Unjust Enrichment and Contract
Unjust Enrichment and Contract
CASES
Unjust Enrichment and Contract
Peter Jaffey*
Benedetti v Sawiris was concerned with the measure of a quantum meruit, and in particular
whether a ‘subjective’ or ‘objective’ measure should be preferred. The Supreme Court addressed
the issue broadly in line with the approach in the mainstream academic literature on unjust
enrichment, according to which this is a problem of how to measure benefit. The article argues
that this unjust enrichment approach is misguided because it obscures the role of agreement and
conflates transfer and exchange, and that a contractual analysis of the case would make the issues
clearer and easier to resolve.
INTRODUCTION
On the face of it, Benedetti v Sawiris1 (Benedetti) is a case on a narrow and technical
point on the measure of the quantum meruit in the law of unjust enrichment,
but it is significant beyond this in what it says, or implies, about the law of unjust
enrichment generally and its relationship with the law of contract.
The facts of the case are complicated, but so far as they are relevant for present
purposes they can be summarised quite simply. Benedetti approached Sawiris to
see if he would be interested in collaborating in the acquisition of a company
called Wind. The original idea was that Sawiris would become a shareholder
along with Benedetti in a new company established to take over Wind, but most
of the funding for the acquisition would come from other investors that
Benedetti would find. This was set out in the Acquisition Agreement. It seems
to have been envisaged that Benedetti would profit from the venture as an
investor or director in the new company when the Acquisition Agreement was
implemented. In the end, however, no other investors were found and so the
Acquisition Agreement was abandoned. Sawiris decided to continue with the
takeover by providing the funding himself, and Benedetti continued to work on
his behalf towards the acquisition on this new basis, though there was no longer
any written contract governing the relationship between them, and there was no
explicit agreement for Benedetti’s remuneration. The acquisition of Wind by
Sawiris was eventually successful. Although Sawiris accepted that Benedetti was
entitled to be paid for what he had done, the two parties could not agree on the
amount, and Benedetti sued Sawiris on various bases including contract and
unjust enrichment. By the time the matter reached the Supreme Court, the only
issue was the measure of recovery in unjust enrichment, Sawiris having accepted
© 2014 The Author. The Modern Law Review © 2014 The Modern Law Review Limited. (2014) 77(6) MLR 983–1008
Published by John Wiley & Sons Ltd, 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford OX4 2DQ, UK and 350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148, USA
Unjust Enrichment and Contract
that he was liable in unjust enrichment, and the other bases, including contract,
having been rejected by the lower courts.
© 2014 The Author. The Modern Law Review © 2014 The Modern Law Review Limited.
984 (2014) 77(6) MLR 983–1008
Peter Jaffey
for payment. This is typically the position in the case of ‘necessitous interven-
tion’, where the claimant saves the defendant or his property from harm in an
emergency where negotiation was impossible and the defendant would certainly
have sought and paid for assistance if he could have done.2 One might treat in
a similar way the situation where goods or services are supplied but no genuine
agreement is reached because of a mistake by one or other or both parties.
Although the alternative rule may be defensible in these types of case, if the
contractual rule is adopted (as of course it should be and has been), it is surely
clear that there is no room to apply the alternative rule where there is no
impediment to contracting and no mistake. The alternative rule should not
operate to allow a supplier simply to confer a benefit and demand payment
without taking the trouble to make an agreement first. This would completely
undermine the process of negotiation leading to contract, which is based on the
assumption that only if an agreement is reached can there be any liability to pay
for a benefit conferred. It would be bound to create uncertainty and to lead to
opportunistic and disingenuous behaviour in tendering and negotiations.
If and when the alternative rule does apply, it is illuminating to say that, in a
manner of speaking, the court makes a contract for the parties. Of course this is
not literally the case – it is in the nature of an agreement that it can only be made
by the parties. But the rationale of the law is to secure a mutually beneficial
exchange of goods or services for payment, which is what the parties try to
secure through a contract. One can reasonably say that liability in the absence of
a contract is assessed by extension from or by analogy with contract. One might
say that there is an imputed or simulated contract.3 There is no fiction in the
sense of applying a rule that operates on the basis of facts that are taken to be true
but are not. There is no false assumption that there is in fact an agreement.
Thus one might say that the contractual context includes the basic rules (1)
that parties who make an agreement are bound by it, (2) that, where the parties
have made an agreement, liability for payment is governed by the agreement, (3)
that in the absence of an agreement parties are not liable to pay for a benefit if
contracting was feasible, ie, there was no mistake or impediment to contracting,
and, one might add, that (4) where contracting was not feasible there may
sometimes be a liability for payment by analogy with contract to secure a fair
exchange. One might say that these rules form an extended law of contract, or
at least a contract-oriented legal regime governing exchange.4 These rules, or at
least the first three, are surely taken for granted by ordinary business people in
negotiating their contracts. They represent at least the starting point of the
2 See generally A. Burrows, The Law of Restitution (Oxford: OUP, 3rd ed, 2011) ch 18.
3 There are a number of contractually-oriented approaches in the literature for this type of case,
including S. Stoljar, The Law of Quasi-Contract (Sydney: The Law Book Co, 2nd ed, 1989); S.
