Paul Guyer - Idealism in Modern Philosophy (2023)
Paul Guyer - Idealism in Modern Philosophy (2023)
Paul Guyer - Idealism in Modern Philosophy (2023)
Idealism in Modern
Philosophy
PAUL GUYER
AND
ROLF-PETER HORSTMANN
Great Clarendon Street, Oxford, OX2 6DP,
United Kingdom
Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford.
It furthers the University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship,
and education by publishing worldwide. Oxford is a registered trade mark of
Oxford University Press in the UK and in certain other countries
© Paul Guyer and Rolf-Peter Horstmann 2023
The moral rights of the authors have been asserted
First Edition published in 2023
Impression: 1
All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in
a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, without the
prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted
by law, by licence or under terms agreed with the appropriate reprographics
rights organization. Enquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of the
above should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford University Press, at the
address above
You must not circulate this work in any other form
and you must impose this same condition on any acquirer
Published in the United States of America by Oxford University Press
198 Madison Avenue, New York, NY 10016, United States of America
British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data
Data available
Library of Congress Control Number: 2022945794
ISBN 978–0–19–284857–4 (hbk.)
ISBN 978–0–19–284858–1 (pbk.)
DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780192848574.001.0001
Printed and bound by
CPI Group (UK) Ltd, Croydon, CR0 4YY
Links to third party websites are provided by Oxford in good faith and
for information only. Oxford disclaims any responsibility for the materials
contained in any third party website referenced in this work.
Contents
Preface vii
1. Introduction 1
2. Idealism in Early Modern Rationalism 15
3. Idealism in Early Modern British Philosophy 25
4. Kant 47
5. German Idealism 70
6. The German Response to Idealism I: Schopenhauer
and Nietzsche 110
7. British and American Idealism 125
8. The Rejection of British Idealism 150
9. The German Response to Idealism II: Neo-Kantianism
without Idealism 159
10. Further into the Twentieth Century 174
11. Conclusion 203
Bibliography 207
Index 229
Preface
The terms “idealism” and “idealist” are by no means used only within
philosophy; they are used in many everyday contexts as well. Optimists
who believe that, in the long run, good will prevail are often called
“idealists.” This is not because such people are thought to be devoted to a
philosophical doctrine but because of their outlook on life generally; indeed,
they may even be pitied, or perhaps envied, for displaying a naive worldview
and not being philosophically critical at all. Even within philosophy, the
terms “idealism” and “idealist” are used in different ways, which often makes
their meaning dependent on the context. However, independently of context
one can distinguish between a descriptive (or classificatory) use of these
terms and a polemical one, although sometimes these different uses occur
together. Their descriptive use is best documented by paying attention to the
large number of different “idealisms” that appear in philosophical textbooks
and encyclopedias, ranging from metaphysical idealism through epistemo-
logical and aesthetic to moral or ethical idealism. Within these idealisms one
can find further distinctions, such as those between subjective, objective, and
absolute idealism, and even more obscure characterizations such as specu-
lative idealism and transcendental idealism. It is also remarkable that the
term “idealism,” at least within philosophy, is often used in such a way that it
gets its meaning through what is taken to be its opposite: as the meaningful
use of the term “outside” depends on a contrast with something considered
to be inside, so the meaning of the term “idealism” is often fixed by what is
taken to be its opposite. Thus, an idealist is sometimes taken to be someone
who is not a realist, not a materialist, not a dogmatist, not an empiricist, and
so on. Given the fact that many also want to distinguish between realism,
materialism, dogmatism, and empiricism, it is obvious that thinking of the
meaning of “idealism” as determined by what it is meant to be opposed to
leads to further complexity and gives rise to the impression that underlying
such characterizations lies some polemical or, at least, critical intent.
Within modern philosophy there are generally taken to be two fundamental
conceptions of idealism:
Idealism in Modern Philosophy. Paul Guyer and Rolf-Peter Horstmann, Oxford University Press.
© Paul Guyer and Rolf-Peter Horstmann 2023. DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780192848574.003.0001
2
have in common the view that there can be no physical objects existing
apart from some experience, and this might perhaps be taken as the
definition of idealism, provided that we regard thinking as part of experi-
ence and do not imply by “experience” passivity, and provided we include
under experience not only human experience but the so-called “Absolute
Experience” or the experience of a God such as Berkeley postulates.
(Ewing 1934: 3)
In other words, while reducing all reality to some kind of human perception, if
that is understood passively, is one form of idealism, it is not the only form—
reality may be reduced to the mental understood to involve activity as well as
passivity, or understood to comprise non-human as well as human mentality.
Thus Willem deVries’s more recent definition of idealism as the general
theory that reduces reality to some form or other of the mental is just:
We also agree with Jeremy Dunham, Iain Hamilton Grant, and Sean Watson
when they write that
doctrines, for Tom Rockmore has recently argued that materialist doctrines
since the time of Parmenides have also been based on the premise of a
necessary identity between knowledge and the known (Rockmore 2021)—
the difference is just that in the case of materialism, a view about the nature
of the object of knowledge is transferred to the conception of knowing and
the knower on the basis of the presumed identity, while in the case of
idealism the conception of the nature of knowledge and the knower is
transferred to the conception of the object of knowledge on the basis of
the same presumed identity.
It is in order to preserve the distinction between traditional idealism and
positions such as those of Carnap, Quine, and Davidson, or “conceptual”
and “linguistic idealists” such as Nicholas Rescher and Thomas Hofweber
(Rescher 1973; Hofweber 2017), all of which might be considered expres-
sions of the default position in twentieth-century philosophy held by all but
“naive realists” who believe that we necessarily represent reality exactly as it
is, that we define idealism by the claim that reality is in some way or other
fundamentally mental while recognizing epistemological arguments for
idealism as a metaphysical doctrine rather than epistemological idealism
as a distinct form of idealism. Of course metaphysical and epistemological
arguments for idealism can be combined by a single philosopher. As
we will see, Berkeley does so, and so does Kant in arguing for the transcen-
dental idealist part of his complex position. Others separate them, for
example in late nineteenth- and early twentieth-century British philosophy
F. H. Bradley and J. McT. E. McTaggart constructed metaphysical argu-
ments for idealism, while in the same period the Americans Josiah Royce
and Brand Blanshard offered epistemological arguments for idealism.
In what follows, we will concentrate mainly on the discussion of philo-
sophical theories that either endorse or claim to endorse idealism on onto-
logical and/or epistemological grounds. At some points in its complex
history, however, above all in the social as well as philosophical movement
that dominated British and American universities in the second half of the
nineteenth century and through World War I, idealism in either of its
philosophical forms was indeed connected to idealism in the popular sense
of progressive and optimistic social thought. This was true for figures such as
Bradley and Royce and their predecessors and contemporaries such as
Thomas Hill Green and Bernard Bosanquet. There has recently been con-
siderable interest in British or more generally anglophone idealism as a
movement in social philosophy, or even a social movement, but that aspect
of modern idealism will remain beyond our purview here, even if in some
6
ways that might be its most important aspect (see treatments of idealism as a
moral, political, and social movement: Mander 2011; Boucher and Vincent
2012; Mander ed. 2000; and Mander and Panagakou eds. 2016).
Our distinction between the view that epistemological and ontological
idealism are two distinct forms of idealism, which we reject, and the view
that that there are distinct metaphysical and epistemological arguments for
idealism, which we accept (which is not to say that we will be endorsing
these arguments themselves!), has not always been clearly made. However,
Josiah Royce, in many ways the leading spokesman for idealism in the
history of American philosophy (see Flower and Murphey 1977: ch. 12;
Kuklick 1977: chs. 8, 14–16; Kuklick 1985a; Oppenheim 2005), pointed in
the direction of our distinction at the end of the nineteenth century. On
Royce’s definitions, epistemological idealism
Metaphysical idealism, he says, “is a theory as to the nature of the real world,
however we may come to know that nature” (Royce 1892: xiii), namely a
theory, as he says quoting from another philosopher of the time, based
on the
belief in a spiritual principle at the basis of the world, without the reduction
of the physical world to a mere illusion.
(1892: xiii; quoting Falckenberg 1886: 476)
the more general and extremely widespread view that our knowledge is
always formed within our own point of view, conceptual framework, or
web of belief. This view may well be, as we have suggested, the default
position of much twentieth-century philosophy, “continental” as well as
“analytic,” but it does not by itself entail that reality is essentially mental.
Our distinction between epistemological and metaphysical arguments for
idealism can also be associated with a more general distinction between two
major kinds of motives for idealism: those that are grounded in self-
conceptions, that is, in convictions about the role that the self or the
human being plays in the world, and those based on what might corre-
spondingly be called world-convictions, that is, on conceptions about the
way the world is constituted objectively or at least appears to be constituted
to a human subject. Concerning motives based on self-conceptions of
human beings, idealism has seemed hard to avoid to many who have
taken freedom in one of its many guises (freedom of choice, freedom of
the will, freedom as autonomy) to be an integral part of any adequate
conception of the self, because the belief in the reality of freedom often
goes together with a commitment to some version of mental causation, and
it is tempting to think that the best or at least the most economical way to
account for mental causation consists in “mentalizing” or idealizing all of
reality, or at least to maintain that the kind of causal determinism that seems
to conflict with freedom is only one of our ways of representing the world.
This is a form of ontological argument for idealism. Motives for idealism
based on world-convictions can be found in many different attitudes toward
objectivity. If one believes in science as the best and only way to get an
objective, subject-independent conception of reality, one might still turn to
idealism, because of the conditions supposed to be necessary in order to
make sense of knowledge of a law of nature or of the normativity of logical
inferences with laws of nature; this would be an epistemological argument
for idealism. Then again, if one believes in the non-conventional reality of
normative facts one might also be drawn to idealism in order to account for
their non-physical reality—Plato’s idealism in the theory of Forms, which
asserts the reality of non-physical Ideas to explain the status of norms and
then reduces all other reality to mere simulacra of the former, a forerunner
of all later idealism, might be considered to offer an ontological motivation
for idealism in its explanation of the reality of norms. An inclination
toward idealism might even arise from considerations pertaining to the
ontological status of aesthetic values—is beauty an objective attribute of
objects?—or from the inability or the unwillingness to think of the
8
him idealists like Plato hold that “everything occurs in the soul as if there
were no body” whereas on the materialism of Epicurus “everything occurs in
the body as if there were no soul” (Leibniz 1702: 578). In this text Leibniz
does not call his own position idealism but says that it combines both of
these positions; here he was apparently in the mood in which he considered
physical objects to be real objects correlated with mind-like monads, instead
of the mood familiar from such works as his late essays “On the Principles of
Nature and Grace” and “The Monadology,” familiar to later eighteenth-
century philosophers, in which he unequivocally regarded physical bodies as
the mere appearance of harmoniously related monads to each other.
It seems to have been Christian Wolff who first used “idealism” explicitly
as a classificatory term. Wolff, often considered the most dedicated
Leibnizian of his time (although in fact his position was more eclectic than
at least some versions of Leibniz’s) set out to integrate the terms “idealism”
and “materialism” into his taxonomy of philosophical attitudes of those
“who strive towards the knowledge and philosophy of things” in the “Preface
to the other [second] Edition” of his so-called German Metaphysics (Wolff
1720, second edition 1747). Wolff distinguishes between two basic attitudes,
one of which he sees exemplified by the skeptic, the other by what he calls
“the dogmatist.” The skeptic doubts the possibility of knowledge in general
and thus refuses to defend any positive claim at all. By contrast, the
dogmatist puts forward positive doctrines, and these can be divided into
those which posit as fundamental either one single kind of entities [Art der
Dinge] or two different kinds. Wolff names the supporters of the first
position “monists” and the adherents of the second “dualists.” This amounts
to the division of all dogmatic doctrines, that is, all knowledge-claims with
respect to the ultimate constitution of reality, into monistic and dualistic
theories. Here is where the term “idealist” then makes its appearance in
Wolff ’s typology: he distinguishes within the monists between idealists and
materialists. Idealists “concede only spirits or else those things that do not
consist of matter,” whereas materialists “do not accept anything in philos-
ophy other than the corporeal and take spirits and souls to be a corporeal
force.” Dualists, on the contrary, are happy “to accept both bodies and spirits
as real and mutually independent things.” Wolff then goes on to distinguish
within idealism between “egoism” and “pluralism,” depending on whether
an idealist thinks just of himself as a real entity or whether he will allow for
more than one (spiritual) entity; the first of these positions would also come
to be called solipsism, so that solipsism would be a variety of idealism but
not all idealism would be solipsism.
14
Prior to Wolff, neither defending nor refuting idealism seems to have been a
central issue for rationalist philosophers, and none of them called them-
selves idealists. Yet what are by later lights idealistic tendencies—concepts
and premises for arguments that would later be taken to lead to idealism—
can nevertheless be found among them.
While Descartes’s “first philosophy” clearly defends dualism, he takes his
target to be skepticism rather than idealism, and thus from our point of view
he is concerned to resist the adoption of epistemological grounds for
idealism. Spinoza is often although controversially thought to defend a
form of materialism, but takes his primary target to be pluralism as con-
trasted to monism. Leibniz does not seem overly worried about choosing
between idealist and dualist forms of his “monadology” (Adams 1994
regards Leibniz as having consistently moved toward idealism over the
course of his career, while Garber 2009 presents him as remaining more
equivocal on the topic), but his view that the states of monads can be only
perceptions and appetitions (desires) suggests a metaphysical argument for
idealism, while his famous thesis that each monad represents the entire
universe from its own point of view might be taken to be an epistemological
ground for idealism, even if he does not say as much. Nicolas Malebranche’s
theory of “seeing all things in God” might be the closest we find to an explicit
assertion in seventeenth-century philosophy of an argument for idealism on
both epistemological and ontological grounds, and thus be taken as a
forerunner of the “absolute” idealism of the nineteenth century. While
from a later point of view it may seem surprising that these rationalists
were not more concerned with explicitly asserting or refuting one or both
approaches to idealism, they were more focused on theological puzzles about
the nature and essence of God, metaphysical questions as to how to reconcile
the conception of God with views about the independence or freedom of
finite beings such as ourselves, and epistemological problems as to the
possibility of knowledge and certainty. Once Descartes had distinguished
mental and physical substances, his successors certainly worried about how
two such different kinds of things can interact, and Leibniz adopted the idea
Idealism in Modern Philosophy. Paul Guyer and Rolf-Peter Horstmann, Oxford University Press.
© Paul Guyer and Rolf-Peter Horstmann 2023. DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780192848574.003.0002
16
claim can be seen as providing in the case of Descartes the basis for his
justification of ontological dualism. His distinction between extended and
thinking substances is not just meant to give rise to a complete classification
of all existing things in virtue of their main attributes but also to highlight
the irreducibility of mental (thinking) substances to physical or corporeal
(extended) substances because of differences between their intrinsic natures
(see, e.g., Meditation VI, para. 19, and Principles of Philosophy I, §§51–4).
The opposite, that is the non-reducibility of physical to mental substance,
would also be true, but of less importance to subsequent idealists. In the case
of Spinoza, thinking and extension refer not only to attributes of individual
things but primarily to attributes of God (see Ethics II, Propositions I, II, and
VII, Scholium), making them the fundamental ways in which God himself
expresses his nature in each individual thing. This move gives rise to his
ontological monism because he can claim that all individual things are just
expressions of God’s presence in modes of these two fundamental attributes.
Although the idea that God is the creator of the world of individual
existing things (Descartes) or that God himself is manifested in every
individual existing thing (Spinoza) might already be considered to be suffi-
cient as a motivating force for subsequent disputes as to the true nature of
reality and thus if God himself is conceived in mentalistic terms might have
given rise to what were then called “idealistic” positions in ontology, other
peculiarities within Descartes’s and Spinoza’s position might well have led to
the same result, that is, to the adoption of idealism on ontological grounds.
Denial of the corporeality of God might especially have been such a motive.
Whereas Descartes vigorously denies the corporeality of God (Principles of
Philosophy I, §23) and hence could be seen as starting an argument for
idealism insofar as God is seen as the only truly independent substance (see
Hatfield 2018), Spinoza vehemently insists on God’s corporeality (Ethics I,
Proposition XV, Scholium) and thus could be taken to be in favor of
materialism. Sir Isaac Newton is another seventeenth-century thinker who
conceives of God as present throughout the universe, and thus is taken to
insist on the corporeality of God. But if God were already conceived of as
essentially mind-like, then the theory of divine omnipresence could just as
easily be the beginning of an argument for idealism.
Things are different when it comes to epistemological grounds for
idealism. Descartes’s and Spinoza’s views of knowledge seem to be based
on versions of the traditional conception of truth as adequatio rei et intel-
lectus. They hold that knowledge should accommodate itself to reality, and
thus hardly seem to be paradigms for conceptions according to which
18
The monad which we are here to discuss is nothing but a simple substance
which enters into compounds,
that
There must be simple substances, since there are compounds, [and] the
compounded is but a collection or an aggregate of simples,
but that
Yet monads must have some qualities in order to exist (§8) and to differ
from one another, as they must insofar as they are numerically distinct (§9),
and if the fundamental properties of matter are excluded, this leaves only the
fundamental properties of mind, which Leibniz holds to be perception, “The
passing state which enfolds and represents a multitude in unity” (§14) and
appetition, “the internal principle which brings about change or the passage
from one perception to another” (§15; all from PPL 643–4). This argument
20
clearly seems to imply that all finite substances are ultimately mental in
nature (and the infinite substance, God, is obviously mental in nature); thus
it seems to be a paradigmatic ontological argument for idealism, from which
an epistemological complement would automatically follow, since if there is
knowledge of reality at all, which Leibniz hardly seems to doubt, and reality
is ultimately mental, then knowledge too must be of the mental. Leibniz
would not be arguing from the premise that knowledge must be identical
with the known, thus that reality must be mental because knowledge is, but
would rather be concluding with this identity: since reality itself is mental, it
is after all identical (in kind) with knowledge.
