(Islam in The World) Sophia Vasalou - Al-Ghazali and The Idea of Moral Beauty-Routledge (2021)
(Islam in The World) Sophia Vasalou - Al-Ghazali and The Idea of Moral Beauty-Routledge (2021)
(Islam in The World) Sophia Vasalou - Al-Ghazali and The Idea of Moral Beauty-Routledge (2021)
Beauty
Series Editors:
Katherine Brown, Birmingham University, UK
Jorgen Nielsen, Birmingham University, UK
For more information and a full list of titles in the series, please visit:
https://www.routledge.com/Islam-in-the-World/book-series/ITWF
Al-Ghazālī and the Idea of
Moral Beauty
Sophia Vasalou
First published 2022
by Routledge
2 Park Square, Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon OX14 4RN
and by Routledge
605 Third Avenue, New York, NY 10158
Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group, an
informa business
© 2022 Sophia Vasalou
The right of Sophia Vasalou to be identified as author of this
work has been asserted by her in accordance with sections 77
and 78 of the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988.
All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted
or reproduced or utilised in any form or by any electronic,
mechanical, or other means, now known or hereafter invented,
including photocopying and recording, or in any information
storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing from
the publishers.
Trademark notice: Product or corporate names may be
trademarks or registered trademarks, and are used only for
identification and explanation without intent to infringe.
British Library Cataloguing-in-Publication Data
A catalogue record for this book is available from the British
Library
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
A catalog record has been requested for this book
Acknowledgements vi
1 Introduction 1
7 Concluding comment 52
Notes57
Bibliography74
Index80
Acknowledgements
I’m very grateful to the two reviewers for their careful reading and
constructive suggestions, and to my colleague Katherine Brown for
steering this work to publication. I’m also grateful to the audience at a
talk I gave on the subject at the Oxford Centre for Islamic Studies for
their questions and comments. The 2019 pandemic put paid to other
opportunities to share this work live, but there are brighter days ahead.
1 Introduction
A good way to get into our topic is through a broader question about the
place of aesthetic experience in al-Ghazālī’s thought. “Aesthetics”—
from the Greek aisthesis, “sense” or “sense-perception”—is itself a
modern concept with no exact counterpart in the medieval Islamic
intellectual tradition. Aesthetics was not conceived of and pursued as
a separate subject of inquiry. Yet beauty ( jamāl or ḥusn) was a theme
that preoccupied Muslim intelligentsia across numerous vehicles
of cultural expression, including literature (adab), philosophy, and
Sufism. In philosophy, beauty surfaced as a theme within discussions
organised under rather different headings, such as metaphysical explo-
rations of the nature of God or explorations of literary art inspired by
Aristotle’s Rhetoric and Poetics.1 When we seek to study questions of
“aesthetics” in a particular work or thinker, we will thus often need
to track our subject through a variety of environments and to identify
it using one or both of the following means: the use of core aesthetic
vocabulary (such as jamāl and ḥusn) and the reference to experiences
that we are happy to recognise as instances of the aesthetic in light of
both their objects and their described phenomenology.2
Approaching al-Ghazālī in this manner, one of the first references
to aesthetic experience we find in the Revival of the Religious Sciences
will evoke an immediate sense of scepticism about the status of such
experiences within his concerns. “Anyone who takes delight in the
present world,” he writes in the book On the Condemnation of the
Mundane World, “be it by hearing some birdsong, by gazing upon
some verdure (khu ḍra), or by taking a drink of cool water, will have his
reward in the hereafter diminished several times in proportion.”3 Both
the objects and the broad phenomenology of these experiences allow
us to confidently recognise them (at least the first two) as instances
of aesthetic experience on our terms.4 And al-Ghazālī’s attitude to
such experience seems unmistakably clear: it is one of thoroughgoing
DOI: 10.4324/9781003196556-2
6 Aesthetic experience in al-Ghazālī’s ethics
condemnation. This ties in with the overall theme of the book, and
the jaundiced attitude it adopts towards worldly goods and pleasures.
There is a necessary disjunction, both psychological and evaluative,
between attachment to goods that belong to the present world and
attachment to goods that belong to the next. Attachment to the former
comes at the cost of the latter; and on the level of our fundamental
motivation and conception of the good, only one attachment can reign
supreme.5 To this ascetic view, there would appear to be no exceptions:
all pleasures that form part of the worldly domain and are made pos-
sible by our embodied condition are tarred by the same brush, no mat-
ter whether they come to us through hearing and sight (honoured by
Aristotle in the Metaphysics as the noblest and most intellectual of the
senses) or through taste and feel. This includes the pleasures afforded
by the most ordinary enjoyment of nature and natural beauty.
Yet in fact the attitude conveyed in this book does not tell the whole
story. It may be evident that the above view, which tells us what should
be our ultimate object of desire, leaves open a different way of valuing
the goods and pleasures to be had in the present world. We may not
value them intrinsically, but we may value them as goods that stand in
a subordinate relation to the intrinsic goods of the supernatural realm.
It is not, after all, that we should wholly reject the physical pleasures
of eating and drinking. It is that when we partake of them, we should
regard them under their description as means that enable us to realise
our true end and that give us the power to devote ourselves to what
really matters—to the salutary forms of intellectual and ethical activ-
ity (al-ʿilm waʾl-ʿamal). Seen in this light, eating and drinking become
objects not merely of grudging toleration but of praise and reward
(mashkūr wa-maʾjūr). For “the body is the vessel of the soul, which it
uses to complete its journey toward God.”6 The present world is not an
impediment to the next; it is the means of reaching it.
This way of regarding worldly objects finds its complement in a
rather different mode of valuation. Entities belonging to the mundane
realm may stand in a causal relationship to goods belonging to the
metaphysical realm, which makes us value them in their instrumen-
tal capacity. Yet they may also stand in a signifying relationship to
that realm, which makes us value them in their epistemic capacity and
for their cognitive content. And it is a type of response to the natural
world and its constituents we may recognise as aesthetic in character,
being a response to its beauty and grandeur, that registers that rela-
tionship most strongly.
The best place to observe this attitude at work, in the Revival, is the
book captioned On Contemplation. The contemplation in question has
Aesthetic experience in al-Ghazālī’s ethics 7
a number of different objects, but one of the most important consists
in God’s acts and effects as manifest in the created realm. Like all the
other topics treated in the last quarter of the Revival, this contem-
plative exercise is not a recommended extra of the ethical life, but an
activity we are dutybound to undertake if we are to achieve spiritual
completeness. And this duty essentially takes shape as a duty of won-
der, which reads every aspect of the created realm—from the compo-
nents of our own bodies and the different plants and animals roaming
land and sea to the larger economy of the heavens and the earth—as
a wondrous signifier of God’s attributes, above all his majesty, wis-
dom, knowledge, and power. It is possible that not all wonder has an
aesthetic quality; but this kind of wonder certainly does. The mode
of contemplation that reads the natural world as expressive of God’s
nature is one responsive to its grandeur and beauty. “You have for-
gotten,” as al-Ghazālī observes in one place, “to have regard for the
beauty of the empire of the heavens and the earth.”7
So an aesthetic appreciation of the natural world is not only not
reprehensible but mandated. But its legitimacy rests on our ability to
experience the natural world as pointing to its transcendent cause. To
return to the birdsong that antagonised al-Ghazālī in an earlier book
of the Revival: it’s not taking pleasure in birdsong that is problematic
simpliciter; it’s taking pleasure in birdsong just insofar as it’s birdsong,
and not insofar as it is a glorious expression of God’s nature.
Whether we adopt one or the other of these two modes of valua-
tion—instrumental or epistemic—may be a matter of perspective. The
same object can provide the basis for both, as when we view the article
of food we are consuming as a means to some valorised activity yet
also as a token of the astounding natural economy God has created
and as a signifier of God’s beneficence and creative powers.8
Taken together, this shows that al-Ghazālī has a more nuanced atti-
tude to aesthetic enjoyment. The positive attitude he displays towards
the enjoyment of nature has its counterpart in the view he takes of
certain forms of art. The most notable example is music, the subject
of extensive controversy in the Islamic tradition. Al-Ghazālī is deeply
impressed by the power of music, and by what our profound response
to it says about our own nature and about the higher spiritual reali-
ties. Our response to music reveals the presence of a “divine spark” in
us, and “beautiful, harmonious, well-proportioned sound produces an
image of the wonders of that [higher spiritual] world.”9 As with nature,
the value of music thus derives from the access it gives us, cognitive
and emotional, to the transcendent realm, its beauty a reflection and
conduit of transcendent beauty.
3 The good and/as the
beautiful in context
Some of these categories speak for themselves. Love of self will seem
self-evident. This type of love, al-Ghazālī explains, manifests itself in
our concern to perpetuate our existence, but also to perfect our exist-
ence. Many of the other objects to which we are habitually attached—
our physical integrity and well-being, our material possessions, but
also our children, kinsmen, and friends—are loved precisely under
their description as conducive to preserving or perfecting our exist-
ence.18 Love of beneficence may also seem self-explanatory: we all
love people who act beneficently towards us. This is the description,
al-Ghazālī explains, under which we love teachers and doctors, for
example. Yet we also love people who act beneficently towards others.
In one version of his taxonomy, al-Ghazālī distinguishes these as two
different causes of love, which I will label beneficence 1 (directed to
self) and beneficence 2 (directed to others) for ease of reference. About
type 4, I will have little to say. To type 3, I will return in a moment, as
it is the one that concerns us most.
Even on this synoptic view, al-Ghazālī’s taxonomy may strike us
as creaky. Why, for example, make beneficence 1 a separate category,
instead of filing it under “love of self”?19 Yet putting such issues to the
side, let us instead attend to the general character of this taxonomy.
The taxonomy is meant to be empirical: it intends to represent the
facts of human experience. The different forms of love describe the
different reasons (and with an eye to 4, the causes) on account of which
we actually love. The taxonomy can then be read as accomplishing
two things. First, it provides the basis for claiming that God is the
most appropriate object of love across its entire spectrum of familiar
forms and reasons. If we love our own existence, its perpetuation and
its perfection, God is the being that truly merits our love, as it is he
who secures these goods. If we love benefactors (whether to self or
others), God is the true benefactor, who causally determines, no less,
the beneficence of human agents.20
Yet the taxonomy has a second drift. Because from an evaluative
perspective, these forms are not all equal; some of them are better
Moral beauty 19
than others. I take it to be evident that for al-Ghazālī, the best sort of
love is intrinsic love.21 A second aim of the taxonomy is thus to stake
the claim that this superior form of love—and hence superior way of
loving God—represents a real human possibility.
So what is the nature of that love, and under what description do
we empirically meet it? It is the kind of love, al-Ghazālī explains,
that we experience when we love something for its own sake or being
(li-dhātihi), “and not for any gain (ḥaẓẓ) we stand to make beyond
it; rather, its being is itself the gain (dhātuhu ʿaynu ḥaẓẓihi).”22 It will
be appealing, based on this remark, to describe this form of love as
“disinterested.” Yet as this statement already shows, that would be
misleading if taken to imply that we gain nothing whatsoever from
the experience. In modern philosophy, the distinction between “inter-
ested” and “disinterested” sometimes comes up in the context of char-
acterising the distinctively moral point of view, where it is tied to a
contrast between egoistic and non-egoistic motivation. In this capac-
ity, it is sometimes leveraged to question whether ancient philosophers
had a concept of morality, though in the reverse direction, the ancient
philosophers’ lack of this distinction (most fundamentally in concep-
tualising the virtuous life as the happy one) has also been leveraged to
criticise the modern conception of morality.23 The distinction between
interested and disinterested viewpoints is also commonly mobilised in
another context, in characterising the nature of aesthetic experience.
The issue is ultimately definitional: it depends on how we define
“interest.” For his part, al-Ghazālī clearly intends to mark a distinc-
tion between the kind of concern that shapes the egoistic standpoint
of category 1 and the kind that shapes the standpoint of the present
category, with the latter represented as the superior of the two. Yet it is
also clear that he believes we have an important stake in the experience
he now turns to describe. The experience of intrinsic love affords us a
powerful satisfaction in which our nature finds profound fulfilment.
Each standpoint can in fact be seen as representing different aspects of
our nature, each of which has its corresponding concept of “interest”
and sphere of satisfaction. And it is precisely aesthetic experience that
al-Ghazālī calls upon to supply his paradigm case of intrinsic love as
we humanly know it.
The human love of beauty (al-jamāl waʾl- ḥusn) is the clearest exam-
ple of “disinterested” (in this qualified sense) or intrinsic love. We love
beautiful forms for their own sake, and not because of some instru-
mental purpose they might conceivably serve. Al-Ghazālī’s first frame
of reference in approaching this point is the way we typically respond
to the beauty of the natural world. It is a mistake to think, he writes,
20 Moral beauty
that “the only reason we love beautiful forms (ṣuwar jamīla) is on
account of some [carnal] appetite we want to satisfy.” We know from
experience that
people love vegetation and flowing water not because they want to
drink the water or eat the vegetation or satisfy some need (ḥaẓẓ),
but only on account of the visual perception itself (ruʾya) … it
is the necessary expression of a sound nature (al- ṭibā ʿ al-salīma
qā ḍiya bi-) to take pleasure in the contemplation of lights, flowers,
or well-formed birds with fine-coloured plumage … indeed, one’s
cares and sorrows are dispelled as one contemplates them, for no
other stake beyond mere contemplation.24
The intrinsic love of beautiful forms is here identified with the pleasure
taken in the act of visual contemplation and contrasted with an instru-
mental type of desire towards these objects that might derive from
our appetitive nature. This aesthetic response is claimed as a familiar
empirical fact about human beings. Love of beauty is something we
are naturally disposed to (al-jamāl maḥbūb biʾl- ṭabʿ).25
From a philosophical perspective, al-Ghazālī’s account will seem
especially interesting in evoking open comparison with modern analyses
of aesthetic experience. Although, as I have suggested, his understand-
ing of its “disinterested” character has to be approached carefully, the
contrast that underpins his account places it in clear conversation with
a prominent philosophical view of this character that is often associated
with Kant. The hallmark of aesthetic judgements, on this view, is that
they do not implicate (presuppose or stimulate) desire for their object.
As Roger Scruton puts it, aesthetic experience involves enjoyment of an
object for its own sake, which means having a “desire to go on hearing,
looking at, or in some other way having experience of X, where there
is no reason for this desire in terms of any other desire or appetite that
the experience of X may fulfil.”26 Al-Ghazālī’s emphasis on the ther-
apeutic or palliative effect of aesthetic experience, and the experience
of nature in particular, forges equally suggestive connections. Among
philosophers, a similar view has been paradigmatically expressed by
Schopenhauer. For Schopenhauer, the contemplation of nature ena-
bles us to transcend the will-full perspective of individual subjectivity
and provides us with a temporary reprieve from suffering. “This is why
the man tormented by passions, want, or care, is so suddenly revived,
cheered, and comforted by a single, free glance into nature.”27
Yet it is al-Ghazālī’s next move, and the next frame of reference he
introduces to conceptualise the human love of beauty, that forms the
Moral beauty 21
flagship of his account. And here, his view and that of most modern
philosophers of aesthetics part ways. Contemporary aestheticians,
as mentioned earlier, typically focus on nature and art as the para-
digm objects of aesthetic attention. This focus goes hand in hand with
an emphasis on availability to sensory perception as a criterion for
aesthetic properties. In the view of one prominent exponent, Nick
Zangwill, sensory properties such as colours and sounds are necessary
for aesthetic properties (though they might not be sufficient), so that
“without sensory properties, there would be no aesthetic properties.”
