0% found this document useful (0 votes)
196 views19 pages

Neural Darwinism

Neural Darwinism is a theory proposed by Gerald Edelman that applies Darwinian principles of natural selection to understand brain function. It suggests that neuronal groups in the brain are in constant competition, and those groups whose connections are strengthened through repeated activation are more likely to be preserved. The theory was introduced in Edelman's 1987 book Neural Darwinism and proposes neuronal group selection as the core mechanism underlying brain development and operation. It views the brain as a somatic selective system that evolves through differential selection and amplification of varied neuronal groups, similar to how the immune system adapts via selection of lymphocyte populations.

Uploaded by

ava939
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
196 views19 pages

Neural Darwinism

Neural Darwinism is a theory proposed by Gerald Edelman that applies Darwinian principles of natural selection to understand brain function. It suggests that neuronal groups in the brain are in constant competition, and those groups whose connections are strengthened through repeated activation are more likely to be preserved. The theory was introduced in Edelman's 1987 book Neural Darwinism and proposes neuronal group selection as the core mechanism underlying brain development and operation. It views the brain as a somatic selective system that evolves through differential selection and amplification of varied neuronal groups, similar to how the immune system adapts via selection of lymphocyte populations.

Uploaded by

ava939
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 19

Neural Darwinism

Neural Darwinism is a biological, and more specifically


Darwinian and selectionist, approach to understanding global brain
function, originally proposed by American biologist, researcher and
Nobel-Prize recipient[1] Gerald Maurice Edelman (July 1, 1929 –
May 17, 2014). Edelman's 1987 book Neural Darwinism[2]
introduced the public to the theory of neuronal group selection
(TNGS) – which is the core theory underlying Edelman's
explanation of global brain function.

Owing to the book title, TNGS is most commonly referred to as the


theory of neural Darwinism, although TNGS has roots going back
to Edelman and Mountcastle's 1978 book, The Mindful Brain –
Cortical Organization and the Group-selective Theory of Higher
Brain Function – where Edelman's colleague, the American
neurophysiologist and anatomist Vernon B. Mountcastle (July 15,
1918 – January 11, 2015), describes the columnar structure of the
cortical groups within the neocortex,[3] while Edelman develops his
argument for selective processes operating among degenerate
primary repertoires of neuronal groups.[4] The development of Edelman giving a lecture, September
neural Darwinism was deeply influenced by Edelman's work in the 30, 2010
fields of immunology, embryology, and neuroscience, as well as his
methodological commitment to the idea of selection as the unifying
foundation of the biological sciences.

Introduction to neural Darwinism


Neural Darwinism is really the neural part of the natural philosophical and explanatory framework Edelman
employs for much of his work – Somatic selective systems. Neural Darwinism is the backdrop for a
comprehensive set of biological hypotheses and theories Edelman, and his team, devised that seek to
reconcile vertebrate and mammalian neural morphology, the facts of developmental and evolutionary
biology, and the theory of natural selection[5] into a detailed model of real-time neural and cognitive
function that is biological in its orientation – and, built from the bottom-up, utilizing the variation that shows
up in nature, in contrast to computational and algorithmic approaches that view variation as noise in a
system of logic circuits with point-to-point connectivity.

The book, Neural Darwinism – The Theory of Neuronal Group Selection (1987), is the first in a trilogy of
books that Edelman wrote to delineate the scope and breadth of his ideas on how a biological theory of
consciousness and animal body plan evolution could be developed in a bottom-up fashion. In accordance
with principles of population biology and Darwin's theory of natural selection – as opposed to the top-
down algorithmic and computational approaches that dominated a nascent cognitive psychology at the time.

The other two volumes are Topobiology – An Introduction to Molecular Embryology [6] (1988) with its
morpho-regulatory hypothesis of animal body plan development and evolutionary diversification via
differential expression of cell surface molecules during development; and The Remembered Present – A
Biological Theory of Consciousness[7] (1989) – a novel biological approach to understanding the role and
function of "consciousness" and its relation to cognition and behavioral physiology.

Edelman would write four more books for the general lay public, explaining his ideas surrounding how the
brain works and consciousness arises from the physical organization of the brain and body – Bright Air,
Brilliant Fire – On the Matter of the Mind[8] (1992), A Universe of Consciousness – How Matter Becomes
Imagination[9] (2000) with Giulio Tononi, Wider Than The Sky – The Phenomenal Gift of
Consciousness[10] (2004), and Second Nature – Brain Science and Human Knowledge[11] (2006).

Neural Darwinism is an exploration of biological thought and philosophy as well as fundamental science;
Edelman being well-versed in the history of science, natural philosophy & medicine, as well as robotics,
cybernetics, computing & artificial intelligence. In the course of laying out the case for neural Darwinism,
or more properly TNGS, Edelman delineates a set of concepts for rethinking the problem of nervous
system organization and function – all-the-while, demanding a rigorously scientific criteria for building the
foundation of a properly Darwinian, and therefore biological, explanation of neural function, perception,
cognition, and global brain function capable of supporting primary and higher-order consciousness.

Population thinking – somatic selective systems


Edelman was inspired by the successes of fellow Nobel laureate[12]
Frank MacFarlane Burnet and his clonal selection theory (CST) of
acquired antigen immunity by differential amplification of pre-
existing variation within the finite pool of lymphocytes in the
immune system. The population of variant lymphocytes within the
body mirrored the variant populations of organisms in the ecology.
Pre-existing diversity is the engine of adaption in the evolution of
populations.

Illustration of disulfide bridges (red)


"It is clear from both evolutionary and immunological linking the light (L, green) and heavy
theory that in facing an unknown future, the (H, purple) chains of Immunoglobulin
fundamental requirement for successful adaption is G (IgG) antibody. The variable (V)
preexisting diversity".[13] – Gerald M. Edelman (1978) regions are located at the antigen-
binding end; and, the constant (C)
domains form the primary frame of
Edelman recognizes the explanatory range of Burnet's utilization of the IgG molecule. Another disulfide
Darwinian principles in describing the operations of the immune bridge holds the two symmetrical
system - and, generalizes the process to all cell populations of the units made up of a light chain
organism. He also comes to view the problem as one of recognition (VL+CL) and a heavy chain
and memory from a biological perspective, where the distinction (VH+CH1+CH2+CH3) together to
and preservation of self vs. non-self is vital to organismal integrity. form the completed antibody.[a]

Neural Darwinism, as TNGS, is a theory of neuronal group


selection that retools the fundamental concepts of Darwin and Burnet's theoretical approach. Neural
Darwinism describes the development and evolution of the mammalian brain and its functioning by
extending the Darwinian paradigm into the body and nervous system.