Yet Leibniz sometimes seems to be trying to avert such a conclusion
by appeal to his idea of “pre-established harmony,” and this is possible
because he himself interprets this idea in two different ways. Early in his
career, in such texts as “Primary Truths” (1680–4) and the “Discourse on
Metaphysics” (1686) (both texts unpublished in Leibniz’s lifetime and not
known to his immediate successors such as Wolff and Baumgarten), Leibniz
introduces the doctrine of pre-established harmony on truth-theoretical
grounds. His argument is that everything that is true of a substance is so
because the predicate of a true proposition is contained in the complete
concept of its subject and because that complete concept reflects the proper-
ties or “traces” in the substance that is that subject; that there are true
propositions linking every substance in the world to every other, thus the
complete concept of each substance must be a complete concept of the
universe itself and each substance must bear within itself as properties traces
of every other in the universe; and thus that each substance must reflect, or,
as mental, represent the entire universe. Yet since (finite) substances are also
defined as existing independently of one another (although not existing
independently from the infinite substance, God), there is a question as to
why each should truthfully represent all the others, which Leibniz answers
by appeal to the idea of a pre-established harmony: although considered
from the point of view of the concept of substance it does not seem necessary
that every substance truly represent all the others, in his goodness, thus in
his preference for a maximally harmonious world, God has nevertheless
made it such that they do.
In this mood, Leibniz tends to explain the existence of body as an artifact
of the fact that each monad represents the world from its own point of view:
physical locations and the bodies that occupy them are just the way in which
the difference in the points of view of the monads is represented by them,
but have no deeper reality; or, as Leibniz often says, space, spatiality, and
21
bodies are just phenomena bene fundata, that is, “well-founded modes of our
consideration” (PPL 270).
Perhaps Leibniz obscured the completely idealist implications of his
monadology from himself and some followers as well by the ambiguity of
his conception of the pre-established harmony among all substances, an
assumption that itself does not turn on any epistemological premise but on a
theological premise, that of God’s benevolence, which might be considered
metaphysical in character. In many places, Leibniz considers the appearance
of spatial relation to be nothing but the way in which the pre-established
harmony between monads that properly speaking have only mental proper-
ties appears to those monads, and thus considers space and everything
insofar as it seems spatial to be phaenomena bene fundata, an obvious source
for Kant’s later conception of the spatio-temporal realm as merely phenom-
enal. Sometimes, however, Leibniz wrote as if the mental and the physical,
that is, the spatially extended, are two separate realms, each of which evolves
according to its own internal principles, but with a pre-established harmony
between them creating the appearance of interaction between them.
Sometimes Leibniz interpreted his pre-established harmony in a monisti-
cally idealist way, sometimes in defense of metaphysical dualism. Perhaps
Leibniz was genuinely undecided between two interpretations of the pre-
established harmony and two conceptions of the reality of body, sometimes
being a committed idealist and sometimes a dualist. As we will see later, even
among the most committed absolute idealists of the nineteenth century it is
not always clear whether they are actually denying the existence of matter or
only subordinating it to mind in one way or another. But his basic concep-
tion of the monads, which did not seem to vary much between 1686 and
1714, entailed idealism, whether Leibniz liked this result or not. (So in the
end we agree with Adams 1994.)
Leibniz’s monadology can thus be seen as a forerunner of an ontological
argument for idealism that brings an idealist epistemology in its train. His
conception of space and time as phenomena bene fundata was clearly a
forerunner of Kant’s conception of the transcendental ideality of space and
time, if not of the whole package of his transcendental idealism, which also
affirms the existence of things in themselves of unknowable nature, which
are therefore not all determinable as mental or having representations,
except perhaps in our own case. But as we have just seen, Leibniz did not
himself unequivocally affirm idealism, and as we will shortly see subsequent
Leibnizians such as Alexander Gottlieb Baumgarten argued for dualism and
for a corresponding interpretation of pre-established harmony.
22
not only more substances but also more kinds of substances rather than
fewer is a more perfect universe, and necessarily exists in preference to the
other; and a universe that contains not only multiple minds rather than a
single mind but also bodies in addition to minds is therefore a more perfect
universe than either of the former would be, and is therefore the kind of
world that actually exists. In his words,
the egotistical world, such as an egoist posits, is not the most perfect. And
even if there is only one non-intellectual monad possible in itself that is
compossible with spirits in the world, whose perfection either subtracts
nothing from the perfection of the spirits, or does not subtract from the
perfection of the spirits so much as it adds to the perfection of the whole,
then the idealistic world, such as is posited by the idealist, is not the most
perfect (Metaphysics, §438; Baumgarten [1739] 2013: 183)
and hence not the kind of world that exists. No one outside of the immediate
sphere of Leibnizianism would ever again proffer such a refutation of
idealism. But both Baumgarten’s recognition of idealism and his refutation
of it in a university textbook make it clear that by the middle of the
eighteenth century idealism had become a standard topic for philosophical
discussion, a position it would retain for another century and a half or more.
3
Idealism in Early Modern British
Philosophy
Idealism in Modern Philosophy. Paul Guyer and Rolf-Peter Horstmann, Oxford University Press.
© Paul Guyer and Rolf-Peter Horstmann 2023. DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780192848574.003.0003
26
For they represent to us Things under those appearances which they are
fitted to produce in us: whereby we are enabled to distinguish the sorts of
particular Substances, to discern the states they are in, and so to take them
for our Necessities, and apply them to our Uses. (Essay IV.IV, §4)
At the very least, how things appear to us is the basis of our knowledge of
them and sufficient for our successful interaction with them—Locke might
be seen as an ancestor of later pragmatism as much as idealism. And the
faculties that shape how things appear to us were attributed by the British
philosophers as well as by their Continental counterparts to what was called
“spirit” or “mind” (mens, consciousness, Bewußtsein), an attribution that
resulted in moving the “operations of the mind” into the center of philo-
sophical attention. Reflections on the conditions of the possibility of knowl-
edge certainly pushed Hobbes and Locke away from any form of naive
realism in spite of their ontological commitments to materialism or dualism
respectively, while Berkeley concluded that their epistemology would lead to
a skepticism that could be avoided only by his own more radical “immate-
rialist” ontology. Hume’s position remains complex and for this reason
controversial. His thesis that our beliefs in causation, external objects, and
even the self are all founded on “custom” and imagination rather than
“reason” may be considered an epistemological position without ontological
implications, thus not an argument for idealism; but while he sometimes
seems to attempt to avoid commitment on ontological questions altogether,
at other times, as in his argument that the existence of external objects in
addition to our impressions is only a fiction, he comes close to inferring
28
The first principle of knowledge therefore is that we have such and such
conceptions; the second, that we have thus and thus named the things
29
whereof they are conceptions; the third is, that we have joined those names
in such manner, as to make true propositions; the fourth and last is, that we
have joined those propositions in such manner as they be concluding.
(Elements of Law I.6.4)
Now things may be considered, that is, be brought into account, either as
internal accidents of our mind, in which manner we consider them when
the question is about some faculty of the mind; or as species of external
things, not as really existing, but appearing only to exist, or to have a being
without us [emphasis added]. And in this manner we are now to
consider them. (Elements of Law II.7.1)
I shall not at present meddle with the physical consideration of the mind;
or trouble myself to examine, wherein its essence consists, or by what
motions of our spirits, or alterations of our bodies, we come to have any
sensation by our organs, or any ideas in our understandings; and whether
those ideas do in their formation, any, or all of them, depend on matter or no
[emphasis added]: These are speculations, which, however curious and
entertaining, I shall decline. (Essay I.I, §2; see also II.XXI, §73)
causes and these sources. What we know is the content and structure of our
own ideas, although we have no reason to deny the existence of external
objects and we may even assume that in some regards external objects
resemble our ideas of them, namely in the case of primary qualities such
as shape, size, solidity, and number, at least in kind if not in detail. (That is,
Locke assumes, the microscopic particles of which bodies are hypothesized
to consist must have some shape, size, etc., but there is no reason to think
that those qualities resemble the particular versions of them that we perceive
in macroscopic objects.)
Point (3) is obviously important for the question whether Locke’s con-
ception of the operations of the mind is dualist or actually idealist. As in the
case of Hobbes, Locke’s position was intended to be neutral against and
compatible with all these alternatives and he wanted to remain agnostic with
respect to them. This is clear from his account of substance and from his
remarks concerning the limits of knowledge. Substances, Locke famously
holds,
will find he has no other Idea of it at all, but only a Supposition of he knows
not what support of such qualities, which are capable of producing simple
Ideas in us. (Essay II.XXIII, §2)
Locke has a short argument for this supposition: while we cannot make
sense of the idea of unsupported qualities or ideas subsisting by themselves
and therefore must assume some support or “substratum” for them, the
general idea of substance in the ideas of all particular kinds of substances,
nevertheless since we know that “a certain number of these simple Ideas go
constantly together” or “exist together” only from experience we have no
source for and therefore cannot make any sense of the idea of an additional
support or “substratum” for these ideas (Essay II.XXIII, §§2–3). Although
Locke thinks of this argument as compelling, he sees quite well that it neither
justifies nor excludes any claim as to what a substance or a thing really is,
what its nature or constitution consists in. Thus he never tires of emphasiz-
ing that we have only a confused idea of substance (a claim also made by
Leibniz about three-quarters of our knowledge, although he held that we
32
have a clear concept of what substance is), and repeats quite often (at least
three times in Essay II.XXIII alone) that
metaphysical knowledge of any kind is beyond our reach. Yet this is nothing
for us to be concerned about:
any one of my ideas, but a thing entirely distinct from them, wherein they
exist or, which is the same thing, whereby they are perceived.
(1710: Part I, §2)
If we look but ever so little into our thoughts, we shall find it impossible for
us to conceive a likeness except only between our ideas. Again, I ask
whether those supposed originals or external things, of which our
ideas are the pictures or representations, be themselves perceivable or
no? if they are, then they are ideas, and we have gained our point; but if
you say they are not, I appeal to any one whether it be sense, to assert a
colour is like something which is invisible; hard or soft, like something
which is intangible; and so of the rest. (1710: Part I, §8)
To be sure, the last step of this argument depends on the presupposition that
external objects could not be colored, hard or soft, etc., in themselves, or that
these sorts of properties are properties of ideas only. The likeness argument
cannot stand without that assumption, so cannot count as an entirely self-
standing argument for Berkeley’s immaterialism.
There is a third metaphysical claim that is essential to both Berkeley’s
criticism of Locke and the idealistic position he is going to adopt for himself.
This is the claim (3) that ideas are passive and causally inert, that is, they can
neither produce nor alter another idea (1710: Part I, §25). This claim he also
purports to base on observation:
36
whoever shall attend to his ideas, whether of sense or reflection, will not
perceive in them any power or activity; there is therefore no such thing
contained in them. A little attention will discover to us that the very being
of an idea implies passiveness and inertness in it, insomuch that it is
impossible for an idea to do any thing, or, strictly speaking, to be the
cause of any thing. (1710: Part I, §25)
other non-human, that is, divine mind. This divine mind cannot be itself an
idea because it must be conceived as an active principle that can be the cause
of ideas, a principle of which we can have no idea but only a “notion” (1710:
Part I, §26, §27; Dicker 2011: 252–80). Therefore, the very fact that we take
things or substances to be real commits us to the claim that things are ideal
entities perceived by the mind of God. Idealism, one could say, is the only
tenable basis for a realistic stance for Berkeley, but it leads to a realism about
minds, human and divine, rather than of what he always calls material
substance. And if one were to accept his interpretation of causality as a
relation between ideas in terms of his theory of marks and signs, in partic-
ular his theory that what we think of as ideas of objects are signs of (God’s
plan for) future possible ideas for us, a view obviously influenced by
Malebranche (cf. 1710: Part I, §65f.), then one would also have to agree to
idealism. In Berkeley’s view, the only alternative to idealism is not materi-
alism but skepticism.
Berkeley’s argumentation for his immaterialism was much more of a mix
of epistemological and metaphysical considerations than Leibniz’s purely
metaphysical arguments. When Berkeley makes arguments in his Three
Dialogues between Hylas and Philonous (1713) such as that heat might be
thought to exist outside the mind, while pain is surely thought to exist only
within the mind, yet “they are both immediately perceived at the same time,
and the fire affects you with only one simple, or uncompounded idea,” so
that “the intense heat immediately perceived, is nothing distinct from a
particular sort of pain” (Berkeley, Three Dialogues, in Berkeley 1948–57: 2:
176), and is thus as mental as the pain is, this might be considered a
metaphysical argument, namely that since heat and pain cannot be sepa-
rated, they must be one and the same thing, and since pain is clearly mental,
so must be heat (see Dicker 2011: 90–100). But it might also be considered
an epistemological argument, namely that if we cannot know heat without
knowing pain, then heat and pain must be the same thing, and since the
latter is mental, or an idea, the former, and in due course other supposedly
physical properties, must also be mental. Some of Berkeley’s arguments in
the somewhat more technical Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human
Knowledge might also be considered epistemological, such as the “master
argument” on which he claims he is “content to put the whole upon,”
namely that you cannot conceive of anything existing unconceived because
you cannot do this without conceiving yourself conceiving it, so in fact no
conceiving or perceiving is ever anything more than “framing in your mind
certain ideas” (Berkeley 1710: Part I, §§22–3, in Berkeley 1948–57: 2: 50),
38
that too turns on claims about what we can conceive or perceive. But when
Berkeley claims that “the existence of an idea consists in being perceived”
and “an idea can be like nothing but an idea” (Berkeley 1710: Part I, §3, §8,
in Berkeley 1948–57: 2: 42, 44), those are metaphysical claims, made on the
basis of assumptions about the very nature of ideas. It is not that we have no
way of knowing whether an idea could exist without being perceived, or
whether it could be like something that is not an idea; it is that these are not
even possible, at least in Berkeley’s view. His further claim that ideas are
passive, causally inert, thus that they can neither produce nor alter other
ideas (Berkeley 1710: Part I, §25, in Berkeley 1948–57: 2: 51), is also a
metaphysical rather than epistemological claim, although it might also
lead only to a parasitical argument: it could ground an argument that
nothing outside our ideas could cause them only if it were already supposed
that the only candidate for anything outside our ideas was more ideas, which
by the metaphysical premise could then not cause our ideas. But idealism
would already have been presupposed in such an argument.
This argument might also cause difficulties for Berkeley’s theology. Faced
with the question of why we think objects have continued existence when
our ideas of them do not, Berkeley appeals to the divine mind, infinite in
capacity, that has all ideas all the time. But if one idea does not cause
another, God’s ideas cannot cause our ideas, so the solution can only be
that of Nicolas Malebranche: that we humans directly perceive, though only
intermittently, the ideas in the mind of God. Of course, then we are
perceiving something outside our own ideas, so this may be problematic
for Berkeley. However, this does not have to be discussed here. The relevant
point here is just to emphasize that he offers epistemological as well as
metaphysical arguments for idealism.
Up until the point at which he introduces the mind of God into his
argument, all of Berkeley’s epistemological considerations might be thought
of as expressions of the basic insight that we can only conceive of reality
from our own point of view, which are then extended into full-blown
idealism in order to avoid the whiff of agnosticism or skepticism and
supplemented with the existence of a divine mind in order to satisfy
our ineliminable tendency to believe in the existence of something
more than just one’s own mind or even of human minds in general. We
will later see that the tendency to preserve both the impulse to idealism
and the conviction that there is something more than ordinary human
minds by positing a more than human mind is characteristic of many
versions of idealism until the end of its glory days at the beginning of
39
the twentieth century. As we will see, this tendency is definitely absent from
the philosophy of David Hume.
Before we turn to Hume, however, a look at Arthur Collier, a close
contemporary of Berkeley who also defended idealism, will be in order.
Arthur Collier was a much more obscure clergyman than Berkeley. He
published his Clavis Universalis: Or, A New Inquiry after Truth, Being a
Demonstration of the Non-Existence, or Impossibility, of an External World
in 1713, the same year that Berkeley’s Three Dialogues appeared and three
years after Berkeley’s Treatise on the Principles of Human Knowledge;
however, he states that he had originally conceived his position a decade
earlier, so before he could have read Berkeley. Although the work was not
widely read, it was translated into German by Johann Christian Eschenbach
in 1756, and then noticed by Thomas Reid and following him Dugald
Stewart. It was republished in English in 1837 along with Collier’s other
philosophical work, A Specimen of True Philosophy, in a collection of
Metaphysical Tracts edited by Samuel Parr, and then again in 1909, edited
with an introduction by Ethel Bowman. By “external,” mentioned in the title
of his book, Collier meant “independent, absolute, or self-existent,” and his
position is that “all matter, body, extension, &c.” (which he also frequently
calls “expansion”) depends “on mind, thought, or perception, and that it is
not capable of an existence, which is not thus dependent” (Collier 1713
[1909: 6]). Collier’s position is thus full-throated idealism, which he empha-
sizes is neither skepticism nor a denial that bodies exist, but the position that
such and such bodies, which are supposed to exist, do not exist externally;
or in universal terms, that there is no such thing as an external world.
(1713 [1909: 9])
Collier argues for his idealism on both epistemological and more purely
metaphysical grounds. His work, although a footnote in the history of
philosophy, is interesting precisely because it so clearly illustrates the dual
strategies for arguing for idealism.
Collier’s most purely epistemological argument is that we are all familiar
with (visual) experiences that are assumed to be of external objects but
which do not differ from similar experiences that are clearly not of external
objects, yet that there is no discernible difference between the latter and the
former, thus that if the latter are in or entirely dependent upon the mind,
then so must be the former. His argument might be thought to be a variant
of Descartes’s argument that there is no obvious difference between the
40
more likely that Collier’s argument that the difference between what we
ordinarily take to be a veridical perception and a mere imagination or
hallucination is merely a matter of vividness, and that the latter can become
as vivid as the former and thereby undermine any use of vividness as a
criterion of externality (1713 [1909: 19–20]), could have been known to
Hume and influenced his formulation of the distinction between impres-
sions and ideas in his Treatise of Human Nature (1739–40). So at this point
we can turn to Hume.
