Lec 14
Lec 14
Exchange Economy
• At some level, there is no such thing as the market for a single good.
• All changes in quantities or prices feed back into the demand and/or supply
for other goods through:
1. income effects
2. substitutability/complementarity of goods whose prices rise/fall
3. changes in the abundance/scarcity of other resources
— 2 goods
— 2 people
— Pure exchange. (No production in this first model, though we will
add this.)
— Perfect expression of the economic concept of opportunity costs.
• Their consumption:
F S
XA = (XA , XA )
F S
XB = (XB , XB )
• Without trade:
XA = EA
XB = EB
2
• With trade, many things can happen, but the following must be true:
F F F F
XA + XB = EA + EB
S S S S
XA + XB = EA + EB
• Starting from point E, the initial endowment, where will both parties end
up if they are allowed to trade?
• It is not fully clear because either or both could be made better off without
making either worse off. But it’s clear that they need to be somewhere in
the lens shaped region between UA0 and UB0 .
• How do we know this, because all of these points Pareto dominate E :
one or both parties could be made better off without making the other
worse off. There are potential gains from trade.
• A would prefer more food and less shelter, B would prefer less food and
more shelter.
• So hypothetically
S S
A gives up EA − XA
F F
A gains XA − EA
F F
B gives up XA − EA
S S
B gains EA − XA
3
2. Cannot make 1 person better off without making at least 1 other
person worse off.
3. All gains from trade exhausted.
E
EFA EFB
UA0
U B0
A
ESA
Shelter
1. In the initial endowment, the market clears (that is, all goods con
sumed) but the allocation is not Pareto efficient.
2. So, an auctioneer could announce some prices and then both parties
could trade what they have for what they preferred at these prices.
3. Problem: Choices would then be Pareto efficient but would not nec
essarily clear the market.
4. It’s possible there would be extra F and not enough S or vice versa.
5. So, must re-auction at new prices...
• See Figure 2.
14#2
Food
UB
UA
Proposed price
Shelter
At proposed prices:
5
• What should auctioneer do? Raise PF /PS .
• When the auctioneer gets the price ratio correct, the market clears. No
excess demand or supply for any good.
• This is a market equilibrium, competitive equilibrium, Walrasian equilib
rium, etc:
1. Each consumer choosing his most preferred bundle given prices and
his initial endowment.
2. All choices are compatible so that demand equals supply.
3. Pareto efficient consumption (‘Allocative Efficiency’):
µ ¶ µ ¶
∂U/∂F ∂U/∂F
=
∂U/∂S A ∂U/∂S B
where EDxA is A0 s ‘excess demand’ for good X. Note that excess demand
can be positive or negative (so more precisely, excess demand or excess
supply).
• Note that the excess demand is the amount of good A would like to con
sume relative to her current endowment (her ‘supply’).
• This equation states that given an initial supply (endowment) of goods
and a set of prices, an individual’s total excess demand for goods is zero.
Simply put, a consumer cannot buy more than the value of the goods she
holds, since the value of these goods is her budget constraint.
• A similar budget holds for consumer B:
Px EDxB + Py EDyB = 0.
Which is to say, that there cannot be either excess demand or excess supply
for all goods simultaneously.
• This observation — that total excess demand must equal zero — is called
Walras’ Law (after Leon Walras who first provided this proof).
• Hence, if there are n goods, and there is no excess demand for n − 1 of
these goods, then there is also no excess demands for the nth good.
• In our two-good exchange economy above, this proves that if the market
for food clears with no excess demand or excess supply, then the market
for shelter clears simultaneously.
7
• In partial equilibrium analysis, we have taken prices as exogenous. At the
individual level, this is true. For all practical purposes, my preferences do
not influence the price of Coca Cola.
• But in aggregate, prices depend on preferences. The market trade-off
among goods — that is, the price ratio — depends on the aggregation of the
psychic trade-offs among all potential consumers.
• What Walras showed, and what is clear from the Edgeworth box, is that
a competitive market will exhaust all of the gains from trade
• A free market, in equilibrium, is Pareto efficient.
• ...if the following conditions are true:
1. No externalities
2. Perfect competition
3. No transaction costs
4. Full information
— Along the contract curve, every point represents the tangency point
of two indifference curves
8
— This tangency point corresponds to a price ratio that separates the
two tangent indifference curves
— This price ratio clearly must exist if the indifference curves are tan-
gent and each is convex (so they don’t recross at some later point)
— This price ratio is therefore the market price vector that will support
that particular Pareto efficient allocation.
• Hence, it is immediate from the Edgeworth box that all Pareto efficient
distributions — that is, all points on the CC — are feasible as market equi
libria.
• As long as the assumptions above are met, a competitive equilibrium will
exist merely because each person is self-interestedly maximizing her own
well-being.
• This equilibrium cannot be improved upon without making at least one
person worse off. In other words, it’s Pareto efficient.
• Moreover, any Pareto efficient allocation can be maintained as a compet
itive equilibrium.
• This means that the problems of equity/distribution and efficiency can be
separated.
• Hence, another statement of 2nd welfare theorem is: There is no intrinsic
trade-off between equity and efficiency.
• When we discussed consumer versus producer surplus last class, I asserted
that it was justified to maximize the sum of the two rather than worry
ing about their division. The 2nd welfare theorem is what justified that
assertion.
1.7 Conclusions
• The fundamental welfare theorems provide some very basic policy guid
ance:
— The purpose of the price system is to ensure that all resources are
consumed in a Pareto efficient fashion — all gains from trade are
exhausted.
— This occurs automatically as prices adjust to clear the market.
— Distorting the price system to achieve equity is intrinsically a bad
idea (as we discussed in the partial equilibrium taxation example
prior to the first mid-term).
— Distorting the price system truly does create a trade-off between
efficiency and equity — which is exactly what the Welfare theorems
say we do not need to do.
9
— However, this does not mean we should ignore equity. We can achieve
whatever ‘equitable’ allocations of resources is desirable through lump-
sum distributions.
• Is this dictum — don’t distort prices — always correct? No. Because the
strong assumptions underlying the Welfare Theorems are not always — or
perhaps ever — met.
• But it does build a prima facie case that free market outcomes may be
efficient — or at least hard to improve upon.
• Hence, one should not presume that one can improve upon the market.
Instead:
• This insight—that the free market system generates a Pareto efficient equi
librium — is non-obvious. Why would anyone assume that prices are other
than arbitrary social creations?
• And in fact in most of human history, prices and market operations have
been viewed with a great deal of suspicion.
• But economic theory suggests that market equilibria:
10
• But Keayne is so distraught over his sin that he prostrates himself before
the church elders and “with tears acknowledges his covetous and corrupt
heart.”
• The minister off Boston cannot resist this golden opportunity to make an
example of Keayne.
• He uses the example of Keayne’s avarice to denounce during his Sunday
sermon on “some false principles of trade:”
1. That a man might sell as dear as he can, and buy as cheap as he can.
2. If a man loses by casualty of sea, etc., in some of his commodities,
he may raise the price of the rest.
3. That he may sell as he bought, though he paid too dear...
11