Antibodies and NCAM – the emerging understanding of somatic selective


systems
Edelman was a medical researcher, physical chemist, immunologist,
and aspiring neuroscientist when he was awarded the 1972 Nobel
Prize in Physiology or Medicine (shared with Rodney Porter of
Great Britain). Edelman's part of the prize was for his work
revealing the chemical structure of the vertebrate antibody by
cleaving the covalent disulfide bridges that join the component
chain fragments together, revealing a pair of two-domain light
chains and four-domain heavy chains. Subsequent analysis revealed
the terminal domains of both chains to be variable domains
responsible for antigen recognition.[14]

The work of Porter and Edelman revealed the molecular and


genetic foundations underpinning how antibody diversity was
generated within the immune system. Their work supported earlier
ideas about pre-existing diversity in the immune system put forward
by the pioneering Danish immunologist Niels K. Jerne (December
23, 1911 – October 7, 1994); as well as supporting the work of
Frank MacFarlane Burnet describing how lymphocytes capable of
binding to specific foreign antigens are differentially amplified by
clonal multiplication of the selected preexisting variants following
antigen discovery.

Edelman would draw inspiration from the mechano-chemical


aspects of antigen/antibody/lymphocyte interaction in relation to
recognition of self-nonself; the degenerate population of
Clonal selection theory (CST):
lymphocytes in their physiological context; and the bio-theoretical
foundations of this work in Darwinian terms.
hematopoietic stem cells (1)
differentiate and undergo genetic
By 1974, Edelman felt that immunology was firmly established on
rearrangement to produce a
solid theoretical grounds descriptively, was ready for quantitative
population of cells possessing a
experimentation, and could be an ideal model for exploring
wide range of pre-existing diversity
evolutionary selection processes within an observable time
with respect to antibody expression
(2). Lymphocytes expressing
period.[15]
antibodies that would lead to
His studies of immune system interactions developed in him an
autoimmunity are filtered from the
awareness of the importance of the cell surface and the membrane-
population (3), while the rest of the
population represents a degenerate
embedded molecular mechanisms of interactions with other cells
pool of diversity (4) where antigen-
and substrates. Edelman would go on to develop his ideas of
selected variants (5) can be
topobiology around these mechanisms – and, their genetic and
differentially amplified in response epigenetic regulation under the environmental conditions.
(6). Once the antigen has been
During a foray into molecular embryology and neuroscience, in
cleared, the responding population
will decrease, but not by as much as
1975, Edelman and his team went on to isolate the first neural cell-
it was amplified, leaving behind a
adhesion molecule (N-CAM), one of the many molecules that hold
boosted capacity to respond to the animal nervous system together. N-CAM turned out to be an
future incursions by the antigen – a important molecule in guiding the development and differentiation
form of enhanced recognition and of neuronal groups in the nervous system and brain during
memory within the system. embryogenesis. To the amazement of Edelman, genetic sequencing
revealed that N-CAM was the ancestor of the vertebrate
antibody[16] produced in the aftermath of a set of whole genome
duplication events at the origin of vertebrates[17] that gave rise to the entire super-family of immunoglobulin
genes.
Edelman reasoned that the N-CAM molecule which is used for self-self recognition and adherence between
neurons in the nervous system gave rise to their evolutionary descendants, the antibodies, who evolved self-
nonself recognition via antigen-adherence at the origins of the vertebrate antibody-based immune system. If
clonal selection was the way the immune system worked, perhaps it was ancestral and more general – and,
operating in the embryo and nervous system.

Variation in biological systems – degeneracy, complexity, robustness,


and evolvability

Degeneracy, and its relationship to variation, is a key concept in


neural Darwinism. The more we deviate from an ideal form, the
more we are tempted to describe the deviations as imperfections.
Edelman, on the other hand, explicitly acknowledges the structural
and dynamic variability of the nervous system. He likes to contrast
the differences between redundancy in an engineered system and
degeneracy in a biological system. He proceeds to demonstrate how
the "noise" of the computational and algorithmic approach is
actually beneficial to a somatic selective system by providing a
wide, and degenerate, array of potential recognition elements.[18]
The degeneracy of the genetic code
Edelman's argument is that in an engineered system, buffers biological systems from the
effects of random mutation. The
a known problem is confronted ingenuous 1964 Nirenberg and Leder
a logical solution is devised experiment would identify the mRNA
codons, a triplet sequence of
an artifice is constructed to implement the resolution to
ribonucleotides, that coded for each
the problem
amino acid; thus elucidating the
To insure the robustness of the solution, critical components are universal genetic code within the
DNA when the transcription process
replicated as exact copies. Redundancy provides a fail-safe backup
was taken into account. Changes in
in the event of catastrophic failure of an essential component but it
the third position of the codon, the
is the same response to the same problem once the substitution has
wobble position, often result in the
been made.
same amino acid, and oftentimes
the choice comes down to purine or
If the problem is predictable and known ahead of time, redundancy
pyrimidine only when a choice must
works optimally. But biological systems face an open and
be made. Similar, but variant, codon
unpredictable arena of spacetime events of which they have no
sequences tend to yield similar
foreknowledge of. It is here where redundancy fails – when the
classes of amino acid – polar to
designed answer is to the wrong problem...
polar, non-polar to non-polar, acidic
to acidic, and basic to basic
Variation fuels degeneracy – and degeneracy provides somatic
residues.
selective systems with more than one way to solve a problem; as
well as, the ability to solve more than one problem the same way.
This property of degeneracy has the effect of making the system
more adaptively robust in the face of unforeseen contingencies, such as when one particular solution fails
unexpectedly – there are still other unaffected pathways that can be engaged to result in the comparable
final outcome. Early on, Edelman spends considerable time contrasting degeneracy vs. redundancy,
bottom-up vs. top-down processes, and selectionist vs. instructionist explanations of biological phenomena.

Rejection of computational models, codes, and point-to-point wiring


Edelman was well aware of
the earlier debate in
immunology between the
instructionists, who believed
the lymphocytes of the
immune system learned or
was instructed about the
antigen and then devised a
response; and the
selectionists, who believed
The four major classes of biological
that the lymphocytes already amino acids – polar (hydrophilic),
Relationships between degeneracy, contained the response to nonpolar (hydrophobic), acidic, and
complexity, robustness, and the antigen within the
evolvability – 1) degeneracy is the basic side chain residues. The
existing population that was amino acid backbone is amino group
source of robustness. 2) degeneracy
differentially amplified linked to an alpha carbon, on which
is positively correlated with
within the population upon resides the side chain residue and a
complexity. 3) degeneracy increases
contact with the antigen. hydrogen atom, that is connected to
evolvability. 4) evolvability is a
And, he was well aware that a terminal carboxylate group. Aside
prerequisite for complexity. 5)
the selectionist had the from the disulfide bridge, there are
complexity increases to improve
evidence on their side. quite a number of degenerate
robustness. 6) evolvability emerges
combinations of sidechain residues
from robustness.
Edelman's theoretical that make up the tertiary structure
approach in Neural (H-bonding, hydrophobic, and ionic
Darwinism was conceived bridges) in the determination of
of in opposition to top-down algorithmic, computational, and protein structure.
instructionist approaches to explaining neural function. Edelman
seeks to turn the problems of that paradigm to advantage instead;
thereby highlighting the difference between bottom-up processes like we see in biology vis a vis top-down
processes like we see in engineering algorithms. He sees neurons as living organisms working in
cooperative and competitive ways within their local ecology and rejects models that see the brain in terms
of computer chips or logic gates in an algorithmically organized machine.