Whether or not David Hume (1711–76) learned from Collier, he learned
a great deal from Berkeley, above all his empiricist epistemology. He tried to
avoid Berkeley’s outright commitment to idealism, but there are parts of
Hume’s philosophy that it is difficult to read as other than idealist. Hume’s
view that our knowledge consists of our ideas, our recognition of “philo-
sophical” relations among them, such as identity and difference, and our
recognition of “natural” relations among them such as causation, which are
established by imagination and custom, could constitute an epistemological
ground for idealism—causality, in particular, which Hume regards as the
basis of all our knowledge of existence, is reduced to a way of feeling and
thinking, in other words a state of mind. But depending on how he is read,
Hume either accepts the skepticism about possible external objects that
Berkeley tries to avoid with his ontology that renders any external objects
other than other human or divine minds impossible, or else holds that even
if there are valid arguments for skepticism it is psychologically impossible
for human beings to remain in a skeptical frame of mind, thus we naturally
even if not rationally believe in the existence of objects apart from our ideas
of them. (The “skeptical” reading of Hume which prevailed in the eighteenth
century and was extensively stated in Green 1874, has in recent years been
defended in Flew 1961, Fogelin 1985, and De Pierris 2015; the “naturalist”
reading, that Hume is explaining our beliefs without attempting to under-
mine them, goes back to Kemp Smith 1941 and more recently Stroud 1977.
Garrett 1997 presents Hume as using skeptical arguments to advance his
naturalism, while Loeb 2002 sees Hume as starting from naturalism but
lapsing into skepticism. Russell 2008 sees both skepticism and naturalism as
moments in Hume’s attack upon religion, or defense of “irreligion.”)
However, in those passages, prominently in Book I, Part IV of his early
Treatise of Human Nature (1739–40), where Hume entertains a kind of
monism that sees both “minds” and “objects” as nothing but different sets or
“bundles” of one sort of thing, namely, perceptions, impressions and their
paler copies, ideas, his position might seem much like Berkeley’s idealism,
42
with the difference that while he reduces all reality to mental states like
impressions and ideas he does not see these as properties that must inhere in
substantial minds any more than in substantial bodies. For Hume, both of
these are fictions that we introduce in order to explain continuities among
those impressions or ideas—although it may be difficult to explain who is
introducing those fictions without resorting to substantial minds after
all, in which case it is hard to see how Hume’s position ultimately differs
from Berkeley’s except in his aversion to actually asserting a metaphysical
thesis.
Hume’s potentially idealist approach to causation is clearly on view in his
1748 Enquiry Concerning Human Knowledge, which was quickly translated
into German and would eventually provide Kant with the stimulus for his
own aprioristic rather than empiricist argument for idealism with regard not
only to causation but to all of what he called the categories of pure reason,
including especially substance and interaction as well as causation. But since
Kant was not completely familiar with the contents of Hume’s earlier
Treatise of Human Nature, he did not know, or at least acknowledge, that
Hume too had generalized his approach to causality to the cases of mind and
body, nor did he know that Hume may have tried to sidestep Berkeley’s
commitment to substances but not his idealism altogether by his theory of
both minds and bodies as bundles of perceptions. Kant would try to avert
Berkeley’s version of idealism by a different stratagem, but before we come
to that we must consider Hume’s position more fully. Hume accepted from
Locke and Descartes before him that the immediate objects of consciousness
are what they had called ideas, although he reserves that word for copies or
subsequently recalled perceptions rather than the originally experienced
perceptions that he calls impressions. He also adopts the view of his pre-
decessors that knowledge lies in the recognition of relations among impres-
sions, ideas, or both, and divides those relations into two kinds,
philosophical and natural. Philosophical relations are those immediately
evident on reflection on or comparison of particular ideas, and include
resemblance, identity, spatial and temporal relations such as above and
below or before and after, number and degree, and logical contrariety
(Hume 1739–40: I.I.5), while natural relations are those that are not imme-
diately evident on reflection on a single impression or idea or in a single
comparison of any number, but which instead become evident, or more
properly are formed, only through repeated experience. Hume’s best-known
argument is then that causation is not a philosophical but a natural relation:
the causal relation comprises temporal succession, spatial contiguity, and
43
necessary connection, and while the first two are philosophical relations that
are immediately apparent, the necessary connection between different
ideas—those of a cause and its separate effect—is, unlike the necessary
identity of two qualitatively similar ideas, not immediately apparent, as
Hume puts it, to reason (1739–40: I.III.2), but instead grows only out of
repeated experience: The repeated experience of qualitatively similar pairs of
impressions causes them to become linked in the mind, as we would
ordinarily say, or at least in consciousness, as the careful Hume should say
at most (1739–40: I.III.6). In fact, Hume’s argument is that repeated expe-
rience itself has two effects: it creates a habit of thought such that upon the
presentation of an impression of one kind that has repeatedly been experi-
enced in spatial and temporal conjunction with one of another kind,
a vivid version of the idea of the kind of impression with which the first
kind of impression has been repeatedly associated immediately occurs—this
is the essence of causal inference or belief, because a belief is nothing but an
idea that is almost as vivid and forceful as the impression of which it was
once a copy (1739–40: I.III.7–8; this is the thought Hume could
have learned from Arthur Collier)—and second, there is an actual feeling
of the mind (as we would ordinarily say) being tugged from the one
impression to the other idea—this is the basis of the idea of necessary
connection, a connection which the mind then “spreads” upon its objects
to form the idea of a necessary connection among them or their states
(1739–40: I.III.14). (A systematic treatment of Hume on causation is
Beebee 2006, while Stove 1973 focuses specifically on Hume’s account of
induction.)
Hume’s account of our idea of and belief in causation might be considered
to already take one step toward idealism by relocating the relation of
causation from the external objects where we would ordinarily suppose it
to obtain to the mind, which we would ordinarily suppose knows but does
not constitute the relation known. In Hume’s words,
Tho’ the several resembling instances, which give rise to the idea of power,
have no influence on each other, and can never produce any new quality in
the object, which can be a model of that idea [of power or causation], yet
the observation of this resemblance produces a new impression in the
mind, which is its real model. . . . Necessity, then, is the effect of this
observation, and is nothing but an internal impression of the mind, or a
determination to carry our thoughts from one object to another.
(1739–40: I.III.14, para. 20)
44
Several things may be noted about this theory. For one, if it had been
Hume’s intent to raise a general skepticism about causation, based on the
famous worry about induction that he himself raises, especially in the
subsequent Enquiry, namely that an assertion of causality claims that future
impressions will occur in the same patterns as past ones but there is no basis
“in reason” for assuming that the future will resemble the past, then the
relocation of causation from the domain of objects to the domain of the
mind should make no difference, because we have no more reason to believe
that the mind will behave the same way in the future as it has in the past than
we do to believe that about anything else. So we must either believe that
Hume is very confused, not realizing that his skepticism about induction as
applied to external objects must undermine our confidence in his applica-
tion of induction to the mind itself, or else that he is very arch, and that he
means us to do his skeptical work for him by carrying over skepticism about
induction to the case of the mind itself, or else that he is not really worrying
about issues of justification and thus of the threat of skepticism at all, but just
means to be giving a plausible description of the only possible basis for causal
inference, namely the mind’s experience of itself. The last possibility may
well seem to be the most plausible, leading to the “naturalist” reading of
Hume promoted by Norman Kemp Smith, Barry Stroud, and Don Garrett
rather than the “skeptical” reading of Hume accepted by Hume’s contem-
poraries such as James Beattie and Thomas Reid and defended recently and
more skillfully by Robert Fogelin.
There is a further issue with Hume’s treatment of causation that is largely
suppressed in the Enquiry but that was evident in the Treatise, namely, that
although, as we saw in the last passage quoted, Hume sometimes describes
necessary connection as being displaced from the object to the mind, on his
own strict interpretation of empiricism there is a problem in positing the
existence of either objects or minds distinct from perceptions. This is what
pushes Hume toward his own even if unacknowledged form of idealism.
That is, although we naturally speak of perceptions as being of objects and in
or by the mind, on the view that all knowledge is founded on perception and
that in perception we are immediately acquainted with nothing but percep-
tions, it becomes problematic how we could have knowledge either of the
mind itself or of any object of perceptions distinct from those perceptions.
Hume puts the former point succinctly by arguing that we have no percep-
tion of the self distinct from our perception of its perceptual states:
For my part, when I enter most intimately into what I call myself, I always
stumble on some particular perception or other, of heat or cold, light or
45
shade, love or hatred, pain or pleasure. I can never catch myself at any time
without a perception, and never can observe any thing but the perception.
(1739–40: I.IV.6.3)
and that the idea of a continuous self is but a fiction or illusion created by
relations of resemblance and continuity among perceptions in the bundle,
just as both the idea of and belief in causal connection were created by
repetition of pairs of impressions. Without saying that the objects of per-
ception are also nothing but bundles of related perceptions, Hume presents a
similar account of how the idea of objects distinct from our perceptions of
them is generated by our impression of continuity among perceptions:
although only philosophers reflect on this, in fact we know that perceptions
are fleeting and transitory; we mistake continuity among them for enduring
identity; and we then invent something other than perceptions, something
not fleeting and transitory, to which to ascribe that enduring identity
(1739–40: I.IV.2). In neither case, however, do we nor can we actually
have a clear idea of any object or substance distinct from our perceptions,
because all our basic ideas must be copied from impressions and we do not
have impressions of these things. Thus we do not have an idea of external
objects or their substance, but neither do we have a clear idea of the mind or
its substance. We may not reflect upon this fact in ordinary life (perhaps we
cannot keep it in mind in ordinary life), but in philosophy we cannot
avoid it.
Hume’s attack on the supposition that we have an idea of the mind as
distinct from its impressions thus constitutes a rejection of Berkeley’s
commitment to the existence of mental substances, but not of idealism
altogether. On Hume’s account, we are not entitled to assert the existence
of both ideas and the minds, human or divine, that have them, but only the
existence of the former. Hume does not admit that we are forced into
skepticism about either minds or external objects by his approach, that is,
into a position that there may really be minds and external objects but we
cannot know that fact or their real qualities, nor does he confront
Descartes’s argument that skepticism about the existence of one’s own
mind is impossible; yet he still has a lingering worry that although there
46
are psychological mechanisms that lead us to form the fictions of minds and
bodies beyond perceptions, we do not really know what we are talking about
when we talk about such things, and thus cannot even coherently doubt
whether we have knowledge of them—our talk about them is explicable but
meaningless. Hume thus seems to end up with an uneasy compromise
between idealism and agnosticism.
4
Kant
Idealism in Modern Philosophy. Paul Guyer and Rolf-Peter Horstmann, Oxford University Press.
© Paul Guyer and Rolf-Peter Horstmann 2023. DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780192848574.003.0004
48
based on moral grounds; indeed he holds ultimately that God is nothing but
our idea of our own capacity for morality (see Guyer 2000); so in this case we
still do not have genuine knowledge of the nature of something existing in
itself. The other case is that of our own freedom, which according to Kant
must be a “transcendental freedom” that is incompatible with the thorough-
going causal determinism of the world as we experience it because it must be
a freedom to choose to do the right thing no matter what our circumstances
and prior history might seem to determine us to do, and which must
therefore be a capacity of our “noumenal” selves or of our selves as they
really are rather than of our “phenomenal” selves or selves as they appear to
us. In this case Kant may be allowing genuine knowledge of our selves as
they are in themselves, and attributing to them a capacity that is incompat-
ible with the properties of bodies as we ordinarily experience them; but as he
does not hold that all things in themselves have this capacity, neither is he
insisting that all reality is essentially mental in nature. Thus his position
remains distinct from the thoroughgoing idealism of Berkeley or indeed of
Leibniz.
The sources as well as the form of Kant’s position are complex. Kant was
deeply impressed by what he knew of Leibniz (the qualification “what he
knew of” is necessary because many of the texts that are crucial to later
understandings of Leibniz, such as “Primary Truths” and the “Discourse on
Metaphysics” (1686) were entirely unknown during Kant’s lifetime, and
others, such as the New Essays on Human Understanding, were published
only when Kant was well into his career, in 1765, and may already have fixed
his view of Leibniz), in particular by Leibniz’s view that space and time are
phaenomena bene fundata, “well-founded phenomena” but not representa-
tive of the real nature of things; indeed, Leibniz is the obvious source for
Kant’s use of the term “phenomena” to designate how things appear to us,
although his use of the counterpart term “noumena” to designate how they
might be in themselves seems to be his addition to Leibniz’s terminology.
Kant was also influenced by what he knew of Hume and his view that
causation is a form of thinking that we impose upon our experience rather
than something we directly experience. He was more generally impressed by
the empiricist argument that our knowledge of objects depends upon expe-
rience of them: for Kant, our own minds never supply more than the general
forms of intuitions and concepts, of sensibility and understanding, while the
“matter” of experience and thus the content for all empirical concepts is
always supplied by experience—a fact from which Kant draws the far-
reaching consequence that the idea of a complete system of empirical
49
But although Kant insists that his own “transcendental idealism” includes
“empirical realism,” that is, recognition of the pervasive reality of space and
time, thus of enduring external objects, in our experience, he does not want
to call his own position “transcendental realism,” because for him that
would be the view that objects independent of our representations do exist
with the forms that we represent them as having. That is, in Kant’s terms,
transcendental realism would be the view that things really are spatial and
temporal independently of our representing them as such. Nor would he
even be happy to call this conception of things in themselves a kind of
idealism, because it is part of his position that, at least from what he calls a
theoretical point of view, we cannot suppose that even our own minds are
really as they appear to us, nor can we assert that the reality that ultimately
underlies the appearance of minds is essentially different from the reality
that ultimately underlies the appearance of bodies. Yet he remains confident
that we are entitled to assert the existence of some sort of reality underlying
the appearance of both minds and bodies. And to make matters even more
complicated, he is confident, as already noted, that we can rationally believe
God to be mental in nature from what he calls a “practical” point of view,
that is, as a necessary presupposition of rationally attempting to do what
morality commands, and even seems to think that our own freedom,
incompatible with the nature of matter, is genuinely known, a “fact of
reason” (CPrR 5:30). A complete characterization of Kant’s position would
thus be empirical realism about space, time, causation, and the other cate-
gories, transcendental idealism about space and time but combined with
realism about the existence of things in themselves, and now even “practical”
idealism about the nature of ourselves as things in themselves and the nature
of God, as in both cases essentially mental or spiritual—a positive assertion
of the special, non-material nature of God and self but not of all things in
themselves.
Kant had already published a number of substantial scientific as well as
philosophical works before the “great light” of transcendental idealism came
to him in 1769, leading to his first statement of it the following year in his
inaugural dissertation, On the Forms and Principles of the Sensible and
Intelligible Worlds (1770), defended on his accession to the chair of logic
and metaphysics at the “Albertina,” the university in Königsberg where he
spent his life. But it would then take him another decade of unrelenting
work, the so-called “silent decade,” to publish his full argument for tran-
scendental idealism in the first edition of the Critique of Pure Reason, which
appeared in 1781. (On the development of the Critique during the “silent
51
decade,” see Haering 1910; Carl 1987; and Guyer 1987: Part I). Even then the
relation between the empirical realism and transcendental idealism that he
developed in that work continued to vex him: the first substantial review of
the book in 1782, by the Breslau “private scholar” Christian Garve
(1742–98) but heavily revised by the editor, the Göttingen empiricist
J. G. H. Feder (1740–1821), charged him with Berkeleianism, in other
words, with idealism as ordinarily understood to allow only mental entities
and states (the “Göttingen” review as originally published as well as Garve’s
original version are both translated in Sassen 2000), and Kant then tried to
rebut that accusation in his attempted popularization of the Critique, the
Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics of 1783, and to further defend that
rebuttal of ordinary idealism in the “Refutation of Idealism” that he added to
the second edition of the Critique of Pure Reason in 1787. (On the develop-
ment of Kant’s position between 1781 and 1787, see Guyer 1987: Part II).
But Kant was still not done with the topic of idealism, as we know from a
dozen further drafts of the “Refutation” that he composed after that second
edition of the Critique (Guyer 1987: Part IV). Indeed, Kant continued to
struggle with the clarification of his own position to the end of his life,
attempting a restatement of transcendental idealism in the uncompleted
material for a final book that has come down to us under the name of the
Opus postumum (see Förster 2000; Emundts 2004; and Guyer 2005: ch. 11).
