates your acceptance of HeinOnline's Terms and
Conditions of the license agreement available at
https://heinonline-org-rcldigitallibrary.knimbus.com/HOL/License
-- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text.
-- To obtain permission to use this article beyond the scope of your license, please use:
Copyright Information
DOANDROIDS DREAM OF COPYRIGHT?:
EXAMINING Al COPYRIGHT OWNERSHIP
GiaJungt
I. INTRODUCTION
If Shakespeare were an android, would we care? Would it make his work
less worthy of praise, or less important to society? If Shakespeare, reincarnated
as an android by a clever programmer, published a new play today, would we
deny that play copyright? As outlandish as this hypothetical may seem, these
are immediate questions about the state of copyright for works generated by
artistic artificial intelligence (AI). The U.S. Patent and Trademark Office
(USPTO) is aware, but uncertain, of the role and copyrightability of Al works.
Already, programmers and companies have been registering for copyright on
works produced by generative All despite the recent imposition of a "human
authorship requirement" in the Compendium of Copyright Practices.2 Because
the Copyright Office, which administers the registration and recording of
copyright, only needs someone to claim that a work is theirs, companies and
programmers have been taking advantage of the lax investigation into claims
of ownership.3 But Naruto v. Slater" and the newest issue of the Compendium
show that if those copyrights were ever challenged, they would likely be
invalidated. Scholarly arguments as to the best formal regimes and a request by
the USPTO for comments6 characterize, but not clarify, this uncertainty. As it
stands now, there is a disparity between what companies are doing in practice
and what the Copyright Office allows on paper.
DOI: https://doi.org/10.15779/Z383J3922D
©2020 Gia Jung.
t J.D., University of California, Berkeley, School of Law, Class of 2021.
1. Dani Deahl, The USPTO Wants to Know if Artifidal Intelligence Can Own the Content it
Creates, THE VERGE (Nov. 13, 2019, 1:45 PM), https://www.theverge.com/2019/11/13/
20961788/us-government-ai-copyright-patent-trademark-office-notice-artificial-intelligence.
2. U.S. COPYRIGHT OFFICE, COMPENDIUM OF U.S. COPYRIGHT OFFICE PRACTICES
313.2 (3d ed. 2014).
3. See, e.g., infra note 35.
4. Naruto v. Slater, No. 15-cv-04324-WHO, 2016 U.S. Dist. LEXIS 11041, 2016 WL
362231 (N.D. Cal. Jan. 28, 2016), affd, 888 F.3d 418 (9th Cir. 2018).
5. See, e.g., Kalin Hristov, Artifidal Intelligence and the Copyright Dilemma, 57 IDEA 431
(2017).
6. See Request for Comments on Intellectual Property Protection for Artificial
Intelligence Innovation, 84 Fed. Reg. 58,141 (Oct. 30, 2019).
1152 BERKELEY TECHNOLOGY LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 35:1151
Confusion about what Al is extends beyond the general public into the
field itself. Scholars' and practitioners' definitions vary from broad to narrow
and analogize from aspects of human functions that are also hard to define
such as the ability to learn, consciousness, and self-awareness.13 What is most
generally accepted and has made its way into the Oxford English Dictionary is
that AIs are "computer systems able to perform tasks normally requiring
human intelligence, such as visual perception, speech recognition, decision-
making, and translation between languages."" In traditional forms of simple
Al, programmers write many specific instructions for the program to follow
and hope that their instructions are the best way to achieve their end goal.15
Current modes of generative Al are more complex and independent. 16 This
Note focuses on deep learning and generative adversarial neural networks as
the two dominant modes of generative Al.