Hence, any application of aesthetic terms to objects not perceived by
the five senses must be metaphorical.28
More recently, this type of view has come in for sharp critique from
other philosophical quarters.29 It is precisely this narrow view that
al-Ghazālī himself brings up in the next stage of his discussion and offers
to interrogate and refine. This is a view he takes to typify how the ordi-
nary man on the street thinks about beauty. Ordinary people tend to
assume that only concrete physical things, typically things we can see
which have shape and colour and size, more typically still human beings,
can be beautiful. This understanding is too narrow on two counts: in
sidelining the forms of beauty registered by other physical senses and
in overlooking the forms of beauty that are not registered by a physical
sense at all. And here, it is the case of moral beauty—of a beauty attach-
ing to human character—that constitutes al-Ghazālī’s central exemplar.
To correct and enlarge the popular conception of the beautiful,
al-Ghazālī begins by appealing to the data of ordinary language using
a progressively wider palette of examples. We speak not only of a
fine-looking person but also of a “fine horse,” a “fine writing hand”
(khaṭṭ ḥasan), and a “fine sound” or voice (ṣawt ḥasan). More impor-
tantly, we also speak of “fine character” (khuluq ḥasan), of a “fine
course of conduct” (sīra ḥasana),30 and of “beautiful character traits”
(akhlāq jamīla), such as temperance, courage, piety, and generosity.31
These beautiful qualities, which constitute the inner form of a per-
son, are not perceived through the senses, but through inner insight
(al-ba ṣīra al-bā ṭina).
Thus, even though ordinary people, when prompted to pronounce
on the topic of beauty, would be likely to give a restrictive account
of its objects, a more inclusive conception is implicit in their own
patterns of linguistic usage. In the Exalted Aim, al-Ghazālī suggests
these two applications—to sensory and to non-sensory objects—
represent different stages of the development of language, identifying
the former as historically prior. “The term ‘beautiful’ was originally
( fiʾl-a ṣl) appointed to signify the outward form perceivable through
22 Moral beauty
sight … and was later transferred to the inward form perceivable
through insight.”32 Yet even if historically posterior, the latter is now
enshrined in ordinary linguistic usage.
In order for this more inclusive conception of the beautiful to
become reflectively available, the average person needs to consult
not only their linguistic habits but also their patterns of emotional
response—specifically how they respond to the kinds of virtuous
qualities outlined above. “The person characterised by them natu-
rally arouses love (ma ḥbūb biʾl- ṭabʿ) in all those who become cog-
nisant of his features.” Witness the love we experience towards
religious exemplars, such as the prophet Muḥammad, his compan-
ions, and the founders of the schools of law. Our love cannot attach
to the physical form of these figures—that agglomerate of “bones,
flesh, and skin”—as this has long turned to dust. It attaches rather
to the inner form constituted by these praiseworthy characteristics.
It is these characteristics that ground a person’s identity, making it
the case that “Abū Bakr al-Ṣiddīq was Abū Bakr al-Ṣiddīq,”33 and the
form they constitute endures through time.34
The moral and intellectual virtues such figures possess thus spell out
a non-physical form of beauty that we register when we respond with
love. This emotional response—to complete al-Ghazālī’s thought and
draw certain ideas together—tracks a relation of natural fitness that
looks in two directions. On the one hand, these virtues constitute the
proper perfection of their possessors’ nature as human beings. Like
many of his philosophical predecessors, al-Ghazālī refers the concept
of beauty to the concept of perfection. An entity is beautiful when
“it realises the perfection appropriate to and possible for it.” In the
fuller expression of the Exalted Aim, “when the inner form is perfect,
harmoniously constituted, and unites all perfections appropriate to
it, as it ought and in the manner it ought, it is beautiful in relation to
the insight that perceives it”—suited to the observer in a way that pro-
duces in him a sense of joy and delight.35 Beauty, as this remark flags,
is always relative to a perceiver. And taken as an object of perception,
the perfection of others’ nature also represents the natural fulfilment
of the observers’ special cognitive power as human beings.
One important point this also brings out is that the emotional
response at issue is no brute passion, as a long-standing tradition with
both modern and pre-modern supporters would have it, representing
emotions as blind pushes and pulls fundamentally opposed to reason.
Emotions, here, respond to reasons; our love of these exemplars is
based on a judgement about their moral features and is justified on
that basis. In another book of the Revival, al-Ghazālī brings up the
Moral beauty 23
relation between cognitions or beliefs (maʿārif ), states (aḥwāl), and
actions (aʿmāl), and explains that actions result from states, and states
from cognitions. “States,” in al-Ghazālī’s adaptation of this Sufi term,
typically refers to emotions.36 This cognitivist view of emotions is
reflected in his present discussion.
Returning to al-Ghazālī’s previous statement about long-dead figures,
his point can be taken as an attempt to address a puzzle that inevitably
comes up once we accept that we can experience emotional reactions
towards beings that lack physical realisation in the natural world. When
we love a person who lacks physical embodiment for their moral char-
acter, what exactly is it we love? This is a puzzle that comes up equally
whether we’re considering deceased historical characters or imaginary
characters, such as those we meet in fictional works, notwithstanding
the differences between the two cases. With regard to the latter, many
philosophers of art would recognise this as the special problem some-
times labelled the “paradox of fiction.”37 One option would be to say that
what we love is simply the mental representation we have of that char-
acter, regardless of whether there is an actually existing entity that this
is a representation of. Al-Ghazālī, as I read his account, does not want
to take that option (in this respect, he appears uninterested in the emo-
tional responses we might have to purely fictional characters). Instead,
he seems to want to insist that the object of our love has actual existence
external to our mind, and that its existence is temporally enduring.
This begs two obvious questions. In what sense do the non-physical
(moral) features in question endure? And just how do we have epistemic
access to the non-physical (moral) form they spell out? Of these ques-
tions, it is the latter that receives the clearest answer in al-Ghazālī’s
discussion, one that locates his account firmly within the literary prac-
tices of his religious community while also forging links to a wider
context. For a religious believer, access to the religious exemplars of
the historical past is provided by narratives, oral and written. We may
think of the hadith reports detailing the Prophet’s conduct and of
the variety of genres recording the biographies of eminent individu-
als in the Islamic world, such as biographical dictionaries and works
belonging to the genre of laudatory (manāqib) literature. The Prophet
in particular was the focus of a specific literary genre, the shamāʾil (lit-
erally “characteristics”), which built on hadith reports to offer a con-
centrated account of the Prophet’s perfections that both reflected and
was designed to evoke attitudes of admiration and love.38 For a coun-
terpart outside the Islamic world, we only need to think of Plutarch’s
Lives. It is such narratives (siyar), al-Ghazālī indicates, that provide
epistemic access to the moral character of historical individuals.
24 Moral beauty
In certain parts of his discussion, al-Ghazālī encourages us to think
that this way of answering the question about epistemic access to
moral features translates into the following answer to the metaphysi-
cal question about their mode of realisation and temporal endurance:
the beauteous form of these individuals exists in these narratives
(al-jamāl mawjūd fiʾl-siyar).39 Yet closer investigation suggests that, for
al-Ghazālī, this explanation is incomplete. Taken alone, this explana-
tion would allow for the possibility that the object of our love should
be a mere mental construct with no mind-independent correlate.
Al-Ghazālī distances himself from this possibility by making a couple
of related links. On one level, he stakes the claim that there is a causal
relation between the virtuous character of these individuals and the
narratives that represent this character. Such “praiseworthy fea-
tures … are the sources of beautiful accounts [of their lives]” (al- ṣifāt
al-maḥmūda…hiya ma ṣādir al-siyar al-jamīla). Yet this relation is not
merely historical. The implication is that, unlike the physical form
which perishes, these features still endure, and that the statements
found in different narratives are true because the object to which they
refer still exists. It is this existing object to which our own emotional
response attaches when we hear or see it described and we react with
love. “The thing loved is the source of the accounts, that is to say, the
praiseworthy character traits and noble virtues.”40
The above is an attempt to reconstruct al-Ghazālī’s understanding
on the basis of evidence that is not always explicit and unambiguous.
Al-Ghazālī’s interest in this context is not in teasing out these metaphys-
ical and epistemological implications. As reconstructed, his view would
seem to presuppose some version of the immaterial survival of the soul,
in which these kinds of features would inhere. It leaves open a number
of puzzles, including how we might understand the endurance of moral
features that, on al-Ghazālī’s view, only make sense relative to the need to
govern the physical body.41 Also less than fully developed is al-Ghazālī’s
understanding of the exact modality through which verbal and literary
representations can evoke an emotional response to moral virtue. This
seems all the more remarkable given the deep conviction reflected in his
discussion concerning the power of narratives to induce such response.
Now this account of the relationship between the value of action and
character as presented in the Revival is not the same as an explanation
of the relationship between the viewpoints of the two sets of works,
action-focused and virtue-focused. Yet if we take our bearings from
this account, it will be hard to see how the differential focus of each
36 A conflict in al-Ghazālī’s ethics?
set could explain the overall differences in their viewpoints on ethical
value, and why positions that al-Ghazālī adopted vis-à-vis one evalua-
tive object (action) should cease to apply vis-à-vis another (virtue). As
the last quotation suggests, action may not be the ultimate resting place
of our judgement “fine,” but our judgement rests on it nevertheless; and
although its value may be relative, it crucially presupposes a judgement
about what has non-derivative intrinsic value.21 This is a view to which it
is difficult to imagine the al-Ghazālī of the Moderation assenting.
Coming from the Revival, it is in fact easy to envisage how many
of the standard Muʿtazilite examples of morally interesting behaviour
might in principle be re-described using virtue terms. Keeping an
oath at pain of death: an instance of fidelity and courage. Saving the
drowning and helping the blind: an instance of kindness and benevo-
lence. This is a redescription that the al-Ghazālī of the Revival would
wholeheartedly approve of. Yet what is interesting is that the possi-
bility of such a move is signalled by the Quintessence itself, for all its
monocular focus on action as an object of evaluation. Reporting on
the Muʿtazilites, he states their claim that all intelligent beings judge
it good to “show fortitude before the sword” (al- ṣabr ʿalaʾl-sayf ) rather
than betray one’s faith; nobody would deny that the noble traits of
character (makārim al-akhlāq) are fine things.22
These and other considerations make it impossible to keep the
accounts of the two sets of works apart and to prevent them from enter-
ing into relations; and once brought together, they would appear to
be in open conflict. What makes al-Ghazālī’s position in the Revival
doubly remarkable, viewed against the history of theological debates
about ethics, is the following observation. In these debates, the aesthetic
application of the term “fine” or “good” (ḥasan) had been weaponised
by Ashʿarites against the Muʿtazilite position. Al-Ghazālī himself pro-
vides an exemplary specimen of this pattern of argument in both the
Moderation and the Quintessence. Judgements of “moral” approval
regarding actions are not objective, reason-based, and universal—they
are as relative, temperament-based, and idiosyncratic as judgements of
“aesthetic” approval. One person finds x beautiful, another does not.
Wasn’t that exactly what al-Ghazālī said about our moral responses?
One person finds x good, another does not. The following remark from
the Quintessence brings the argument into full view:
In the Revival, the appeal to “nature” serves to make a claim about the
universality of aesthetic reactions. “Nature” means “human nature.”
Here, by contrast, it refers to individual nature, to what is peculiar to
each person rather than shared by all. Aesthetic reactions are taken
to reflect this peculiar nature and to vary accordingly. Nothing in
this discussion or the discussion of the Moderation allows the reader
to entertain the hypothesis that there might be a form of aesthetic
response that is universal and that responds to a moral kind of beauty.
The two views of aesthetic experience are not, after all, mutually
exclusive; it is possible to hold that certain responses are purely indi-
vidual while others are universal. In al-Ghazālī’s own time, this view
was clearly enunciated by a philosopher with whose oeuvre al-Ghazālī
had more than a passing acquaintance, Abū ʿAlī Miskawayh (d. 1030).
In a compendium of questions and answers exchanged with the litter-
ateur Abū Ḥayyān al-Tawḥīdī (d. 1023), Miskawayh fields a question
about what causes us to judge certain kinds of forms beautiful or fine
(istiḥsān al-ṣūra al-ḥasana). He replies by making a distinction between
a “universal and essential” (dhātī kullī) response, which we experience
towards forms that nature has been most successful in imprinting on
matter and that thus correspond most faithfully to the transcendent
ideal found in the soul, and a “particular and accidental” (ʿaraḍī juzʾī)
response that is relative to the (imbalanced) humoural mixture of given
individuals. In the latter case, “what one person finds pleasant the other
finds repugnant, and vice versa.”24 If al-Ghazālī is aware of this type of
possibility, he gives no sign of it, and makes no use of it that would allow
us to unify his positions.
In the above, I have helped myself to the labels “moral” and “aesthetic”
in distinguishing between the different applications of the term ḥasan.
This reflects the kind of conceptual distinctions we ourselves find it nat-
ural to make on both a theoretical and ordinary-language level. Thus,
although I did my best to stick to my principled translation of ḥasan as
“fine” in the above, this translation comes under strain in kalām texts,
and in many regards, it seems more natural to translate “good” or “right”
in one case and “beautiful” in the other. Yet the terms “moral” and
“aesthetic” have no exact counterpart in the parlance of the texts and
thinkers we are considering. This raises an important question about the
relationship between these two meanings of ḥusn which is of immediate
38 A conflict in al-Ghazālī’s ethics?
relevance for the point under discussion. In what sense are they distinct,
from the perspective of these thinkers, in the absence of a definite termi-
nological demarcation? Does this assumption reflect our own theoreti-
cal and linguistic prejudices rather than real features of the intellectual
schemes of these Muslim thinkers? As we saw earlier, this is a question
that has a counterpart in the case of the Greek term kalon. One argu-
ment we reviewed (Irwin’s) suggested that Aristotle, for his part, clearly
distinguished between two different senses of the word, “morally right”
and “beautiful,” recognising these as two distinct properties. What about
these philosophical speakers of Arabic?
Now it is important to keep in mind that the theological works writ-
ten by Ashʿarites, Muʿtazilites, and others were polemical in nature,
and the positions expressed were always functional to some argu-
mentative end. The argumentative ends of Ashʿarite theologians, as
the above makes clear, were best served by refusing to make a strong
distinction between different semantic dimensions of the terms ḥasan
and qabī ḥ.25 Things were otherwise for the Muʿtazilites, who, for obvi-
ous reasons, were deeply invested in developing that distinction and
putting clear blue water between (what we may call) the terms’ moral
and aesthetic applications. This reflects the important fact that the
Muʿtazilites accepted the Ashʿarite understanding of aesthetic experi-
ence as relative, idiosyncratic, temperament-based.