Edelman's commitment to the Darwinian underpinnings of biology, his emerging understanding of the
evolutionary relationships between the two molecules he had worked with, and his background in
immunology lead him to become increasingly critical and dissatisfied with attempts to describe the
operation of the nervous system and brain in computational or algorithmic terms.

Edelman explicitly rejects computational approaches to explaining biology as non-biological. Edelman


acknowledges that there is a conservation of phylogenetic organization and structure within the vertebrate
nervous system, but also points out that locally natural diversity, variation and degeneracy abound. This
variation within the nervous system is disruptive for theories based upon strict point-to-point connectivity,
computation, or logical circuits based upon codes. Attempts to understand this noise present difficulties for
top-down algorithmic approaches - and, deny the fundamental facts of the biological nature of the problem.

Edelman perceived that the problematic and annoying noise of the computational circuit-logic paradigm
could be reinterpreted from a population biology perspective – where that variation in the signal or
architecture was actually the engine of ingenuity and robustness from a selectionist perspective.

Completing Darwin's program – the problems of evolutionary


and developmental morphology
In Topobiology, Edelman reflects upon Darwin's search for the connections between morphology and
embryology in his theory of natural selection. He identifies four unresolved problems in the development
and evolution of morphology that Darwin thought important:[19]

Explaining the finite number of body plans manifested since the Precambrian.
Explaining large-scale morphological changes over relatively short periods of geological
time.
Understanding body size and the basis of allometry.
How adaptive fitness can explain selection that leads to emergence of complex body
structures.

Later, In Bright Air, Brilliant Fire, Edelman describes what he calls Darwin's Program for obtaining a
complete understanding of the rules of behavior and form in evolutionary biology.[20] He identifies four
necessary requirements:

An account of the effects of heredity on behavior – and behavior, on heredity.


An account of how selection influences behavior – and, how behavior influences selection.
An account of how behavior is enabled and constrained by morphology.
An account of how morphogenesis occurs in development and evolution.

It is important to notice that these requirements are not directly stated in terms of genes, but heredity instead.
This is understandable considering that Darwin himself appears to not be directly aware of the importance
Mendelian genetics. Things had changed by the early 1900s, the Neodarwinian synthesis had unified the
population biology of Mendelian inheritance with Darwinian natural selection. By the 1940s, the theories
had been shown to be mutually consistent and coherent with paleontology and comparative morphology.
The theory came to be known as the modern synthesis on the basis of the title of the 1942 book Evolution:
The Modern Synthesis by Julian Huxley.[21]

The modern synthesis really took off with the discovery of the structural basis of heredity in the form of
DNA. The modern synthesis was greatly accelerated and expanded with the rise of the genomic sciences,
molecular biology, as well as, advances in computational techniques and the power to model population
dynamics. But, for evolutionary-developmental biologists, there was something very important missing... –
and, that was the incorporation of one of the founding branches of biology, embryology. A clear
understanding of the pathway from germ to zygote to embryo to juvenile and adult was the missing
component of the synthesis. Edelman, and his team, were positioned in time and space to fully capitalize on
these technical developments and scientific challenges – as his research progressed deeper and deeper into
the cellular and molecular underpinnings of the neurophysiological aspects of behavior and cognition from
a Darwinian perspective.

Edelman reinterprets the goals of "Darwin's program" in terms of the modern understanding about genes,
molecular biology, and other sciences that weren't available to Darwin. One of his goals is reconciling the
relationships between genes in a population (genome) which lie in the germ line (sperm, egg, and fertilized
egg); and the individuals in a population who develop degenerate phenotypes (soma) as they transform
from an embryo into an adult who will eventually procreate if adaptive. Selection acts on phenotypes
(soma), but evolution occurs within the species genome (germ).

Edelman follows the work of the highly influential American geneticist and evolutionary biologist Richard
Lewontin (March 29, 1929 – July 4, 2021), drawing particular inspiration from his 1974 book, The Genetic
Basis of Evolutionary Change.[22] Edelman, like Lewontin, seeks a complete description of the
transformations (T) that take us from:[23]
Genome-germ (zygotes) – the paternal and maternal gene contributions are recombined in
the fertilized egg, along with the maternal endowment of proteins, and mRNAs, and other
developmental components, but the individuals newly formed diploid genetic complement is
not in control of the zygote yet; it needs to be activated, or bootstrapped, into the zygotes
ongoing maternally-inherited metabolism and physiology. Shortly after recombination the
zygote proceeds through transformation (T1) to the point where genetic control of the zygote
has been handed off to the individual,
Phenotype-soma (embryo) – the embryo, which transforms (T2) according to the rules that
govern the relationship between the genes, cellular behavior, and the epigenetic
contingencies of nature, into
Phenotype-soma (adult) – an adult, who procreates (T3) with another individual to bring
together a new genetic recombination by each introducing a gamete in the form of
Genome-germ (gametes) – sperm and egg, which contain the haploid genetic contribution of
each parent which is transformed (T4)...
Genome-germ (zygotes) -into a diploid set genes in a fertilized egg, soon to be a newly
individual zygote .

Lewontin's exploration of these transformations between genomic and phenotypic spaces was in terms of
key selection pressures that sculpt the organism over geological evolutionary time scales; but, Edelmans
approach is more mechanical, and in the here and now – focusing on the genetically constrained mechano-
chemistry of the selection processes that guide epigenetic behaviors on the part of cells within the embryo
and adult over developmental time.

Mechano-chemistry, mesenchyme, and epithelia – CAMs & SAMs


in morphoregulatory spacetime
Edelman's isolation of NCAM lead him to theorize on the role of
cell adhesion molecules (CAMs) and substrate adhesion molecules
(SAMs) in the formation of the animal bodyplan in both realtime
and over evolutionary time. Topobiology is primarily dedicated to
this issue that is foundational to the understanding of neural
Darwinism and the formation of the primary repertoire of TNGS.
Mesenchymal-epithelial transitions –
In his regulator hypothesis, Edelman hypothesizes about the role of epithelia to mesenchyme (EMT) and
cell surface molecules in embryogenesis and how shifting mesenchyme to epithelia (MET)
expression of these molecules in time and place within the embryo transitions utilizing CAMs and SAMs
can guide the development of pattern.[24] Later, he will expand the to form epethelia; and, growth
hypothesis into the morpho-regulatory hypothesis.[25] He describes factors and inducers to mediate the
the embryonic cell populations as either organized as mesenchyme transition to mesenchyme as the
or epetheilia. CAMs and SAMs are withdrawn or
localized on the cell membrane.
Edelman characterizes the two population types as follows:

Epithelia – a population of cells that are organized into coherent tissues, that have well
established CAM patterns; as well as a stable pattern of substrate adhesion between the
cells and the extracellular matrix.
Mesenchyme – a population of cells that are loosely associated and migratory, that have
retracted (or localized) their CAM and SAM molecules such that they can follow homophilic
and heterophilic gradients within other cell populations of the embryo.
He envisages a CAM, and SAM, driven cycle where cell populations transform back and forth between
mesenchyme and epithelia via epithelial-mesenchymal transformations,[26] as the development of the
embryo proceeds through to the fetal stage. The expression of the CAMs and SAMs is under genetic
control, but the distribution of these molecules on the cell membrane and extracellular matrix is historically
contingent upon epigenetic events, serving as one of the primary bases for generating pre-existing diversity
within the nervous system and other tissues.