Deep learning and neural networks seek to create programs that behave as
though they are interconnected brain cells. Programmers create multiple layers
of processing "neurons" to allow the Al to learn how to recognize a solution
on its own by looking for signature patterns of appearance, behaviors, or
features at varying scales. 17 Each level of neurons provide insight and passes
that information to the next, more senior level. 18 After learning to recognize
something based off of labeled data or supervised self-learning, deep learning
programs can then apply that knowledge to recognize raw information and
produce outcomes based on those understandings.19
Generative adversarial neural networks (GANs) set two neural networks
against each other to improve the quality of the results. One generates
imitations of the target material, and one evaluates whether or not the
productions are forgeries. Learning in tandem, as the latter gets better at
detecting forgeries, the former must become better at creating them.20 In
contrast to deep learning, GANs do not rely on a large amount of training data,
as the interaction between the two networks itself creates a large amount of
data from a limited source that continues to be cross-checked against each
other."
1. Artistic and Creative GenerativeAl
By their very design, deep learning and GANs (hereinafter generative AI)
seek to imitate the process of human learning and creativity. Consequently,
they produce creative works that are outside the control of the original
programmer. Some scholars, including Professor Jane Ginsburg, dismiss the
concept of Al authorship outright, claiming that Al is a mere tool, and its
results are absolutely dependent on the inputs of the programmer.22 If this
were the case, the extensive scholarship, debate, and calls for input by the
USPTO would be moot; copyright already protects machine created works
where there is creative input or intervention from a human author.23 The issue
at hand arises because the machines described here are generating works with
an increasing level of independence from human intervention. And, as others
have noted, the incorporation of randomness into a generative Al means it is
only constrained to the same parameters as a human author-grammar,
18. See Simon L6bfwander, About Artifidal Intelligence, Neural Networks, & Deep Learning
AYiMA (Jan. 24, 2017), https://www.ayima.com/blog/artificial-intelligence-neural-networks-
deep-learning.html.
19. Id
20. Bernard Marr, Arifidal Intelligence Explained: What are GenerativeAdversarial Networks
(GANs)?, FORBES (June 12, 2019, 12:23 AM), https://www.forbes.com/sites/bernardmarr/
2019/06/12/ artificial-intelligence-explained-what-are-generative-adversarial-networks-gans
/
#32aad65a7e00.
21. Id
22. Jane C. Ginsburg & Luke Ali Budiardjo, Authors and Machines, 34 BERKELEY TECH.
L.J. 343, 396 (2019).
23. U.S. COPYRIGHT OFFICE, sufpra note 2, 313.2.
2020] DO ANDROIDS DREAM OF COPYRIGHT? 1155
cohesion, and genre-specific devices.24 To that end, it could be said that in this
context, the programmer has as much claim to an AI's work as Shakespeare
does to any iteration of the star-crossed lovers narrative.25
This Note specifically addresses artistic generative Al. These types of Al
will consistently be referred to as "creative" or "artistic" as a way of reflecting
the independent process of recognition, analysis, and generation that the Al
undergoes to produce a unique work. The three below examples illustrate the
generative Al referenced throughout this Note. The first, Chris Rodley's
"Deep Dinosaur" (Figure 1) produces novel and striking images by combining
two sets of inputs-here, vintage flowers and dinosaurs. 26 Rodley and his Deep
Dinosaurs are not the product of a large project like Google's Deepmind, but
an independent creative project undertaken by a PhD candidate at the
University of Sydney. 27 Using a technique known as style transfer or deep style,
the Al learns to recognize characteristics of images, then reproduce them,
synthesizing the two characteristics to produce a recognizable amalgam. 28
24. See Annemarie Bridy, Coding Creativity: Copyright and the Arifidally Intelligent Author,
2012 STAN. TECH. L. REv. 5, 12 (2012).
25. By this, I mean works like High SchoolMusical(instead of feuding families, high-school
cliques) and West Side Story (instead of feuding families, rival New York gangs) wherein the
conceit is the same, but a court would likely not consider them derivative works of Romeo and
Juliet. See also Nichols v. Universal Pictures Corporation, 45 F.2d 119 (2d Cir. 1930).
26. Rodley, supra note 15.
27. Chris Rodley, Me, CHRIS RODLEY, https://chrisrodley.com/me/ (last visited Feb. 9,
2020).