In his magnum opus, The Sufficiency in God’s Unity and Justice, the
Baṣran Muʿtazilite thinker ʿAbd al-Jabbār (d. 1025) makes the point by
distinguishing between the different objects to which the term qabī ḥ
may be applied—actions on the one hand and physical forms on the
other—and between the basis on which it is applied in each case. The
application of the term to actions is based on cognitive judgements of
desert shared by all people. When an action is called “bad” (qabī ḥ),
this means that a person who freely chooses it deserves blame for per-
forming it unless mitigating circumstances are present. Thus, “every
person endowed with reason (ʿāqil) knows that someone who commits
injustice deserves blame on that account, unless a preventative factor
arises.” The application of the term to physical forms is based on con-
tingent emotional reactions of repugnance or attraction which vary
from person to person and even from time to time. Thus, “a [physi-
cal] form is called ‘ugly’ (qabī ḥ) insofar as one finds it repugnant to
look at it.”26 Especially important is the specific suggestion that ʿAbd
al-Jabbār offers about how to understand the relationship between
these meanings. He identifies two possible positions: that both mean-
ings are proper or primary (ḥaqīqa), and that one is proper and the
other figurative or metaphorical (majāz). His own stated preference
A conflict in al-Ghazālī’s ethics? 39
lies with the latter view: it is the meaning that is sound from the per-
spective of reason (ya ṣiḥḥu ʿaqlan) that is proper and the term is applied
to physical objects by way of resemblance or analogy (tashabbuh).27
ʿAbd al-Jabbār’s definition of the term in its moral sense, of course,
reflects the basic commitments of the Muʿtazilites. And taken as an
account of ordinary linguistic usage, it was contested by Ashʿarite
thinkers (recall al-Ghazālī’s account of good and bad as whatever
agrees with the speaker’s purposes). It is not my concern here to adju-
dicate between these competing accounts, though at a minimum, we
might agree that taking “conformity with a rational perspective” as
a criterion is probably not the best methodological foundation for a
faithful descriptive account of actual linguistic usage. The important
point to notice, however, is that Muʿtazilite thinkers had thus made a
distinction between different semantic dimensions of the ḥasan-qabī ḥ
pair, “moral” and “aesthetic,” albeit avant la lettre. As an Ashʿarite
polemicist, al-Ghazālī would likely have been familiar with this way of
articulating the distinction. This is what makes it so striking that in his
discussion in the Revival, he should make no allusion to the issue and
give no evidence of recognising that the space for such a distinction
might fundamentally exist, let alone provide a principled account of
it to vie with the Muʿtazilites’. Doing so, crucially, would have meant
forging direct links between the type of discussion taking place in
works of dialectical theology and the type of discussion undertaken in
the Revival and affiliated works.
Al-Ghazālī comes close to offering a principled view of this type of
semantic relation in connection with the concept of beauty ( jamāl), as
we saw earlier. Referring to its two applications in the Exalted Aim—
to outward and inward form—he identifies the latter as a historically
posterior semantic expansion. Yet among other things, it is signifi-
cant that the focus of these comments is the term jamāl. This term, as
mentioned earlier, featured strongly in texts influenced by philosoph-
ical ideas, but it was not the term that organised theological debates
about ethics. The key term in these debates was ḥusn. In the Revival,
al-Ghazālī treats the terms ḥusn and jamāl as interchangeable, often
juxtaposing them in the same breath, and he says nothing that would
call to mind the special life the former concept had led in theological
debates. Above all, he does not engage with the semantic distinctions
that certain parties to this debate had made between the ethical and
aesthetic applications of this concept. This is also a way of saying that
he marks no distinction comparable to Aristotle’s, and ultimately
provides no explicit account of the relation between the good and the
beautiful on our terms.
40 A conflict in al-Ghazālī’s ethics?
The effect of this, combined with everything mentioned above, is
to make one wonder whether al-Ghazālī was going out of his way to
discourage the reader from considering the links between the two
contexts represented by his legal/theological and philosophical/Sufi
ethical works. And even if we don’t go so far as to attribute to him a
deliberate intention to thwart certain natural comparisons, the prob-
lem is one and the same: the viewpoints expressed by al-Ghazālī in
these two separate contexts appear to be in fundamental conflict.
6 Resolving the conflict
An interpretive toolbox
Chronology
The first strategy is the simplest: it takes the appearance of conflict
at face value and postulates that it is the result of intellectual change.
This strategy has the virtue of recognising that even the greatest
thinkers may change their minds on important issues over their life-
time. This was the solution adopted by Montgomery Watt, for exam-
ple, when faced with the most philosophical of al-Ghazālī’s treatises
on ethics, The Scale of Action, which he found to be incompatible
with the critical view of philosophical ethics he took to be expressed
in al-Ghazālī’s autobiography, the Deliverer from Error. His opinion
was that al-Ghazālī likely rejected much of what he had written in
that treatise as his enthusiasm for philosophy deflated. The momen-
tous events depicted in the Deliverer, where al-Ghazālī chronicles the
rupture his social and professional life underwent in 1095 following
his dramatic decision to abandon his teaching post and family life
in Baghdad and devote himself to the practice of Sufism, have often
served as a keystone for this type of interpretation, with his “spiritual
conversion” taken to herald seismic changes on an intellectual level.2
This understanding of al-Ghazālī’s biography has come under heated
criticism more recently, and there has been a considerable body of work
highlighting the continuity in his intellectual commitments, particularly
his commitments to philosophical views (including views on ethics).3 Yet
be that as it may, this strategy is of no help in the present case, for the
simple reason that the works in which al-Ghazālī expresses apparently
conflicting views resist arrangement in a suitably tidy chronological
order. On one widely accepted view, the Revival was written after the
Moderation (which was likely written in the same year as the Scale) and
before the Quintessence.4 That is, it was sandwiched between two works
in which al-Ghazālī appears to defend traditional Ashʿarite views.
Doctrine of discourse
The term was coined by Timothy Gianotti in a book dedicated to set-
tling the fractious question of al-Ghazālī’s understanding of the soul
as expressed across different works.5 The concept, however, is much
older. On one account, in fact, it was introduced by al-Ghazālī himself
in a much-discussed passage at the end of the Scale. Asked to state his
doctrine (madhhab) in the book—is it ranged with Ashʿarite doctrine
Resolving the conflict 43
or with Sufism?6 —he distinguished between three doctrinal levels, or
three senses in which we might speak of a person’s doctrine. There’s
the doctrine to which one pledges allegiance in public disputations,
which depends on environmental and geographical contingencies and
inherited loyalties (that’s how one person ends up a Muʿtazilite, say,
and another an Ashʿarite); the doctrine one teaches, which depends
on the understanding and capabilities of one’s student; and the doc-
trine one privately believes based on the results of one’s own reflec-
tive inquiry, which one only shares with those who share one’s level of
comprehension. Al-Ghazālī concluded with an admonition to inquire
into the truth independently and to avoid pre-packaged doctrines.7
Numerous commentators past and present, beginning from
Ibn Ṭufayl, have converged in regarding this passage as the key for
unlocking al-Ghazālī’s work and resolving its apparent tensions.
From this standpoint, these tensions are no accident, but the result
of a deliberate and judiciously chosen method on al-Ghazālī’s part.
Specifically, the positions that al-Ghazālī expresses need to be consid-
ered against the genre of the particular work in which they appear and
against al-Ghazālī’s reflective view of the nature and function (and
hence audience) of that genre. Each genre, Gianotti notes, has its own
“parameters and qualifications”; once we have taken stock of this and
relativised al-Ghazālī’s statements to the relevant genre, “perceived
conflicts between statements belonging to separate genres are rendered
far less problematic.”8 This hermeneutic incorporates a pro tanto com-
mitment to the fundamental consistency of al-Ghazālī’s work. In the
words of Richard Frank, one of the best-known latter-day exponents
of this approach: “There is a basic, integrated theoretical system that
underlies al-Ghazālī’s logical and theological writings, orders them,
and gives them consistency.” Al-Ghazālī’s oeuvre turns out to be an
“essentially consistent, albeit rhetorically modulated, address” to his
intellectual community.9
This obviously requires a careful sorting of the different genres
that al-Ghazālī plied, a task that both Frank and Gianotti undertake.
Without going into the details, I will mention one shared element of
their analysis, and this is the emphasis on the epistemic limitations of
one specific discourse, namely, dialectical theology (kalām). Dialectical
theology, in al-Ghazālī’s view, has indeed a legitimate function in the
religious community, to defend correct theological doctrine against
heresy. Yet its role is purely defensive, and its disputational character
and dialectical reliance on endoxa (mashhūrāt) make it a poor instru-
ment for the discovery of truth (kashf al- ḥaqāʾiq wa-maʿrifatuhā ʿalā
mā hiya ʿalayhi).10 The inferior epistemic status of theological works is
44 Resolving the conflict
reflected in the profile of their intended audience. Frank describes both
the Moderation and the Jerusalem Epistle—the short theological tract
incorporated in the Revival—as “lower-level handbooks” for “simple,
uneducated people.”11 In Frank’s view, al-Ghazālī’s theological works
are Ashʿarite solely in veneer and camouflage his true metaphysics,
which rather owes to Avicenna. If we wish to hear al-Ghazālī’s real
views, we should look away from his theological works.
Now how might this help us approach our present question?
Following the example of these commentators, one obvious possibil-
ity would be to query the depth of al-Ghazālī’s commitment to the
viewpoint on ethics expressed in his theological works (or the theo-
logical segments embedded within his works of legal theory, such as
the Quintessence). Here is one way of fleshing out this possibility more
concretely. Perhaps we should distinguish between the propositions
that constitute the true creed defended in kalām works—and it seems
we must uphold al-Ghazālī’s commitment to the truth of that12—and
between the arguments used in such works to defend them. Perhaps
al-Ghazālī’s rejection of ethical rationalism and objectivism should
be seen as merely dialectical: a claim he thought effective for defend-
ing the proposition that really mattered, but not necessarily true. The
proposition that really mattered is that God is not subject to obliga-
tion. It was this proposition that Muʿtazilites had denied, and their
claims about ethical rationalism and objectivism had also been devel-
oped in a functional relationship to it.13
I will be returning to this last proposal shortly from another direc-
tion. Yet how satisfying does this view seem in the present context?
On the one hand, it will resonate with those of us who have often been
beset by a not dissimilar suspicion of dialectical theology as a genre,
and who have wondered how its rigid rules of operation and artifi-
cial polarities of polemical engagement affected the spirit in which
inquiry was pursued, and whether they supported the intellectual
qualities required for the best sort of inquiry to flourish, such as good
faith, open-mindedness, and intellectual honesty. (This would also be
al-Ghazālī’s moral complaint against dialectical theology: that it fos-
ters a pernicious pride and love of glory.) This translates into a sneak-
ing suspicion that perhaps theologians did not always quite believe the
things they declared to great fanfare.
But there is a more germane observation.14 Because if we are to take
the genre of writing in which certain claims appear as a basis for quali-
fying the epistemic status of these claims, this needs to be done consist-
ently. This means that we also need to take into account the nature of
the competing genre (or discourse, given its mould-breaking qualities)
Resolving the conflict 45
in the case we are considering, the one represented by the Revival. Now
certainly the Revival is a work that is more hand-over-heart in certain
obvious ways. It is literally a guide to matters of the heart, and its mis-
sion is to guide its readers along the true road to the true salvation.
Importantly, the Revival also internally includes an evaluation of differ-
ent discourses (a topic of book 1, On Knowledge), and internally declares
its superiority to the discourses of dialectical theology and law. There is
a nice analogy here: just as law ( fiqh) does not deliver the highest form of
practical knowledge required for this spiritual journey (what al-Ghazālī
calls ʿilm al-muʿāmala), so dialectical theology does not deliver the high-
est form of metaphysical knowledge (what he calls ʿilm al-mukāshafa).
Yet the rub is that the Revival does not take it upon itself to provide
the latter kind of knowledge either, often alluding to it but always hast-
ily pulling down the veil over it, in a constant and provocative exercise
of self-limitation. Its stated province is the domain of the practical.
In Gianotti’s description (echoing many other readers’), the Revival is
“designed to be a detailed and accessible handbook for human perfec-
tion.”15 Its goal is to help its readers become better people—the kind
of people they need to be in order to achieve ultimate happiness. This
practical aim explains the overall “non-confrontational style” of the
book, as Taneli Kukkonen has observed, which makes al-Ghazālī
steer clear of the more pugilistic treatment of abstract issues that typi-
fies his theological and legal works.16 While al-Ghazālī does deal with
a host of issues on higher-level terms (the account of love we have seen
is a prime example), he does so within the more-or-less firm bounda-
ries dictated by his practical aims.
Now clearly, al-Ghazālī needs to tell his readers what (he believes)
represents the true road to happiness. But that is eminently compatible
with not telling them the whole truth, and sticking to the truths that
are absolutely essential on a strict need-to-know basis. Readers look-
ing to mend their souls, for example, don’t need to understand the true
nature of the soul (ḥaqīqatuhā fī dhātihā); they only need to under-
stand its qualities and states (ṣifatuhā wa-aḥwāluhā).17 And here is a
key point to consider. In the polemical discussions of ethics featured
in his theological (and legal) works, al-Ghazālī had ultimately con-
ceded to the Muʿtazilites that ordinary people make apparently deon-
tological moral judgements and even choose to act in certain ways that
do not appear to serve their interest and potentially conflict with it.
(Even minds bent to the rigid rules of operation and artificial polari-
ties of polemical engagement of kalām eventually had to acknowledge
such empirical phenomena.) This was the newest and most devastat-
ing Ashʿarite strategy: grant that people make such judgements and
46 Resolving the conflict
perform such actions, but question what really stands behind them.
As al-Ghazālī put it in the Quintessence, “we do not deny that such
judgements are widespread among people and are praiseworthy and
widely accepted (maḥmūda mashhūra)”; rather we deny their founda-
tion (mustanad). His ruthless analysis had suggested that this foun-
dation was invariably egoism, suitably harnessed and moulded by
psychological and social processes.18 To use a modern expression,
the al-Ghazālī of the Moderation and the Quintessence subscribed to
the “veneer theory” of morals. Al-Ghazālī’s more immediate frame
of reference was Avicenna’s analysis of moral judgements as widely
accepted propositions (endoxa or mashhūrāt). Yes, people widely make
such judgements, but this says nothing about their epistemic creden-
tials. It would certainly be a mistake to assume such judgements are
grounded in pure reason, as the Muʿtazilites alleged.19
With this in mind, al-Ghazālī’s discussion of moral beauty may
appear in a new light. Given the practical aims of the Revival, is it
not conceivable that al-Ghazālī may have weighed the options and
decided that from a pedagogical perspective, the moral endoxa were
best left untouched? That the best course was to leave his readers to
the phenomena—to their ordinary moral reactions—and to draw
a veil of silence over his higher-level view of their true nature and
foundation, as revealed in his works of Ashʿarite theology? Between
Muʿtazilite moral objectivism and the Ashʿarite deconstructive
alternative, it’s not hard to say which meta-ethical position is likely
to have better results on the plane of concrete ethical practice. That,
for example, was the reason one later thinker, the Ḥanbalite the-
ologian Ibn Taymiyya (d. 1328), would take up arms against the
Ashʿarite position: it makes for bad ethics (or what’s the same, bad
religion).20 If you think “good” picks out a real property, you’re
more likely to do it.
Thus, one genre seems too dialectical, the other too practical, to
supply an expression of the undiluted truth. Is this the final word to
be pronounced on the topic? I am not too sure. It is not clear to me,
for example, whether the hypothesis just outlined—that al-Ghazālī
stood by the Ashʿarite view of value in the Revival but calculatingly
suppressed it for pedagogical reasons—is entirely consistent with the
role the antagonistic claims are asked to play in the Revival. We may
remember that the human reaction to ethical value (moral beauty)
serves al-Ghazālī as a basis for articulating an ideal of the superior
form of love we can and should direct to God. Within al-Ghazālī’s
scheme, there could be few higher spiritual stakes. Similarly, in
this part of his discussion, al-Ghazālī does not merely let common
Resolving the conflict 47
intuitions be—he enthusiastically embellishes them in calligraphic
print. His affirmation of the existence of a disinterested form of love is
simply too strong and explicit.
