Defining Ethics
Defining Ethics
Ethics is derived from the Greek word “ethos,” which means a characteristic way
of acting which also refers to the principles or standards of human conduct. Ethics is
also called moral philosophy that involves systematizing, defending, and
recommending concepts of right and wrong behavior; thus, ethics is sometimes
referred to as the study of morality. It is said to be a science insofar as it is a body of
systematized knowledge arranged with its accompanying explanation. In terms of
content, it is not to be classified as a course in science. Ethics as a practical science
means that it consists of principles and laws that are applied in daily living. In this sense,
ethics is not a course taken for the sake of contemplation; rather, it is a study taken for
application in a person’s everyday course of action. Ethics then is an applied
knowledge.
Finally, the lack of social consensus on many issues makes it impossible to equate
ethics with whatever society accepts. Some people accept abortion but many others
do not. If being ethical were doing whatever society accepts, one would have to find
an agreement on issues which does not, in fact, exist.
Ethics is not the same with morality but is closely linked to it. While moral standard
or norm of action is fixed and already set, ethics dwells on the use of reason. It is
because we cannot limit philosophy from mere norms of conduct. However, ethics is
identical to moral science or moral philosophy based from the Latin term mos
(nominative) or moris (genitive) which also means custom, or “traditional line of
conduct.” It is from this root word that the word moral or morality is derived. The term
morality is synonymous with the word ethics in etymological meaning; however, ethics
deals more on the principles and laws on the morality of human acts by providing the
person knowledge that s/he may know, what to do and how to do it. In other words,
ethics provides the guides to the performance of an act.
Moral actions or events are those which require the goodness of the object
chosen, the intention or the end in view, and of the circumstances together.
Moral actions are deemed to be good as one performs the moral rules or codes
of the society.
Immoral actions or events are those actions or areas of interest where moral
categories do apply and are considered to be evil, sinful, or wrong according to
the code of ethics. For examples: consciously telling a lie; graft and corruption;
cheating during examinations, gluttony, taking a sip of water fully aware that
there is hemlock in it (suicide), and many more.
Human acts are the fundamental foundation of morality. These acts which are
under the control of the will and therefore done knowingly and willingly; not acts which
happen by accident, as falling, or by nature, as growing, but acts performed by
choice, that is, after deliberation and decision. They are imputable to their human
author to the extent that he has knowledge of his own activity and its import, and to the
extent that he has freedom of election. The moral or ethical character of the human
act lies in this, that it is freely placed with knowledge of its objective conformity or
nonconformity with the law of rational nature.
There are two significant considerations of ethics; the Ethics of Being and the
Ethics of Doing. In the Ethics of Being, the emphasis is on the “character development”
which involves the integrations of virtues, values and personhood; it is looking into the
foundation of actions who is the “good person” while the Ethics of Doing focuses not
only the goodness of the person but on the ability of the person to put into action
his/her ethical conviction (Fr. Ramon Coronel & Fr. Paul Van Parijs, CICM, Bioethics,
1996). It is not enough simply to be contented in believing to be a good person while
forgetting to do good actions; on the other hand, it also not good just to think that you
are doing good while you forget that you are first and foremost a good person. There is
the need to harmonize the two considerations of ethics; hence, you do a good act
because you believe and think that you are a good person capable of doing good.
Both considerations are inseparably related to be better person – intellectually mature,
psychologically stable, socially involved, spiritually nourished and economically well-off;
and, to do good acts.
There are three essential elements to consider any action to be a human act.
Without one of these elements, the action cannot be considered as a human act.
These are knowledge, freedom of the will, and voluntariness.
Freedom of the Will. According to St. Thomas Aquinas, this is the power which
human beings have in determining their actions according to the judgment of their
reasons. This always involves a choice or an option of whether to do or not to do a
certain action. Without this freedom of choice, then responsibility and/or liability on the
part of the individual would be meaningless. Insane people who have no control of
their minds and children who have no idea of what they are doing or are not free to do
or not to do, are not responsible for their actions. Matured people, college students and
professionals are expected to be free from doing or not doing; thus, they are
responsible or liable for their actions.