But since it was Kant’s presentations of his position in the two editions of the
Critique and the Prolegomena that were most influential in his own time and
have been since, we shall concentrate on those texts here. It was in these texts
that Kant attempted to perfect his combination of empirical realism about
space, time, and the categories, transcendental idealism with regard to space
and time, and yet realism about the actual existence of things distinct from
our representations of them combined with agnosticism about their real
nature although together with the outright denial of their spatiality and
temporality and assertion of the fact of freedom in our own case. It was then
primarily in his writings in moral philosophy, above all the Critique of
Practical Reason of 1788, that he developed what we have called his practical
idealism about the real freedom of the noumenal self and the idea and
“postulate” of an immaterial God. The second half of Kant’s third and
final critique, namely, the Critique of Teleological Judgment in the
Critique of the Power of Judgment, uses Kant’s complex position to justify
the revival of a teleological approach to nature that would seem to have
already been outmoded in Kant’s time, but was transformed into a regulative
key (Guyer 2020b) and which had an enormous influence on the formation
52
and that space and time themselves can instead be only our a priori
representations of them and the spatial and temporal features of objects in
space and time only features of our representations of them or of the
“appearances” of objects, because
The decisive point of this argument is the following: although because of our
forms of intuition our particular representations necessarily have spatio-
temporal structure, any objects that had that structure independently of our
53
If there did not lie in you a faculty for intuiting a priori; if this subjective
condition were not at the same time the universal a priori condition under
which alone the object of . . . intuition is possible; if the object ([e.g.,] the
triangle) were something in itself without relation to your subject:
then how could you say that what necessarily lies in your subjective
conditions for constructing a triangle must also necessarily pertain to the
triangle in itself (A 48/B 65);
Pure mathematics, and especially pure geometry, can have objective reality
only under the single condition that it refers merely to objects of the senses,
with regard to which objects, however, the principle remains fixed, that our
sensory representation is by no means a representation of things in them-
selves, but only of the way in which they appear to us,
purposes of practical reason, but they outrun the limits of intuition and
therefore theoretical cognition. This general claim itself does not entail
transcendental idealism, that is, it does not identify space and time with
our own forms of intuition. However, Kant’s claim is that the paradoxes
diagnosed in the “Antinomy of Pure Reason” can only be resolved on the
basis of transcendental idealism. In the case of the first two antinomies he
argues that both sides essentially concern space and time or the things in
them (these are the arguments that as we saw were missing from Arthur
Collier’s anticipation of the first two antinomies), and that since space and
time as forms of intuition are indefinitely extendable and divisible, both sides
of the debates, the theses and the antitheses, are false: space and time and
thus the totality of things and events in them (the world) are neither
bounded and finite nor unbounded and infinite but indefinite (even though
particular things within space or periods within time may have determinate
boundaries). In the case of the third and fourth antinomies, however, Kant
argues that the distinction between appearances and things in themselves
that is at the heart of transcendental idealism makes it possible for both sides
to be considered true, since they concern different objects: in the empirical
world of experience, there are only ever indefinitely extending chains of
causes and effects, each moment of which is necessary relative to its causal
laws (the third antithesis) but contingent because no antecedent cause is
absolutely necessary or necessary considered in itself, but outside of the
empirical world there is nothing to prevent there being an absolutely
necessary thing in itself (God) nor acts of absolute spontaneity on the part
of that absolutely necessary being or even lesser beings, such as finite agents
like us. Thus, Kant argues that the antitheses of the third and fourth
antinomies are actually true of the world as it appears, while the theses of
these two antinomies are possibly true of things in themselves, namely of
God as the ground of the entire world of appearance and of ourselves as
spontaneous agents grounding our own appearances of action—and again,
Kant’s ultimate claim will be that while we have necessary and sufficient
practical grounds for rational belief although not theoretical cognition in the
existence of God (B xxx), the foundational “fact” of pure practical reason
seems to include the real fact of our own noumenal freedom (CPrR 5: 30).
Kant’s antinomies led to the dialectical methods of Fichte, Schelling, and
Hegel, and were thus to prove immensely influential. But it was clearly
controversial whether the antinomies in fact required the distinction
between appearances and things in themselves; Hegel, for example, surely
thought not. For the argument that only transcendental idealism can resolve
57
the antinomies seems to be circular: unless one assumes that our representa-
tions of space and time give us not only reliable but also complete informa-
tion about the nature of space and time and all things in them, there is no
reason to assume that the limits of our representations of space and time—
their indefiniteness and the contingency of any starting or stopping point in
them—are also in fact true of space and time and everything in them in
themselves. Kant’s indirect proof for transcendental idealism therefore is not
conclusive (see Guyer 1987: ch. 18).
Kant himself did not think so, of course. He was utterly committed to
transcendental idealism. When confronted with the challenge that transcen-
dental idealism was nothing but Berkeleianism, however, that is, the reduc-
tion of all reality to ideas and the minds that have them, he recoiled. This
objection was made in the first substantial review of the first edition of the
Critique, written from an empiricist point of view by Christian Garve and
then redacted by J. G. H. Feder in 1782 (Feder and Garve 1782; Garve 1783
in Sassen 2000: 53–8, 59–77). Kant defended himself by a more precise
formulation of his doctrine in the Prolegomena (1783) and further by the
insertion of a “Refutation of Idealism,” specifically “material idealism,” into
the Transcendental Analytic in the second edition of the Critique (1787).
Kant’s claim in the Prolegomena is that his position should be called
“formal” or “critical” idealism rather than “material” idealism because it
merely identifies space and time with our forms of intuition but does not
otherwise deny the reality of the objects in space and time. As he puts it:
There are things given to us as objects of our senses existing outside us, yet
we know nothing of them as they may be in themselves, but are acquainted
only with their appearances, i.e., with the representations that they produce
in us because they affect our senses. Accordingly, I by all means avow that
there are bodies outside us, i.e., things which, though completely unknown
to us as to what they may be in themselves, we know through the repre-
sentations which their influence on our sensibility provides for us, and to
which we give the name of a body—which word therefore merely signifies
the appearance of this object that is unknown to us but is nonetheless real.
Can this be called idealism? It is the very opposite of it.
(Prolegomena §13, Note II, 4: 288–9)
and time from things to our representations of them, just as earlier philo-
sophers had given (different) reasons for relocating properties like color
from object to subject, but has provided no arguments against the existence
of those things themselves, which he, like any other sane person, takes for
granted.
By the time of the second edition of the Critique, however, Kant must
have come to see the need for a positive defense of the assumption of
the existence of things in themselves that ground our spatio-temporal
representations of body (although, since those things in themselves are
not supposed to be spatio-temporal and causality is supposed to be a
spatio-temporal relation, they cannot precisely be said to cause our spatio-
temporal representations). Kant’s argument—which in the following years
he would attempt to improve a dozen times (see Guyer 1983; Guyer 1987:
Part IV; and Kant 2005: Reflexionen 5653–4 and 6311–19, 6323)—is that we
can only achieve “empirically determined consciousness” of our own exist-
ence, or a determinate temporal ordering of our own representations,
by correlating them with something enduring outside of and distinct
from them:
the will as Kant understands it, the radical freedom to choose between any
action and its contrary no matter what one’s past history might seem to
determine, in the non-spatio-temporal domain of things as they actually are,
in themselves, there is at least room for genuine spontaneity, that is the
origination of a series of events from a first cause that is not itself caused and
thus determined by anything else. In the first instance, Kant argues that this
allows for the possible existence of God as an uncaused ground outside of
the entire series of events that comprise the world of experience, but he also
notes that the distinction between uncaused ground at the noumenal
level and always causally determined events at the phenomenal allows for
the possibility of multiple instances of noumenal spontaneity, thus for the
possibility of completely free choices by ourselves regarded as things in
ourselves rather than as mere appearances. As he puts it, once “the faculty
of beginning a series in time entirely on its own [has been] proved
(though no insight into it is achieved), now we are permitted also to allow
that in the course of the world different series may begin on their own
as far as their causality is concerned, and to ascribe to the substances
in those series”—namely, ourselves—“the faculty of acting from freedom”
(A 450/B 478).
Establishing the possibility of freedom of the human will is as far as the
Critique of Pure Reason is usually thought to have gone, and indeed seems to
be what Kant thought that it had established when he came to write his
moral philosophy: only there, he suggests in the second Critique, can the
reality of freedom as a property of the human but noumenal will be
established. But actually even in the first Critique Kant had at least suggested
a stronger result. In his extended commentary on the resolution of the third
Antinomy, Kant introduces a distinction between “empirical” and “intelli-
gible” character. The former is how we appear to ourselves in space and
time, and as far as this is concerned, “its actions, as appearances, would
stand through and through in connection with other appearances in accord-
ance with constant natural laws, from which, as their conditions, they could
be derived.” No room for freedom of the will here. But transcendental
idealism allows for the possibility of intelligible character at the noumenal
level, “through which it”—that is, the human will—“is indeed the cause of
those actions as appearances, but which does not stand under any conditions
of sensibility and is not itself appearance” (A 539/B 567). Plenty of room for
freedom here, although it would not seem that the distinction between
phenomenal and noumenal, transposed into the domain of character, the
subject of moral responsibility, as the distinction between empirical and
62
intelligible, does anything more than leave room for the possibility of
freedom. However, a few pages later Kant writes:
Yet the human being, who is otherwise acquainted with the whole of nature
solely through sense, knows himself also through pure apperception, and
indeed in actions and inner determinations which cannot be counted at all
among impressions of sense; he obviously is in one part phenomenon, but
in another part, namely in regard to certain faculties, he is a merely
intelligible object, because the actions of this object cannot at all be
ascribed to the receptivity of sensibility. We call these faculties understand-
ing and reason . . . Now that this reason has causality, or that we can at least
represent something of the sort in it, is clear from the imperatives that we
propose as rules to our powers of execution in everything practical.
(A 546–7/B 574–5)
Here Kant seems to be going beyond the position that the distinction
between appearances and things in themselves makes freedom of the will
possible; he seems to be saying that in addition to our knowledge of ourselves
as sensibly affected and passive, we have, through “pure apperception,”
knowledge of ourselves as genuinely active, or spontaneous, and able to
act in accordance with imperatives, including those of morality, no matter
what the history of our empirical character might seem to predict or entail.
This is very much the position that Kant will adopt in the Groundwork and
Critique of Practical Reason, and which might be called transcendental
idealism proper, attributing to ourselves as we really are a property compat-
ible with our nature as mental even if not with our spatio-temporal, causally
determined appearance. Or we might call this position the transcendental
realism of idealism: it asserts that we really are mind-like free wills, not really
causally determined bodies at all.
Yet in the first Critique Kant again seems to shy away from this assertion,
going so far as to say that “we have not even tried to prove the possibility of
freedom, . . . because from mere concepts a priori we cannot cognize any-
thing about the possibility of any real ground or any causality. Freedom is
treated here only as a transcendental idea . . . that nature at least does not
conflict with causality through freedom—that was the one single thing we
could accomplish . . .” (A 558/B 586).
But whether or not Kant thought that he could show that we have genuine
knowledge through pure apperception of the real freedom of our will in the
Critique of Pure Reason, that is exactly the claim that he makes in the
63
free will remains the same, he reverses the order of argument for it (see
Ameriks 1982/2000: ch. 6): instead of arguing from our knowledge of our
real self-activity as intelligence to the binding validity of the moral law for us,
as he does in the Groundwork, Kant argues that we have immediate aware-
ness of the binding force of the moral law, as the fundamental “fact of
reason,” but that this brings along with it knowledge of our possession of a
“pure will”: the moral law directs us to set aside all “empirical conditions”—
that is, desires—for our actions, and our pure will makes it possible for us to
actually do so (CPrR 5: 30–1). Kant illustrates this with an example, a person
who knows that because he ought to refuse to bear false witness he can do so
(even if he does not know whether he will). This illustration relies on the
principle that “ought implies can,” but this principle becomes an essential
part of Kant’s argument only in the further book Religion within the
Boundaries of Mere Reason because there Kant has separated the pure will
into two parts, the pure Wille which gives the moral law and is thus identical
to pure practical reason, and the faculty of choice, or Willkür, by which the
agent decides whether or not to act in accordance with the moral law. These
two separate parts need to be linked by the principle that “ought implies
can,” while in the Critique of Pure Practical Reason the ability to give
ourselves a pure moral law and the ability to choose to act in accordance
with it were two sides of the one coin immediately given as the “fact of
reason.” But either way, the basic position remains the same as in the
Groundwork: while our empirical character is spatio-temporal and fully
subject to causal laws and thus to determinism, our real, intelligible charac-
ter is that of spontaneous rationality. This must be considered a full-
throated version of idealism.
When it comes to immortality and God, however, Kant’s position in the
second Critique is qualified as “rational belief ” or “postulate” rather than
straightforward “fact of reason.” Kant’s position also seems to be conflicted.
For he argues that we need to postulate personal immortality in order to
allow sufficient progress toward the full realization of virtue, which we
certainly do not observe in ordinary human nature as empirically known
(5: 122), but he also argues that we need to postulate God as the author or
“supreme cause” of a nature the laws of which are compatible with the moral
law, and thus allow for the realization of happiness as a consequence of
virtue in nature (5: 125–6). These two postulates seem contradictory because
they suppose that human virtue can be perfected only in a non-natural
eternal existence but that the happiness that should ensue from the perfec-
tion of virtue must be able to be realized within nature, thus apparently
66
those involve the faculty of reason, or in the case of fine art, ideas of reason
as well), and imagination and understanding, as the conditions of the
possibility of knowledge in general, can be assumed to work the same way
in all human beings (§§21, 38). But then he sets up an “antinomy of taste”
which, like all of Kant’s antinomies, is supposed to be resolved only by
transcendental idealism, namely, by the supposition that there is a “super-
sensible substratum” that grounds both harmony among human cognitive
natures and between the human cognitive capacities and nature itself. This is
clearly a step toward a substantive idealism. Along the way, Kant argues that
although our pleasure in beauty must in the first instance be disinterested,
we take an interest in the fact of the existence of such pleasure, based in the
fact that natural beauty gives us a clue that nature is receptive to our
concerns, including foremost our moral concerns (§42)—of course we
have an interest, the interest of reason, in the possibility of the realization
of our moral goals, and therefore in the existence of any sort of evidence for
this realizability. Kant interprets our experience of natural beauty as some
sort of evidence of the harmony between nature and morality that is the
condition of the possibility of the highest good, grounded in the second
Critique in the postulate of or rational belief in the existence of God.
This line of thought becomes more explicit in the second half of the third
Critique, the “Critique of the Teleological Power of Judgment.” (See
McLaughlin 1990; Guyer 2005b: Parts I and III; and Zuckert 2007.) Here
Kant argues that we humans are capable of understanding organic processes
such as growth, self-maintenance, and reproduction only by thinking of
organisms “as if” they had been designed by an intelligent designer, an
obvious step toward idealism. Although his approach is no doubt undercut
by the synthesis of Darwinian natural selection and Mendelian genetics
characteristic of twentieth-century biology, which has the general form of
a physical or mechanical explanation of such apparent purposiveness in
biology, Kant thought that the “antinomy” between the mechanical expla-
nation that we seek in all science and the teleological explanation, explana-
tion by antecedent design, that we are forced to in thinking about organisms,
and that we then generalize to nature as a whole, could be resolved only by
thinking of nature as a whole “as if ” it were the product of an intelligent
designer outside of nature, achieving its purposes—for it must have such—
through the laws of nature (§§73, 77). Kant maintains that this is not
“dogmatic,” thus not constitutive theoretical metaphysics; thus he does
not go so far toward real idealism here as he does in the case of our own
freedom. Nevertheless he links this line of argument to the fact of our
68
own freedom by arguing that the “final end” of nature can only be some-
thing “unconditioned” and therefore outside of nature, and that this can be
nothing other than human freedom, fully developed in morality but also
requiring the realizability of the highest good in nature (§84; see especially
Guyer 2005b: ch. 12). Thus Kant’s entire philosophy culminates in a com-
plex form of idealism: transcendental ideality with regard to space and time,
which includes the assertion of the non-spatiality and -temporality of things
in themselves, including ourselves as we are in our selves, outright assertion
of the freedom of our own intelligible character, and therefore its essentially
mental rather than physical character, and the postulate or possibility of
rational belief in if not theoretical knowledge of an intelligent, therefore
mind-like, ground of nature itself.
It is in this context, further, that Kant discusses the idea of an intuitive
understanding, a concept that would become of utmost importance for the
post-Kantian German idealists, especially the early Fichte and Schelling, in
their attempts to give a new foundation to what they took to be the ultimate
aim of Kant’s philosophy. In §77 of the third Critique, Kant, somewhat
regretfully, dismisses the idea that human beings can rely in our explana-
tions of natural phenomena on an intuitive understanding because of the
ineliminable discursivity of our understanding, by which he means that we
always have to apply general concepts to particular intuitions, although
general concepts can never capture all of the richness of particular objects
(an idea that Kant gets from Leibniz and Baumgarten). According to Kant, it
is also because of this discursivity that we human beings are not allowed to
think of ends as real causes. Instead, we have to treat all explanations that
involve the concept of an end, that is, all teleological explanations and
especially those that concern organisms understood as natural ends
(Naturzwecke), as only subjectively valid and provisional. They are condi-
tioned by our inability “to represent the possibility of parts (with respect to
their constitution and their relation) as being dependent on the whole,” an
inability that is rooted in the discursive character of human thought. The
early German idealists not only did not share this Kantian humility about
the limitations of our human understanding; they vehemently resisted it in a
number of different ways, all designed to overcome Kant’s assessment.
Kant himself ended up with a complex position, combining the undeniable
insight that the most fundamental forms of knowledge ultimately depend on
fundamental operations of self-consciousness with more contentious claims,
such as that the possibility of morality requires a kind of freedom incompat-
ible with the most basic assumption of natural science, that causal explanation
69
Kant’s view about how we must conceive of both the natural and the moral
world in all its different aspects had an enormous impact both within and
beyond the academic scene in late eighteenth-century Germany. His
uncompromising fight for reason and rationality as the sole arbiter of
right and wrong in all spheres of life provoked massive reactions in many
intellectual communities, especially those involved in theological, political,
and social debates. All these debates took place within the overall struggle
in the third part of the eighteenth-century between supporters of the
Enlightenment on the one hand and their anti-Enlightenment opponents
on the other. The main representatives of the later German Enlightenment
movement at that time were Moses Mendelssohn, the philosopher and
biblical scholar, as well as businessman Gotthold Ephraim Lessing
(1729–81), the dramatist, art critic, and philosopher as well, and of course
Kant himself. They were vigorously opposed by notables including Friedrich
Heinrich Jacobi, a novelist, what we now call a public intellectual, and also a
philosopher (both his philosophical works and his novel Allwill are trans-
lated in Jacobi 1994); Thomas Wizenmann (1759–87), a young Protestant
theologian whom Kant mentions in a footnote of his second Critique,
although to straighten him out on the difference between a postulate of
pure practical reason and mere wish-fulfillment (CPrR 5: 143n.); Johann
Gottfried Herder (1744–1803), a former student of Kant’s who became one
of the leading Protestant theologians and cultural philosophers of his time,
considered now one of the founders of historicism and cultural relativism
(although those terms were not available at the time); and Johann Georg
Hamann (1730–88), another wayward friend of Kant who opposed his own
mystical Christianity to Kant’s religion of pure reason. (On the idea of an
anti-Enlightenment, or as he called it the “Counter-Enlightenment,” see
famously Berlin 2013a and 2013b; Guyer 2020a explores relations between
Kant and Mendelssohn as two figures within the German Enlightenment,
while Beiser 1987 and Guyer forthcoming discuss many of Kant’s most
immediate critics.) Whereas Kant and the other dominant figures of the
Enlightenment fought against superstition in religion and for human rights
Idealism in Modern Philosophy. Paul Guyer and Rolf-Peter Horstmann, Oxford University Press.