Levmore, ‘Explaining Restitution’ (1985) 71 Virginia Law Review 65; I. M. Jackman, The Varieties
of Restitution (Annandale: Federation Press, 1998); P. Jaffey, The Nature and Scope of Restitution
(Oxford: Hart, 2000) ch 3; S. Hedley, ‘Implied Contract and Restitution’ (2004) 63 CLJ 435; and
more recently D. Priel, ‘In Defence of Quasi-Contract’ (2012) 75 MLR 54. See also D. Campbell,
‘A Relational Critique of the Third Restatement of Restitution §39’ (2011) 68 Washington and Lee
Law Review 1063.
4 Generally reflected in the contractually-oriented approaches, ibid.
© 2014 The Author. The Modern Law Review © 2014 The Modern Law Review Limited.
(2014) 77(6) MLR 983–1008 985
Unjust Enrichment and Contract
5 See further P. Jaffey, ‘Restitutionary Remedies in the Contractual Context’ (2013) 76 MLR 429.
cf R. Grantham and C. E. F. Rickett, ‘On the Subsidiarity of Unjust Enrichment’ (2011) 117 LQR
273; see also R. A. Havelock, ‘The Valuation of Enrichment in the Supreme Court: Benedetti v
Sawiris’ (2013) 21 RLR 97.
6 See generally Stoljar, n 3 above, and the other works referred to in the same footnote.
© 2014 The Author. The Modern Law Review © 2014 The Modern Law Review Limited.
986 (2014) 77(6) MLR 983–1008
Peter Jaffey
In Benedetti the claim was in unjust enrichment, and, on the face of it, the effect
was to allow a claim for payment for services provided, without reference to any
agreement, in the absence of a mistake and with no impediment to contracting,
even though the parties were dealing with each other and possibly in negotiation
over terms. As discussed above, this is inimical to the law of contract and should
be a matter for serious concern. The underlying problem is that the law of unjust
enrichment obscures the true character of a claim for payment for services.
This was not exactly the problem in Benedetti, however. The position is more
complicated. It seems that in Benedetti there was actually an agreement between
the parties. As Lord Neuberger put it, there was a contract ‘arising from the
parties’ words and conduct . . .’, and ‘it must be at least arguable that there would
be implied into the contract a term that [Benedetti] should be paid a reasonable
sum’,7 which would normally be described as a contractual quantum meruit. In
my view it would have been preferable if the matter had been dealt with in this
way, though possibly this avenue was not open to the Supreme Court.
One might think that under the unjust enrichment approach the presence of
this agreement was irrelevant, but this was not actually the case. Curiously it
appears that the presence of the agreement between the parties was actually a
necessary condition of the unjust enrichment claim. For an unjust enrichment
claim, there must be an ‘unjust factor’.8 This is the category of reason that justifies
a claim for restitution for unjust enrichment in the circumstances in question.
The unjust factor here was given as ‘failure of consideration’, which in this
context is understood to mean not that there is no consideration in the ordinary
contractual sense, but that the benefit is conferred on a basis that fails, or on a
condition that has not been satisfied.9 There is room for argument over what
exactly this means. Can a supplier unilaterally and privately specify that he is
supplying a benefit on the basis that he is to be paid for it, and then demand
payment? This would exactly reproduce the alternative rule. In fact, it seems to
be accepted that there can be a failure of consideration only when there is an
agreement, of some sort, between the parties.10 Presumably the rationale for this
is to protect the recipient’s freedom to choose what benefits to pay for, to ensure
that the exchange is beneficial to him – the same reason, of course, why it is
normally said, in the contractual context, that, rather than applying the alterna-
tive rule, a contractual agreement is required for liability to arise.
Thus, despite appearances, the position in Benedetti was not that the alternative
rule was applied in circumstances where the parties could perfectly well make an
agreement. The claim was actually based on agreement, but in the form of a
claim in unjust enrichment. The effect of invoking the law of unjust enrichment
7 n 1 above at [177].
8 The concept of the unjust factor is due to P. Birks, An Introduction to the Law of Restitution (Oxford:
OUP, rev ed, 1989).
9 See for example, n 1 above at [86] per Lord Reed.
10 This seems to have been the view in this case and has support in the literature: eg, Burrows, n 2
above, 372.
© 2014 The Author. The Modern Law Review © 2014 The Modern Law Review Limited.