There is other evidence one could consider from both sides. In short,
the argument is not over. What my brief discussion at the very least
suggests is that this argument is complex and any solution is unlikely
to please all parties.
Supercharged hermeneutics
For certain of al-Ghazālī’s readers, this type of strategy is inherently
dissatisfactory and should be avoided at all costs. Frank Griffel,
for example, has objected to the use of al-Ghazālī’s remarks in the
Scale as an interpretive key to his project, particularly when coupled
with a division of his works into the “esoteric” and “exoteric.” Such
approaches are usually both a consequence and a cause of shirking the
duties of interpretation. As he acerbically puts it:
Section 1
1. In the epigram, I rely on the translation of the Symposium by Reginald
E. Allen (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1993).
2. The quote is from Jan A. Aersten, Medieval Philosophy and The Transcenden-
tals: The Case of Thomas Aquinas (Leiden: E.J. Brill, 1996), though Aersten
himself isolates kalokagathia as the relevant notion in this context. Just how
to understand the Janus-faced nature of the term kalon, and how to handle
the challenges it poses on translation level, is a question that still attracts
debate. Good starting points for considering these questions are Terence
H. Irwin, “The Sense and Reference of Kalon in Aristotle,” Classical Phi-
lology 105 (2010), 381–396 (Special Issue: Beauty, Harmony, and the Good,
ed. Elizabeth Asmi), and Aryeh Kosman, “Beauty and the Good: Situating
the Kalon,” Classical Philology 105 (2010), 341–357.
3. Kosman, “Beauty and the Good,” 344, though this remark reflects a par-
ticular dialectical stage of his discussion, and Kosman himself is not
arguing this gulf. Cf. Irwin’s related remarks in “Sense and Reference,”
381–382.
4. Panos Paris, “On Form, and the Possibility of Moral Beauty,” Metaphi-
losophy 49 (2018), 711–729.
5. Berys Gaut, Art, Emotion and Ethics (Oxford: Oxford University Press,
2007), 117; Colin McGinn, Ethics, Evil, and Fiction (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1999), 98–99.
6. Charlotte Brontë, Jane Eyre (New York and London: W. W. Norton &
Company, 2001), 62.
7. David Hume, Treatise of Human Nature, ed. L. A. Selby-Bigge, rev. P. H.
Nidditch (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1978, 2nd edn), 470.
8. On the Symposium, see Dimitri Gutas, “Plato’s Symposion in the Ara-
bic Tradition,” Oriens 31 (1988), 36–60, and for a general survey of
the reception of Platonic writings, idem, “Platon. Tradition arabe,”
in Dictionnaire des Philosophes Antiques, vol. Va, ed. Richard Goulet
(Paris: Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique, 2012), 845–863.
For the Theology of Aristotle, see Peter Adamson, The Arabic Plotinus:
A Study of The Theology of Aristotle (London: Duckworth, 2002).
9. Two gateway discussions of this theme in Sufi thought are Kazuyo
Murata, Beauty in Sufism: The Teachings of Rūzbihān Baqlī (Albany,
NY: State University of New York Press, 2017) and Cyrus Ali Zargar,
58 Notes
Sufi Aesthetics: Beauty, Love, and the Human Form in Ibn Arabi and
‘Iraqi (Columbia, SC: University of South Carolina Press, 2011). See
also, with a broader brush, William C. Chittick’s brief but illumi-
nating meditation, “The Aesthetics of Islamic Ethics,” in Sharing
Poetic Expressions: Beauty, Sublime, Mysticism in Islamic and Occi-
dental Culture, ed. Anna-Teresa Tymieniecka (Dordrecht; New York:
Springer, 2011), 3–14, whose themes intersect especially closely with
those of the present study.
10. Existing discussions of this theme of al-Ghazālī’s work include Bin-
yamin Abrahamov, Divine Love in Islamic Mysticism: The Teachings
of Al-Ghazâlî and Al-Dabbâgh (London; New York: Routledge, 2003),
Chapter 2; Richard Ettinghausen, “Al-Ghazzālī on Beauty,” in Fine Arts
of Islamic Civilization, ed. Muḥammad Abdul Jabbar Beg (Cambridge:
M. A. J. Beg, 2006), 25–36; Carole Hillenbrand, “Some Aspects of
al-Ghazālī’s Views on Beauty,” in Gott ist schön und Er liebt die Schönheit
(God is Beautiful and He Loves Beauty), ed. Alma Giese and J. Christoph
Bürgel (Bern: Peter Lang, 1994), 249–265; Taneli Kukkonen, “The Good,
the Beautiful and the True: Aesthetical Issues in Islamic Philosophy,”
Studia Orientalia 111 (2011), 87–103; Simon Van Den Bergh, “The ‘Love
of God’ in al-Ghazālī’s Vivification of Theology,” Journal of Semitic
Studies 1 (1956), 305–321; Mohamed Ahmed Sherif, Ghazālī’s Theory of
Virtue (Albany, NY: State University of New York Press, 1975), 145–153;
and José Miguel Puerta Vílchez, Aesthetics in Arabic Thought from
Pre-Islamic Arabia through al-Andalus, trans. Consuelo López-Morillas
(Leiden; Boston, MA: Brill, 2017), Chapter 3.7.
Section 2
1. There have been a number of recent studies and survey pieces explor-
ing the status of aesthetics in Arabic-Islamic culture more generally
and philosophical culture more particularly. They include Deborah
L. Black, “Aesthetics in Islamic Philosophy,” in Routledge Encyclope-
dia of Philosophy, ed. Edward Craig (London; New York: Routledge,
1998), 75–79; Samir Mahmoud, “Beauty and Aesthetics in Classical
Islamic Thought: An Introduction,” Kalam Journal 1 (2018), 7–21;
Valerie Gonzalez, “Beauty and Aesthetic Experience in Classical Ara-
bic Thought,” in Beauty in Islam: Aesthetics in Islamic Art and Archi-
tecture (London: I.B. Tauris, 2001); Aaron Hughes, “‘God is Beautiful
and Loves Beauty’: The Role of Aesthetics in Medieval Islamic and
Jewish Philosophy,” in The Texture of the Divine: Imagination in Medi-
eval Islamic and Jewish Thought (Bloomington; Indianapolis, IN:
Indiana University Press, 2004); Doris Behrens-Abouseif, Beauty in
Arabic Culture (Princeton, NJ: Markus Wiener, 1998); Oliver Leaman,
Islamic Aesthetics (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2004); and
Vílchez, Aesthetics in Arabic Thought.
2. A recognition that I will here assume does not presuppose agreement
on definitional questions such as what makes an experience, attitude, or
property aesthetic, at least when it comes to core cases such as the ones
discussed next in the main text. These definitional questions remain
open to philosophical debate.
Notes 59
3. Al-Ghazālī, The Revival of the Religious Sciences/I ḥyāʾ ʿulūm al-dīn (Cairo:
Lajnat Nashr al-Thaqāfa al-Islāmiyya, 1356–1357 AH [1937–1938]), 9: 1736;
I cite this edition based on the pagination of the Dar al-Shaʿb edition (n.d.).
4. Above all, the pleasure appears to attach to the object simply insofar as it
is seen or heard, and not insofar as it might serve as a means for satisfying
some other desire; we don’t go on to eat the vegetation and we don’t take
pleasure in the birdsong as an indication of where to point our hunting
weapon. Al-Ghazālī’s entire point (which requires him to single out the
most inoffensive forms of sensory pleasure) pivots on that basis.
5. For some extra comment on this point from the perspective of
al-Ghazālī’s understanding of virtue, see my “Does al-Ghazālī Have
a Theory of Virtue?” in Mysticism and Ethics in Islam, ed. Bilal Orfali,
Mohammed Rustom, and Atif Khalil (Beirut: American University of
Beirut Press, forthcoming).
6. The Scale of Action/Mīzān al-ʿamal, ed. Sulaymān Dunyā (Cairo: Dār
al-Maʿārif, 1964), 310–311; cf. 299: “anything that helps satisfy the needs
of the present world also helps with the next, as the next world is reached
through these worldly means.”
7. I ḥyāʾ, 15: 2833. Al-Ghazālī’s The Wisdom in God’s Creation/al-Ḥikma f ī
makhlūqāt Allāh can be read as a companion piece to this book of the
Revival, as can the earlier book dedicated to the topic of gratitude (and
patience: Kitab al-Ṣabr waʾl-shukr), though its specific focus is on the cre-
ated order qua beneficial. For a comment on the Book of Contemplation
from a different direction, see Binyamin Abrahamov, “Al-Ghazālī and
the Rationalization of Sufism,” in Islam and Rationality: The Impact
of al-Ghazālī, vol. 1, ed. Georges Tamer (Leiden: Brill, 2015), 35–48,
though Abrahamov’s “syllogistic thinking” as a translation for tafak-
kur seems too narrow to capture the more empirically oriented type of
inquiry al-Ghazālī considers under this heading. This empirical dimen-
sion is also Ahmed El Shamsy’s emphasis in his remarks on al-Ḥikma
f ī makhlūqāt Allāh in the context of a broader argument in “The Wis-
dom of God’s Law: Two Theories,” in Islamic Law in Theory: Studies in
Jurisprudence in Honor of Bernard Weiss, ed. Robert Gleave and Kevin
Reinhart (Leiden: Brill, 2014), 19–37; see esp. 32–33.
8. Al-Ghazālī’s taxonomy of the different types of relationship in which
we may stand to our physical needs and their material in I ḥyāʾ,
15: 2755–2756, offers a helpful though partial compass for thinking
through this question.
9. See Hillebrand, “Some Aspects,” 257; the Revival’s dedicated discus-
sion of the topic takes place in book 18. Al-Ghazālī’s attitude to music
has complex roots and reflects a philosophical view that found notable
expression in the work of the Ikhwān al-Ṣafāʾ.
Section 3
1. Immanuel Kant, Critique of the Power of Judgment, trans. Paul Guyer
and Eric Matthews (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000),
154. For a fuller development of this observation, see Robert R. Clewis,
The Kantian Sublime and the Revelation of Freedom (Cambridge: Cam-
bridge University Press, 2009), especially Chapter 2.3.
60 Notes
2. See Arthur Schopenhauer, The World as Will and Representation, trans.
E. F. J. Payne (New York: Dover Publications, 1966), 1: 206–207.
3. Irwin, “Sense and Reference,” 381.
4. Ibid, 395.
5. Though jamāl is more hospitable to the latter, more aesthetically
valenced two options. As Franz Rosenthal points out, there is a small
minority of words denoting what is good or excellent that cannot be
used in an aesthetic sense (“On Art and Aesthetics in Graeco-Arabic
Wisdom Literature,” in his Four Essays on Art and Literature in Islam
[Leiden: Brill, 1971], 12). Jayyid is one example; khayr is another. From
the other direction, Doris Behrens-Abouseif notes that there are a few
terms that denote physical beauty which do not admit a moral applica-
tion, such as malī ḥ or wasīm (Beauty in Arabic Culture, 17). Be that as it
may, the evidence both of ordinary language and of intellectual articu-
lations such as those we will be considering here weighs heavily against
her surprising claim concerning “the separation between the good and
the beautiful in Arabic culture” (ibid, 8). Speculating on the question
which sense—moral or aesthetic—was historically prior, Rosenthal
draws on the evidence of Akkadian to suggest that in at least one case,
jamīl, it was the former, and that the original meaning of the word was
“obliging,” “kind,” and the like (“Art and Aesthetics,” 12–13).
6. Al-Rāghib al-Iṣfahānī, An Exposition of the Obscure Terms of the Qurʾan/
Mufradāt f ī gharīb al-Qurʾān, ed. Ṣafwān ʿAdnān Dawūdī (Damascus:
Dār al-Qalam; Beirut: al-Dār al-Shāmiyya, 2009, 4th edn), 202 (al-jamāl
[huwa] al- ḥusn al-kathīr). Compare the definition of jamāl in the Lisān
al-ʿarab and the Tāj al-ʿArūs; the term ḥusn appears as a definiens in
both works. See respectively Ibn Manẓūr, The Arabic Tongue/Lisān
al-ʿarab (Beirut: Dār Ṣādir, 1956), 11:126 and Murtaḍā al-Zabīdī, The
Bridal Crown from the Gems of the Dictionary/Tāj al-ʿArūs min jawāhir
al-Qāmūs, ed. Maḥmūd Muḥammad al-Tanāḥī, rev. ʿAbd al-Salām
Muḥammad Hārūn and editorial committee (Kuwait: Maṭbaʿat Ḥukū-
mat al-Kuwayt, 1993), 28:236.
7. Part of this awkwardness is a product of the substantive analyses of
the concepts advanced by specific schools. Among Baṣran Muʿtazilites,
for example, “good” (ḥasan) was a superordinate category that incor-
porated three separate qualifications: “obligatory” (wājib), “recom-
mended” or “supererogatory” (nadb and tafa ḍḍul), and “plain good” or
“permissible” (mubā ḥ). See briefly my Moral Agents and their Deserts:
The Character of Mu ʿtazilite Ethics (Princeton, NJ: Princeton Univer-
sity Press, 2008), 72–73, and also 237, n. 5.
8. “Mukhtaṣar min Kitāb ‘al-Akhlāq’ li-Jālīnūs,” in Dirāsāt wa-nu ṣū ṣ
fiʾl-falsafa waʾl-ʿulūm ʿinda al-ʿarab, ed. ʿAbd al-Raḥmān Badawī (Beirut:
al-Muʾassasa al-ʿArabiyya liʾl-Dirāsāt waʾl-Nashr, 1981), 190–211; see,
e.g., p. 199.
9. The Arabic Version of the Nicomachean Ethics, ed. Anna A. Akasoy and
Alexander Fidora, with an introduction and annotated translation by
Douglas M. Dunlop (Leiden: Brill, 2005), 163.10. Usually but not invari-
ably; see the editors’ glossary entry on to kalon. Jamīl is also the term of
choice for kalon in the Arabic translation of the Topics, though the trans-
lator had to reach for more creative alternatives to convey the intricacies
Notes 61
of Aristotle’s remarks about kalon as a homonymous term at 106a20–22.
He opted for naẓīf, whose meanings include both “clean” and “beautiful.”
See the relevant passage in Manṭiq Arisṭū, ed. ʿAbd al-Raḥmān Badawī
(Beirut: Dār al-Qalam; Kuwait: Wakālat al-Maṭbūʿāt, 1980), 2:511.
10. Vílchez, Aesthetics in Arabic Thought, 585.
11. “Mukhtaṣar,” 196.
12. For all the above, see “Uthūlūjiyā Arisṭāṭālīs,” in Plotinus Apud Arabes/
Aflū ṭīn ʿinda al-ʿarab, ed. ʿAbd al-Raḥmān Badawī (Cairo: Maktabat
al-Nahḍa al-Miṣriyya, 1955), 56–64.
13. Adamson, The Arabic Plotinus, 3.2.
14. Abū Naṣr al-Fārābī, On the Perfect State/Mabādiʾ ārā ʾ ahl al-madīna
al-fā ḍila, trans. Richard Walzer (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1985),
83–85. Cf. Avicenna’s remarks in The Book of Salvation/Kitāb al-Najāt,
ed. Majid Fakhry (Beirut: Dār al-Āfāq al-Jadīda, 1985), 281–282: “the
beauty and splendour of an entity consists in its being as is necessary for
it to be (or: as it ought).”