The developmental genetic question

There are many developmental questions to be considered, but Edelman is able to succinctly summarize the
problem in a way that will show a clear explanatory path forward for him. The developmental genetic
question defines the problem - and, the theoretical approach for him.

"How does a one-dimensional genetic code specify a three-dimensional animal?" [27] – Gerald
M. Edelman, from the glossary of Topobiology

By 1984, Edelman would be ready to answer this question and combine it with his earlier ideas on
degeneracy and somatic selection in the nervous system. Edelman would revisit this issue in Topobiology
and combine it with an evolutionary approach, seeking a comprehensive theory of body plan formation and
evolution.

The regulator hypothesis

In 1984, Edelman published his regulator hypothesis of CAM and SAM action in the development and
evolution of the animal body plan.

Edelman would reiterate this hypothesis in his Neural Darwinism book in support of the mechanisms for
degenerate neuronal group formation in the primary repertoire. The regulator hypothesis was primarily
concerned with the action of CAMs. He would later expand the hypothesis in Topobiology to include a
much more diverse and inclusive set of morphoregulatory molecules.

The evolutionary question

Edelman realized that in order to truly complete Darwin's program, he would need to link the
developmental question to the larger issues of evolutionary biology.

"How is an answer to the developmental genetic question (q.v.) reconciled with the relatively
rapid changes in form occurring in relatively short evolutionary times?"[28] – Gerald M.
Edelman, from the glossary of Topobiology

The morphoregulator hypothesis


Shortly after publishing his regulator hypothesis, Edelman expanded his vision of pattern formation during
embryogenesis - and, sought to link it to a broader evolutionary framework. His first and foremost goal is to
answer the developmental genetic question followed by the evolutionary question in a clear, consistent, and
coherent manner.

TNGS – the theory of neuronal group selection


Edelman's motivation for developing the theory of neuronal group selection (TNGS) was to resolve "a
number of apparent inconsistencies in our knowledge of the development, anatomy, and physiological
function of the central nervous system."[29] A pressing issue for Edelman was explaining perceptual
categorization without reference to a central observing homunculus or "assuming that the world is
prearranged in an informational fashion."[29]

To free himself of the demands, requirements, and contradictions of information processing model;
Edelman proposes that perceptual categorization operates by the selection of neuronal groups organized
into variant networks that are differentially amplified of their responses in conjunction with hedonic
feedback over the course of experience, from within a massive population of neuronal groups being
confronted by a chaotic array of sensory input of differing degrees of significance and relevance to the
organism.

Edelman outright rejects the notion of a homunculus, describing it as a "close cousin of the developmental
electrician and the neural decoder", artifacts of the observer-centralized top-down design logic of
information processing approaches. Edelman properly points out that "it is probably a safe guess that most
neurobiologists would view the homunculus as well as dualist solutions (Popper and Eccles 1981) to the
problems of subjective report as being beyond scientific consideration."[30]

Necessary criteria for a selectionist theory of higher brain function

Edelman's first theoretical contribution to neural Darwinism came in 1978, when he proposed his group
selection and phasic reentrant signalling.[4] Edelman lays out five necessary requirements that a biological
theory of higher brain function must satisfy.[31]

The theory should be consistent with the fields of embryology, neuroanatomy, and
neurophysiology.
The theory should account for learning and memory, and temporal recall in a distributed
system.
The theory should account how memory is updated on the basis of realtime experience.
The theory should account for how higher brain systems mediate experience and action.
The theory should account for the necessary, if not sufficient, conditions for the emergence of
awareness.

Organization of the TNGS theory

Neural Darwinism organizes the explanation of TNGS into three parts – somatic selection, epigenetic
mechanisms, and global functions. The first two parts are concerned with how variation emerges through
the interaction of genetic and epigenetic events at the cellular level in response to events occurring at the
level of the developing animal nervous system. The third part attempts to build a temporally coherent model
of globally unitary cognitive function and behavior that emerges from the bottom up through the
interactions of the neuronal groups in real-time.
Edelman organized key ideas of the TNGS theory into three main tenets:

Primary repertoire – developmental formation and selection of neuronal groups;


Secondary repertoire – behavioral and experiential selection leading to changes in the
strength of connections between synaptic populations that bind together neuronal groups;
Reentrant signaling – the synchronous entrainment of reciprocally connected neuronal
groups within sensorimotor maps into ensembles of coherent global activity.

The primary repertoire is formed during the period from the beginning of neurulation to the end of
apoptosis. The secondary repertoire extends over the period synaptogenesis and myelination, but will
continue to demonstrate developmental plasticity throughout life, albeit in a diminished fashion compared to
early development.

The two repertoires deal with the issue of the relationship between genetic and epigenetic processes in
determining the overall architecture of the neuroanatomy – seeking to reconcile nature, nurture, and
variability in the forming the final phenotype of any individual nervous system.

There is no point-to-point wiring that carries a neural code through a computational logic circuit that
delivers the result to the brain because

firstly, the evidence does not lend support to such notion in a manner that is not problematic,
secondly, the noise in the system is too great for a neural code to be coherent,
and third, the genes can only contribute to, and constrain, developmental processes; not
determine them in all their details.

Variation is the inevitable outcome of developmental dynamics.

Reentrant signalling is an attempt to explain how "coherent temporal correlations of the responses of
sensory receptor sheets, motor ensembles, and interacting neuronal groups in different brain regions
occur".[32]

Primary repertoire- developmental selection

The first tenet of TNGS concerns events that are embryonic and run up to the neonatal period. This part of
the theory attempts to account for the unique anatomical diversification of the brain even between
genetically identical individuals. The first tenet proposes the development of a primary repertoire of
degenerate neuronal groups with diverse anatomical connections are established via the historical
contingencies of the primary processes of development. It seeks to provide an explanation of how the
diversity of neuronal group phenotypes emerge from the organism's genotype via genetic and epigenetic
influences that manifest themselves mechano-chemically at the cell surface and determine connectivity.