(2014) 77(6) MLR 983–1008 987
Unjust Enrichment and Contract
THE REMEDY
The legal issue identified by the Supreme Court was apparently quite simple. For
the purposes of the claim in unjust enrichment, the measure of recovery was the
value of the benefit received by Sawiris from Benedetti, and the question was
whether this benefit should be measured ‘objectively’ or ‘subjectively’. Accord-
ing to the court, the objective measure of the value of services is their market
value, whereas the subjective measure is the value actually attributed to them by
the recipient, which could be higher or lower than the market price. If a
recipient values the benefit at less than the market values it, the issue is whether
he can rely on a principle of ‘subjective devaluation’ to reduce the measure of
recovery from the market price, and if he values it more highly than the market,
the question is whether the claimant-supplier can insist on ‘subjective revalua-
tion’ to justify a higher measure of recovery.14 Here it was subjective revaluation
that was in issue, because Benedetti argued that there was evidence that Sawiris
valued the services more highly than the market, but subjective devaluation was
considered first, as a step in the argument and because it is the more common
case.
One problem concerning valuation is not explicitly addressed in the judge-
ments. As I have said, the unjust enrichment claim is conceived of as undoing or
reversing a transfer and thereby removing a benefit, as in the case of a mistaken
11 This has commonly been argued by opponents of the unjust enrichment approach though it now
appears in Burrows, n 2 above, 372.
12 See eg n 1 above at [31] per Lord Clark.
13 As argued in Jaffey, n 5 above.
14 These expressions are again derived from the unjust enrichment literature, in particular Birks, n 8
above, 109–110.
© 2014 The Author. The Modern Law Review © 2014 The Modern Law Review Limited.
988 (2014) 77(6) MLR 983–1008
Peter Jaffey
payment, but in this sort of case the claim is better understood as securing
payment for a benefit and so effecting an exchange. The real issue is not the value
of the defendant’s benefit or gain, but the appropriate price for it. This is clear
where the quantum meruit is contractual, and it is equally true here where it is
non-contractual. The objective value or objective price is the ordinary market
price. However, as the court discussed, there may be a specialist market price, the
price in a sub-market for suppliers and buyers with the particular features of the
parties involved.15 Furthermore, where there is no actual market at all, one can
ask what a reasonable person in the recipient’s position would have had to pay.16
As I understand this, it is an assessment of what would have been agreed between
the parties taking account of objective or public circumstances, which is
described as a market price, though it is not a price ascertained from an actual
market. These are variants of the objective price.
By contrast, the subjective price is the price that would have been agreed by
these parties in the light of all the factors that would actually have influenced
them in deciding whether to contract, including their private preferences, plans
and resources.17 If the parties do actually negotiate, they may typically accept the
market price if there is one, but they may instead arrive at a different price, a
subjective price in this sense. The market price merely represents the price at
which supply meets demand. It does not mean that there is necessarily a
mutually-beneficial exchange for the parties at that price or that there cannot be
a mutually beneficial exchange at another price. A buyer might insist on a lower
price and a supplier might well agree to a lower price, even though he makes less
than he would at the market price, if this happens to be the best option open to
him in the circumstances.
In Benedetti, if there had been a contractual claim based on the agreement, the
remedy would have been a contractual quantum meruit. This is ‘reasonable
payment’, normally understood to be payment at the market price.18 The
rationale is presumably that this was implicitly agreed. Parties who contract
without agreeing a specific price can be taken to have agreed to an objective
price, in the sense of the market price or the price that a reasonable person in the
buyer’s position would have had to pay. Since they chose not to negotiate a
price, it seems right that neither party should be able to insist on the subjective
price that they might have negotiated in the light of additional private consid-
erations. However, if a supplier confers a benefit in circumstances where there
was no agreement but the recipient is liable under the alternative rule, because
it was impossible to negotiate or because of mistake, normally the market price
should apply again, but here the assumption must be not that the parties
implicitly agreed to this, but that they would have agreed to it if they had
negotiated. Furthermore, it may well be justified to adjust the price on the basis
that, if the parties had been able to negotiate, they would have agreed a higher
© 2014 The Author. The Modern Law Review © 2014 The Modern Law Review Limited.
(2014) 77(6) MLR 983–1008 989
Unjust Enrichment and Contract
or lower price than the objective price in the light of private considerations. In
other words, here a subjective price is appropriate.
The claim in Benedetti was not in contract but in unjust enrichment. One
might think that, if one were to adopt a rule for a non-contractual, unjust
enrichment claim, it should be the approach applicable for the alternative rule,
in the absence of an agreement, so that the court should be prepared to depart
from the market rate according to subjective devaluation or revaluation.