28. Rodley, supra note 15.
1156 BERKELEY TECHNOLOGY LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 35:1151
29. Luke Dormehl, Move Over, Shakespeare: This Sonnet-Writing A.I. is the Poet We Need,
DIGITAL TRENDS (July 30, 2018, 12:32 PM), https://www.digitaltrends.com/cool-tech/ai-
generates-shakespearean-sonnets/.
30. Jey Han Lau, Trevor Cohn, Timothy Baldwin, Julian Brooke, and Adam Hammond,
Deep-speare:A Joint NeuralModel of Poetic Language, Meter and Rhyme, 56 PROC. ANN. MEETING
Ass'N FOR COMPUTATIONAL LINGUISTICS 1948 (2018).
31. Id. (noting that a literature expert was not fooled-the stress, rhyme, and meter were
all human-passable but the Al underperformed on readability and emotion).
2020] DO ANDROIDS DREAM OF COPYRIGHT? 1157
Congress "[t]o promote the [p]rogress of [s]cience and useful [a]rts, by securing
for limited [t]imes to [a]uthors and [i]nventors the exclusive [r]ight to their
respective [w]ritings and [d]iscoveries." 36 This order, written intentionally
broadly, 37 does not explicitly preclude non-human authors. However, the
concept of "romantic authorship," in which creativity can only stem from "an
individual creative personality, a solitary originator of stylistically consistent
works," has long been the guiding concept for understanding how authorship
and creativity interact.38 As a result, disputes in the copyright field have
developed over the scope of what constitutes "authors" and "writings" when
it is not clear that the author was entirely human.
A. PHOTOGRAPHY AND TORAH SOFT-EXTENDING COPYRIGHT FROM
MACHINE TO MAN
text or musical works were a far cry from the word processing capabilities
implied by the Commission. 54 In particular, the OTA report referenced the
"blurring of the distinction between the copyrighted work and its product." 55
The report concluded by suggesting that interactive computer programs, if not
considered co-authors of the output produced, at least raised several troubling
questions of copyright ownership and creativity requirements. 56
U.S. case law has not yet dealt with the copyrightability of an artistic work
produced by Al. 57 However, a Southern District of New York case, Torah Soft
Ltd. v. Drosnin,51 comes within the realm of dealing with the output of an
algorithm. Torah Soft, makers of a biblical-code-finding algorithm, sued over
infringement of printouts of output generated by their computer program. 59
According to Bible code researchers, the Hebrew Bible is purported to be
embedded with a code that is revealed by finding words and phrases which
appear in the Bible at equidistant letter skips. 60 This software analyzed and
found these code words and phrases. 61 Interestingly, this court did not concern
itself with authorship. The court suggested in passing that copyright protection
afforded to the computer program may also extend to the output files. If the
program does the "lion's share of the work" in creating the output files and
the end-user's input is "marginal," then it follows that the protection extends. 62
Regardless, the court focused on whether the outputs contained protectable
elements. 6 Because the software was made to comply with religious rules that
were functional in nature, the court determined that the outputs were also
functional and therefore not protectable. 64
54. Id.
55. Id.
56. Id.
57. This statement is accurate as of December 2019. But see BETA WRITER, LITHIUM-
ION BATTERIES: A MACHINE-GENERATED SUMMARY OF CURRENT RESEARCH (2019) (a
machine-generated book that claims copyright but is not registered in the U.S. Copyright
Office's Public Catalog); Leo Kelion, Al system 'shouldbe recognisedas inventor,' BBC NEWS (Aug.
1, 2019), https://www.bbc.com/news/technology-49191645 ("[wo professors from the
University of Surrey have teamed up with the Missouri-based inventor of Dabus Al to file
patents in the system's name with the relevant authorities in the UK, Europe and US.").
58. 136 F. Supp. 2d 276 (S.D.N.Y 2001).