15. See Avicenna, “Risāla fiʾl-ʿishq,” in Jāmiʿ al-badāʾiʿ, ed. Muh ỵ ī al-Dīn Ṣabrī
al-Kurdī (Cairo: Maṭbaʿat al-Saʿāda, 1917), 68–91. Avicenna’s concrete ref-
erence points include well-ordered sounds and tastes, though he takes a
special interest in the response to the physical beauty of human beings.
16. Vílchez suggests that the term jamīl as applied to patience does not
mean “beautiful” but “abundant,” taking this to illustrate the broader
point that “the lexicon related to the root j-m-l in the Quran can rarely
be understood in a purely aesthetic sense” (Aesthetics in Arabic Thought,
64). He is likely basing this point on al-Rāghib’s discussion (Mufradāt,
202: yuqālu ‘ jamīl’…ʿalaʾl-takthīr); but al-Rāghib, it is worth recalling,
defines jamāl as an abundance specifically of ḥusn. The semantic scope
of the latter, of course, is not confined to the aesthetic domain. More
could be said about this, yet what is at the very least clear is that ḥasan
is a term of praise; this is also the force of jamīl in the relevant Qurʾanic
passages. Can the same be said of “abundant”?
17. See Fakhr al-Dīn al-Rāzī, The Keys to the Unseen/Mafātī ḥ al-ghayb
(Beirut: Dār al-Fikr, 1981), 18:106–107, for the above, and for a fuller
explication of the criteria of the appropriate kind of patience. As
al-Rāzī suggests, self-command is ultimately submission to God’s com-
mand (dhālika al- ṣabr lā yakūnu jamīlan; waʾl- ḍābiṭ anna…kulla mā
kāna li- ṭalab ʿubūdiyyat Allāh ta ʿālā kāna ḥasanan wa-illā fa-lā). Note
the unselfconscious reduction of jamīl to ḥasan in this account.
18. Tāj al-ʿArūs, 28:236.
19. Mufradāt, 202. In his discussion of ḥusn (ibid, 235–236), al-Rāghib dis-
tinguishes between a type of fineness/beauty that is accessible to sight
(ba ṣar) and to insight (ba ṣīra); this distinction will play an important
role in al-Ghazālī’s account, as we will see shortly.
Section 4
1. Good starting points for this part of al-Ghazālī’s oeuvre include Sherif,
Ghazālī’s Theory of Virtue; Muhammad Abul Quasem, The Ethics of
al-Ghazālī: A Composite Ethics in Islam (Petaling Jaya: Muhammad
62 Notes
Abul Quasem, 1976); and Kenneth Garden, The First Islamic Reviver:
Abū Ḥāmid al-Ghazālī and His Revival of the Religious Sciences (Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 2014). See also my “Does al-Ghazālī Have a
Theory of Virtue?” for an exploration of some aspects of this intellectual
“partnership” (between Sufi and philosophical ideas) in al-Ghazālī’s
ethics.
2. Just how to understand the relationship between these disparate ethi-
cal emphases is a topic I have explored from one direction in “Virtue
and the Law in al-Ghazālī’s Ethics,” in Islamic Ethics as Educational
Discourse: Thought and Impact of the Classical Muslim Thinker Miska-
wayh, ed. Sebastian Günther and Yassir El Jamouhi (Tübingen: Mohr
Siebeck, 2021).
3. I ḥyāʾ, 8:1434.
4. Ibid.
5. I ḥyāʾ, 1:89.
6. This of course presupposes that the connection between virtue and
beauty may not be transparent to the inquirer. The possibility of this
cognitive shortfall is consistent with al-Ghazālī’s discussion elsewhere,
as we will see.
7. I have discussed this concern further in relation to al-Ghazālī’s and other
intellectuals’ articulation of the virtues of magnanimity and greatness
of spirit in Virtues of Greatness in the Arabic Tradition (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2019); see especially 31–34 and 144 ff. Cf. Panos Paris’
comment on this point in “Moral Beauty and Education,” Journal of
Moral Education 48 (2019), 406–407.
8. The normative accent in the quoted remark is in fact partly a construct
of the context, as al-Ghazālī is distinguishing between different types of
motivation for the pursuit of intellectual understanding, and urging this
motivation over a less salutary type directed to external goods such as
honour and wealth.
9. This idea finds its clearest expression in The Most Exalted Aim in Expound-
ing God’s Beautiful Names/Al-Maqṣad al-asnā fī sharḥ maʿānī asmāʾ Allāh
al-ḥusnā, ed. Fadlou A. Shehadi (Beirut: Dar El-Machreq, 1971), 126–127.
10. I ḥyāʾ, 13:2335 (innamā al-maḥmūdu f ī nafsihi…kullu mā yajūzu an yū ṣafa
Allāhu ta ʿālā bihi, wa-mā lā yajūzu…fa-laysa bi-kamālin f ī dhātihi).
Though it is one of the main thrusts of the Maqṣad to add a twist to this
view: what is a virtue in God will typically have to be exemplified in a
rather different sense by human beings.
11. Maqṣad, 44.
12. This may of course seem question-begging, and not to fully address the
depth of the concern framed above. See the concluding section for an
additional set of remarks that place this point in context.
13. Love of an object, after all, depends on awareness of that object, as
al-Ghazālī points out in On Love (I ḥyāʾ, 14:2574). This is also a key
theme of the discussion in Maqṣad; see especially 42 ff.
14. I ḥyāʾ, 14:2574. Once again this echoes ideas expressed by the falāsifa;
compare e.g. the discussion in Avicenna, Najāt, 282.
15. There is some textual prevarication as to whether this sense consists in
the heart or is located in the heart: I ḥyāʾ, 14:2575.
16. Ibid.
Notes 63
17. Al-Ghazālī seems to present different drafts of this taxonomy as his
discussion progresses; I rely on the overview provided at ibid, 2581.
18. It may be noted that many of these objects of attachment correspond to
the objectives of the Law (maqā ṣid al-sharī ʿa) as tabulated by legal theo-
rists, including al-Ghazālī himself. Al-Ghazālī clearly tags these objects
as egoistic—a point that can be placed in conversation with his account
of the limitations of jurisprudential science in book 1 of the Revival.
19. There is a related paradox, as we will see shortly, as to why beneficence
2 is not filed under intrinsic love. Further, logically speaking, love of self
is also a form of intrinsic love. I am not the first to notice certain wrin-
kles in al-Ghazālī’s presentation, or to attempt to iron them out; from
a different direction, see e.g. Abrahamov, Divine Love, 51, and Van Den
Bergh, “The ‘Love of God’,” 314.
20. Al-Ghazālī unfolds this argument in concentration at I ḥyāʾ, 14:2581–2592.
21. This is the sort he describes as the “profound true love that can be
trusted to endure” at ibid, 2577.
22. Ibid.
23. In combination, more broadly, with the ancient tendency to make the
ethical focus the quality of our lives as a whole. Good starting points
for thinking through these questions are Julia Annas, The Morality of
Happiness (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993), Chapter 2.7; idem,
Intelligent Virtue (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011), 152–163; and
more briefly with reference to Aristotle, Terence H. Irwin, The Develop-
ment of Ethics, vol. 1: From Socrates to the Reformation (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2007), §114.
24. I ḥyāʾ, 14:2577–2578.
25. Ibid, 2578.
26. Scruton, Art and Imagination: A Study in the Philosophy of Mind (South
Bend, IN: St Augustine’s Press, 1998), 148. This view is certainly not
without its critics; see, for example, briefly, Gaut, Art, Emotion and Eth-
ics, Chapter 2.1. This view of aesthetic experience is often taken to sup-
ply important grounds for distinguishing between art and pornography.
Al-Ghazālī himself does not focus on the outward human form as an
aesthetic object, so does not confront the special challenges this poses.
This contrasts interestingly with Avicenna, who takes pains to distin-
guish between two different modes of responding to (of loving) physical
human beauty, one associated with our appetitive animal nature and
the other with our intellectual nature. See “Risāla fiʾl-ʿishq,” 80–83.
27. The World as Will and Representation, 1:197. The therapeutic effect of
exposure to nature is of course also widely discussed outside philosoph-
ical circles these days.
28. See the discussion in Nick Zangwill, The Metaphysics of Beauty (Ithaca,
NY; London: Cornell University Press, 2001), Chapter 8; 127 quoted.
29. See text to notes 4 and 5, Section 1.
30. Or “course of life”; the term can also refer to a record or account of this
course (vita), as will emerge further on.
31. I ḥyāʾ, 14:2578–2579.
32. Maqṣad, 126.
33. An alternative translation is possible: “making the truthful Abū Bakr
truthful.”
64 Notes
34. I ḥyāʾ, 14:2579–2580.
35. See, respectively, I ḥyāʾ, 14:2578, and Maqṣad, 126.
36. “Typically,” though al-Ghazālī’s terminology raises difficult ques-
tions which complicate this statement. For a survey of scholarly
perspectives on the topic and an attempt to resolve these questions,
see my “Does al-Ghazālī Have a Theory of Virtue?” And see I ḥyā ʾ,
12:2171 for the passage cited. Insofar as the love of virtuous exem-
plars incorporates an express judgement of value, al-Ghazālī’s
understanding aligns itself closely with some of the most prominent
recent cognitivist accounts of emotions. See e.g. Martha C. Nuss-
baum, Upheavals of Thought: The Intelligence of Emotions (Cam-
bridge; New York: Cambridge University Press, 2001), for a notable
account along these lines intended to contest the conception of emo-
tions as irrational or brute.
37. For a well-known statement of this “paradox,” see Colin Radford,
“How Can We Be Moved by the Fate of Anna Karenina?” Proceedings
of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes 49 (1975), 67–80. As
Derek Matravers reformulates the point (without endorsing it), it is the
problem posed by the fact that “[a]mongst the causes of an emotion
felt towards p, it is necessary that there be a belief that p is actual, or
likely to be actual, or has been actual”—a condition that our emotional
response to fictional characters and events appears to violate. See his
Fiction and Narrative (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014), 103, and
generally Chapter 8 for critical discussion.
38. For discussion, see Anne-Marie Schimmel, And Mohammed Is His
Messenger: The Veneration of the Prophet in Islamic Piety (Chapel
Hill, NC; London: University of North Carolina Press, 1985), Chap-
ter 2. One of the best-known exemplars of this genre, by the Mālik-
ite jurist and traditionist Qāḍī ʿIyāḍ (d. 1149), dwells at some length
on the necessity of loving the Prophet. See al-Qāḍī ʿIyāḍ, The Cura-
tive Knowledge of the Claims of the Chosen Prophet/al-Shifā ʾ bi-ta ʿrīf
ḥuqūq al-mu ṣṭafā, ed. ʿAlī Muḥammad al-Bajāwī (Beirut: Dār
al-Kitāb al-ʿArabī, 1984), 2:563ff. (Parts of this discussion in fact echo
al-Ghazālī’s account of love in the Revival so closely they can only be
thought of as a direct adaptation of it; see especially 2:579–581.) At
the same time, the author clearly presupposes the existence of such
attitudes in his reader and seems to think of his persuasive aim not so
much to generate them ab ovo as to deepen and develop them, as the
opening lines of 1:77 suggest (“You who love this noble Prophet … and
who are seeking to go beyond generalities to grasp the particulars of
his sublime status …”).
39. I ḥyāʾ, 14:2580.
40. Ibid.
41. On one level, al-Ghazālī theorises the virtues as simply different ways of mas-
tering the bodily appetites and attachments to worldly goods. This is reflected
in his description of the virtues and the vices as, respectively, “dispositions
of domination” (hayʾāt istilāʾiyya) and “dispositions of subservience” (hayʾāt
inqiyādiyya)—that is, relative to the appetites. The Scale of Action/Mīzān
al-ʿamal, ed. Sulaymān Dunyā (Cairo: Dār al-Maʿārif, 1964), 204.
42. A more literal translation: “in describing him as courageous, generous,” etc.
Notes 65
43. I ḥyāʾ, 14:2580.
44. Ibid, cf. 2585.
45. Kukkonen, “The Good, the Beautiful,” 87.
46. Al-Ghazālī has rather more to say on this topic in an earlier book
of the Revival, namely On Intimacy, Brotherhood and Companionship,
where he offers a related but not identical taxonomy of the different types
of love that human beings may attract (I ḥyāʾ, 5:931). The first type, intrin-
sic love, anticipates the discussion of beauty in On Love (ibid, 931–934).
Interestingly, in one passage al-Ghazālī appears to discount this as a form
of love “based [merely] on natural disposition and psychic appetite” (ḥubb
biʾl-ṭabʿ wa-shahwat al-nafs) which even non-believers may experience. It
is unclear from the context, however, whether this evaluation concerns
only the response to physical beauty (mentioned in the vicinity of this
remark) or also to moral beauty, thus declaring the human love based on
the latter inferior to the spiritual companionship that al-Ghazālī goes on
to describe as “love for and in God” (ḥubb liʾl-Lāh wa-fiʾl-Lāh), in which
love of other human beings derives from the relation they bear to God as
the primary object of love. If the latter, it would suggest that the intrinsic
love of moral beauty is deficient insofar as it makes no reference to God,
and that the best way of loving virtue is not for its own sake (under its
aspect as beautiful) but for the sake of God (under its aspect as loved
by God). Cf. e.g. the phrasing at ibid, 938: athmara ḥubba kulli man fīhi
ṣifa murḍiya ʿinda Allāhi min khuluq ḥasan, though this remark admits
of more than one reading. This focus—on evaluative objects as valued
or disvalued qua loved or hated by God—also dominates the perspec-
tive of the book On Meditation, though mainly apropos action. Taken
as an account of the best type of moral motivation (we should love the
virtues because God loves them), my sense is that this interpretation can
be harmonised with al-Ghazālī’s overall approach. Taken as an account
of moral ontology (they are in fact virtues because God loves them), it
seems more problematic, and it would have important implications for
the present discussion, especially for the issues raised in the next section;
but the evidence for it does not seem decisive.
47. Wittgenstein, “Philosophy of Psychology—A Fragment, §25,” in Phil-
osophical Investigations, ed. Peter M. S. Hacker and Joachim Schulte,
trans. G. E. M. Anscombe, Peter M. S. Hacker, and Joachim Schulte
(Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell, 2009, 4th rev. edn).
48. Cf. George Orwell’s well-known epigram, as I read it: “At 50, everyone
has the face he deserves.”
49. Ian James Kidd, “Admiration, Attraction and the Aesthetics of Exemplar-
ity,” Journal of Moral Education 48 (2019), 373–374. See also his “Beauty,
Virtue, and Religious Exemplars,” Religious Studies 53 (2017), 171–181. His
account in turn builds on David E. Cooper’s discussion, e.g. in his “Beau-
tiful People, Beautiful Things,” British Journal of Aesthetics 48 (2008), 247–
260, in the context of a larger and rather radical conception of beauty. Kidd
does not directly address the limitations of this view taken as a general
account of the aesthetic experience of character, given that it is restricted
to exemplars with whom one has “personal” rather than “testimonial” or
“narrative” encounters, on his terms (“Admiration, Attraction,” 370–371).
50. Mīzān, 299.
66 Notes
51. Nietzsche, Twilight of the Idols and the Anti-Christ, trans. R. J. Holling-
dale (London: Penguin, 1990), 40.
52. This is the line suggested by Avicenna, for example, in “Risāla fiʾl-ʿishq,”
81–82. And see Rosenthal, “On Art and Aesthetics,” for some references
to the idea in wisdom literature, with an emphasis on its contestation.