Edelman list the following as vital to the formation of the primary repertoire of neuronal groups but, also
contributing to their anatomical diversification and variation:

Cell division – there are repeated rounds of cell division in the formation of neuronal
populations
Cell death – there is extensive amounts of pre-programmed cell death that occurs via
apoptosis within the neuronal populations.
Process extension and elimination – the exploratory probing of the embryonic environment
by developing neurons involve process extension and elimination as the neurons detect
molecular gradients on neighboring cell surface membranes and the substrate of the
extracellular matrix.
CAM & SAM action – the mechanochemistry of cell and surface adhesion molecules plays a
key role in the migration and connectivity of neurons as they form neuronal groups within the
overall distributed population.

Two key questions with respect to this issue that Edelman is seeking to answer "in terms of developmental
genetic and epigenetic events" are:[33]

"How does a one-dimensional genetic code specify a three-dimensional animal?"


"How is the answer to this question consistent with the possibility of relatively rapid
morphological change in relatively short periods of evolutionary time?"

Secondary repertoire – experiential selection

The second tenet of TNGS regards postnatal events that govern the development of a secondary repertoire
of synaptic connectivity between higher-order populations of neuronal groups whose formation is driven by
behavioral or experiential selection acting on synaptic populations within and between neuronal groups.
Edelman's notion of the secondary repertoire heavily borrows from work of Jean-Pierre Changeux, and his
associates Philippe Courrège and Antoine Danchin – and, their theory of selective stabilization of
synapses.[34]

Synaptic modification

Once the basic variegated anatomical structure of the primary repertoire of neuronal groups is laid down, it
is more or less fixed. But given the numerous and diverse collection of neuronal group networks, there are
bound to be functionally equivalent albeit anatomically non-isomorphic neuronal groups and networks
capable of responding to certain sensory input. This creates a competitive environment where neuronal
groups proficient in their responses to certain inputs are "differentially amplified" through the enhancement
of the synaptic efficacies of the selected neuronal group network. This leads to an increased probability that
the same network will respond to similar or identical signals at a future time. This occurs through the
strengthening of neuron-to-neuron synapses. These adjustments allow for neural plasticity along a fairly
quick timetable.

Reentry

The third, and final, tenet of TNGS is reentry. Reentrant signalling "is based on the existence of
reciprocally connected neural maps."[32] These topobiological maps maintain and coordinate the real-time
responses of multiple responding secondary repertoire networks, both unimodal and multimodal – and their
reciprocal reentrant connections allow them to "maintain and sustain the spatiotemporal continuity in
response to real-world signals."[32]

The last part of the theory attempts to explain how we experience spatiotemporal consistency in our
interaction with environmental stimuli. Edelman called it "reentry" and proposes a model of reentrant
signaling whereby a disjunctive, multimodal sampling of the same stimulus event correlated in time that
make possible sustained physiological entrainment of distributed neuronal groups into temporally stable
global behavioral units of action or perception. Put another way, multiple neuronal groups can be used to
sample a given stimulus set in parallel and communicate between these disjunctive groups with incurred
latency.

The extended theory of neuronal group selection – the dynamic


core hypothesis
In the aftermath of his publication of Neural Darwinism, Edelman continued to develop and extend his
TNGS theory as well as his regulator hypothesis. Edelman would deal with the morphological issues in
Topobiology and begin to extend the TNGS theory in The Remembered Present. Periodically over the
intervening years, Edelman would release a new update on his theory and the progress made.

In The Remembered Present, Edelman would observe that the mammalian central nervous system seemed
to have two distinct morphologically organized systems – one the limbic-brain stem system which is
primarily dedicated to "appetitive, consumatory, and defensive behavior";[35] The other system is the highly
reentrant thalamocortical system, consisting of the thalamus along with the "primary and secondary sensory
areas and association cortex"[35] which are "linked strongly to exteroceptors and is closely and extensively
mapped in a polymodal fashion."[35]

The limbic-brain stem system - the interior world of signals

The neural anatomy of the hedonic feedback system resides in the brain stem, autonomic, endocrine, and
limbic systems. This system communicates its evaluation of the visceral state to the rest of the central
nervous system. Edelman calls this system the limbic-brain stem system.

The thalamocortical system - the exterior world of signals

The thalamus is the gateway to the neocortex for all senses except olfactory. The spinothalamic tracts bring
sensory information from the periphery to the thalamus, where multimodal sensory information is integrated
and triggers the fast response subcortical reflexive motor responses via the amygdala, basal ganglia,
hypothalamus and brainstem centers. Simultaneously, each sensory modality is also being sent to the cortex
in parallel, for higher-order reflective analysis, multimodal sensorimotor association, and the engagement of
the slow modulatory response that will fine-tune the subcortical reflexes.

The cortical appendages – the organs of succession

In The Remembered Present, Edelman acknowledges the limits of his TNGS theory to model the temporal
succession dynamics of motor behavior and memory. His early attempts at replication automata proved
inadequate to the task of explaining the realtime sequencing and integration of the neuronal group
interactions with other systems of the organism. "Neither the original theory nor simulated recognition
automata deal in satisfactory detail with the successive ordering of events in time mediated by the several
major brain components that contribute to memory, particularly as it relates to consciousness."[36] This
problem lead him to focus on what he called the organs of succession; the cerebellum, basal ganglia, and
hippocampus.

Reception
An early review of the book Neural Darwinism in The New York Review of Books[37] by Israel Rosenfield
invited a lively response on the part of the neurosciences community.[38] Edelman's views would be seen as
an attack on the dominant paradigm of computational algorithms in cognitive psychology and
computational neuroscience – inviting criticism from many corners.

There would be copious complaints about the language difficulty. Some would see Edelman coming across
as arrogant, or an interloper into the field of neuroscience, from neighboring molecular biology. There were
legitimate arguments raised as to how much experimental and observational data had been gathered in
support of the theory at that time. Or, if the theory was even original or not.

But more often, rather than dealing with Edelman's critique of computational approaches, the criticism
would be centered around whether Edelman's system was a truly proper Darwinian explanation.
Nonetheless, Neural Darwinism, both the book and the concept, received fairly broad critical acclaim.

One of the most famous critiques of Neural Darwinism would be the 1989 critical review by Francis Crick,
Neural Edelmanism.[39] Francis Crick based his criticism on the basis that neuronal groups are instructed
by the environment rather than undergoing blind variation. In 1988, the neurophysiologist William Calvin
had proposed true replication in the brain,[40] whereas Edelman opposed the idea of true replicators in the
brain. Stephen Smoliar published another review in 1989.[41]

England, and its neuroscience community, would have to rely on bootleg copies of the book until 1990, but
once the book arrive on English shores, the British social commentator and neuroscientist Steven Rose was
quick to offer both praise and criticism of its ideas, writing style, presumptions and conclusions.[42] The
New York Times writer George Johnson published "Evolution Between the Ears", a critical review of
Gerald Edelman's 1992 book Brilliant Air, Brilliant Fire.[43] In 2014, John Horgan wrote a particular
insightful tribute to Gerald Edelman in Scientific American, highlighting both his arrogance, brilliance, and
idiosyncratic approach to science.[44]

It has been suggested by Chase Herrmann-Pillath that Friedrich Hayek had earlier proposed a similar idea
in his book The Sensory Order: An Inquiry into the Foundations of Theoretical Psychology, published in
1952.[45] Other leading proponents of a selectionist proposals include Jean-Pierre Changeux (1973,
1985),[34][46] Daniel Dennett, and Linda B. Smith. Reviews of Edelman's work would continue to be
published as his ideas spread.