59. Id. at 280.
60. Id.
61. Id.
62. Id. at 283.
63. Id. at 283-84.
64. Id. at 287.
2020] DO ANDROIDS DREAM OF COPYRIGHT? 1161
Another interesting line of cases that involve non-human works are those
dealing with psychography, or automatic writing. Psychography is the
production of writing or drawing supposedly by a spiritual agent, in which the
human is merely a scribe. 65 Although parties seeking copyright protection in
these cases claim that authorship actually lies with non-human, usually celestial
or spiritual, beings, courts have found a sufficient nexus to human creativity
to sustain copyright.66
In each of these cases, courts apply Feist Publications, Inc., v. Rural Telephone
Service Co. 67 to determine whether a compilation possesses the requisite
originality for copyright protection. In Feist, the Court established that
copyright demanded a minimal degree of creativity, which did not include an
alphabetically arranged phonebook. 68 Nonetheless, compilations of facts may
be copyrightable if arranged creatively, i.e., beyond a merely functional
arrangement.6' Referencing Burrow-Giles, the Court held that an author who
claims infringement must prove the existence of "intellectual production, of
thought, and conception." 70 This showing can be demonstrated through active
and intentional choices, where changes were not accidental or externally
motivated. 71 Feist thus sets a low bar for determining whether a work is creative
or merely functional.
Along these lines, the Ninth Circuit in UrantiaFound. v. Maaherra72 upheld
73
a copyright granted on behalf of a "non-human" author. There, the claimed
work was dictated by a deity listed as "the Divine Counselor, the Chief of the
Corps of Superuniverse Personalities, and the Chief of the Archangels of
Nebadon." 74 It was transcribed by the human whose name ended up on the
copyright. 75 Pushing past the non-human element, the court found that the
originality requirement necessary for a valid copyright was satisfied because
the human beings who "compiled, selected, coordinated, and arranged" the
book did so "in such a way that the resulting work as a whole constitutes an
original work of authorship." 76
A similar case, Penguin Books U.S.A., Inc. v. New Christian Church of Full
Endeavor, Ltd77 held that, "[a]s a matter of law, dictation from a non-human
source should not be a bar to copyright." 78 There, a "Voice" the transcriber
identified as Jesus dictated a manuscript and gave legal advice.79 According to
the author, Jesus advised that the copyright page should not have the author's
name in case people confused the copyright author with the actual author
(Jesus and the Holy Spirit). 80 In a compromise, the copyright registration listed
the work's author as "[Anonymous] (Helen Schucman)." 81 The court held that,
irrespective of independent editorial judgment in the process of recording the
work, copyright could subsist in a non-human work so long as there is a
sufficient human nexus. Helen's acknowledgement of her involvement was
sufficient.82
creativity would best suit a tradition that inextricably intertwines the concepts
of originality with authorship? This Note grapples with these questions to
preclude a similar in-court outcome for Al generated works.
III. ORIGINALITY
The U.S. Compendium of Copyright Practices, citing Feist, states,
"originality is 'the bedrock principle of copyright' and 'the very premise of
copyright law.' "98 To qualify for copyright protection, a work must be original
to the author, which means that the work must be "independently created by
the author," and it must possess "at least some minimal degree of creativity.""
This next Section shows that works by Al satisfy both elements by the nature
of the process of output and by the underlying policies of copyright law.
A. INDEPENDENTLY CREATED
B. MODICUM OF CREATIVITY
105. See Karjalam, supra note 9, at 201; Feist, 499 U.S. at 346 (creating the standard that
creativity is a low bar that works to filter out utilitarian works like an alphabetized phone
book).
106. Trade-Mark Cases, 100 U.S. 82, 94 (1879).
107. Burrow-Giles Lithographic Co. v. Sarony, 111 U.S. 53, 58 (1884).
108. Oren Bracha, The Ideology ofAuthorship Revisited: Authors, Markets, andLiberal Values in
Eary Amencan Copynght, 118 YALE L.J. 186, 188 (2008) (investigating the role of romantic
authorship as a pervasive myth that is cyclically invoked or diminished depending on the
interests at stake).
109. Bridy, supra note 24, at 4.
110. SHAKESPEARE IN LOVE (Universal Pictures 1998) ("A blank page. A hand is writing:
TWELFTH NIGHT. We see Will sitting at his table ... Will looks up from the table. 'And
her name will be... 'Viola.' He looks down at the paper, and writes: 'Viola"').