© Paul Guyer and Rolf-Peter Horstmann 2023. DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780192848574.003.0005
71
Kant’s intentions in the three Critiques is by no means obvious and has been
controversial ever since. (The literature on German idealism and its relation
to Kant is far too great to list here; for a start, see Beiser 2002; Pinkard 2002;
Henrich 2003; Horstmann 2004; di Giovanni 2005; and Förster 2011 [2013].
For an exhaustive survey of the “systems of pure reason and their critique,
1785–1845,” see Jaeschke and Arndt 2012. For a multi-author collection, see
Ameriks ed. 2000b.)
Although all of the German idealists proclaimed their commitment to
what they called the “spirit” of Kant’s philosophy throughout their careers,
they were at the same time his harshest critics. They complained not about
what they took to be the intentions lying behind Kant’s so-called “critical”
project but about the execution of this task in the form of the three Critiques.
These complaints addressed many different aspects of Kant’s philosophy,
among them most prominently (1) what they called the insurmountable
“dualisms” (see Guyer 2000) that are supposed to play an essential role in
both Kant’s theoretical and practical philosophy and in his resolution of the
supposed antinomy of teleological judgment as well. They also complained
about (2) the subjectivism characteristic of his teachings in all of their parts,
that is his view that the world of experience as the object of science but also
of aesthetic and teleological judgment is very much our own construction,
and they were very critical of (3) what for them was the most implausible
consequence of Kant’s transcendental idealism, namely that no knowledge
of things in themselves is possible (although, as we saw, Kant never doubted
the existence of things in themselves, and also seemed to breach the insu-
perable barrier to our knowledge of their nature at least in the case of
freedom of the will). As to (1) they objected (a) that in his theoretical
philosophy Kant insisted on the irreducible opposition between the faculties
of sensibility and understanding and hence between intuitions and concepts
in the fabric of knowledge, (b) that in his practical philosophy he advocated
the acceptance of two totally disjointed worlds, a sensible and an intelligible
world (mundus sensibilis atque intelligibilis), in both of which a rational
person has to be situated, and (c) that in order to account for the organic
world of living beings one has to accept two different modes of explanation,
the mechanical and the teleological, of which only the former has objective
validity while the latter is merely subjectively valid (a distinction that Kant
made within the empirical standpoint, since from the point of view of
transcendental idealism all of our representations of the world are informed
by our own cognitive structure, the forms of intuition on the one hand and
of conceptualization and judgment on the other). The charge (2) of
74
in the First and Second Introduction into the Doctrine of Science. (For
commentaries on Fichte’s argument, see Henrich 2019; Neuhouser 1990;
Horstmann 2004; Zöller 1998; and Breazeale 2013.)
Following the early Doctrine of Science, we must, according to Fichte,
accept three fundamental principles (Grundsätze) of human knowledge
without which we could not even make sense of the idea that we can
know that there is something real at all. The first states that self-
consciousness or the I is a spontaneous, unconditioned act that creates or
“posits” the I as having existence or being (ein Akt, der im Vollzug sein
eigenes Sein schafft). The I understood as this self-positing act that gives
rise to its own being and reality Fichte characterizes as “deed-act”
(Tathandlung), also translated as “Act,” and it is through this deed-act
that what we take to be real or having being comes to the fore. Fichte arrives
at his first principle of human knowledge on the basis of two assumptions.
The first is the (actually quite traditional) assumption that we can be
properly said to know only assertions (judgments or propositions) that
exhibit the character of certainty (Gewissheit), or express what is actually
and certainly the case; the second assumption (which borrows a Kantian
term) maintains that a regress in the process of justification of such asser-
tions can be avoided only if we can furnish some principle or fundamental
proposition that is “utterly unconditioned” (schlechthin unbedingt) (as
Fichte puts it), one, that is, which cannot be derived from any other
principle, and which, for its part, is such that it alone guarantees the utter
certainty, and thus the indubitability, that is, the immunity to skeptical
objections, of any given proposition. This second assumption leads him to
the claim that the unquestionable certainty of a proposition can never be
demonstrated discursively (by appeal to purely conceptual considerations)
or intuitively (by appeal to any sensuous perception); on the contrary, the
ground of unconditional certainty can only be found in the constitution of
self-consciousness itself. Fichte identifies as an appropriate method for
deriving the principle in question a procedure that he calls “abstractive
reflection.” This kind of reflection, according to Fichte, takes its point of
departure from a proposition that everyone regards as unquestionably
certain, a so-called “fact of empirical consciousness.” From this fact, this
indubitable proposition, the process of reflection isolates or abstracts the
elements that belong to the content of such a proposition, that is, belong to
that about which the proposition asserts something. What is supposedly left,
after this abstraction, is simply the form of the proposition, which consists
precisely in affirming the ascription, or non-ascription, of a predicate to a
79
subject. The proposition that Fichte selects as the point of departure for his
“abstractive reflection” is the logical law of identity in the form “A = A,” a
law that is rightly regarded as utterly certain, that is, certain without recourse
to any further grounds, and thus as intrinsically certain. This fact alone
already shows that we have the capacity (the faculty) to claim something as
certain without reference to any further grounds, or, in Fichte’s own termi-
nology, of “positing” something absolutely (etwas schlechthin zu setzen).
Reflection on this fact shows, according to Fichte, that the utter certainty of
the law of identity is grounded in a self-positing activity or an I-activity,
which in this case posits identity between A and A, an activity that consists
precisely in the act of positing being, in this case of identity. However, as the
result of an I-activity identity could not have being, could not be a real
relation that indeed binds together A and A, that is, binds together A with
itself, if the I-activity itself were not itself real. Because there is no other
positing activity available than the I-activity, in order to be real this activity
has to posit itself as real. Thus, in order to account for the utter certainty of
the law of identity the I-activity, best expressed in the formula “I am,” has to
be seen as positing its own being.
This result, however, is not yet sufficient to give us the first unconditioned
and fundamental principle of all knowledge in the form of the I-activity
“I am.” This is because we have arrived at the “I am” as the guarantor of the
absolute certainty of a proposition only on the basis of an empirical fact,
namely the proposition “A is A” that has been presupposed as utterly
certain. Fichte now rightly observes that the “I am,” as the condition of
the certainty of an empirical fact, itself merely possesses the status of an
empirical fact (Tatsache)—if the utterly certain proposition were not given,
one would never be able to affirm the utter certainty of the “I am.” Up to this
point the “I am” has “only been grounded on a fact, and possesses no other
validity than that attaching to a fact” (GA I, 2: 257). But in order to discover
the first utterly unconditioned principle of all knowledge, we must establish
not only the utter certainty of the law of identity, but also the unconditional
certainty of the “I am” in a way that does not depend upon the presence of a
fact at all. In other words: we must be able to answer the question, how the
utterly unconditioned certainty of the proposition “I am” is possible. Fichte’s
reflections on this question lead to his conception of the “I am” as a deed-act
(Tathandlung). He reasons along the following lines: We know from our
analysis of the conditions of certainty of the law of identity that the “I am”
has the capacity to posit something absolutely in the I, that is, in performing
the I-activity. But in order to be able to posit something absolutely in the I,
80
the “I am” itself must be posited. We have also already seen that the absolute
positing of the I consists in the activity of positing being. If this is so, and if
the “I am” is to depend on nothing else as its condition, we must think of the
I as the product of its own positing activity, since it would otherwise be quite
impossible to explain its being. Now this, in turn, is supposed to imply that
we must think the I as an activity that posits its own existence insofar as it is
active: the I
is at the same time the actor and the product of the act; the actor, and that
which the activity brings forth; act and deed are one and the same; and the
“I am” is therefore the expression of an Act. (GA I, 2: 259)
For Fichte, a deed-act is not supposed to be a fact, that is, something that is
simply already discovered as given, since the deed-act is logically and
ontologically prior to any facts insofar as it ultimately constitutes (posits)
everything that can be a fact for an I. The I, understood as deed-act, is
supposed to be something absolutely posited precisely because it posits itself,
and this self-positing constitutes its essence and guarantees its being, its
reality. Again, as Fichte says: “That whose being (essence) merely consists in
positing itself as being, is the I, as absolute subject” (GA I, 2: 259). This
means, for Fichte, that the I, so understood, displays all the characteristics
that make it an appropriate candidate for the first utterly unconditioned
principle of all knowledge. Fichte tries out various formulations for expres-
sing this first principle in a really adequate fashion. His most adequate
formulation might be the one that he furnishes at the end of section 10 of
the first paragraph of the Doctrine of Science: “The I originally posits its own
being absolutely” (GA I, 2: 261). This insight that the I must be conceived as
self-positing activity, an activity whose performance consists in its self-
actualization, is meant to make any distinction between epistemological
and metaphysical grounds for idealism obsolete, thus to transcend all
traditional grounds for and forms of idealism.
The second principle postulates a necessary act of counter-positing
(Entgegensetzen) to the self-positing activity of the I, resulting in what
Fichte calls a Non-I, and the third focuses on an activity that gives rise to
the concept of divisibility. Fichte attempts to justify the introduction of these
two principles on systematic grounds, although these principles can only be
described as unconditional in a qualified respect, by exploiting his own
distinction between the form and the content of a proposition. According
to Fichte, every proposition or judgment can be treated as either conditioned
81
are essentially mental in nature and because in the end these activities,
according to Fichte, are, metaphysically speaking, all there is: “for the
philosopher there is acting, and nothing but acting; because, as a philoso-
pher, he thinks idealistically” (Second Introduction, section 7; Werke 1: 498).
Idealism thus starts to become what could be called from a traditional point
of view a “hybrid” position that intimately connects epistemological and
ontological elements in explaining “the determinations of consciousness,”
that is, our common sense conception of reality as an object of cognition and
agency, “out of the acting of the intellect [Intelligenz]” yet without thinking
of the intellect as some sort of existing subject:
For idealism the intellect is an acting and absolutely nothing else; one
should not even call it something active because by this expression one
points to something substantial which is the subject of this activity.
(First Introduction, section 7, Werke 1: 440)
Nature” (IP 42; SW 1: 151) thereby making room for an idealistic conception
of reality as World-Soul (On the World-Soul is also the title of a 1798
publication by Schelling).
As a systematic counterpart to the construction of the phenomena of
nature out of different dynamic factors (forces, activities), in 1800 Schelling
presented his System of Transcendental Idealism. Here he set out to demon-
strate the development of mental phenomena out of these factors which he
here calls the unconscious and the conscious activity starting with sensation
(Empfindung) and intuition (Anschauung) until he arrives via acts of
willing at the aesthetic activity manifested in works of art. He thinks of
these transcendental idealistic demonstrations as a necessary complement to
his philosophy of nature (cf. SW 3: 331f.) and describes their mutual
relation thus:
In the end, then, after 1800 Schelling (arguably as well as Fichte in his post-
Jena period) seems pushed toward a “non-dogmatic” idealism that combines
ontological as well as epistemological idealism within a monistic framework.
(The preceding sketch of Fichte and Schelling is based on Horstmann 2008a
and 2017. For surveys of the development of Schelling’s philosophy, see
Bowie 1993 and Snow 1996, and the multi-author collections Norman and
Welchman eds. 2004 and Ostaric ed. 2014.)
Although Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel too embraces a dynamical
conception of idealism in the spirit of Fichte and Schelling, he departs
from both of them by not relying on the self-positing activity of an I (the
“of ” understood as indicating both a genetivus subjectivus and objectivus,
i.e., the I as that which does the positing and as that which is posited) or on
some primordial subjectless cognitive act that brings about subject and
object as the most basic features of reality. He thus tries to transcend any
traditional form of idealism that identifies the fundamental level of reality
exclusively with the subject or mind. Given his deep distrust of irreconcilable
87
on Hegel’s metaphysics and logic, see Henrich 1971; Pippin 1989 and Pippin
2019; Bristow 2007; Longuenesse 2007; and Emundts 2012. For a volume
that explores Hegel’s relations to British idealism and American pragma-
tism, see Stern 2009. On Hegel’s rejection of dualism, see Guyer 2017.)
However, a closer look at how Hegel tries to realize a monistic idealism
reveals that it proved difficult to establish a philosophical system based on
the identity of thinking and being or subject and object. At the outset this
project was to be realized within the boundaries of two conditions. The first
was to present an argument in favor of the superiority of idealism that would
not just make the endorsement of idealism a question of individual character
or what a person wants to be, a move that Hegel thought to be characteristic
of both Fichte’s and Schelling’s defenses of idealism. The second was to
abandon the view that was, according to Hegel, also sometimes to be found
in Fichte and Schelling, that one has to think of idealism as an alternative
and in opposition to materialism, which they also called “dogmatism” or
“realism.” Not to meet these two conditions were in Hegel’s eyes unaccept-
able shortcomings of any attempt to establish a convincing idealistic world-
view. He expressed his dissatisfaction with attempts of this kind to establish
idealism as the superior approach in philosophy quite early (Faith and
Knowledge, 1802) by referring to them under the title “philosophy of
reflection of subjectivity” (Reflexionsphilosophie der Subjektivität). This
kind of philosophy of reflection, although favoring subjectivity and hence
giving priority to the conceptual and in this sense ideal contributions of
the mind to what is called reality is, according to Hegel, still stuck in what
he later came to call the “opposition of consciousness” (Gegensatz des
Bewusstseins) (in both Phenomenology [1807] and the Science of Logic
[1812, 1813, and 1816]). This kind of philosophy is committed to a mode
of thinking that takes place within a framework in which the opposition of
thinking and being or subject and object is still basic, dissolved only super-
ficially by either abstracting from one of the opposed sides or by establishing
a relation of domination between the opposed elements, without transcend-
ing and transforming them into a whole, his renowned “Subject-Object,” a
whole that is both constituted by these elements, the subject and the object,
and that at the same time constitutes them as its own internal differentia-
tions. This way of overcoming oppositions by thinking of the elements
opposed as having significance only insofar as their mutual relation can be
conceived of as being constituted by the unity they together form led Hegel
to claim that in order to avoid the idea of self-standing or irreducible
oppositions and hence to escape the charge of one-sidedness in cases
90
united. But even such an admission would not lead directly to an argument
for the superiority of idealism. It would only provide a reason for favoring a
position that could be described as real-idealism (Real-Idealismus), a syn-
thetic product that integrates idealism and its opposites into a unity whose
elements, though still distinguishable, are at the same time in some sense
identical or, in Hegel’s idiom, sublated (aufgehoben). It is easy to show that
most of the German idealists were strongly attracted by this positive solu-
tion. At some point in their philosophical careers both Fichte and Schelling
explicitly used the term “real-idealism” in order to characterize their views.
Even Hegel late in life, in a review of a treatise by Ohlert (GW 16: 287ff.),
made use of this term as a name for his metaphysical teachings.
The positive solution just outlined seems to have been in line with Hegel’s
way of conceiving of how to overcome oppositions in his early Jena writings,
such as the “Difference” text. Unsurprisingly, however, he became dissatis-
fied with such a tactic because of its inherent limitations. This dissatisfaction
shows up explicitly for the first time in the Preface to the Phenomenology of
Spirit (1807), Hegel’s first and perhaps still most widely read extended
philosophical book. From then on he tried in different ways to find a
justification of idealism in sensu stricto, that is, a justification of a view
that (1) attributes priority to non-sensible activities, especially to the activity
of thinking, that (2) makes the traditional alternatives of materialism,
realism, and/or dogmatism obsolete, and that (3) allows for subject–object
identity without thereby being committed to real-idealism. The reasons for
his dissatisfaction with attempts that lead to real-idealism, among them
most of his own pre-phenomenological systematic sketches, are quite sim-
ple. (Here “phenomenological” connotes Hegel’s 1807 view that the differ-
ent, inadequate conceptions of reality appear in successive form in human
history until an adequate conception is finally reached, not Edmund
Husserl’s early twentieth-century conception of a “bracketed” Wesenschau
or “inspection of essences” that reveals the timeless structure of objective
experience and thought.) In the first place, it is obvious that the attempt to
transcend oppositions by making the opposed elements parts of an integrat-
ing unity looks like a makeshift, a terminological stipulation that cannot do
justice to what it is meant to achieve, namely, to allow the opposed elements
to develop out of a unity that is prior to them. Instead of commencing with a
developing unity, this move, according to Hegel, remains damaged by
presupposing the opposed components as self-standing, thereby making
the unity dependent on the elements rather than the other way around.
Secondly, the unity presented as resulting from a process of integration of
92
features that are shared by the subject’s claim and the object on the basis of
which a knowledge relation can be established. Hegel maintains that the
relevant structural feature in the case of knowledge is conceptual presence of
both subject (claim) and object which implies that not only the claim but
also its object must be treated as conceptual items. This is the assumption of
isomorphism that underlies any epistemologically motivated move toward
idealism; the fundamental difference between Hegel’s strategy and Kant’s is
that for Kant this approach requires the reduction of objects of genuine
knowledge to appearances, or our own way of representing objects, while
Hegel is trying to avoid this reduction by conceiving of real objects that are
structured in the same way as our thoughts are without being reduced
to them.