53. Mīzān, 300. Al-Ghazālī’s specification of beauty further down (300–301)
introduces an extra layer of complexity, which I won’t try to grapple
with here.
54. See, respectively, Sara B. Algoe and Jonathan Haidt, “Witnessing Excel-
lence in Action: The ‘Other-Praising’ Emotions of Elevation, Gratitude,
and Admiration,” Journal of Positive Psychology 4 (2009), 105–127;
Jonathan Haidt, “Elevation and the Positive Psychology of Morality,”
in Flourishing: Positive Psychology and the Life Well-Lived, ed. Corey
L. M. Keyes and Jonathan Haidt (Washington, DC: American Psycho-
logical Association, 2003), 275–280; Kristján Kristjánsson, “Emotions
Targeting Moral Exemplarity: Making Sense of the Logical Geography
of Admiration, Emulation and Elevation,” Theory and Research in Edu-
cation 15 (2017), 20–37; Panos Paris, “The Empirical Case for Moral
Beauty,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 96 (2018), 642–656.
55. Compare Ibn Taymiyya’s understanding of human nature as discussed
in my Ibn Taymiyya’s Theological Ethics (New York: Oxford Univer-
sity Press, 2016), Chapter 2, esp. 89–90. Taken together, in fact, all
the above suggests that we must regard al-Ghazālī as one of the most
important influences on the special brand of moral sentimentalism
developed by Ibn Taymiyya, which likewise drew the moral into close
connection with the aesthetic and was articulated as a form of ethi-
cal naturalism. For further comment on al-Ghazālī’s conception of
fi ṭra from a different direction, see Frank Griffel, “Al-Ghazālī’s Use
of “Original Human Disposition” (Fi ṭra) and Its Background in the
Teachings of al-Fārābī and Avicenna,” Muslim World 102 (2012), 1–32.
56. An alternative or complementary explanation is that the Revival is not
the type of work in which al-Ghazālī would confront such challenges;
see the discussion in Section 6.
57. On this point, see, briefly, my “Does al-Ghazālī Have a Theory of Vir-
tue?” As al-Ghazālī puts the point more generally in I ḥyāʾ, 13:2340, using
fa ḍīla in the sense of “value”: “the value of any given thing depends
on its utility for conducing to the happiness that consists in encounter-
ing God” (inna fa ḍīlat al-shayʾ bi-qadr ghināʾihi fiʾl-ifḍāʾ ilā saʿādat liqāʾ
Allāh). The question how these two explanatory views relate could take
interesting discussion.
Section 5
1. Put very briefly: his account of God’s virtues is overwhelmingly nega-
tive and rests on an analytical reduction of the virtues (in their entire
colourful rainbow) to two features, knowledge and power. Both moves
would seem to introduce a gulf between our reaction to God and our
ordinary reactions to human beauty of character.
2. I have especially in mind Paris, “On Form.”
3. “Mukhtaṣar,” 195 ff; 199: mayl al-nās ilaʾl-jamīl biʾl- ṭabʿ kabīr.
Notes 67
4. See Rosenthal, “On Art and Aesthetics.”
5. Arent J. Wensinck’s view (La Pensée de Ghazzālī [Paris: Adrien-Mai-
sonneuve, 1940], 24ff) is approvingly echoed by Richard Walzer in The
Perfect State, 350–351; Van den Bergh makes the same assumption,
though apparently more from prejudice than from evidence, in his
rather patronising discussion in “The ‘Love of God’.” Vílchez also views
al-Ghazālī’s discussion as derivative (Aesthetics in Arabic Thought,
737ff) though his focus is not exclusively on philosophical influences.
6. “On Art and Aesthetics,” 12.
7. Mufradāt, 202 and 235–236, as quoted earlier.
8. For this point, and for al-Rāghib’s influence on al-Ghazālī, see Wilferd
Madelung, “Ar-Rāġib al-Iṣfahānī und die Ethik al-Ġazālīs,” in
Islamwissenschaftliche Abhandlungen Fritz Meier zum sechzigsten
Geburtstag, ed. Richard Gramlich (Steiner: Wiesbaden, 1974), 152–163;
Hans Daiber, “Griechische Ethik in islamischem Gewande: Das Beispiel
von Rāġib al-Iṣfahānī (11. Jh.),” in Historia Philosophiae Medii Aevi: Stu-
dien zur Geschichte der Philosophie des Mittelalters, ed. Burkhard Mojsisch
and Olaf Pluta (Amsterdam; Philadelphia: Grüner, 1991), 1:181–192; Jules
Janssens, “Al-Ghazālī’s Mīzān al-ʿAmal: An Ethical Summa Based on Ibn
Sīnā and al-Rāghib al-Iṣfahānī,” in Islamic Thought in the Middle Ages:
Studies in Text, Transmission and Translation in Honour of Hans Daiber, ed.
Anna Akasoy and Wim Raven (Leiden: Brill, 2008), 123–137; and Yasien
Mohamed in several pieces, including “The Ethical Philosophy of
al-Rāghib al-Iṣfahānī,” Journal of Islamic Studies 6 (1995), 51–75, and “The
Ethics of Education: al-Iṣfahānī’s al-Dharī ʿa as a Source of Inspiration for
al-Ghazālī’s Mīzān al-ʿAmal,” Muslim World 101 (2011), 633–657.
9. This would be the case even if we took the (contestable) view that Islamic
ethics just is Islamic law.
10. The Quintessence of the Principles of Law/Al-Musta ṣfā min ʿilm al-u ṣūl
(Būlāq: al-Maṭbaʿa al-Amīriyya, 1322 [1904]), 1:56, in the context of a
threefold classification of the meanings of the term ḥasan. Cf. Vasalou,
Ibn Taymiyya’s Theological Ethics, 26–27.
11. Moderation in Belief/Al-Iqti ṣād fiʾl-iʿtiqād, ed. Ibrahim Agâh Çubukçu
and Hüseyin Atay (Ankara: Nur Matbaasi, 1962), 190.
12. For more detail on this aspect of Ashʿarite ethical thinking, and on
al-Ghazālī’s more specific contribution, see my Ibn Taymiyya’s Theolog-
ical Ethics, Chapter 3.
13. Musta ṣfā, 1:61; cf. Ibn Taymiyya’s Theological Ethics, 38–39.
14. I ḥyāʾ, 14:2575, as quoted earlier. Cf. the apposition of reason and nature
two lines down (“the inclination of sound nature and right reason,”
mayl al- ṭabʿ al-salīm waʾl-ʿaql al- ṣaḥī ḥ).
15. For more on the Muʿtazilite use of such empirical claims and on
al-Ghazālī’s and his fellow-Ashʿarites’ critique, see my Ibn Taymiyya’s
Theological Ethics, 38–39, 110–113.
16. It’s not incidental to note that the emphasis on the Prophet’s extensive
beneficence shapes the corresponding discussion in al-Qāḍī ʿIyāḍ’s
al-Shifāʾ bi-ta ʿrīf ḥuqūq al-mu ṣṭafā (2:579–581) which, as suggested
above, reads like a direct adaptation of the Revival.
17. See I ḥyāʾ, 10:1837–1838, and my Virtues of Greatness, 35–37, for some
context and discussion.
68 Notes
18. For a fuller discussion of this point, see my “Virtue and the Law in
al-Ghazālī’s Ethics.”
19. I ḥyāʾ, 14:2586.
20. Treatise of Human Nature, 477.
21. “Intrinsic value”? This characterisation might seem open to question
given what was said earlier concerning al-Ghazālī’s higher-level views
about virtue: a character trait is a virtue if it is a virtue in God, and for
moral virtues, if it is instrumental to the realisation of our intellectual
potentialities. Both of these views entail that the value of the virtues
exemplified by human beings is in fact relative on either one or both of
those levels. This description would appear to align the viewpoint of the
Revival rather more closely with the viewpoint of al-Ghazālī’s theological
and legal works. It would also suggest that ordinary judgements on the
virtues may be mistaken insofar as they take the virtues to be intrinsically
valuable (presumably al-Ghazālī would not consider that when ordinary
people perceive certain kinds of character as beautiful, their judgements
are grounded in an awareness, however inarticulate, of these higher-level
facts about what makes a character trait a virtue). There would then be an
ostensible analogy with the viewpoint expressed in al-Ghazālī’s theologi-
cal and legal works (to be outlined shortly in the main text) with reference
to ordinary judgements on certain classes of actions. Just as we may think
certain actions, such as lying, are intrinsically/absolutely bad because we
don’t grasp the psychological foundations of our evaluative responses
(namely, our egoistic drives), we may think certain traits are intrinsically
good because we don’t grasp the metaphysical foundations of the right
evaluative responses (and in both cases, mistakes on this meta-ethical
level translate into mistakes in the evaluation of substantive actions and
traits). Yet the analogy is ultimately not the strongest, as closer scrutiny
of this last framing would already show. In the main text, I will suggest
some additional reasons why I am sceptical of this attempt to reconcile
the two viewpoints (taking the al-Ghazālī of the Revival to be deliberately
limiting himself to epistemically dubious moral endoxa), but I am aware
the issue could take far more discussion and disentangling.
22. Musta ṣfā, 1:58; though it is worth noting that the Muʿtazilites, like the
al-Ghazālī of the Musta ṣfā, viewed acts, not states of character, as the
main object of moral concern.
23. Ibid, 1:56; cf. Iqti ṣād, 164. Compare briefly, apropos Ibn Taymiyya’s
related move, Vasalou, Ibn Taymiyya’s Theological Ethics, 42–43.
24. See Abū Ḥayyān al-Tawḥīdī and Abū ʿAlī Miskawayh, The Philosopher
Responds: An Intellectual Correspondence From the Tenth Century, ed.
Bilal Orfali and Maurice A. Pomerantz, trans. Sophia Vasalou and
James E. Montgomery (New York: New York University Press, 2019),
1:212–219. Cf. Vílchez, Aesthetics in Arabic Thought, 210–212.
25. Though even al-Ghazālī marks a certain sort of distinction in the Mod-
eration when he refers to the “aesthetic” application of ḥasan as “sen-
sory” or “physical” (al- ḥusn al-maḥsūs). Iqti ṣād, 164.
26. ʿAbd al-Jabbār, The Sufficiency in God’s Unity and Justice/al-Mughnī
f ī abwāb al-tawḥīd waʾl-ʿadl, vol. 6/1: al-Taʿdīl waʾl-tajwīr, ed. Aḥmad
Fuʾād al-Ahwānī (Cairo: al-Muʾassasa al-Miṣriyya al-ʿĀmma liʾl-Taʾlīf
waʾl-Tarjama waʾl-Ṭibāʿa waʾl-Nashr, 1962), 19–21. As ʿAbd al-Jabbār
Notes 69
makes clear, from his perspective it is of secondary importance whether
the analysis of the terms he provides (ḥusn, qubḥ, etc.) constitutes an
accurate descriptive account of linguistic usage, as against of intelligi-
ble reality (the level of ma ʿnan); yet he nevertheless maintains that his
analysis does represent such an account. See especially the remark at
ibid, 25. For further comment on ʿAbd al-Jabbār’s definition of evil,
including his attempt to differentiate between ethical and aesthetic
judgements, see George F. Hourani, Islamic Rationalism: The Ethics of
ʿAbd al-Jabbār (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1971), Chapter 4, especially
49–55. Interestingly, Hourani assumes the aesthetic meaning was pri-
mary and was transferred to ethical qualities at a secondary stage.
27. Taʿdīl, 25. Cf. Mānkdīm Shashdīw’s distinction between what is bad/
ugly “from the perspective of look and appearance” (min jihat al-marʾā
waʾl-manẓar) and “from the perspective of reason and wisdom” (min
jihat al-ʿaql waʾl- ḥikma) in [Ta ʿlīq] Sharḥ al-Uṣūl al-khamsa, ed. ʿAbd
al-Karīm ʿUthmān (Cairo: Maktabat Wahba, 1965), 505–506.
Section 6
1. For more context on this point, see my “Ethics as Medicine: Moral Ther-
apy, Expertise, and Practical Reasoning in al-Ghazālī’s Ethics,” Archiv für
Geschichte der Philosophie (2021). https://doi.org/10.1515/agph-2020-5006
2. For the above, see W. Montgomery Watt, “Al-Ghazālī,” in Encyclo-
paedia of Islam, Second Edition, ed. P. Bearman, Th. Bianquis, C.E.
Bosworth, E. van Donzel, and W.P. Heinrichs. Consulted online on 23
August 2020: http://dx.doi.org/10.1163/1573-3912_islam_COM_0233. Cf.
the remarks in Watt, Muslim Intellectual: A Study of al-Ghazālī (Edin-
burgh: Edinburgh University Press, 1963), 67–68. The Deliverer’s view
of philosophical ethics that Watt references is arguably more irenic
than he suggests. For some discussion, see Vasalou, Virtues of Great-
ness, 53–54, in the context of trying to resolve another apparent conflict
in al-Ghazālī’s expressed positions; Sherif, Ghazālī’s Theory of Virtue,
17–18; and more extensively, Taneli Kukkonen, “Al-Ghazālī on the Ori-
gins of Ethics,” Numen 63 (2016), 271–298. Another strategy for negoti-
ating observed conflicts is to take them as grounds for reappraising the
authenticity of certain of al-Ghazālī’s works, or certain parts of these
works. This strategy was also adopted by Watt apropos the Mīzān in
“The Authenticity of the Works Attributed to al-Ghazālī,” Journal of
the Royal Asiatic Society of Great Britain and Ireland 1/2 (1952), 38–40.
3. See, e.g., Frank Griffel, Al-Ghazālī’s Philosophical Theology (New York:
Oxford University Press, 2009), especially the positioning statement on
p. 43. The point has been made with reference to al-Ghazālī’s ethics
more specifically by Garden in The First Islamic Reviver; cf. his “Revis-
iting al-Ghazālī’s Crisis Through his Scale for Action (Mizān al-ʿAmal),”
in Islam and Rationality: The Impact of al-Ghazālī, vol. 1, ed. Georges
Tamer (Leiden: Brill, 2015), 207–228. This is also Sherif’s implicit
assumption in Ghazālī’s Theory of Virtue.
4. See George F. Hourani, “A Revised Chronology of Ghazālī’s Writings,”
Journal of the American Oriental Society 104 (1984), 289–302.
70 Notes
5. Timothy J. Gianotti, Al-Ghazālī’s Unspeakable Doctrine of the Soul:
Unveiling the Esoteric Psychology and Eschatology of the Iḥyāʾ (Leiden:
Brill, 2001).
6. This styling of the question itself represents a fine instance of dust-
throwing given that little in the book evokes the Ashʿarite perspective
and much evokes the philosophical one, which al-Ghazālī does not even
entertain as a possible self-identification.
7. Mīzān, 405–409.
8. Gianotti, Al-Ghazālī’s Unspeakable Doctrine, 6.
9. Richard M. Frank, Al-Ghazālī and the Ashʿarite School (Durham, NC;
London: Duke University Press, 1994), 86, 87. I should note that this
basic methodological convergence leaves ample room for other disa-
greements between Gianotti and Frank.
10. I ḥyāʾ, 1:168; and see generally the discussion 163–171. Cf. Gianotti,
Al-Ghazālī’s Unspeakable Doctrine, 45–50; Frank, Al-Ghazālī and the
Ashʿarite School, Chapter 2 and passim.