111. J. M. Pressley, Shakespeare's Source Material, SHAKESPEARE RES. CTR.,
http://www.bardweb.net/content/ac/sources.html (last visited Dec. 13, 2019).
112. See Bracha, supra note 108, at 203 (In Emerson v. Davies, "Justice Story turned to the
market as the sole arbiter of value"). See also Peter Jaszi, Toward a Theory of Copynght: The
1166 BERKELEY TECHNOLOGY LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 35:1151
and 1845 Justice Story decided cases based on a more practical understanding
of the interdependent and cumulative nature of creativity." 3 He relied on "the
market as the only criterion for assessing value."" 4 Justice Story saw that works
imitate and build on each other. A work did not have to add anything new or
culturally significant to be beneficial and protectable. If it was in demand, it
was worthwhile. 115
Justice Holmes was likewise unconcerned with romantic authorship. In
Bleistein a. Donaldson Lithographing,116 Holmes affirmed that courts have no role
in making aesthetic judgements. Using content neutrality and market value, the
Court found that copyright had no threshold requirement of objective
aesthetic value. 117 Holmes focused not on the author or the merit of the
advertisement, but on how the approval of the public eye and aesthetic
elements placed them under statutory protection. 118 Bleistein shows that works
need not be particularly novel or skillful to be worthy of incentivization and
protection.
As illustrated above, courts have competing views of originality. There
remains a split on how and where creativity arises, and how important it is to
copyright. Precedent like Feist, Torah-Soft, and Justice Story's cases suggests AI-
generated works meet the creativity bar. The demand for Al systems like Endel
and Deep Dinosaur demonstrate enough market interest to satisfy Justice
Story's and Justice Holmes' tests for creativity.119 Likewise, the choices Al
systems make when generating content meet Feist and Torah-Soft's standards
for creativity in authorship.120 Unlike an alphabetical phonebook or code-
Metamorphoses ofAuthorsh/p, 1991 DUKE L.J. 455,481-85 (1991) (examining cases in which "the
'[a]uthor' vanishes" in the commercialization of cultural production).
113. Bracha, supra note 108, at 204. See, e.g., Gray v. Russell, 10 F. Cas. 1035 (C.C.D. Mass.
1839) (No. 5,728); Emerson v. Davies, 8 F. Cas. 615 (C.C.D. Mass. 1845) (No. 4,436).
114. Bracha, supra note 108, at 204.
115. Id.
116. 188 U.S. 239 (1903) (holding that commercial lithographs are copyrightable beyond
their mere commercial value).
117. Bracha, supra note 108, at 200.
118. See Jaszi, supranote 112, at 482.
119. See, e.g., Andrew Liszewski, A NeuralNetwork Turned a Book of Flowers into Shockingjy
Lovely DinosaurArt, GIZMODO (June 19, 2017, 11:27 AM), https://gizmodo.com/a-neural-
network-turned-a-book-of-flowers-into-shocking-1796221045 ("The estate of M.C. Escher
may have just lost its lucrative stranglehold on the dorm room poster market thanks to ... a
deep learning algorithm."); Endel.io, supra note 33 ("[Endel] will be introduced to a larger
audience through the extensive reach of the Arts Music division's marketing and distribution
resources . . . with investors including Amazon Alexa Fund, Avex Inc., Major Lazer's
Jillionaire, Plus 8 Equity Partners, Kima Ventures, Impulse Ventures, and world-famous DJ
La Fleur.").
120. See supra Section IIB; see also Karjalam, supra note 9, at 172.
2020] DO ANDROIDS DREAM OF COPYRIGHT? 1167
IV. AUTHORSHIP
Like creativity, authorship's reliance on the role of the romantic author has
created discomfort with recognizing machine produced works. The 2017
update to the Compendium on Copyright Practices repeatedly makes very clear
that a human author must have created the work to be copyrighted.1
"
However, prior to Naruto and the 2017 edition of the Compendium,
authorship was always impliedly, but not explicitly, human." Specifically, that
definition states, "the creator of the original expression in a work is its author.