A recent review by Fernando, Szathmary and Husbands explains why Edelman's neural Darwinism is not
Darwinian because it does not contain units of evolution as defined by John Maynard Smith. It is
selectionist in that it satisfies the Price equation, but there is no mechanism in Edelman's theory that
explains how information can be transferred between neuronal groups.[47] A recent theory called
evolutionary neurodynamics being developed by Eors Szathmary and Chrisantha Fernando has proposed
several means by which true replication may take place in the brain.[48]

These neuronal models have been extended by Fernando in a later paper.[49] In the most recent model,
three plasticity mechanisms i) multiplicative STDP, ii) LTD, and iii) Heterosynaptic competition, are
responsible for copying of connectivity patterns from one part of the brain to another. Exactly the same
plasticity rules can explain experimental data for how infants do causal learning in the experiments
conducted by Alison Gopnik. It has also been shown that by adding Hebbian learning to neuronal
replicators the power of neuronal evolutionary computation may actually be greater than natural selection in
organisms.[50]

See also
Evolutionary
biology portal

Anthropic mechanism
Complex adaptive system
Darwinism
Evolutionary psychology
Genetic programming
Long-term potentiation
Meme
Modern Synthesis
Neurodevelopment
Psychological nativism
Society of mind theory
The Neurosciences Institute
Universal Darwinism

Notes
a. Work by Rodney Porter with the enzyme papain resulted in cleavage of the antibody into
Fab and Fc fragments, while work by Gerald Edelman lead to the reduction of the disulfide
bridges so as to separate the molecule into light- and heavy-chain fragments. Together, this
work allowed the antibody structure to be sequenced and reconstructed, resulting in the
awarding of the Nobel Prize in Physiology or Medicine in 1972.

Citations
1. Edelman & Porter 1972.
2. Edelman 1987b.
3. Mountcastle & Edelman 1978, p. 7-50, An Organizing Principle For Cerebral Function: The
Unit Module And The Distributed System.
4. Mountcastle & Edelman 1978, p. 51-100, Group Selection and Phasic Reentrant Signalling:
A Theory of Higher Brain Function.
5. Darwin 1859.
6. Edelman 1988.
7. Edelman 1989.
8. Edelman 1992.
9. Edelman & Tononi 2000.
10. Edelman 2004.
11. Edelman 2006.
12. Burnet & Medawar 1960.
13. Mountcastle & Edelman 1978, p. 56.
14. Edelman 1972.
15. Edelman 1974.
16. Edelman 1987a.
17. Dehal & Boore 2005.
18. Tononi, Sporns & Edelman 1999.
19. Edelman 1988, p. 45.
20. Edelman 1992, Chapter 5 Morphology and Mind: Completing Darwin's Program.
21. Huxley 1942.
22. Lewontin 1974.
23. Edelman 1988, p. 45-47.
24. Edelman 1987b, p. 93-100, The Regulatory Hypothesis.
25. Edelman 1988, p. 127-172, The Morphoregulator Hypothesis: Mechanochemistry linked to
developmental genetics.
26. Edelman 1988, p. 67-71,219.
27. Edelman 1988, p. 217.
28. Edelman 1988, p. 219.
29. Edelman 1987b, p. 4.
30. Edelman 1987b, p. 41.
31. Mountcastle & Edelman 1978, p. 52.
32. Edelman 1987b, p. 5.
33. Edelman 1987b, p. 75.
34. Changeux, Courrège & Danchin 1973.
35. Edelman 1989, p. 152.
36. Edelman 1989, p. 112.
37. Rosenfield 1986.
38. Young, Ayala & Szentagothai 1987.
39. Crick 1989.
40. Calvin 1988.
41. Smoliar 1989.
42. Rose 1990.
43. Johnson 1992.
44. Horgan 2014.
45. Herrmann-Pillath 2006.
46. Changeux 1985.
47. Fernando, Szathmáry & Husbands 2012.
48. Fernando, Karishma & Szathmáry 2008.
49. Fernando 2013.
50. Fernando, Goldstein & Szathmáry 2010.