11. Frank, Al-Ghazālī and the Ashʿarite School, 75. In terms of the three-
tiered scheme of the Scale (discussed in ibid, 96–97), Frank reads the
Moderation as belonging either to the first or the second tier (represent-
ing al-Ghazālī’s doctrine for scholastic disputation or public teaching);
ibid, 99.
12. Al-Ghazālī, to be sure, distinguishes between different levels of assent
to, and understanding of, the truth; but he remains adamant that these
different levels—exterior and interior, overt and covert (ẓāhir/bā ṭin,
ʿalin/sirr, jaliyy/khafiyy)—cannot be in conflict. See the discussion in
I ḥyāʾ, 1:171–180. As far as I can see, the fivefold taxonomy of esoteric
truths he provides in this context also furnishes no analytical tools that
would help us account for the apparent conflict we are considering,
though that could take longer discussion.
13. For some discussion of this point, see my Moral Agents and their Deserts,
Chapter 2.
14. Besides the point outlined next, there is a further consideration, which
introduces too many complexities to mention in the main text. The
epistemic demotion of al-Ghazālī’s theological works has usually been
proposed in the context of—and motivated by—a perceived conflict
between his expressed views, where his other views are aligned with the
intellectual paradigm of the philosophers (notably Avicenna). Yet what-
ever conflicts might be perceived in other areas, in the specific topic of
metaethics Ashʿarite theology had entered into a deep partnership with
Avicennan ideas, harnessing Avicenna’s account of widely accepted
propositions or endoxa (mashhūrāt) to serve the campaign against the
Muʿtazilite claim that moral qualities are objective and moral prop-
ositions are known by reason. (For more on this, see my Ibn Taymi-
yya’s Theological Ethics, esp. 58–65, 112–113; for a number of reasons,
I am unconvinced by Frank’s attempt to bring out the latent conflict
of al-Ghazālī’s account of ethics in the Moderation with traditional
Ashʿarite doctrine in Al-Ghazālī and the Ashʿarite School, 32–36.) In this
case, therefore, the motivation for this type of hermeneutic appears to be
lacking. At the same time, this will seem curious given the influence of
philosophical texts in shaping the very rationalist-objectivist perspective
Notes 71
of al-Ghazālī’s virtue-centred works, which I have been describing as
conflicting with that of his kalām works. Buried here might be the seed
of some yet-unimagined “supercharged” interpretation.
15. Gianotti, Al-Ghazālī’s Unspeakable Doctrine, 32.
16. Kukkonen, “The Good, the Beautiful,” 99–100.
17. I ḥyāʾ, 8:1344, using the term qalb. The former knowledge belongs to the
science of disclosure, ʿilm al-mukāshafa (I ḥyāʾ, 1:91). Cf. I ḥyāʾ, 8:1406,
responding to a request that he clarify whether it is one devil or many
discrete ones that collude to entice one to discrete kinds of sin.
18. Musta ṣfā, 1:58. Al-Ghazālī names a second possible cause or founda-
tion, namely adherence to religious belief (al-tadayyun biʾl-sharāʾiʿ); but
at least at the stage of initial motivation, the two coincide.
19. See note 14 (this section) and references there. The term “veneer theory”
is associated with the Dutch primatologist Frans de Waal in his writings
on morality.
20. I’m slightly simplifying, and there’s also a more complex story to be told
concerning Ibn Taymiyya’s relation to Ashʿarism, as I’ve argued in Ibn
Taymiyya’s Theological Ethics, especially Chapter 3.
21. Griffel, Al-Ghazālī’s Philosophical Theology, 286. While I wholeheart-
edly agree with this sentiment, I am far less convinced of the interpreta-
tion of the Scale to which Griffel conjoins it; see ibid, 359, n. 45.
22. The quoted remark is from ibid, 278. Griffel’s emphasis on the disjunction
between the domains of metaphysical explanation and practical action
(where “commonly held assumptions” about causality, p. 285, may be
allowed to operate unchecked) may evoke al-Ghazālī’s earlier distinc-
tion between commonly held assumptions about ethics (mashhūrāt) and
their deeper foundations (mustanad). Might it thus be possible to rede-
ploy Griffel’s explanation to the latter case and use it to unlock its puzzle?
The analogy seems suggestive, but closer consideration would reveal too
many differences between the two cases to make it fruitful.
23. Abuʾl-Ḥasan al-Ashʿarī, Spotlights on the Confrontation of Deviance and
Innovation/Kitāb al-Lumaʿ fiʾl-radd ʿalā ahl al-zaygh waʾl-bidaʿ, ed. Ḥam-
mūda Ghurāba (Cairo: Maṭbaʿat Miṣr, 1955), 117.
24. This is not meant to overlook the more expansive evaluative spectrum
to be found in both theological and legal works, such as the concept of
supererogation (tafa ḍḍul) in Muʿtazilite ethics, or the concept of dis-
couraged (makrūh) and recommended (mustaḥabb) actions in the con-
text of law. The latter evaluations, in particular, have sometimes been
described as testaments to the aspirational aspect of the sharī ʿa, where
its concern shades out of the legal and into the ethical and it seeks to
promote, in Mohammad Hashim Kamali’s words, “moral virtues and
the attainment of excellence in conduct” (Shari’ah Law: An Introduction
[Oxford: Oneworld, 2008], 18).
25. Henry Sidgwick, The Methods of Ethics (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett,
1981, 7th edn), 105.
26. Kosman, “Beauty and the Good,” 356.
27. Carl Ernst’s implicit distinction between two different ways of regarding the
Prophet—as an object of obedience, and as an object of attraction, the lat-
ter particularly pronounced in Sufi literature—seems especially suggestive
in pointing to this diremption of paradigms, one defined by obedience and
72 Notes
a morality of law-like command, the other by admiration and a morality of
beautiful example. See his “Muḥammad as the Pole of Existence,” in The
Cambridge Companion to Muḥammad, ed. Jonathan E. Brockopp (Cam-
bridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010), esp. 129–132, for discussion.
The contrast, again, cannot be drawn too sharply. Inter alia, Sufis typically
emphasised the importance of adherence to the sharī ʿa taken as a system
of rules. And the Prophet’s personal example also has legislative force and
serves as the source of law-like commands. Unsurprisingly, these two para-
digms coexist in important representatives of the textual tradition; al-Qāḍī
ʿIyāḍ’s al-Shifāʾ bi-taʿrīf ḥuqūq al-muṣṭafā is again a good example, the
emphasis on the human obligation of loving the Prophet sharing its space
in the book with the emphasis on the obligation of obeying him.
28. This concern registers strongly in the Maqṣad, which develops the idea
of imitating God’s attributes (or acquiring His beautiful names) against
a sharp distinction between the sense in which these attributes are pred-
icated of God and the sense in which they apply to and can be realised
by human beings. This points to a fundamental tension in the Maqṣad
about how to reconcile God’s immanence and transcendence, or his com-
parability and incomparability. For a deeper meditation on this theme,
see Yousef Casewit, “Al-Ghazālī’s Virtue Ethical Theory of the Divine
Names: The Theological Underpinnings of the Doctrine of Takhalluq in
al-Maqṣad al-Asnā,” Journal of Islamic Ethics 4 (2020), 155–200.
29. See my brief remarks in Ibn Taymiyya’s Theological Ethics, 47–48.
Though Ibn Taymiyya, for his part, focuses on action rather than states
of character in developing his view; and the wheels it greases more
immediately, as I suggest, concern Ibn Taymiyya’s assertion of the nat-
ural human love for the good.
30. See, for example, the discussion in Iqti ṣād, 192–195; cf. Ibn Taymiyya’s
Theological Ethics, 156–157 and references there.
31. I ḥyāʾ, 8:1426. Al-Ghazālī’s view of this conduciveness, it is true, builds
on a claim about the serviceability of moral to intellectual virtue (hence
loving cognition of God) that he would appear to have absorbed from the
Greek philosophical tradition, where it was supposedly developed with-
out access to religious scripture. Perhaps the account he provides in the
Deliverer, where he reverses the explanatory order by claiming it was the
philosophers who derived their ethical insights from mystics and religious
men (The Deliverer From Error/Al-Munqidh min al- ḍalāl, ed. Jamīl Ṣalībā
and Kāmil ʿAyyād [Beirut: Dār al-Andalus, 1967], 86), should here be see-
ing as supplying the missing piece and plugging the remaining gap.
32. This point is central, for example, to the account of admiration on
which Linda T. Zagzebski builds her moral theory in Exemplarist
Moral Theory (New York: Oxford University Press, 2017), though she
approaches the idea of “cognitive processing” on rather more specific
terms. Compare Kristján Kristjánsson’s view as discussed in Sophia
Vasalou, “Admiration, Emulation, and the Description of Character,”
Journal of Aesthetic Education 54 (2020), 47–69.
33. “At least in part,” because al-Ghazālī holds that possession of the vir-
tues is also a means to this-worldly happiness, its value thus in principle
transparent even within a naturalistic framework free from such meta-
physical baggage. See Mīzān, 190–193.
Notes 73
Section 7
1. Kosman, “Beauty and the Good,” 353. Cf. Charles Kahn: besides its aes-
thetic overtones, the pair kalon-aischron “refers primarily to the realm
of honour and respect, social approval and disapproval” (“Pre-Platonic
Ethics,” Ethics—Companions to Ancient Thought: 4, ed. Stephen Ever-
son [Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998], 27).
2. For all the above, see Kosman, “Beauty and the Good,” 353–355.
3. Bernard Williams, Shame and Necessity (Berkeley, LA: University of
California Press, 1993), 78 and 82; the other may not be a particular
individual or the representative of a particular social group but instead
identified in ethical terms as an idealised and generalised observer
“whose reactions I would respect” (ibid, 81–84). Cf. Peter Hacker:
“the conceptual iconography of feeling ashamed is the eye of others”
(“Shame, Embarrassment, and Guilt,” Midwest Studies in Philosophy
41 [2017], 219).
4. Hacker, “Shame, Embarrassment,” 203, rehearsing an understanding
of the distinction between shame and guilt cultures popularised by the
anthropologist Ruth Benedict.
5. This is a theme of my Virtues of Greatness, which casts a spotlight on
the preservation and renegotiation of a specific set of pre-Islamic Arab
values, as represented by the heroic virtue of greatness of spirit (ʿiẓam/
bu ʿd al-himma). See especially 108ff.
6. Books 28 and 29 of the Revival: On the Condemnation of Status and Dis-
simulation, and On the Condemnation of Pride and Conceit.
7. Hacker, “Shame, Embarrassment,” 202.
8. Friedrich Nietzsche, “On the Uses and Disadvantages of History for
Life,” Untimely Meditations, ed. Daniel Breazeale, trans. R. J. Holling-
dale (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997), 67, 68.
Bibliography
ʿAbd al-Jabbār ibn Aḥmad al-Asadābādī. The Sufficiency in God’s Unity and
Justice/al-Mughnī f ī abwāb al-tawḥīd waʾl-ʿadl, vol. 6/1: al-Taʿdīl waʾl-tajwīr,
edited by Aḥmad Fuʾād al-Ahwānī. Cairo: al-Muʾassasa al-Miṣriyya
al-ʿĀmma liʾl-Taʾlīf waʾl-Tarjama waʾl-Ṭibāʿa waʾl-Nashr, 1962.
Abrahamov, Binyamin. Divine Love in Islamic Mysticism: The Teachings of
Al-Ghazâlî and Al-Dabbâgh. London; New York: Routledge, 2003.
———. “Al-Ghazālī and the Rationalization of Sufism.” In Islam and
Rationality: The Impact of al-Ghazālī, vol. 1, edited by Georges Tamer, 35–48.
Leiden: Brill, 2015.
Abul Quasem, Muhammad. The Ethics of al-Ghazālī: A Composite Ethics in
Islam. Petaling Jaya: Muhammad Abul Quasem, 1976.
Adamson, Peter. The Arabic Plotinus: A Study of the Theology of Aristotle.
London: Duckworth, 2002.
Aersten, Jan A. Medieval Philosophy and the Transcendentals: The Case of
Thomas Aquinas. Leiden: E.J. Brill, 1996.
Algoe, Sara B., and Jonathan Haidt. “Witnessing Excellence in Action: The
‘Other-Praising’ Emotions of Elevation, Gratitude, and Admiration.” Journal
of Positive Psychology 4 (2009), 105–127.
Annas, Julia. The Morality of Happiness. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993.
———. Intelligent Virtue. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011.
Aristotle. Manṭiq Arisṭū, edited by ʿAbd al-Raḥmān Badawī. Beirut: Dār al-Qa-
lam; Kuwait: Wakālat al-Maṭbūʿāt, 1980. 3 vols.
———. The Arabic Version of the Nicomachean Ethics, edited by Anna A.
Akasoy and Alexander Fidora, with an introduction and annotated transla-
tion by Douglas M. Dunlop. Leiden: Brill, 2005.
Al-Ashʿarī, Abuʾl-Ḥasan. Spotlights on the Confrontation of Deviance and
Innovation/Kitāb al-Lumaʿ fiʾl-radd ʿalā ahl al-zaygh waʾl-bidaʿ, edited by
Ḥammūda Ghurāba. Cairo: Maṭbaʿat Miṣr, 1955.
Avicenna. See Ibn Sīnā.
Behrens-Abouseif, Doris. Beauty in Arabic Culture. Princeton, NJ: Markus
Wiener, 1998.
Bergh, Simon Van Den. “The ‘Love of God’ in al-Ghazālī’s Vivification of
Theology.” Journal of Semitic Studies 1 (1956), 305–321.
Bibliography 75
Black, Deborah L. “Aesthetics in Islamic Philosophy.” In Routledge
Encyclopedia of Philosophy, edited by Edward Craig, 75–79. London; New
York: Routledge, 1998.
Brontë, Charlotte. Jane Eyre. New York; London: W. W. Norton & Company,
2001.
Casewit, Yousef. “Al-Ghazālī’s Virtue Ethical Theory of the Divine Names:
The Theological Underpinnings of the Doctrine of Takhalluq in al-Maqṣad
al-Asnā.” Journal of Islamic Ethics 4 (2020), 155–200.
Chittick, William C. “The Aesthetics of Islamic Ethics.” In Sharing Poetic
Expressions: Beauty, Sublime, Mysticism in Islamic and Occidental Culture, edited
by Anna-Teresa Tymieniecka, 3–14. Dordrecht; New York: Springer, 2011.
Clewis, Robert R. The Kantian Sublime and the Revelation of Freedom.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009.
Cooper, David E. “Beautiful People, Beautiful Things.” British Journal of
Aesthetics 48 (2008), 247–260.
Daiber, Hans. “Griechische Ethik in islamischem Gewande: Das Beispiel von
Rāġib al-Iṣfahānī (11. Jh.).” In Historia Philosophiae Medii Aevi: Studien zur
Geschichte der Philosophie des Mittelalters, edited by Burkhard Mojsisch and
Olaf Pluta, vol. 1, 181–192. Amsterdam; Philadelphia, PA: Grüner, 1992.
El Shamsy, Ahmed. “The Wisdom of God’s Law: Two Theories.” In Islamic
Law in Theory: Studies in Jurisprudence in Honor of Bernard Weiss, edited by
Robert Gleave and Kevin Reinhart, 19–37. Leiden: Brill, 2014.
Ernst, Carl. “Muḥammad as the Pole of Existence.” In The Cambridge
Companion to Muḥammad, edited by Jonathan E. Brockopp, 123–138.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010.