The author is also the owner of copyright unless there is a written agreement
... In cases of works made for hire, the employer ... is considered to be the
author."13 2 Copyright law does not distinguish between individuals,
corporations, or metaphysical beings for the incentivization of aesthetic works.
Al can and should fit into this regime. The next Section explains how lessons
from the works made for hire doctrine can ground Al authorship as a viable
concept.
A. LESSONS FROM THE WORKS FOR HIRE REGIME
The works made for hire (WMFH) regime is an exception to the rule that
only the author can rightfully claim copyright. If a work is made for hire, an
127. See, e.g., BENJAMIN, SUNSPRING (an Al produced science fiction screenplay that
repeats the line "I don't know"').
128. Michael Nordine, Watch 'Sunspring ' a Short Sd-Fi Film Written by an Atifidal Intelligence
Algorithm, INDIEWIRE (June 9, 2016, 3:10 PM), https://www.indiewire.com/2016/06/watch-
sunspring-sci-fi-artificial-intelligence-ai-written-1201687033/.
129. Liszewski, supra note 119.
130. U.S. COPYRIGHT OFFICE, supra note 2, 302, 306, 313.2, 803.5(C), 808.7(C)
(wherever authors are mentioned, the human author requirement is reiterated: the cited
sections are the human authorship requirement itself as well as examples of where it arises
throughout the Compendium).
131. See Definitions, U.S. COPYRIGHT OFFICE, http://www.copyright.gov/help/faq-
definitions.html (last visited Feb. 11, 2020).
132. Id.
2020] DO ANDROIDS DREAM OF COPYRIGHT? 1169
141. The Ninth Circuit in Naruto v. Slater noted that, although courts have allowed
corporations to sue, corporations "are formed and owned by humans; they are not formed or
owned by animals." Nevertheless, this distinction made by the court only serves to illuminate
how corporations under the WMFH regime are interpreted as non-human human entities
nonetheless entitled to legal rights. 888 F.3d 418, 426 n.9 (9th Cir. 2018). See Bridy, supra note
24, at 26 ("The work made for hire doctrine is a more fitting framework within which to situate
the problem of Al authorship because it represents an existing mechanism for directly vesting
ownership of a copyright in a legal person who is not the author-in-fact of the work in
question.").
142. See Bridy, supra note 24, at 26 ("the work made for hire doctrine acknowledges a
disidentity between the author-in-fact (the employee or contractor) and the author-in-law (the
employer or other person for whom the work was made)").
143. Bracha, supranote 108, at 260-61.
144. Bridy, supra note 24, at 22.
145. U.S. COPYRIGHT OFFICE, supra note 2, at 1.
2020] DO ANDROIDS DREAM OF COPYRIGHT? 1171
Under the current copyright regime, Al works are in the public domain.
Even though it is the official status quo, enforcing it would likely mean
heightened scrutiny on behalf of the Copyright Office to ensure that
programmers are not copyrighting Al generated works, as they currently are.
Proponents of this model claim that incentive is maintained in two ways.152
First, because programmers can register copyright on the Al software itself,
there is no logical reason for furthering the stream of ownership down to the
146. Hong Kong Copyright Ordinance, (1997) Cap. 528, 40, 44, 11(3), 17(6).
147. Copyright (Amendment) Act, 1994, No. 38, Acts of Parliament, 1994 2(vi) (India).
148. Copyright And Related Rights Act 2000 (Act No. 28/2000) (Ir.) 21(f), available at
http://www.irishstatutebook.ie/eli/2000/act/28/section/21/enacted/en/html#sec21,
archived athttps://perma.cc/XWA4-D7QP.
149. Copyright Act 1994, s 5(2)(a) (N.Z.).
150. Each country's statutory language either replicates or closely matches the United
Kingdom's, where "[i]n the case of a literary, dramatic, musical, or artistic work which is
computer-generated, the author shall be taken to be the person by whom the arrangements
necessary for the creation of the work are undertaken," and only differ in the term granted-
either seventy or fifty years from the date of creation. Copyright, Designs and Patents Act
1988, c. 1, 9(3), 12(2) (Eng.).