References
Burnet, Frank MacFarlane; Medawar, Peter Brian (1960). "The Nobel Prize in Physiology or
Medicine 1960" (https://www.nobelprize.org/prizes/medicine/1960/summary/).
NobelPrize.org.
Calvin, William (June 24, 1988). "Neural Darwinism: The Theory of Neuronal Group
Selection" (http://williamcalvin.com/1980s/1988Science.htm). Science.
Changeux, Jean-Pierre (1985). Neuronal Man – The Biology of Mind. Translated by
Laurence Carey. Pantheon Books, New York. ISBN 0-394-53692-4.
Changeux, Jean-Pierre; Courrège, Philippe; Danchin, Antoine (1973). "A theory of the
epigenesis of neural networks by selective stabilization of synapses" (https://www.ncbi.nlm.n
ih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC427150). Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA. 70 (10): 2974–2978.
Bibcode:1973PNAS...70.2974C (https://ui.adsabs.harvard.edu/abs/1973PNAS...70.2974C).
doi:10.1073/pnas.70.10.2974 (https://doi.org/10.1073%2Fpnas.70.10.2974). PMC 427150 (h
ttps://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC427150). PMID 4517949 (https://pubmed.ncbi.
nlm.nih.gov/4517949).
Crick, Francis (1989). "Neural Edelmanism". Trends Neurosci. 12 (7): 240–248.
doi:10.1016/0166-2236(89)90019-2 (https://doi.org/10.1016%2F0166-2236%2889%299001
9-2). PMID 2475933 (https://pubmed.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/2475933). S2CID 3947768 (https://ap
i.semanticscholar.org/CorpusID:3947768).
Darwin, Charles (1859). On the Origin of Species by Means of Natural Selection, or the
Preservation of Favoured Races in the Struggle for Life (https://books.google.com/books?id=
ez9KAAAAYAAJ&q=1869+On+the+Origin+of+Species+by+Means+of+Natural+Selection,+o
r+the+Preservation+of+Favoured+Races+in+the+Struggle+for+Life). D. Appleton and
Company, New York, 1869.
Darwin, Charles (1872). The Expression of the Emotions in Man and Animals – with a
preface by Konrad Lorentz (https://books.google.com/books?id=p_ZJCgAAQBAJ&q=The+E
xpression+of+the+Emotions+in+Man+and+Animals). The University of Chicago Press,
Chicago & London, 1965. ISBN 0-226-13656-6.
Darwin, Charles (1887). The Autobiography of Charles Darwin 1809–1882. With the Original
Omissions Restored. Edited and with Appendix and Notes by his Granddaughter Nora
Barlow. W.W. Norton & Company, 1969. ISBN 0-393-00487-2.
Edelman, Gerald M. (1972). Jan Lindsten (ed.). Antibody Structure and Molecular
Immunology (In: Nobel Lectures, Physiology or Medicine 1971-1980) (https://www.nobelpriz
e.org/prizes/medicine/1972/edelman/lecture/). World Scientific Publishing Co., Singapore
1992. ISBN 978-9810207915.
Edelman, Gerald M. (1974). Gerald M. Edelman (ed.). Origins and Mechanisms of Specificity
in Clonal Selection (In: Cellular Selection and Regulation in the Immune Response).
Society of General Physiologists Series. Vol. 29. Raven Press, New York 1974. ISBN 0-
911216-71-5.
Edelman, Gerald M. (1975). "Molecular Recognition in the Immune and Nervous Systems".
In Worden, F.G.; Swazey, J.P.; Adelman, G. (eds.). The Neurosciences: Paths of Discovery (h
ttps://link.springer.com/chapter/10.1007/978-1-4684-6817-5_4). Boston: I. Birkhäuser
(published 1990). pp. 65–74. doi:10.1007/978-1-4684-6817-5_4 (https://doi.org/10.1007%2F
978-1-4684-6817-5_4). ISBN 978-1-4684-6817-5.
Edelman, Gerald M. (1984). "Cell adhesion and morphogenesis: The regulator hypothesis"
(https://www.pnas.org/content/pnas/81/5/1460.full.pdf) (PDF). Proceedings of the National
Academy of Sciences, USA. 81 (5): 1460–1464. Bibcode:1984PNAS...81.1460E (https://ui.a
dsabs.harvard.edu/abs/1984PNAS...81.1460E). doi:10.1073/pnas.81.5.1460 (https://doi.org/
10.1073%2Fpnas.81.5.1460). PMC 344856 (https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC
344856). PMID 6584892 (https://pubmed.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/6584892).
Edelman, Gerald M. (1987a). "CAMs and Igs: cell adhesion and the evolutionary origins of
immunity" (https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/j.1600-065X.1987.tb00526.x).
Immunological Reviews. 100: 11–45. doi:10.1111/j.1600-065x.1987.tb00526.x (https://doi.or
g/10.1111%2Fj.1600-065x.1987.tb00526.x). PMID 3326819 (https://pubmed.ncbi.nlm.nih.go
v/3326819). S2CID 24972419 (https://api.semanticscholar.org/CorpusID:24972419).
Edelman, Gerald M. (1987b). Neural Darwinism – The Theory of Neuronal Group Selection
(https://books.google.com/books?id=hOdqAAAAMAAJ). Basic Books, New York. ISBN 0-
465-04934-6.
Edelman, Gerald M. (1988). Topobiology – An Introduction to Molecular Embryology (https://
www.hachettebookgroup.com/titles/gerald-m-edelman/topobiology/9780465086535/). Basic
Books, New York. ISBN 978-0-465-08653-5.
Edelman, Gerald M. (1989). The Remembered Present – A Biological Theory of
Consciousness (https://www.hachettebookgroup.com/titles/gerald-m-edelman/remembered-
present/9780465069101/). Basic Books, New York. ISBN 0-465-06910-X.
Edelman, Gerald M. (1992). Bright Air, Brilliant Fire – On the Matter of the Mind (https://www.
hachettebookgroup.com/titles/gerald-m-edelman/bright-air-brilliant-fire/9780465007646/).
Basic Books, Inc. ISBN 0-465-05245-2.
Edelman, Gerald M. (1993). "Neural Darwinism: selection and reentrant signaling in higher
brain function" (https://www.cell.com/neuron/pdf/0896-6273(93)90304-A.pdf) (PDF). Neuron.
10 (2): 115–25. doi:10.1016/0896-6273(93)90304-a (https://doi.org/10.1016%2F0896-627
3%2893%2990304-a). PMID 8094962 (https://pubmed.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/8094962).
S2CID 8001773 (https://api.semanticscholar.org/CorpusID:8001773).
Edelman, Gerald M. (1998). GM. Edelman; J-P Changuex (eds.). Building A Picture of the
Brain (In: The Brain). Routledge, Taylor & Francis Group, London and New York 2000.
ISBN 978-0-7658-0717-5.
Edelman, Gerald M. (2004). Wider Than The Sky – The Phenomenal Gift of Consciousness
(https://yalebooks.yale.edu/book/9780300107616/wider-sky). Yale University Press.
ISBN 978-0-300-10761-6.
Edelman, Gerald M. (2006). Second Nature – Brain Science and Human Knowledge (https://
yalebooks.yale.edu/book/9780300125948/second-nature). Yale University Press. ISBN 978-
0-300-12594-8.
Edelman, Gerald M.; Gally, Joseph A. (2001). "Degeneracy and Complexity in Biological
Systems" (https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC61115). Proceedings of the
National Academy of Sciences, USA. 98 (24): 13763–13768.
Bibcode:2001PNAS...9813763E (https://ui.adsabs.harvard.edu/abs/2001PNAS...9813763
E). doi:10.1073/pnas.231499798 (https://doi.org/10.1073%2Fpnas.231499798). PMC 61115
(https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC61115). PMID 11698650 (https://pubmed.nc
bi.nlm.nih.gov/11698650).
Edelman, Gerald M.; Gally, Joseph A. (2013). "Reentry: a key mechanism for integration of
brain function" (https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC3753453). Frontiers in
Integrative Neuroscience. 7 (63): 63. doi:10.3389/fnint.2013.00063 (https://doi.org/10.3389%
2Ffnint.2013.00063). PMC 3753453 (https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC375345
3). PMID 23986665 (https://pubmed.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/23986665).
Edelman, Gerald M.; Porter, Rodney R. (1972). "The Nobel Prize in Physiology or Medicine
1972" (https://www.nobelprize.org/prizes/medicine/1972/summary/). NobelPrize.org.
Edelman, Gerald M.; Tononi, Giulio (2000). A Universe of Consciousness – How Matter