Ettinghausen, Richard. “Al-Ghazzālī on Beauty.” In Fine Arts of Islamic
Civilization, edited by Muhammad Abdul Jabbar Beg, 25–36. Cambridge:
M. A. J. Beg, 2006.
Al-Fārābī, Abū Naṣr. On the Perfect State/Mabādiʾ ārāʾ ahl al-madīna al-fāḍila,
translated by Richard Walzer. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1985.
Frank, Richard M. Al-Ghazālī and the Ashʿarite School. Durham, NC; London:
Duke University Press, 1994.
Galen. “Mukhtaṣar min Kitāb ‘al-Akhlāq’ li-Jālīnūs.” In Dirāsāt wa-nuṣūṣ
fiʾl-falsafa waʾl-ʿulūm ʿinda al-ʿarab, edited by ʿAbd al-Raḥmān Badawī,
190–211. Beirut: al-Muʾassasa al-ʿArabiyya liʾl-Dirāsāt waʾl-Nashr, 1981.
Garden, Kenneth. The First Islamic Reviver: Abū Ḥāmid al-Ghazālī and His
Revival of the Religious Sciences. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014.
———. “Revisiting al-Ghazālī’s Crisis Through his Scale for Action (Mizān
al-ʿAmal).” In Islam and Rationality: The Impact of al-Ghazālī, vol. 1, edited
by Georges Tamer, 207–228. Leiden: Brill, 2015.
Gaut, Berys. Art, Emotion and Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007.
Al-Ghazālī, Abū Ḥāmid. The Quintessence of the Principles of Law/
Al-Mustaṣfā min ʿilm al-uṣūl. Būlāq: al-Maṭbaʿa al-Amīriyya, 1904–1906.
2 vols.
———. The Revival of the Religious Sciences/Iḥyāʾ ʿulūm al-dīn. Cairo: Lajnat
Nashr al-Thaqāfa al-Islāmiyya, 1937–38. 16 vols.
76 Bibliography
———. Moderation in Belief/Al-Iqtiṣād fiʾl-iʿtiqād, edited by Ibrahim Agâh
Çubukçu and Hüseyin Atay. Ankara: Nur Matbaasi, 1962.
———. The Scale of Action/Mīzān al-ʿamal, edited by Sulaymān Dunyā. Cairo:
Dār al-Maʿārif, 1964.
———. The Deliverer from Error/Al-Munqidh min al-ḍalāl, edited by Jamīl
Ṣalībā and Kāmil ʿAyyād. 7th edn. Beirut: Dār al-Andalus, 1967.
———. The Most Exalted Aim in Expounding God’s Beautiful Names/Al-Maqṣad
al-asnā f ī sharḥ maʿānī asmāʾ Allāh al-ḥusnā, edited by Fadlou A. Shehadi.
Beirut: Dar El-Machreq, 1971.
Gianotti, Timothy J. Al-Ghazālī’s Unspeakable Doctrine of the Soul: Unveiling
the Esoteric Psychology and Eschatology of the Iḥyāʾ. Leiden: Brill, 2001.
Gonzalez, Valerie. Beauty in Islam: Aesthetics in Islamic Art and Architecture.
London: I.B. Tauris, 2001.
Griffel, Frank. Al-Ghazālī’s Philosophical Theology. New York: Oxford
University Press, 2009.
———. “Al-Ghazālī’s Use of “Original Human Disposition” (Fiṭra) and Its
Background in the Teachings of al-Fārābī and Avicenna.” Muslim World 102
(2012), 1–32.
Gutas, Dimitri. “Plato’s Symposion in the Arabic Tradition.” Oriens 31 (1988),
36–60.
———. “Platon. Tradition Arabe.” In Dictionnaire des Philosophes Antiques,
vol. Va, edited by Richard Goulet, 845–863. Paris: Centre National de la
Recherche Scientifique, 2012.
Hacker, Peter. “Shame, Embarrassment, and Guilt.” Midwest Studies in
Philosophy 41 (2017), 202–224.
Haidt, Jonathan. “Elevation and the Positive Psychology of Morality.” In
Flourishing: Positive Psychology and the Life Well-Lived, edited by Corey
L. M. Keyes and Jonathan Haidt, 275–280. Washington, DC: American
Psychological Association, 2003.
Hillenbrand, Carole. “Some Aspects of al-Ghazālī’s Views on Beauty.” In Gott ist
schön und Er liebt die Schönheit (God is Beautiful and He Loves Beauty), edited
by Alma Giese and J. Christoph Bürgel, 249–265. Bern: Peter Lang, 1994.
Hourani, George F. Islamic Rationalism: The Ethics of ʿAbd al-Jabbār. Oxford:
Clarendon Press, 1971.
———. “A Revised Chronology of Ghazālī’s Writings.” Journal of the American
Oriental Society 104 (1984), 289–302.
Hughes, Aaron. The Texture of the Divine: Imagination in Medieval Islamic and
Jewish Thought. Bloomington; Indianapolis, IN: Indiana University Press, 2004.
Hume, David. Treatise of Human Nature, edited by L. A. Selby-Bigge, revised
by P. H. Nidditch. 2nd edn. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1978.
Ibn Manẓūr, Muḥammad ibn Mukarram. The Arabic Tongue/Lisān al-’arab.
Beirut: Dār Ṣādir, 1955–1956. 15 vols.
Ibn Sīnā, Abū ʿAlī. “Risāla fiʾl-ʿishq.” In Jāmiʿ al-badāʾiʿ, edited by Muḥyī
al-Dīn Ṣabrī al-Kurdī, 68–91. Cairo: Maṭbaʿat al-Saʿāda, 1917.
———. The Book of Salvation/Kitāb al-Najāt, edited by Majid Fakhry. Beirut:
Dār al-Āfāq al-Jadīda, 1985.
Bibliography 77
Irwin, Terence H. The Development of Ethics, vol. 1: From Socrates to the
Reformation. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007.
———. “The Sense and Reference of Kalon in Aristotle.” Classical Philology
105 (2010), 381–396.
Al-Qāḍī ʿIyāḍ, Abuʾl-Faḍl ibn Mūsā. The Curative Knowledge of the Claims
of the Chosen Prophet/Al-Shifāʾ bi-taʿrīf ḥuqūq al-muṣṭafā, edited by
ʿAlī Muḥammad al-Bajāwī. Beirut: Dār al-Kitāb al-ʿArabī, 1984. 2 vols.
Janssens, Jules. “Al-Ghazālī’s Mīzān al-ʿAmal: An Ethical Summa Based on
Ibn Sīnā and al-Rāghib al-Iṣfahānī.” In Islamic Thought in the Middle Ages:
Studies in Text, Transmission and Translation in Honour of Hans Daiber,
edited by Anna Akasoy and Wim Raven, 123–137. Leiden: Brill, 2008.
Kahn, Charles. “Pre-Platonic Ethics.” In Ethics—Companions to Ancient
Thought, vol. 4, edited by Stephen Everson, 27–48. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1998.
Kamali, Mohammad Hashim. Shari’ah Law: An Introduction. Oxford:
Oneworld, 2008.
Kant, Immanuel. Critique of the Power of Judgment, translated by Paul Guyer
and Eric Matthews. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000.
Kidd, Ian James. “Beauty, Virtue, and Religious Exemplars.” Religious Studies
53 (2017), 171–181.
———. “Admiration, Attraction and the Aesthetics of Exemplarity.” Journal of
Moral Education 48 (2019), 369–380.
Kosman, Aryeh. “Beauty and the Good: Situating the Kalon.” Classical
Philology 105 (2010), 341–357.
Kristjánsson, Kristján. “Emotions Targeting Moral Exemplarity: Making Sense
of the Logical Geography of Admiration, Emulation and Elevation.” Theory
and Research in Education 15 (2017), 20–37.
Kukkonen, Taneli. “The Good, the Beautiful and the True: Aesthetical Issues in
Islamic Philosophy.” Studia Orientalia 111 (2011), 87–103.
———. “Al-Ghazālī on the Origins of Ethics.” Numen 63 (2016), 271–298.
Leaman, Oliver. Islamic Aesthetics. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2004.
Madelung, Wilferd. “Ar-Rāġib al-Iṣfahānī und die Ethik al-Ġazālīs.” In
Islamwissenschaftliche Abhandlungen Fritz Meier zum sechzigsten Geburtstag,
edited by Richard Gramlich, 152–163. Wiesbaden: Steiner, 1974.
Mahmoud, Samir. “Beauty and Aesthetics in Classical Islamic Thought: An
Introduction.” Kalam Journal 1 (2018), 7–21.
Mānkdīm Shashdīw, Aḥmad ibn al-Ḥusayn. [Taʿlīq] Sharḥ al-Uṣūl al-khamsa,
edited by ʿAbd al-Karīm ʿUthmān. Cairo: Maktabat Wahba, 1965.
Matravers, Derek. Fiction and Narrative. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014.
McGinn, Colin. Ethics, Evil, and Fiction. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999.
Mohamed, Yasien. “The Ethical Philosophy of al-Rāghib al-Iṣfahānī.” Journal
of Islamic Studies 6 (1995), 51–75.
———. “The Ethics of Education: al-Iṣfahānī’s al-Dharīʿa as a Source of Inspiration
for al-Ghazālī’s Mīzān al-ʿAmal.” Muslim World 101 (2011), 633–657.
Murata, Kazuyo. Beauty in Sufism: The Teachings of Rūzbihān Baqlī. Albany,
NY: State University of New York Press, 2017.
78 Bibliography
Murtaḍā al-Zabīdī, Muḥammad ibn Muḥammad. The Bridal Crown from the
Gems of the Dictionary/Tāj al-ʿArūs min jawāhir al-Qāmūs, edited by various
editors. Kuwait: Maṭbaʿat Ḥukūmat al-Kuwayt, 1965–2001. 40 vols.
Nietzsche, Friedrich. Twilight of the Idols and the Anti-Christ, translated by
R. J. Hollingdale. London: Penguin, 1990.
———. Untimely Meditations, edited by Daniel Breazeale and translated by
R. J. Hollingdale. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997.
Nussbaum, Martha C. Upheavals of Thought: The Intelligence of Emotions.
Cambridge; New York: Cambridge University Press, 2001.
Paris, Panos. “On Form, and the Possibility of Moral Beauty.” Metaphilosophy
49 (2018), 711–729.
———. “The Empirical Case for Moral Beauty.” Australasian Journal of
Philosophy 96 (2018), 642–656.
———. “Moral Beauty and Education.” Journal of Moral Education 48 (2019),
395–411.
Plato. Symposium, translated by Reginald E. Allen. New Haven, CT: Yale
University Press, 1993.
Plotinus. Plotinus Apud Arabes/Aflūṭīn ʿinda al-ʿarab, edited by ʿAbd al-Raḥmān
Badawī. Cairo: Maktabat al-Nahḍa al-Miṣriyya, 1955.
Puerta Vílchez, José Miguel. Aesthetics in Arabic Thought from Pre-Islamic
Arabia through al-Andalus, translated by Consuelo López-Morillas. Leiden;
Boston, MA: Brill, 2017.
Radford, Colin. “How Can We Be Moved by the Fate of Anna Karenina?”
Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes 49 (1975), 67–80.
Al-Rāghib al-Iṣfahānī, Abuʾl-Qāsim ibn Muḥammad. An Exposition of the Obscure
Terms of the Qurʾan/Mufradāt fī gharīb al-Qurʾān, edited by Ṣafwān ʿAdnān
Dawūdī. 4th edn. Damascus: Dār al-Qalam; Beirut: al-Dār al-Shāmiyya, 2009.
Al-Rāzī, Fakhr al-Dīn. The Keys to the Unseen/Mafātīḥ al-ghayb, Beirut: Dār
al-Fikr, 1981. 32 vols.
Rosenthal, Franz. Four Essays on Art and Literature in Islam. Leiden: Brill, 1971.
Schimmel, Anne-Marie. And Mohammed is His Messenger: The Veneration of
the Prophet in Islamic Piety. Chapel Hill, NC: London: University of North
Carolina Press, 1985.
Schopenhauer, Arthur. The World as Will and Representation, translated
by E. F. J. Payne. New York: Dover Publications, 1966. 2 vols.
Scruton, Roger. Art and Imagination: A Study in the Philosophy of Mind. South
Bend, IN: St Augustine’s Press, 1998.
Sherif, Mohamed Ahmed. Ghazālī’s Theory of Virtue. Albany, NY: State
University of New York Press, 1975.
Sidgwick, Henry. The Methods of Ethics. 7th edn. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett,
1981.
Al-Tawḥīdī, Abū Ḥayyān, and Abū ʿAlī Miskawayh. The Philosopher Responds:
An Intellectual Correspondence From the Tenth Century, edited by Bilal Orfali
and Maurice A. Pomerantz and translated by Sophia Vasalou and James E.
Montgomery. New York: New York University Press, 2019.
Bibliography 79
Watt, W. Montgomery. “The Authenticity of the Works Attributed to
al-Ghazālī.” Journal of the Royal Asiatic Society of Great Britain and Ireland
1/2 (1952), 24–45.
———. Muslim Intellectual: A Study of al-Ghazālī. Edinburgh: Edinburgh
University Press, 1963.
———. “Al-Ghazālī.” In Encyclopaedia of Islam, edited by P. Bearman,
Th. Bianquis, C. E. Bosworth, E. van Donzel, and W. P. Heinrichs. 2nd edn.
Consulted online on 23 August 2020: http://dx.doi.org/10.1163/1573-
3912_islam_COM_0233
Wensinck, Arent J. La Pensée de Ghazzālī. Paris: Adrien-Maisonneuve, 1940.
Williams, Bernard. Shame and Necessity. Berkeley, LA: University of California
Press, 1993.
Wittgenstein, Ludwig. Philosophical Investigations, edited by Peter M. S. Hacker
and Joachim Schulte, translated by G. E. M. Anscombe, Peter M. S. Hacker,
and Joachim Schulte. 4th rev. edn. Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell, 2009.
Vasalou, Sophia. Moral Agents and their Deserts: The Character of Muʿtazilite
Ethics. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2008.
———. Ibn Taymiyya’s Theological Ethics. New York: Oxford University Press,
2016.
———. Virtues of Greatness in the Arabic Tradition. Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 2019.
———. “Admiration, Emulation, and the Description of Character.” Journal of
Aesthetic Education 54 (2020), 47–69.
———. “Virtue and the Law in al-Ghazālī’s Ethics.” In Islamic Ethics as
Educational Discourse: Thought and Impact of the Classical Muslim Thinker
Miskawayh, edited by Sebastian Günther and Yassir El Jamouhi. Tübingen:
Mohr Siebeck, 2021.
———. “Does al-Ghazālī Have a Theory of Virtue?” In Mysticism and Ethics
in Islam, edited by Bilal Orfali, Mohammed Rustom, and Atif Khalil. Beirut:
American University of Beirut Press, forthcoming.
———. “Ethics as Medicine: Moral Therapy, Expertise, and Practical Reasoning
in al-Ghazālī’s Ethics.” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie (2021). https://
doi.org/10.1515/agph-2020-5006
Zagzebski, Linda T. Exemplarist Moral Theory. New York: Oxford University
Press, 2017.
Zangwill, Nick. The Metaphysics of Beauty. Ithaca, NY; London: Cornell
University Press, 2001.
Zargar, Cyrus Ali. Sufi Aesthetics: Beauty, Love, and the Human Form in Ibn
Arabi and ‘Iraqi. Columbia, SC: University of South Carolina Press, 2011.
Index