151. Andres Guadamuz, Artificial intel/gence and copyright, WIPO MAG. (Oct. 2017),
https://www.wipo.int/wipo-magazine/en/2017/05/article_0003.html.
152. Ana Ramalho, Will Robots Rule the (Artistic) World?A ProposedModelfor the Legal Status
of Creationsby ArtificialIntelgence Systems, 21 J. INTERNET L. 11, 21-22.
1172 BERKELEY TECHNOLOGY LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 35:1151
153. Id.
154. Id.
155. Id.
156. See Kristen Senz, Are Paywalls Saving Newspapers?, HARVARD Bus. SCH. WORKING
KNOWLEDGE (July 8, 2019), https://hbswk.hbs.edu/item/are-paywalls-saving-newspapers;
see also Mike Masnick, The Media's Paywall Obsession Will End In DisasterForMost, TECHDIRT
(May 8, 2018, 9:37 AM), https://www.techdirt.com/articles/20180506/11501539779/
medias-paywall-obsession-will-end-disaster-most.shtml ("It's not that we think that paywalls
are somehow "bad," but that (1) for most publications, they won't actually work and (2) they
are quite frequently counterproductive.").
157. Adi Robertson, Inside Patreon, The Economic Engine Of Internet Culture, THE VERGE
(Aug. 3, 2017, 11:36 AM), https://www.theverge.com/2017/8/3/16084248/patreon-profile-
jack-conte-crowdfunding-art-politics-culture.
158. See, e.g., Phil Wang, Phil Wang is creating This Person Does Not Exist, PATREON, https://
www.patreon.com/lucidrains (last visited Feb. 11, 2020) (the creator of
thispersondoesnotexist.com currently has seventeen patrons at $37 dollars a month as of
February 2020).
2020] DO ANDROIDS DREAM OF COPYRIGHT? 1173
159. See Music Licensing ModerniZation Act, U.S. COPYRIGHT OFFICE, https://
www.copyright.gov/music-modernization/115/ (last visited Feb. 11, 2020).
160. See Andrew J. Wu, From Video Games to Artificial Intelligence: Assigning Copyright
Ownership to Works Generated by Increasingly Sophisticated Computer Programs, 25 AIPLA Q.J. 131
(1997).
161. Hristov, supranote 5, at 447.
162. See, e.g., id. at 445.
163. 17 U.S.C. 201(b) (2018).
1174 BERKELEY TECHNOLOGY LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 35:1151
to the programmer, the incentive clearly rewards the work done to create the
Al, and also ensures that liability for infringement falls on the person best
placed to prevent it.
But some scholars, like Professor Shlomit Yanisky-Ravid, suggest that
when users interact with generative Al, they should be considered the owners
of the works. 164 For tool-like Al, this makes sense, because the user is doing
the lion's share of the work. But these works can already receive copyright
protection because they involve substantial human creativity. 165 When it comes
to truly generative works, it is unfair to attribute copyright to a user. Unless
mitigated through licensing or contract, an unaware user clicking through a site
like thispersondoesnotexist.com166 could suddenly be on the hook for an
infringing work that they had no part in producing, other than clicking
"generate."
This model also acknowledges the issue of protection term length. A
traditional work is protected by copyright for the life of the author plus seventy
years. 167 The term of copyright protection of a work made for hire is ninety-
five years from the date of publication or one hundred twenty years from the
date of creation, whichever expires first. 168 While still an excessively long
period amount of time for Al works to be protected, this explicit limit
nonetheless speaks to fairness within the copyright system and ensures works
eventually enter the public domain.
This model aims to quickly address protecting Al works using an existing
copyright mechanism. However, the Supreme Court has suggested that the
WMFH doctrine is very limited in scope, and applies only where "Congress
has expressed a clear and explicit intent to override section 102."169 Because
implementing such a substantial change to the doctrine would require new
legislation, it seems ineffective to try and push Al into a regime that is primarily
about assignation of agency. 170 As of yet, Al are not sentient and do not have
agency-so it is incongruous to incorporate them in a regime that requires a
164. Yanisky-Ravid, supra note 140, at 707 ("[W]e should view Al systems as working for
the users, and hence the users should bear accountability for the systems' production, in
addition to the benefits thereof").
