Introduction To Comparative Constitutionalism
Introduction To Comparative Constitutionalism
9-1-2002
Recommended Citation
Nussbaum, Martha C. (2002) "Introduction to Comparative Constitutionalism," Chicago Journal of
International Law: Vol. 3: No. 2, Article 12.
Available at: https://chicagounbound.uchicago.edu/cjil/vol3/iss2/12
This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Chicago Unbound. It has been accepted for inclusion in
Chicago Journal of International Law by an authorized editor of Chicago Unbound. For more information, please
contact [email protected].
Introduction to Comparative Constitutionalism
Martha C. Nussbaum"
Ernst Freund Distinguished Service Professor of Law and Ethics, The University of Chicago: Law
School, Philosophy Department, and Divinity School; Board, Human Rights Program;
Coordinator, Center for Comparative Constitutionalism. The Symposium was the inaugural event
for the new Center for Comparative Constiturionalism at the University of Chicago. This
interdisciplinary Center (which includes faculty from Law, Political Science, Philosophy, Sociology,
and other disciplines) will study the implementation of constitutional entitlements, particularly for
disadvantaged groups, and the social forces (such as education and religion) that affect this
implementation.
1. Mark Tushner, State Action, Social Welfare Rights, and the JudicialRole: Some ComparativeObservations, 3
ChiJ Intl L 435 (2002).
CbicagoJournal'ofInternationa(Law
2. For my general reflections on the need for more international study in legal education, see Martha
Nussbaum, Cultivating Humanity in Legal Education, 69 U Chi L Rev (forthcoming 2002).
'O0( 3 W. 2
Introduction to ComparativeConstitutionafism 9vuss6aum
Fall 2002
Cbicagojourna[ of Internationa(Law
3. Republic of South Africa v Grootboom, Case No CCT 11/00 (Con Ct S Africa, Oct 4, 2000), available
online at <http://www.concourt.gov.za/judgments/2000/grootbooml.pdf> (visited Sept 9, 2002).
4. Such is the position, for example, of Liam Murphy and Thomas Nagel, The Myth of Ownersbip 45
(Oxford 2002).
Vf- 3 N(o. 2
Introduction to Comparative Constitutionafism N¢ussbaum
by a state. The term "first-generation rights" now designates the former, "second-
generation rights" the latter. But the papers make it very clear that the two categories
are not easily separated. Sunstein insists that the rights in the first group have a
material element. They do not come into being on their own, but require the state to
allocate money if they are to be effective and real in people's lives. Thus in an
important sense all rights are welfare rights. Epstein suggests, by contrast, that we can
still make a clear and coherent distinction between some traditional activities of the
state, protecting people against force and fraud, and the new activities discussed
sympathetically in Tushnet's paper. In his view, the state is ill-advised to venture into
the realm of welfare, although he would presumably not deny that the rights he favors
do have a monetary cost. Getting clear about these issues, conceptually and practically,
is a major future task of work in comparative constitutionalism.
Constitutions and Consequences. A pervasive concern of the papers is with outcomes.
Whether or not constitutional provisions and their interpretation have a prepolitical
moral basis, they have consequences. And the authors appear to agree that both texts
and interpretive traditions can reasonably be evaluated by looking at how they work.
Do they produce stability or instability? Do they deliver the welfare that they seek to
deliver? Tushnet and Young are sympathetic not only to the goals of social democracy,
but also to its choice of means, its use of the political and legal sphere to guarantee a
certain level of welfare to all. Epstein believes that government involvement typically
makes things worse, and that the best course for government, in South Africa and
elsewhere, is to hold back and let private forces solve the problems as best they can.
Implementation. The papers do not focus directly on the topic of implementing
rights, but it is a pervasive theme in all of them. One question we may reasonably ask
about any constitution, together with its traditions of interpretation, is whether its
implementation of rights is real or capable of being made real. Sunstein formerly held
(in the earlier paper cited by Tushnet) that social and economic rights were a mistake
because they could not be implemented effectively. He now no longer holds this, nor
does Tushnet-although Tushnet's paper shows how difficult it is for courts to lay
out a path to the implementation of the rights of which they speak. All the papers
recognize that both political and economic forces are of primary importance in
determining whether rights that exist on paper ever become real. In some nations
(though by no means all) courts may give instructions for legislation; but they cannot
exactly legislate; nor can they bring about the economic climate within which the
problems they are trying to solve will be solved. (Epstein argues, for example, that the
solution to the problem of homelessness in South Africa lies far more in the private
sphere than in the legal and political spheres.)
There are other social forces, not mentioned in the papers, that are extremely
important in determining whether rights become real. One of the most important is
education. A nation, half of whose people cannot read or write, is not likely to be a
nation of citizens who vigorously claim their rights. One can predict that in such a
nation rights will be more real for some people than for others. Even access to the legal
Fall2002
CbicagojournafofInternationa(Law
system requires literacy, and meaningful participation in claiming rights requires more
than mere literacy.
Another very significant factor is public health. Many nations of Africa are
ravaged by HIV/AIDS to an extent that compromises the ability of these nations to
support a meaningful regime of rights. In South Africa approximately 25 percent of
adults, and in Botswana an astonishing 38 percent of adults, are living with HIV.
Such people-especially in the absence of good medical care-are not likely to be
effective as citizens in claiming rights; and their inability to work creates massive
problems for the delivery of all rights, including the right to housing articulated in the
landmark case Grootboom.
A third factor that needs sustained study is the interaction between religion and
the implementation of constitutional rights. Especially in areas where rights clash with
entrenched traditions, religious bodies and their leaders play a very important role in
either securing or impeding rights. At the same time, the way a constitution shapes
the role of religion has a major impact on the way religion will function either as a
deliverer or impeder of rights.
These are only some of the social factors not mentioned in the papers that
require study if we are ever to acquire an adequate understanding of comparative
constitutionalism. Other such topics are the nature of security, policing, and the
protection of bodily integrity; the nature of the family; and the nature of the legal
profession and legal education. All these issues are present, so to speak, in the margins
of these eloquent papers, suggesting a rich menu of topics for future study in this
young and exciting field.
cV01 3 N0. 2