Hegel’s concept of knowledge as a correspondence relation between
subject and object has to be distinguished from the process by which
knowledge is established. The exemplary scenario that Hegel has in mind
when talking about the acquisition of knowledge in the Phenomenology
might be described as follows: knowledge obtains if a (conscious) subject
affirms a claim about the characteristics (whether essential or not) of an
object, state of affairs, or event (henceforth just “object,” thus this should not
be understood just to mean that which endures through some state of affairs
or event) that corresponds to what the subject takes to be true of the object,
state of affairs, or event that is addressed. For example, if a subject claims
that such and such is the case then this claim amounts to knowledge if it
turns out that such and such really is the case. (Thus far, Hegel’s analysis
does not seem much different than Alfred Tarski’s famous correspondence
analysis of truth, “ ‘p’ is true only if p”; Tarski 1936 and 1944.) Knowledge is
thus understood as the positive result of a comparison between what a
subject takes to be true and what is true of the object. It is easy to decide
what a subject takes to be true. This is expressed by the claim. What is not
that easy to decide is whether this claim is true, that is, whether the object is
indeed adequately characterized by the claim. (This is why Tarski’s defini-
tion of truth is not an epistemology of truth.) It is here that according to
Hegel experience comes into play. In order to come to a decision as to the
adequacy of its claim to the object, a subject has to rely on experience. (Thus
far, of course, any empiricist, and Kant as well, would say the same.) If a
subject experiences that its way of conceiving and referring to what it takes
to be the case is deficient and is somehow refuted, undermined, or made
obsolete by the way the object presents itself in experience, it has to give up
the knowledge-claim and to replace it by a different claim. Experience
96
between totally independent items makes no sense. Instead, that the very
attempt to establish such an (unreasonable) conception already presupposes
that there indeed is a structural affinity between subject and object, an
affinity that enables an object to be an object for a subject and that enables
the subject to relate to the object. Hegel wants us to think of this mutual
affinity in terms of conceptual determinations necessary to come up with
both the concept of an object of knowledge and a tenable account of a
knowing subject. Thus in the case of, for example, “sense certainty” the
affinity claim is expressed in the result that in order to be an epistemic object
an object of cognition has to exhibit the conceptual characteristics of uni-
versality (Allgemeinheit) and singularity (Einzelnheit) provided by the sub-
ject and that the subject itself, in order to be thought of as an epistemic
subject, must have at its disposal the conceptual resources (in this case the
concepts of universality and singularity) necessary to determine the con-
ceptual features of its object. The entire process run through in the
Phenomenology is meant to enrich the features a subject and an object
have to share in order to arrive at a complete concept of what both a subject
and an object are. This is Hegel’s version of the age-old assumption that
knowledge and the known must be isomorphic.
Thus, in the Phenomenology the initial scenario of “sense certainty” that is
based on the absolute opposition between the knowing subject and the
object known sets the stage for a long series of configurations or models of
knowledge that is aimed at demonstrating that knowledge in a complete or
absolute sense can only take place in a setting where subject and object share
all their respective structural features, that is, where both, the subject and the
object, have the same conceptual determinations and thus are identical. This
amounts according to Hegel to the insight that if knowledge is analyzed in
terms of a subject–object relation then in the end there is for knowledge
(Erkennen) no difference between the subject and the object or, as he is fond
of saying, that there is a difference that is no difference (ein Unterschied, der
keiner ist). Among other things this means for Hegel that knowledge in the
strict sense is ultimately self-knowledge or a state of affairs where a subject
that stands in the relation of knowing (erkennen) to an object is “in truth”
related to itself. As he famously puts it, in the act of knowing (Erkenntnisakt)
the subject “is in the other (the object) with itself (exclusively related to
itself)” (im Anderen bei sich selbst sein).
However, the demonstration that the difference between subject and
object of knowledge is based on their original identity does not seem to
lead directly to the justification of a metaphysical claim about the real nature
100
which is tackled in a separate part of the Science of Logic. The first part he
calls “objective logic” containing a “logic of being” and a “logic of essence,”
the second is called “subjective logic” and contains a “logic of the Concept.”
The metaphysical process starts from the most basic objective manifesta-
tions of thinking that give rise to qualitative, quantitative, and relational
determinations in a variety of forms. They are followed by subjective
manifestations that show up in the shape of the logical and methodological
rules that govern inferences and scientific explanations until a stage is
reached in which thinking arrives at self-transparency, understanding itself
as the originator of both all the objective and subjective determinations so
far. This understanding confirms to thinking that it indeed is all of reality,
that is, all that there is, or that thinking and being are the same. According to
Hegel, it also confirms to thinking that the subject–object divide has no
metaphysical reality but is just a way in which thinking internally divides
itself in order to account for the possibility of knowledge which thus turns
out to be self-knowledge. It is precisely here that Hegel collapses Kant’s
distinction between general and transcendental logic. As is only to be
expected, Hegel’s logico-metaphysical identification has been and still is
debated by both sympathizers with and opponents of his philosophical
project, especially in the English-speaking world. This ambivalent attitude
toward his metaphysical teachings might have been a reason why people
attracted to Hegel’s work have often been more interested in the epistemo-
logical side of his enterprise, thus in the Phenomenology of Spirit, than in its
logico-metaphysical side. In recent years, however, a re-evaluation of his
metaphysics seems to have taken place, as is documented in an increasing
number of texts on logico-metaphysical topics (e.g., Stern 2009; Kreines
2015; Pippin 2019).
Putting the point without Hegel’s terminology but relying heavily on his
own preliminary remarks on the question “With What must the Beginning
of Science be made?” in the Science of Logic, the relation between his
metaphysical and his epistemological line of thought can be sketched
roughly thus: The Phenomenology has given an epistemological argument
that knowledge understood as the conceptual activity of a subject that relates
to an object can only be realized if it can be seen as having established a
relation of correspondence between real items. It also has demonstrated that
in order for these items to stand in such a relation they have to be structur-
ally identical. Thus, realized or “real” knowledge (wahres Wissen), that is,
knowledge where the items related to each other do correspond and are
indeed identical, has to be taken as a relation between conceptual items.
105
Idealism in Modern Philosophy. Paul Guyer and Rolf-Peter Horstmann, Oxford University Press.
© Paul Guyer and Rolf-Peter Horstmann 2023. DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780192848574.003.0006
111
This simple and perhaps inescapable thought may be regarded as the most
fundamental epistemological motivation for any form of idealism. On the
basis of this proposition, Schopenhauer then tries to distinguish his position
from what he takes to be the skepticism of Hume, that there is a real
question about whether there is either a subject or an object in addition to
representations, and from the dogmatism of Fichte, that both of these can be
proved; his own view as initially stated is rather that
the object as such always presupposes the subject as its necessary correlate:
so the subject always remains outside the jurisdiction of the principle of
sufficient reason. (WWR §5, p. 35)
space and time can not only be conceived abstractly, on their own and
independently of their content, but they can also be intuited immediately,
and that
properties of time and space, as they are known a priori in intuition, apply
to all experience as laws that it must always come out in accordance with.
(WWR §3, p. 27)
By this remark, Schopenhauer indicates his recognition that Kant derives his
epistemological idealism from his understanding of the implications of our a
priori cognition of space and time, but he does not attempt to explain Kant’s
inference or to add any argument of his own. Schopenhauer also does not
doubt that there is something other than the representing subject beyond
what it represents, an underlying reality beginning with its own body as it is
rather than as it merely appears. He accepts Kant’s insistence that there can
be no appearance without something that appears (CPuR B xxvi).
However, Schopenhauer’s fundamental departure from Kant is already
suggested in this passage:
Will . . . this alone gives him the key to his own appearance, reveals to him
the meaning and shows him the inner workings of his essence, his deeds,
his movements; (WWR §18, p. 124)
and what we discover when we look closely at our wills is that they are
governed not by reason but by impulse, at its most fundamental level a
113
“dark, dull driving” (WWR §27, p. 174), and even at its highest, most
clarified level, still desires or apparently “creative drives” that only “seem
to perform their tasks from abstract, rational motives” (WWR §27, p. 182). It
is not our planning and calculating drives that best express the real nature of
the will but our genitals (WWR §20, p. 133). Of course, it is well known that
following the lead of one’s genitals is a pretty good formula for disappoint-
ment, and for Schopenhauer this reveals the frustration to which a will
driven by desire ultimately leads: either one does not get what one wants,
the object of one’s desire, and is frustrated, or one does, but then one
wants more, and either does not get that, so is frustrated, or does, but
then wants more, and so on ad infinitum. Trying truly to satisfy desire is
the height of irrationality, but for Schopenhauer there is nothing else we can
will—we can at best try to escape from the clutches of will altogether,
whether through art, asceticism, or compassion.
But of course, if the underlying nature of reality, the thing in itself, is
nothing other than will, then escape from its clutches should not really be
possible but should at most be apparent. And not only does Schopenhauer
equate our experience of ourselves “from the inside” as desire-driven will
with our own ultimate reality, our character as things in themselves; he also
argues that we have no choice but to think of the underlying reality of all
appearance in this way, because this is our only form of insight into—or
acquaintance with—anything as a thing in itself. We can only “take the key
to the understanding of the essence in itself of things” to be the
key provided . . . by the immediate cognition of our own essence, and apply
it to [the] appearances in the inorganic [and organic] world as well,
even appearances that are more remote from us than any others. Ultimate
reality, because, Schopenhauer assumes,
it is everywhere one and the same, . . . must be called will here as well as
there, a name signifying the being in itself of every thing in the world and
the sole kernel of every appearance. (WWR §23, pp. 142–3)
allegedly immediate rather than empirical insight into the character of our
own wills and the very problematic premise that at bottom everything is
essentially one. His position thus begins from an epistemological premise,
namely that we can know ultimate reality through knowing ourselves, and
reaches an ontological conclusion, that ultimate reality must be like our-
selves, but in opposition to Kant and the other German idealists he assumes
that our own nature is essentially non-rational and therefore that the
ultimate character of reality, although it is in a certain sense like the mental,
is also fundamentally non-rational.
It may seem far-fetched to think of Friedrich Nietzsche (1844–1900) as an
idealist. After all, he presented himself as an almost fanatical anti-idealist
throughout his life. In many of his published and unpublished writings
as well as in his letters he expresses over and again his dislike and his
disdain for what he calls “idealism.” A telling summary of his position
concerning idealism is to be found in his letter to Malwida von
Meysenbug (October 20, 1888):
throughout history from the era of the ancient Greeks up to his own time
(because of his contempt for Kant’s postulates of pure practical reason,
Nietzsche gave little credence to Kant’s theoretical critique of traditional
metaphysics). He took philosophy in this traditional shape to be a somewhat
enigmatic endeavor to pursue the mutually excluding tasks of (culture-
forming) art and religion on the one hand and of (cognition-focused)
science on the other (see Nachgelassene Fragmente: Notebook 19, [47],
[62], [218]; KSA 7: 434). It is doomed to failure because of two fundamental
shortcomings. The first is that it gives a privileged status to truth in declaring
truth to be the ultimate goal at which it aims. This preoccupation with truth
is based on the implicit assumption that truth has some overriding value.
This assumption has never been justified, not even addressed by any phi-
losopher. Nietzsche writes in the Genealogy of Morals (1887: section 24):
Turn to the most ancient and most modern philosophies: all of them lack a
consciousness of the extent to which the will to truth itself needs a
justification, here is a gap in every philosophy—where does it come
from? Because the ascetic ideal has so far been lord over all philosophy,
because truth was set as being, as god, as the highest authority itself,
because truth was not allowed to be a problem. Do you understand this
“allowed to be”?—From the very moment that faith in the God of the
ascetic ideal is denied, there is a new problem as well: that of the value of
truth.—The will to truth needs a critique—let us hereby define our own
task—the value of truth is tentatively to be called into question.”
(KSA 5: 401; Third Essay)
However, it is not the problem of the value of truth but the second short-
coming that, in Nietzsche’s eyes, leads directly to metaphysics. It is the
tendency of philosophers to deny the obvious, to neglect surfaces in favor
of what is allegedly behind them, out of habitual weakness and anxiety to
prefer the stable and immutable over and against change and becoming, so
exemplified at the very beginning of Western philosophy by Plato. Nietzsche
often expresses this critical sentiment in his published and unpublished
writings. The following note is a nice example:
In sum: all philosophical idealism until now was something like an illness,
except where, as in the case of Plato, it was the caution of an overabundant
and dangerous health, the fear of overpowerful senses, the shrewdness of a
shrewd Socratic”. (KSA 3: 623)
However, there are other passages where Nietzsche is not in such a chari-
table mood and where he presents the ultimate reasons for Plato’s strong
leanings toward idealism as rooted in weakness and resentment just as with
all the other idealists in the history of philosophy (e.g., Ecce Homo 3; KSA 6:
311). His ultimate verdict on metaphysics in all its ancient and modern
forms is nicely expressed in the following note:
domination, sexual lust, etc.) has been treated by humans most hostile and
eliminated from the “true” world. Thus they have step by step wiped out
the affects—claimed God to be the opposite of the evil, i.e., reality to consist
in the negation of desires and affects (which is to say precisely in nothing-
ness). Likewise they hate the irrational, the arbitrary, the accidental (as the
cause of countless physical suffering). Consequently they negate this ele-
ment in that-which-is-in-itself, they conceive it as absolute “rationality”
and “purposiveness.” In the same way they fear change, transitoriness:
therein is expressed an oppressed soul, full of mistrust and bad experience.
(The case of Spinoza: an inverted sort of person would count this change as
charming). A playful being overladen with power would call precisely the
affects, unreason, and change good in an eudaimonistic sense, together
with their consequences, with danger, contrast, dissolution, etc.
(KSA 13: 536)
Against positivism, which would stand by the position “There are only
facts,” I would say: no, there are precisely no facts, only interpretations.
We can establish no fact “in itself”: it is perhaps nonsense to want such
a thing. You say “Everything is subjective”: but that is already an
interpretation, the “subject” is not anything given, but something invented
and added, something stuck behind . . . To the extent that the word
“knowledge” [Erkenntnis] has any sense, the world is knowable: but it is
interpretable differently, it has no sense behind it, but innumerable senses,
“perspectivism.” It is our needs that interpret the world: our drives and
their to and fro. Every drive is a kind of domination, every one has its
perspective, which it would force on all other drives as a norm.
(Notebook 7 [60]; KSA 12: 315)
character of reality. His deeply rooted hostility against the idea that the
ultimate constitution of the reality is revealed to us by processes of cognition
runs like a leitmotiv (to borrow a term from another of Nietzsche’s heroes,
Richard Wagner) through all his writings both published and unpublished.
One of the most explicit expressions of this distrust in the power of knowl-
edge/cognition is already to be found in The Birth of Tragedy, which is both
his very first book, published in 1871 under the title The Birth of Tragedy
from the Spirit of Music, and one of his latest, published in a second edition
in 1886 under the title The Birth of Tragedy or Hellenism and Pessimism. In
this book, the 27-year-old Nietzsche expounds an aestheticism that relies
heavily with respect to both content and terminology on Schopenhauer’s
metaphysics of the irrational will. According to this aestheticism, the cog-
nitive access of human beings to the world is founded in and strongly
mediated by the interaction of two antagonistic drives, named after two
figures in Greek mythology the Dionysian and the Apollonian, that “con-
spire” (sich miteinander verschwören) to establish an illusionary worldview.
The resulting conception of reality is an aesthetic one in that it does not
claim to be “true” in the sense of giving an adequate account of the world
and its ultimate constitution, rather it confesses to its deceitfulness, to its
intention to deliberately falsify (verfälschen) essential aspects of reality in
order to allow the individual person to endure and to overcome the inevi-
table sufferings of life. Nietzsche maintains that the delicate balance between
the two drives is based on their mutually influencing each other, as is shown
especially vividly in the Attic Greek tragedy which he takes to be the most
felicitous artistic document of a worldview that is formed by these drives and
rests not on objective data provided by scientific experience but on the needs
of the individual human being to come to grips with the encounter of a
world that comes across as an utterly chaotic natural and socio-cultural
environment. This aesthetic worldview, according to Nietzsche, is under-
mined by what he calls “the theoretical man” (der theoretische Mensch) (BoT
section 15; KSA 1: 98). He identifies Socrates as the first and paradigmatic
representative of this species who is possessed by a “profound delusion . . . ,
namely the imperturbable belief that thought, as it follows the thread of
causality, reaches down into the deepest abysses of being, and that it is
capable, not simply of understanding existence, but even of correcting it.
This sublime metaphysical illusion is an instinct which belongs inseparably
to science” (tiefsinnige Wahnvorstellung, . . . jener unerschütterliche Glaube,
dass das Denken, an dem Leitfaden der Causalität, bis in die tiefsten
Abgründe des Seins reiche, und dass das Denken das Sein nicht nur zu
121
Idealism in Modern Philosophy. Paul Guyer and Rolf-Peter Horstmann, Oxford University Press.
© Paul Guyer and Rolf-Peter Horstmann 2023. DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780192848574.003.0007
126
The terms “real” and “objective” . . . have no meaning except for a con-
sciousness which presents its experiences to itself as determined by rela-
tions, and at the same time conceives a single and unalterable order of
relations determining them, with which its temporary presentation, as each
experience occurs, of the relations determining it may be contrasted.
(1893: 17)
in the growth of our experience, in the process of our learning to know the
world, an animal organism, which has its history in time, gradually
becomes the vehicle of an eternally complete consciousness. (1893: 72)
can deny that and still make sense—so these traditional ideas of reality must
be false. Thus Bradley rejects any identity between ultimate reality and our
ordinary modes of perception and conception (“thought”). He substantiates
this claim by examining a range of central concepts from metaphysics and
epistemology, among them the concepts of primary and secondary qualities,
of substance and attribute, of quality and relation, space and time, of
causality as well as the concept of a thing and that of the self. The best
known of his destructive arguments against these conceptions is that against
qualities and relations because it played a role in the discussion that arose at
the turn of the twentieth century between Bradley, Russell, and Moore
(among others) about the logical and ontological status of relations, that
is, whether they are “internal” or “external” to their terms. As to qualities
and relations Bradley claims:
The arrangement of given facts into relations and qualities may be neces-
sary in practice, but it is theoretically unintelligible. The reality, so char-
acterized, is not true reality, but is appearance. (1893: 25 [1897: 21])
He starts with pointing out that “[q]ualities are nothing without relations”
(ibid.). This is so because in order to be qualities they have to differ from
other qualities and hence have to be distinct. However, without relations
they could not be distinct. But distinctiveness presupposes plurality and
plurality relations.