However, the court said that the starting point for measuring a benefit in unjust
enrichment is the objective measure.19 Lord Reed offered the following expla-
nation for this:
The object of the remedy . . . is . . . to correct the injustice arising from the
defendant’s receipt of the claimant’s services on a basis which was not fulfilled. That
injustice cannot be corrected by requiring the defendant to provide the claimant
with the reward which either party might have been willing to agree. That is
because, in the absence of a contract, neither party’s intentions or expectations can
be determinative of their mutual rights and obligations. Nor can the court make the
parties’ contract for them: a contract which might have included many other terms
and conditions besides a price. In such circumstances the unjust enrichment arising
from the defendant’s receipt of the claimant’s services can only be corrected by
requiring the defendant to pay the claimant the monetary value of those services,
thereby restoring both parties, so far as a monetary award can do so, to their previous
positions.20
19 n 1 above at [15]–[16] per Lord Clarke; at [99] per Lord Reed; at [180] per Lord Neuberger.
20 ibid at [99]. See also at [123]. The other judges did not offer any comparable explanation.
21 ibid at [123] per Lord Reed.
© 2014 The Author. The Modern Law Review © 2014 The Modern Law Review Limited.
990 (2014) 77(6) MLR 983–1008
Peter Jaffey
was justified to use the market price. If one were to ignore the agreement, it
would seem appropriate to try and determine a subjective price in the light of
whatever subjective factors would have influenced the parties if they had nego-
tiated, since this in the end would be a better way to determine what would be
a fair price as between these two parties. This counterfactual exercise of deter-
mining a subjective price in the absence of agreement does not of course draw
on actual intentions and expectations.
Consistently with this, the court proceeded to say that, although the objective
measure is the standard measure in unjust enrichment, subjective devaluation
should generally be allowed.22 The reason for this is not explored in the
judgments. Lord Reed’s argument quoted above seems to imply that it should
not be available. In Benedetti, subjective revaluation was in issue rather than
subjective devaluation. Although the court favoured subjective devaluation, it
was against subjective revaluation.23 The reason given was that subjective
revaluation is unnecessary to protect the defendant. However, the question is
whether fairness to the claimant calls for subjective revaluation if this will not be
unfair to the defendant. If a claim is allowed where there is no agreement, there
may be an argument for allowing the claimant the benefit of a higher price if the
parties would have agreed to this.
In any case, where there is ‘free acceptance’, according to the court, the law
reverts to the objective measure. The reason appears to be that, if the defendant
‘freely accepted’ the benefit, he cannot then deny its objective value and insist on
a subjective valuation. This argument might be attractive if the defendant freely
accepted the benefit on the understanding that he would have to pay the market
price for it, but not if his understanding was that he would not have to pay for
it at all, or that he would be liable at a lower price than the market price.24 Thus
Lord Reed preferred what he called the ‘choice of benefit’ principle.25 A
defendant’s liability should depend on the basis on which he chose to accept the
benefit.26 This approach is preferable, according to Lord Reed, because it
protects the defendant’s autonomy, in the sense of his right to control the
deployment of his resources. This seems correct as far as it goes, but the
defendant surely cannot unilaterally stipulate the basis on which the benefit is
supplied, any more than the claimant can. The only way to uphold the
autonomy or freedom to choose of both parties is to base the claim on agree-
ment. The choice of benefit principle to protect autonomy is really what is
behind the traditional requirement that claims for payment for benefits conferred
must be based on agreement, understood to mean confining the claim to
contract. Thus, again, the true justification for applying a market rate without
subjective devaluation in Benedetti is that the claim was based on agreement.
© 2014 The Author. The Modern Law Review © 2014 The Modern Law Review Limited.
(2014) 77(6) MLR 983–1008 991
Unjust Enrichment and Contract
Lord Reed said he preferred the choice of benefit principle to the principle of
subjective devaluation, but these are not really alternatives. As I have suggested,
the choice of benefit principle really implies that agreement should be preferred
as the basis for a claim for payment for a benefit, where agreement is feasible,
whereas the principle of subjective devaluation – the principle that the subjective
price should be preferred in order to take account of the particular preferences,
plans and resources of the parties in determining the value of the benefit – is
properly applicable, it seems to me, where it is justified to allow a claim in the
absence of an agreement, under the alternative rule.
27 ibid at [119].
© 2014 The Author. The Modern Law Review © 2014 The Modern Law Review Limited.
992 (2014) 77(6) MLR 983–1008
Peter Jaffey
28 Examples of this type of problem arising from the unjust enrichment fallacy are discussed in P.
Jaffey, Private Law and Property Claims (Oxford: Hart, 2007) ch 8.
© 2014 The Author. The Modern Law Review © 2014 The Modern Law Review Limited.
(2014) 77(6) MLR 983–1008 993
Copyright of Modern Law Review is the property of Wiley-Blackwell and its content may not
be copied or emailed to multiple sites or posted to a listserv without the copyright holder's
express written permission. However, users may print, download, or email articles for
individual use.