Voluntariness. This is an act of consenting or accepting a certain action whether
it is done whole-heartedly, half-heartedly, or non-heartedly. According to Aristotle, the
moral evaluation of an action presupposes the attribution of responsibility to a human
agent; thus, responsible action must be undertaken voluntarily (Nicomachean Ethics III).
Agapay presented four modes of voluntariness. These are perfect, imperfect,
conditional, and simple voluntariness.
Perfect Voluntariness is actualized by a person who is fully aware and who fully
intends an act. The person, under perfect voluntariness, is fully convinced of his action
including its consequences. A politician who, in his right mind, engages in graft and
corruption is considered to be acting with perfect voluntariness. Imperfect Voluntariness
is seen in a person who acts without the full awareness of his action or without fully
intending the act. A drunken person who, acting irrationally, jumps from a ten-storey
building is said to be exhibiting an imperfect voluntariness. Conditional Voluntariness is
manifested by a person who is forced by his circumstances beyond his control to
perform an action which he would not do under normal condition. A freshman college
student who is forced by his parents to enroll in a course which is against his will is
showing a conditional voluntariness. Simple Voluntariness is exhibited by a person doing
an act willfully regardless of whether he likes to do it or not. It can either be positive or
negative. It is a positive simple voluntariness when the act requires the performance of
an act. For examples: Studying one’s lesson; participating in class discussions; engaging
in sports, and so on. It is a negative simple voluntariness when the act does not require
the performance of an act. For examples: Remaining silent or choosing to be alone;
deciding not to go to a drinking spree; avoiding to take illegal drugs; and so on.
Freedom makes man a moral subject. When he acts deliberately, man is, so to
speak, the master of his acts. Human acts, that is, acts that are freely chosen in
consequence of a judgment of conscience, can be morally evaluated. They are either
good or evil. The morality of human acts depends on the object chosen; the end in
view or the intention; and the circumstances of the action. These are the factors to
consider in making ethical judgement in determining the morality of human acts.
Object Chosen: This is a good toward which the will deliberately directs itself. The
chosen object resides out the acting subject. The object chosen morally specifies the
act of the will, insofar as reason recognizes and judges it to be or not to be in conformity
with the true good. Examples of Good Chosen Objects: nutritious foods; hard-earned
money or wealth; educational books and films; and the like. Examples of Bad Chosen
Objects: Forbidden drugs; Pornographic materials; Leakages for examinations; and
others.
The Intention: This is a movement of the will toward the end. It is concerned with
the goal of the activity. The end is the first goal of the intention and indicates the
purpose pursued in the action. It aims at the good anticipated from the action
undertaken. Intention is not limited to directing individual actions but can guide several
actions toward one and the same purpose; it can orient one's whole life toward its
ultimate end. For example, a service done with the end of helping one's neighbor can
at the same time be inspired by the love of the Divine Being as the ultimate end of all
our actions. One and the same action can also be inspired by several intentions, such
as performing a service in order to obtain a favor or to boast about it. The intention
resides in the acting subject as contrast to the object chosen. Because it lies at the
voluntary source of an action and determines it by its end, intention is an element
essential to the moral evaluation of an action.
In Summary: A morally good act requires the goodness of the object, of the end,
and of the circumstances together. An evil end corrupts the action, even if the object is
good in itself (such as praying and fasting "in order to be seen by men"). The object of
the choice can by itself vitiate an act in its entirety. There are some concrete acts - such
as fornication - that it is always wrong to choose, because choosing them entails a
disorder of the will, that is, a moral evil. It is therefore an error to judge the morality of
human acts by considering only the intention that inspires them or the circumstances
(environment, social pressure, duress or emergency, etc.) which supply their context.
There are acts which, in and of themselves, independently of circumstances and
intentions, are always gravely illicit by reason of their object; such as blasphemy and
perjury, murder and adultery. One may not do evil so that good may result from it.
The object, the intention, and the circumstances make up the three "sources" of
the morality of human acts. The object chosen morally specifies the act of willing
accordingly as reason recognizes and judges it good or evil. "An evil action cannot be
justified by reference to a good intention" (cf. St. Thomas Aquinas, Dec. praec. 6). A
morally good act therefore requires the goodness of its object, of its end, and of its
circumstances together. There are concrete acts which are always wrong to choose,
because their choice entails a disorder of the will, i.e., a moral evil. One may not do evil
so that good may result from it.