Their plurality depends on relation, and, without that relation, they are not
distinct. But, if not distinct, then not different, and therefore not qualities.
(1893: 28 [1897: 24])
The result of his examination not just of the concepts of quality and relation
but of all the other concepts he deals with consists in the verdict that all
attempts to capture the true nature of reality in terms of these categories are
futile because all these concepts are unintelligible, inconsistent, and in the
end self-contradictory. He even applies this critique to two concepts
accepted without demure by many other idealists, those of the self and of
God (Passmore 1966: 65). This means that what is designated by means of
these concepts cannot be real, but can only reflect the way the world appears
to us, not the way it really is. This diagnosis is based on Bradley’s funda-
mental conviction that “ultimate reality is such that it does not contradict
itself” (1893: 136 [1897: 120]). He takes this to be “an absolute criterion”
(ibid.). However, to be just appearance is not to be unreal in the sense of an
illusion. On the contrary, although appearance is “inconsistent with itself,”
one cannot deny its existence or “divorce it from reality” because “reality, set
on one side and apart from all appearance, would assuredly be nothing”
(1893: 132 [1897: 114]).
But does this ontological argument for idealism exclude epistemology
altogether? That is, since appearance always proves to be an inadequate way
in which reality is present to us, is it beyond our means ever to become
acquainted with the true essence of ultimate reality or can we avoid skepti-
cism and claim that it is indeed possible for us to have access to the
constitutive nature of reality? Bradley emphatically endorses the latter
possibility. According to him, the self-contradictoriness of what is appear-
ance already implies that there is positive knowledge of reality: reality has to
be One in the sense that it does not allow discord and it must be such that it
can include diversity (cf. 1893: 140 [1897: 123]), that is, “the Absolute is . . .
an individual and a system” (1893: 144 [1897: 127]). This character of reality
as an internally diversified individual system is revealed to us in sentient
experience. “Sentient experience . . . is reality, and what is not this is not real”
(ibid.). According to Bradley it is this sentient experience that “is commonly
called psychical existence” (ibid.). The material basis of sentient experience
is exhausted in feeling, thought, and volition. Thus reality consists in what
132
in Moral Science at Trinity College, and there the tutor of both Moore and
Russell. (On McTaggart, see Passmore 1966: 76–82; Broad 1933–8; Geach
1979; Mander 2011: ch. 10.1.3). His earliest work, “The Further Determination
of the Absolute” (first published as a pamphlet in 1893, then as chapter IX of
Studies in Hegelian Cosmology [1901a] and in Philosophical Studies [1934]),
starts with the following proclamation:
And the last of his writings published in his lifetime (“An Ontological
Idealism”) starts with the confession, explicitly employing the same termi-
nology that we have used here: “Ontologically I am an Idealist, since I believe
that all that exists is spiritual” (1924 [1934: 273]). He takes spirit to be the
sum total of individual spirits or selves connected by the relation of love, and
bases this conviction on the claim that only this conception of what ultimate
reality consists in allows us to overcome unavoidable contradictions con-
nected with all other attempts to reconcile unity and diversity as the
distinguishing marks of reality. Harmony between unity and diversity can
be established only on the basis of an all-encompassing relation of love
between all the characteristic elements of reality, which in turn presupposes
thinking of ultimate reality as a community of spirits or as Spirit. These—as
McTaggart himself admits (1924 [1934: 271f.])—rather mystical-sounding
assertions, which he adhered to all his life, he tries to back up by a number of
different considerations. In his earliest writing he relies heavily on views held
by Bradley to the effect that we have to accept that contradictions are a
criterion for non-reality. However, he does not employ this criterion as a
logical maxim with an implication for the nature of reality but transforms it
into a more active ontological principle according to which nothing that
prevents harmony can be real—so the active principle of reality must rather
be something positive, namely love. In his last work, his attempt to present
an argument for his ontological idealism is based mainly on (1) mereological
considerations concerning the structure of substances which aim to show
that only spirits can claim the status of a substance, and on (2) his theory of
time, the unreality of which he famously had proven in his magnum opus
The Nature of Existence (1921–7). In the first volume of this work he
134
and to ask
there is no B-series in a temporal sense (cf. NE §333) yet that (b) the (more
fundamental) A-series leads to time determinations of a state of affairs that
are contradictory. The result:
We conclude that the distinctions of past, present and future are essential
to time, and that, if the distinctions are never true of reality, then no reality
is in time. (NE §324)
Though never true of reality these distinctions are not empty, because
according to McTaggart they have to be taken as appearances of a third
series, the C-series, “a series which is not a time series, but under certain
conditions appears to us to be one.” This C-series “does actually exist in
every case in which there is the appearance of a time-series” (NE §347).
McTaggart thinks of the C-series (at least in The Nature of Existence) as an
“Inclusion Series” (NE §575)
whose members are connected by the relations “inclusive of” and “inclu-
sive in”, so that of any two terms one will be inclusive of the other, and the
other will be included in it. (NE §575)
The existence of matter can also not be inferred on the basis of the prima
facie existence of what we perceive “by means of the sense organs of our
bodies”, that is, of what he calls “sensa” (NE §373), because it is erroneous to
believe that matter as the presumed outside cause of a sensum has the same
qualities as a sensum and thus has to exist (cf. NE §365). He conjectures that
if there are outside causes of sensa they must be substances which are “of a
spiritual nature” (NE §371).
When it comes to (c) sensa, McTaggart holds that one has to distinguish
between two classes of percepta, those perceived by introspection (mental
136
states, spiritual data) and those that are given by means of sense organs
(sensa). The latter do not really exist, they just lead to the illusion that they
exist. This is so because of a confusion between a perception that is part of
the percipient and therefore spiritual or mental in character and what is
perceived, that is, the object of a perception or the perceptum (cf. NE §373).
However, a perceptum as a sensum cannot, according to McTaggart, have
parts within parts to infinity and thus cannot really exist because what exists
has no simple parts (cf. 355). Having disposed of matter and sensa this way,
he then discusses the ontological status of (d) spirit or spirituality. He
declares that “the quality of spirituality . . . is the quality of having content,
all of which is the content of one or more selves” (NE §381) and states that
“nothing can have this quality except substances, and so nothing but sub-
stances are spiritual” and exist or are real (ibid.). A self or an I he takes to be
a simple quality of a substance which is known to me to be myself by direct
perception, that is, is known by acquaintance, not by description. The
distinction between knowledge by acquaintance and knowledge by descrip-
tion he explicitly takes up from Russell (NE §382, cf. also §44). He then
surmises that it is very likely that the I, that is, the substance that possesses
the quality of being a self, persists through time because “I perceive myself as
persisting through time, or the real series which appears as a time-series”
(NE §395). He also holds that selves are conscious without having to be self-
conscious (NE §397) and that no experience is possible “which is not part of
a self ” (NE §400) though it cannot belong to more than one self (NE §401).
He concludes:
As all the content of spirit falls within some self, and none of it falls within
more than one self, it follows that all existent selves form a set of parts of
that whole which consists of all existent spirits. (NE §404)
. . . spirit, unlike matter and sense, can really exist. But it can do so only if it
contains no parts except perceptions and groups of perceptions. (NE §426)
No substance has material or sensal qualities, and all reality is spirit. This
conclusion I propose . . . to call by the name of Idealism” (NE §432),
his career in that he claims that only minds exist because of their substan-
tiality. His main argument for this position proceeds, like Leibniz’s, by
positing criteria for genuine substancehood that only minds can satisfy.
Contrary to Leibniz, however, McTaggart supposes that genuine substance
must be infinitely divisible, but then, closer to Leibniz, that their infinite
parts must be related by “determining correspondence,” each part deter-
mining every other. He then concludes that mind or spirit, which can
represent infinite divisibility and determining correspondence as well, is
the only candidate for genuine substancehood, and hence the only thing
that really exists. In further similarity to Leibniz, he supposes that there is a
multiplicity of minds, harmoniously related, although by their own love for
one another rather than by an external act of God (NE ch. XLI). McTaggart
admits that there is something provisional about his argument, for it is only
our “experience” and our “imagination” that suggest that the only candi-
dates for reality are matter, sensa, and mind. Thus there is no a priori proof
that his enumeration is complete, so “we are entitled to hold all substance to
be spiritual, not as a proposition which has been rigorously demonstrated,
but as one which it is reasonable to believe and unreasonable to disbelieve”
(NE §428). Here then he seeks to back off his dogmatic idealism, coming
back to something closer to Bradley’s position. But he does employ what
might be considered an epistemological rule of inference in his metaphysical
argument—crudely put, don’t worry about possibilities you can’t even
imagine—and he is not troubled by any doubt about this principle.
Idealism was also a major mode of philosophy in the United States during
the late nineteenth century. It had to compete with pragmatism—a compe-
tition personalized at Harvard from the 1880s until the death of William
James (b. 1842) in 1910 by his friendly rivalry with Josiah Royce
(1855–1916)—but while pragmatism remained prominent throughout the
twentieth century, whether under that name or not, the reputation of
idealism was permanently damaged by a movement toward “realism” early
in the century (which also attacked pragmatism, although without the same
effect). Earlier in the nineteenth century, the popular essayist Ralph Waldo
Emerson, the most philosophical of the New England “Transcendentalists,”
had struck many idealist themes, and after the Civil War a school of
“St. Louis Hegelians” emerged, whose efforts were primarily exegetical. But
the leading American idealist was Josiah Royce. Deeply influenced by the
lectures Charles Sanders Peirce (1839–1914) gave in Cambridge in 1898
(Royce was one of the first to earn a Ph.D. in philosophy at the new Johns
Hopkins University in 1878, but that was one year before Peirce began
139
Either then there is no error, or else judgments are true and false only in
reference to a higher inclusive thought, which they presuppose, and which
must, in the last analysis, be assumed as Infinite and all-inclusive.
(1885: 393)
Royce holds that we must have some sort of apprehension of the “higher
inclusive thought” in order to be able even to make our errors, and then that
the growth of human knowledge over time consists in increasing apprehen-
sion of this all-inclusive truth without any limit being prescribed by our
subordinate status. This is the epistemological optimism that pervades all
Royce’s work, including his subsequent debate with Bradley, to which we
will return.
This account does not yet make clear why Royce thought that epistemol-
ogy must lead to ontological idealism; that becomes clearer in his subsequent
works. Royce’s next major statement of his idealism came in The Spirit of
Modern Philosophy (1892). The second part of the book more fully develops
Royce’s own arguments for idealism. Here Royce gives a clear definition of
his conception of idealism and adds to the previous argument from error a
140
second argument, from meaning. The core of this argument is that the
intended object of an expression or thought must itself be conceived or
understood in some way, so that we always mean what are in some sense our
own ideas, although of course at any particular moment we hardly know or
understand everything about the object to which we refer; that is why the
idea that is the ultimate object of reference may be much greater than the
idea that refers. In Royce’s words,
The self that is doubting or asserting, or that is even feeling its private
ignorance about an object, and that still, even in consequence of all this, is
meaning, is aiming at such an object, is in essence identical with the self for
which this object exists in its complete and consciously known truth.
(1892: 370–1)
calls the theory of “validity,” is that “To be real now means, primarily, to be
valid, to be true, to be in essence the standard for ideas” (1: 202). This
conception of being tries to retain realism’s recognition of independence
through the thought that “some of my ideas are already, and apart from my
private experience, valid, true, well-grounded” (1: 204) and mysticism’s
identification of subject and object through the thought that reality is itself
possible experience, but adds structure to the now unified realms of thought
and being instead of eliminating structure. It brings out the epistemology
characteristic of much idealism.
The fourth conception of being, however, is a fuller development of the
conception of meaning that Royce had introduced in The Spirit of Modern
Philosophy (1892). He now links meaning to purpose, and his thought is that
the meaning of a term is an intended purpose, a problem to be solved, for
example a mathematical problem to be solved or object to be constructed,
and that in using a term the user already has some approach to solving the
problem in mind but the full solution remains to be developed, may never be
fully developed in the life of a particular individual, but is in some sense
already included in the larger thought that constitutes reality. Reaching back
to both Hegel and Kant—an idealist conception of purpose (Zweck) was
after all the central and unifying concept of Kant’s third Critique—Royce
conceives of the progress of knowledge as making the meaning of our ideas
more determinate. This development also displays the influence of Peirce
and Royce’s attempt to assimilate pragmatism into his version of idealism:
his notion of meaning is clearly a version of Peirce’s approach to truth, on
which a proposition is true if it would be affirmed at the final stage of human
inquiry, with the difference that while for Peirce the final stage of
human inquiry is essentially a regulative ideal without ontological commit-
ment, for Royce, the comprehensive meaning in which all ideas would be
fully determinate is actually thought, although by a sort of super-self, not by
any particular finite human self or even by all the selves thinking at any one
time. Royce makes the transition from thought to being by stating that
Royce’s arguments for idealism, which in many ways return to the basic
form of modern idealism pioneered by Green, whose Prolegomena had been
published just a couple of years before Royce’s own career began, collectively
142
manuscripts he wrote for different lecture series but never published. They
comprise the early Harvard lectures on The Logic of Science (1865) and the
early Lowell Lectures on the same topic (1866) as well as the Cambridge
Lectures on Reasoning and the Logic of Things (1898) and the later Harvard
lectures on Pragmatism (1903). (On Peirce, see Murphey 1961; Passmore
1966: 136–44; Flower and Murphey 1977; Kuklick 1977.)
Peirce’s metaphysical views are intimately connected with his claim
“that logic is the science of representations in general, whether mental or
material” (CE 1: 169) and with his stipulations concerning the structure
and status of what he calls “representation.” In his early writings, while
trying to answer the question as to the grounds of the objective validity of
synthetic inferences (a question which he takes to be at the center of
Kant’s theoretical philosophy), he develops a notion of representation
according to which
As we will see, the effort to accept much of the epistemology of idealism but
to reject its metaphysics would also be characteristic of the nearly contem-
poraneous Neo-Kantian movement in Germany, and through the influence
of that along with the influence of pragmatism of much subsequent analytic
philosophy.
He proclaims, most unambiguously in his Harvard lectures on
Pragmatism (1903), that one can establish Pragmatism as a methodological
maxim on the basis of epistemological (in later years: semiotic) considera-
tions that have to start from a phenomenological analysis of experience. To
provide this analysis is the task of what he calls Phenomenology (with
Peirce’s capital “P,” used explicitly in allusion to Hegel, cf. EP 2: 143f.)
which is in Peirce’s taxonomy the first of the main branches of philosophy
because on it rest what he takes to be the other branches of philosophy, that
is, normative science and metaphysics (cf. EP 2: 146f.). Phenomenology is
the discipline
whose task is to make out what are the elements of appearance that present
themselves to us every hour and every minute whether we are pursuing
earnest investigations, or are undergoing the strangest vicissitudes of
experience, or are dreamily listening to the tales of Scheherazade.
(EP 2: 147)
being a Third, or Medium, between a Second and its First. That is to say, it
is Representation as an element of the Phenomenon. (EP 2: 160)
gives room for explanations of many facts which without it are absolutely
and hopelessly inexplicable; and further that it carries along with it the
following doctrines: first, a logical realism of the most pronounced type;
second, objective idealism; third, tychism, with its consequent thorough-
going evolutionism. We also notice that the doctrine presents no hin-
drances to spiritual influences, such as some philosophies are felt to do.
(CP 6: 163)
Tychism “or the doctrine that absolute chance is a factor of the universe”
(CP 6: 201) he takes to be an essential element of synechistic philosophy
because it
Idealism and all the arguments for it came under massive attack in Britain at
the turn of the twentieth century by George Edward Moore (1873–1958) and
Bertrand Russell (1872–1970), while in the United States Royce’s position
was attacked by a school of younger “New Realists,” to some extent inspired
by his lifelong interlocutor William James, who included E. B. Holt and his
younger Harvard colleague Ralph Barton Perry, and later Roy Wood Sellars
(the father of Wilfrid Sellars, who later moved back to a form of
Kantianism), and Arthur Lovejoy. Both Moore and Russell had more of an
enduring influence on the course of analytic philosophy than did the
American New Realists. But they also reveal the continuing impulse to
idealism in spite of their own efforts, so we will focus on them. Both of
them take idealism to be spiritualism in the vein of Berkeley and Bradley
(neither of them mentions their own Cambridge tutor McTaggart, perhaps
because his main work was not published until several decades after their
attack on Bradley), that is, they think of idealism as a position characterized
by the claim that the universe (Moore) or whatever exists or whatever can be
known to exist (Russell) is spiritual (Moore) or in some sense mental
(Russell). Although their attack was so influential that even more than a
hundred years later, any acknowledgment of idealistic tendencies is viewed
in the English-speaking world with reservation, it is by no means obvious
that they actually thought they had disproved idealism. On the contrary,
neither Moore nor Russell claimed to have demonstrated that the universe
or what exists or can be known to exist is not spiritual or mental. All that
they take themselves to have shown is that there are no good philosophical
(in contradistinction to, e.g., theological or psychological) arguments avail-
able to support such a claim. Moore especially is very explicit about this
point. He devotes the first five pages of his famous piece The Refutation of
Idealism from 1903 to assuring the reader over and over that
I do not suppose that anything I shall say has the smallest tendency to
prove that reality is not spiritual . . . . Reality may be spiritual, for all I know;
and I devoutly hope it is . . . . It is, therefore, only with idealistic arguments
Idealism in Modern Philosophy. Paul Guyer and Rolf-Peter Horstmann, Oxford University Press.