165. See supra Section IIB.
166. THIS PERSON DOES NOT EXIST, https://thispersondoesnotexist.com/ (last visited
Feb. 11, 2020) (a web-based GAN that generates a new human face each time the site is
refreshed).
167. U.S. COPYRIGHT OFFICE, WORKS MADE FOR HIRE, supra note 133, at 3.
168. Id.
169. Yanisky-Ravid, supranote 140, at 715.
170. See U.S. COPYRIGHT OFFICE, WORKS MADE FOR HIRE, supranote 133, at 2 (devoting
a section to "Agency Law").
2020] DO ANDROIDS DREAM OF COPYRIGHT? 1175
clearly distinguished within the text of the law to limit disputes arising out of
ambiguity.
B. PROPOSED MODEL: Al AS THE AUTHOR-IN-FACT AND THE
PROGRAMMER AS THE AUTHOR-IN-LAW
This Note's proposed model lists the Al as the author-in-fact and the
programmer as the author-in-law. This distinction serves to explicitly indicate
that Al generated works will be treated differently than traditional
copyrightable works and allows the Copyright Office to easily delineate
between the two. This model would include a term limit-either fifty years to
meet international standards 178 or fewer depending on what is deemed
equitable by the legislature. For fair allocation of benefits and risks, the
programmer, not the user, is explicitly listed as the author. Thus, the person
reaping rights-based incentives also faces liability if their program is faulty. This
model specifically incentivizes creators of generative Al who would be unable
to monetize their software without monetizing the output.
Creators are already copyrighting their Al generated works and profiting
off them. But there is no mechanism for enforcing the right against
infringement nor does the term of life of the programmer plus seventy years
accurately reflect the payoff of time and resources for the process of
generation following the initial creation of the Al. Further, any legal challenge
against a generated work would likely lead to its release into the public domain,
as implied in Naruto v. Slater. A definitive regime needs to be put into place to
clearly delineate the bounds of what rights are and are not applicable to AI-
generated works. As proponents of the WMFH model suggest, it is expedient
to rely on ties to existing U.S. copyright law. This model uses a legal fiction of
authorship parallel to the one put forth by WMFH, in which copyright vests
as a matter of law in someone who is not the author-in-fact. As with the
WMFH and U.K. models, this proposed model would ensure that the market
continues to encourage creators of Al, while the term limit reflects that each
work is less impactful as a human-created work.
Finally, this modification would be made directly to the Copyright Office's
"Copyrightable Authorship" section. Legislation is needed to make any of the
changes listed in the above models (excepting public domain). It is
unproductive for the legislature to decide on an adequate or easy-sounding,
but problematic option, such as WMFH. 179 An independent clause on Al
VI. CONCLUSION
It is important to encourage creative, not just utilitarian, Al. Artistic Al not
only develops the full potential and breadth of Al but provides a point of
insight into what creativity means, how humans reflect on creative works, and
how alternative creative sources can drive new understandings and
innovations. As AI-as-an-industry and source of creative works continues to
expand, the need for clarification and a modified regime is pressing. A patch
fix like adding "human" to authorship requirements or modifying the
definition of "employee" to slip Al into an ill-fitting regime is inefficient. The
coming update needs to keep the policies and historical trajectories behind
copyright in mind. Congress and the courts have altered the doctrine and
requirements in the face of new technologies before-this Note and its
proposed changes argues for a continuing willingness to adapt the law to
technological advances. While AIs do not dream of copyright protection, their
creators and proponents do. They need a copyright regime that adequately
reflects and delineates the protection of that dream.
42 (1982) (explaining that the contractual nature of WMFH imposes limitations on redefining
the meaning of "employee").
1178 BERKELEY TECHNOLOGY LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 35:1151