Becomes Imagination (https://www.hachettebookgroup.com/titles/gerald-m-edelman/a-unive
rse-of-consciousness/9780786722587/). Basic Books, Inc. ISBN 978-0-465-01377-7.
Eriksson, Peter S.; et al. (1998). "Neurogenesis in the Adult Human Hippocampus" (https://d
oi.org/10.1038%2F3305). Nature Medicine. 4 (11): 1313–1317. doi:10.1038/3305 (https://do
i.org/10.1038%2F3305). PMID 9809557 (https://pubmed.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/9809557).
Fernando, C.; Karishma, K.K.; Szathmáry, E. (2008). "Copying and Evolution of Neuronal
Topology" (https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC2582483). PLOS ONE. 3 (11):
3775. Bibcode:2008PLoSO...3.3775F (https://ui.adsabs.harvard.edu/abs/2008PLoSO...3.37
75F). doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0003775 (https://doi.org/10.1371%2Fjournal.pone.0003775).
PMC 2582483 (https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC2582483). PMID 19020662
(https://pubmed.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/19020662).
Fernando, C.; Goldstein, R.; Szathmáry, E. (2010). "The Neuronal Replicator Hypothesis" (ht
tps://zenodo.org/record/3439373). Neural Computation. 22 (11): 2809–2857.
doi:10.1162/NECO_a_00031 (https://doi.org/10.1162%2FNECO_a_00031).
PMID 20804380 (https://pubmed.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/20804380). S2CID 17940175 (https://api.s
emanticscholar.org/CorpusID:17940175).
Fernando, C.; Szathmáry, E.; Husbands, P. (2012). "Selectionist and evolutionary
approaches to brain function: a critical appraisal" (https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/
PMC3337445). Frontiers in Computational Neuroscience. 6 (24): 24.
doi:10.3389/fncom.2012.00024 (https://doi.org/10.3389%2Ffncom.2012.00024).
PMC 3337445 (https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC3337445). PMID 22557963
(https://pubmed.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/22557963).
Fernando, C. (2013). "From Blickets to Synapses: Inferring Temporal Causal Networks by
Observation" (https://doi.org/10.1111%2Fcogs.12073). Cognitive Science. 37 (8): 1426–
1470. doi:10.1111/cogs.12073 (https://doi.org/10.1111%2Fcogs.12073). PMID 23957457 (ht
tps://pubmed.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/23957457).
Hayek, F.A. (1952). The Sensory Order: An Inquiry into the Foundations of Theoretical
Psychology. Routledge & Kegan Paul, London. ISBN 0-226-32094-4.
Herrmann-Pillath, Carsten (2006-12-10). "The Brain, Its Sensory Order and the Evolutionary
Concept of Mind, On Hayek's Contribution to Evolutionary Epistemology". Journal of Social
and Evolutionary Systems. 15 (2): 145–187. doi:10.1016/1061-7361(92)90003-v (https://doi.
org/10.1016%2F1061-7361%2892%2990003-v). SSRN 950592 (https://papers.ssrn.com/sol
3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=950592).
Hill, Charlotte; Wang, YYihua (2020). "The importance of epithelial-mesenchymal transition
and autophagy in cancer drug resistance" (https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC71
00899). Cancer Drug Resistance. 3 (1): 38–47. doi:10.20517/cdr.2019.75 (https://doi.org/10.
20517%2Fcdr.2019.75). PMC 7100899 (https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC710
0899). PMID 32226927 (https://pubmed.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/32226927).
Horgan, John (May 22, 2014). "My Testy Encounter with the Late, Great Gerald Edelman" (ht
tps://blogs.scientificamerican.com/cross-check/my-testy-encounter-with-the-late-great-gerald
-edelman/). Scientific American. Retrieved April 30, 2021.
Huttenlocher, P.R. (1990). "Morphometric study of human cerebral cortical development".
Neuropsychologia. 28 (6): 517–527. doi:10.1016/0028-3932(90)90031-i (https://doi.org/10.1
016%2F0028-3932%2890%2990031-i). PMID 2203993 (https://pubmed.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/22
03993). S2CID 45697561 (https://api.semanticscholar.org/CorpusID:45697561).
Huxley, Julian (1942). Evolution: The Modern Synthesis. London, G. Allen & Unwin ltd.
Johnson, George (April 19, 1992). "Evolution Between the Ears" (http://www.santafe.edu/~jo
hnson/reviews.edelman.html). New York Times.
Lewontin, Richard C. (1974). The Genetic Basis of Evolutionary Change. Columbia
University Press. ISBN 0231033923.
Mountcastle, Vernon Benjamin; Edelman, Gerald M. (1978). The Mindful Brain – Cortical
Organization and the Group-selective Theory of Higher Brain Function (https://mitpress.mit.e
du/books/mindful-brain). MIT Press. ISBN 978-0-262-55007-9.
Rose, Steven (June 9, 1990). "Review: Darwin on the brain" (https://www.newscientist.com/
article/mg12617205-400-review-darwin-on-the-brain/). www.newscientist.com. New
Scientist. Retrieved 18 April 2021.
Rosenfield, Israel (October 9, 1986). "Neural Darwinism: A New Approach to Memory and
Perception" (https://www.nybooks.com/articles/1986/10/09/neural-darwinism-a-new-approac
h-to-memory-and-perc/). The New York Review of Books. Retrieved April 27, 2021.
Smoliar, Stephen W. (1989). "Review of G.M. Edelman (book review)" (https://books.google.
com/books?id=FVJ9xib-XxMC&q=artificial+intelligence+smoliar+%22Neural+darwinism%2
2&pg=PA431). In William J. Clancey; Stephen W. Smoliar; Mark Stefik (eds.). Contemplating
minds: a forum for artificial intelligence. MIT Press (published 1996). pp. 431–446.
ISBN 978-0-262-53119-1. (originally published in Artificial Intelligence 39 (1989) 121–139.)
"In Memoriam: Gerald Edelman (1929–2014)" (https://www.scripps.edu/newsandviews/e_20
140602/edelman.html). News & Views - Vol 14, Issue 17. The Scripps Research Institute
(TSRI). June 2, 2014. Retrieved July 21, 2021.
Tononi, Giulio; Sporns, Olaf; Edelman, Gerald M. (1999). "Measures of degeneracy and
redundancy in biological networks" (https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC15929).
PNAS. 96 (6): 3257–3262. Bibcode:1999PNAS...96.3257T (https://ui.adsabs.harvard.edu/ab
s/1999PNAS...96.3257T). doi:10.1073/pnas.96.6.3257 (https://doi.org/10.1073%2Fpnas.96.
6.3257). PMC 15929 (https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC15929).
PMID 10077671 (https://pubmed.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/10077671).
Young, J.Z.; Ayala, Francisco J.; Szentagothai, J. (March 12, 1987). "Neural Darwinism: An
Exchange (reply by Israel Rosenfield)" (https://www.nybooks.com/articles/1987/03/12/neural
-darwinism-an-exchange/). The New York Review of Books. Retrieved April 27, 2021.

Further reading
How Brains Think: Evolving Intelligence, Then and Now by William H. Calvin (http://faculty.
washington.edu/wcalvin/bk8/)
Neurogenesis in the Adult Human Brain (https://web.archive.org/web/20040305165352/htt
p://www.abacon.com/pinel/hot_sept.html)

External links
The Complete Work of Charles Darwin Online (http://darwin-online.org.uk/)
Wikiversity – Neuroscience
Wikiversity – Fundamentals of Neuroscience
Wikiversity – Introduction to Non-Genetic Darwinism
Webpage of William Calvin (https://www.williamcalvin.com)
Webpage of Daniel Dennett (https://ase.tufts.edu/cogstud/dennett/)
Webpage of Chrisantha Fernando (https://web.archive.org/web/20111117034941/http://ww
w.cogs.susx.ac.uk/users/ctf20/dphil_2005/index.htm)

Retrieved from "https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Neural_Darwinism&oldid=1162769366"

You might also like