© Paul Guyer and Rolf-Peter Horstmann 2023. DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780192848574.003.0008
151
[I]f there were good reasons to regard them [viz. physical objects] as
mental, we could not legitimately reject this opinion merely because it
strikes us as strange. (1912 [1974: 38])
Moore and Russell found two main arguments for idealism to be falla-
cious. The first depends on Berkeley’s idealistic principle that being con-
sists in being perceived, the second on the converse claim, attributed to
Bradley, that thought entails being. Their criticism of the first as well as
their rebuttal of the second argument both stem from certain convictions
about the nature of knowledge that they share. The assault on Berkeley is
staged by Moore most extensively in The Refutation of Idealism (1903).
Here he holds that if there is an argument to prove the idealistic claim that
the universe is spiritual (1903: 433) then this reasoning must rely either at
the beginning or at some point later in the argument on the premise esse
est percipi:
I believe that every argument ever used to show that reality is spiritual has
inferred this (validly or invalidly) from “esse is percipere” as one of its
premisses; and that this again has never been pretended to be proved
except by use of the premiss that esse is percipi. (1903: 437)
According to Moore the proposition esse est percipi “does at least assert that
whatever is, is experienced” (1903: 437) which is meant in turn to assert
that wherever you have x [esse] you also have percipi; that whatever has the
property x also has the property that it is experienced. (1903: 440)
After a lengthy analysis of this proposition he points out that the conception
of the connection between an experience and what is experienced that the
idealist is entertaining has tenuous consequences that give rise to the
question:
152
This line of reasoning, remarkably similar to what Kant had argued in the
Fourth Antinomy in the first edition of the Critique of Pure Reason but
rejected as an inadequate refutation of idealism in the second edition, was
picked up in an abbreviated form by Russell ten years later in the chapter on
idealism in his The Problems of Philosophy, while the attack on Bradley,
although foreshadowed in Russell’s Problems, is spelled out rather lengthily
(and a bit nastily) by Moore in “The Conception of Reality” from 1917–18.
Their main objection against the two idealistic arguments seems to be that
they rely on unjustly presupposing that the mental act of relating to an
object (perceiving, thinking, knowing, experiencing) is a necessary condition
for the existence of this object. The fallacy involved here consists in failing to
make “the distinction between act and object in our apprehending of
things,” as Russell (1912 [1974: 42]) puts it, or, in Moore’s terminology of
“The Refutation”, in wrongfully identifying the content of “consciousness”
with its object (1912 [1974: 19ff.]). As soon as this identification is given up
and that distinction is made it is at least an open question whether things
exist independently of the mind, and idealism insofar as it neglects this
distinction and holds fast to that identification is refuted because it is based
on an invalid argument.
Whether this line of criticism of idealistic positions is indeed successful
might be controversial, and even if it strikes home against Berkeley the
charge that they simply conflate knowledge and object hardly seems to do
justice to the elaborate arguments of the late nineteenth-century idealists.
However, if one is convinced of the correctness of this criticism (as no doubt
Moore and Russell were) then it makes way for interesting new perspectives
in epistemology and metaphysics. This is so because if this criticism is taken
153
Moore is well aware that this analysis of the nature of a proposition leads to
some version of what could be called “conceptual realism,” according to
which that what is “really” real are concepts because they are the ultimate
objects of acquaintance. He explicitly states:
Moore also is very well aware that his view of the nature of concepts
commits him to the claim that the world insofar as it is an object of
propositional knowledge consists of concepts because these are the only
things one can be acquainted with if acquaintance is a condition of knowl-
edge. Thus he writes:
Moore confesses that “I am fully aware of how paradoxical this theory must
appear, and even how contemptible” (1899: para. 14). And indeed one
wonders whether such an account does not raise more problems than it
answers. Fortunately we do not have to be concerned with this question
here. However, if we ask whether Moore’s theory really manages to avoid
idealism, it is hard not to conclude that its metaphysical commitments are
precisely a form of idealism, even if he has been led to his theory by an
attempt to maintain epistemological realism! After all, to claim that only
concepts are real, that they have a mode of being outside of space and time,
that they are non-physical and completely unaffected by any activity of a
thinking subject, does not sound very different from statements that can
rightly be attributed to, for example, Hegel, or even ultimately Plato, and
that are meant to assert idealism. The main difference in this case is that
Moore’s conception of what a concept is has virtually nothing to do with
what Hegel means by “concept,” but this does not suffice to establish
ontological anti-idealism. Although Moore might avoid identifying concepts
with the mental states of particular, finite subjects by his insistence upon the
metaphysical independence of concepts, many avowed idealists had also
done that. Moore comes dangerously close to the point where the difference
between ontological idealism and ontological realism vanishes and this
distinction becomes a question of terminology.
Russell chooses a different path in the attempt to somehow reconcile the
idea that knowledge has to be understood as a relation of acquaintance with
objects with the phenomenon of propositional knowledge. He is more flexible
both with respect to kinds of knowledge and with respect to kinds of objects
with which we can be acquainted than Moore is. First of all, he distinguishes
between knowledge of things and knowledge of truths. He recognizes two
kinds of knowledge of things: knowledge by acquaintance and knowledge by
description. Knowledge by acquaintance obtains whenever
156
when we know that it [i.e., the object] is “the so-and-so”, i.e., when
we know that there is one object, and no more, having a certain
property. (1912 [1974: 53])
Universals are conceptual entities: “These entities are such as can be named
by parts of speech which are not substantives; they are such entities as
qualities or relations” (1912 [1974: 90]). Because universals and particulars
alike are possible objects of acquaintance both have to be real. However,
according to Russell they are real in a different sense. Particulars have
existence in time whereas universals have timeless being. The first ones
exist, the others subsist. They form two different worlds in that the world
of particulars consists of items that are “fleeting, vague, without sharp
boundaries” whereas the world of universals “is unchangeable, rigid,
exact” (1912 [1974: 100]). The echo of Plato is unmistakable.
This rough outline of Russell’s epistemic universe is meant to emphasize
only those aspects of his position that are of relevance for an assessment of
idealistic tendencies in his approach to knowledge. As in the case of Moore,
it is tempting to interpret Russell’s commitment to a timeless world of
universals as if not an endorsement then at least tolerance of a position
that is difficult to distinguish from some version of an ontologically
grounded idealism. Perhaps such a verdict is not very significant because
one could as well describe this position as a version of ontological realism. It
just depends on what the distinctive feature of idealism is supposed to be. If
idealism is a position that takes for granted the reality of conceptual entities
even if it does not hold them to be mind dependent, at least not dependent
on particular, ordinary minds, then both Moore and Russell endorse it. If
idealism is meant to be a position that takes conceptual items to be mind
dependent, that is, dependent on particular minds, then both are realists
rather than idealists with respect to concepts. Either way, it is hard to see
how Russell can avoid the epistemological path to idealism given his views
about physical objects. This is so because of his sense-datum theory, accord-
ing to which what is immediately present to us, that is, what we are
acquainted with when we are acquainted with particulars, are just sense-
data and not objects in the sense of individual things with qualities standing
in relations to each other. For him “among the objects with which we are
acquainted are not included physical objects (as opposed to sense-data)”
(1912 [1974: 52]). Physical objects are constructions that we form out of
sense-data together with some descriptive devices, and only with respect to
these constructions can we have knowledge by description, that is, proposi-
tional knowledge. If idealism is understood (as has been done here) as
158
involving the claim that what we take to be objects of knowledge are heavily
dependent on some activity of the knowing subject, then the very idea of an
object as a construction guarantees the endorsement of idealism. Thus, in
contrast to their self-proclaimed revolt against the idealism of Berkeley and
Bradley, the positions of both Moore and Russell are by no means free of
traits that connect them rather closely to well-known currents in modern
idealism; and these features, above all the supposition that knowers may be
immediately presented with some sorts of informational atoms, whether
properties, sense-data, or whatever, but that all further knowledge, or all
knowledge beyond immediate acquaintance, involves constructive activities
of the mind, are common throughout a great deal of recent philosophy.
9
The German Response to Idealism II
Neo-Kantianism without Idealism
Idealism in Modern Philosophy. Paul Guyer and Rolf-Peter Horstmann, Oxford University Press.
© Paul Guyer and Rolf-Peter Horstmann 2023. DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780192848574.003.0009
160
what is already known not by our minds but by absolute mind. We can also
suggest that the distinction between the use of our own categories to frame
our comprehensive science of nature and our various sciences of our own
experience is also heir to Kant’s distinction between the theoretical and
practical standpoints, although without Kant’s commitment to a radical or
libertarian conception of free will—another metaphysical commitment that
the Neo-Kantians stayed away from, along with any speculation about the
nature of an ontologically independent thing in itself. This is particularly
clear in the Southwest version of Neo-Kantianism, where the subjective or
internal point of view is characterized in terms not only of consciousness but
also of values (Werte), although typically multiple values rather than the
single value of morality or virtue. This connection is hinted at in the title of
Heinrich Rickert’s 1924 book Kant als Philosoph der modernen Kultur
(“Kant as Philosopher of Modern Culture”). One last hint we might throw
out here is that the Neo-Kantian view of the logic of natural science has been
more influential in the history of analytic philosophy than their recognition
of the human or cultural sciences, although some positions in analytical
philosophy, such as non-reductive materialism, the view that all that exists is
ultimately material but that the nature of consciousness and thought cannot
be described in physicalistic terms (e.g., the “anomalous monism” of Donald
Davidson), echo the Neo-Kantian distinction between the natural and the
human sciences.
We can only give some illustrations of these general points here. We can
start with some ideas from Wilhelm Windelband (1848–1914), the elder
statesman of the Southwest school—he was born in Potsdam, studied in
Göttingen with Lotze, and taught briefly at Zürich, none of which were of
course in southwestern Germany, but his main positions were at Freiburg in
Breisgau (1877–82), Strassburg (1882–1903), and then Heidelberg, all of which
were at that time (Strassburg became French again after World War I),
thus the name of the school. At Freiburg he would teach and be succeeded
by Heinrich Rickert, and Edmund Husserl and then Martin Heidegger
would follow there—that would be the end of Southwest Neo-Kantianism.
Windelband perhaps remains best known as a historian of philosophy—his
problem-oriented textbook remained in print for decades—but he published
numerous theoretical and programmatic papers as well, many collected in
Präludien, a volume originally published in 1884 and expanded in further
editions throughout the rest of Windelband’s life. One of Windelband’s
earlier philosophical articles, “Critical or Genetic Method?” from 1883,
starts from a premise that he basically shares with Herman Cohen and the
163
Cohen’s approach to Kant, evident from his first book, was grounded on
the “analytic“ method of the Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics more
than the supposedly “synthetic” method of the Critique of Pure Reason: he
saw Kant as analyzing the presuppositions of the Newtonian physics of his
time taken as “facts” rather than attempting to derive the principles of
Newtonian physics from something even more basic, such as the unity of
apperception or the conditions for time-determination. “Since Newton,
there has existed a science built on principles, conscious of its foundations
and presuppositions, and which proceeds according to the mathematical
method” (Cohen 1883, quoted from Luft 2015: 105). This approach to Kant
was and has continued to be widely influential. But Cohen did not think
of the “facts” of Newtonian science as facts about what the individuals
alive at a particular time happened to believe. A general tendency in
Cohen’s appropriation of Kant’s theoretical philosophy and in his own
theory of knowledge—signaled by his phrase “pure knowledge”—is a non-
psychological account of knowledge: the structures or functions limned by
the transcendental philosophy are not to be identified with psychological
tendencies of individuals, because they are to be universally valid. This “anti-
psychologism” was a common feature of the period, evident in the work of
Frege and Husserl as well, and in all, at least in part, a response to John
Stuart Mill’s attempt at an empiricist philosophy of mathematics. Kant
himself had of course insisted that transcendental philosophy could not be
founded in empirical psychology—that was the gist of his critique of Locke
and Hume. But even if one does not start philosophy with the results of
empirical psychology, but starts instead from a priori principles of logic and
mathematics, or from “value-presuppositions” or “facts,” one must attribute
to human beings at least the psychological abilities necessary to experience
and think in accordance with the presuppositions or structures that are
inferred from scientific beliefs accepted as fact. This would be “transcen-
dental psychology”: psychological generalizations as presuppositions rather
than premises of other scientific principles or facts. It is hard to see how to
eliminate this from philosophy.
Cohen’s book on infinitesimals introduced another idea that would be
crucial to Marburg Neo-Kantianism. The ontological status of infinitesimals
had been an issue since the time of Newton and Leibniz, and how to
understand infinites in general had become a central issue in nineteenth-
century mathematics. Cohen’s particular strategy was to start from Kant’s
often ignored second principle of empirical judgment, the “Anticipations of
Perception,” which asserts that “sensation” and the “real that corresponds to
167
it” always has some degree or “intensive magnitude,” and to argue that we
“are justified in ascribing reality to something when it can be generated or
produced through a continuum of intensive magnitude” (Beiser 2018: 138).
The key move here is to avoid the ontological difficulties that arise in trying
to think of infinitesimals as objects that are always smaller than any object
by instead thinking of them as more like moments in a process of experien-
cing or thinking. Here the philosopher tries to avoid ontology altogether,
although the process of thinking is fundamental. Or, as Cohen puts the point
in more general terms in Kants Theorie der Erfahrung,
Not the stars in the heavens are the objects of [the transcendental] method
teaches us to contemplate, but the astronomical calculations; those facts of
scientific reality are, as it were, the real which is to be accounted for, as
that at which the transcendental gaze is directed. What is the basis of this
reality that is given in such facts? . . . Those facts of law are the objects, not
the star-objects (Cohen 1871: 20).
The objects of knowledge are the processes of thought themselves and their
product, not something standing apart from and over against thought. Not
so different from Rickert’s idea in the Object of Knowledge, Cohen’s thought
thus stands in the tradition of idealism that we saw beginning with Fichte
(although Fichte was not much mentioned throughout the Neo-Kantian
period), and will lead to Cassirer’s most basic philosophical move; also, we
can say, an anti-ontological but epistemologically idealist move, namely,
thinking in terms of functions rather than substances.
We will come back to that shortly, but first one last characteristic idea of
Cohen’s should be mentioned, namely, his reinterpretation of the Kantian
idea of the thing in itself. Like his close contemporary Charles Sanders
Peirce, Cohen did not think of the thing in itself ontologically, as an extant
but otherwise unknowable object that “affects” us with the sensations that
we synthesize, in accordance with the forms of space, time, and the cate-
gories, into our experience of the external and internal worlds. As Beiser has
put it, “Cohen argues that it really makes no sense to talk about a thing-in-
itself as a reality beyond or outside our representations: the objective
correlate and cause of our representations is nothing more than an hypos-
tasis of the concept of an object” (Beiser 2018: 74, emphasis added). This
really implies two things: that we bring the concept of an object, or more
concretely the forms of intuition and conceptualization that we use to think
about objects, to our experience, and that we have the idea of completeness
168
Function but underlying all his work, is to advocate, and argue that the
progress of science requires, a transition from an ontology of substances to
one of relations or “functions.” Thought and knowledge do not consist in
discovering and imitating or reproducing the fixed properties of independ-
ently existing objects, but in establishing relations among our experiences by
means of functions that, like mathematical functions that take us from one
value for a variable to others, can carry us from one experience to others in
ways that we find explanatory, predictive, and useful. Cassirer writes,
This way of looking at things begins with mathematics: numbers are not
things counted, but the products of counting, not objects but so to speak
objectifications of our process of counting, or organizing, calculating, etc. It
continues on to physical science: particles, forces, waves, etc., are not objects
independent of our increasingly refined equations, but objectifications of
our equations, we might even say the sediments they deposit. And so on for
other forms of thought, for example grammatical categories. As Cassirer
continues,
That was what the philosophy of symbolic forms was supposed to do.
And further:
assumption of the reality of our own mental activity: “All objective truth, all
certainty about the outer world as well as all certainty about itself that
mankind is able to attain, appears to depend on the function of representa-
tion. Man knows the world and himself only through the image that he
makes of both” (Philosophy of Symbolic Forms 4 [1996]: 93).
Should we worry if contemporary science cannot explain the fact of
consciousness, as many allege, or be driven to any metaphysical form of
idealism or dualism by that? No, for two reasons. One, just suggested, is that
our own consciousness and abilities of representation and symbolism,
whether or not they are shared by any other forms of being with which we
are acquainted, are facts, as much as any other facts, and we cannot
understand even the most stripped down form of physical science except
as a mode of our own representational and symbolic activity. It would
therefore be self-contradictory for physical science to cast doubt on the
reality of thought, even if it cannot explain it. Second, we have no reason,
certainly on Cassirer’s account, to believe that we have approached anything
like the final stage of physical science. At the very least, assertion of phys-
icalism or materialism as a metaphysical doctrine would be premature. But
in Cassirer’s view we have no particular reason to think that we shall ever
have reached the final stage of natural science. Materialism will always be
premature. But then again, there is no reason to insist upon an idealist
reduction of reality to thought. We just have to allow the reality of thought.
10
Further into the Twentieth Century
Idealism in Modern Philosophy. Paul Guyer and Rolf-Peter Horstmann, Oxford University Press.
© Paul Guyer and Rolf-Peter Horstmann 2023. DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780192848574.003.0010
175
but they do evolve; in one case, he argues, the absolute presupposition of the
Newtonian period that everything happens as a result of a cause has been
replaced in modern physics by the absolute presupposition that “everything
happens according to laws” so that “Cases of impact, for example, are no
longer regarded as cases in which the Laws of Motion are rendered inoper-
ative by interference with one body on the part of another; they are regarded
as cases of ‘free’ motion (that is, motion not interfered with) under peculiar
geometrical conditions, a line of some other kind being substituted for the
straight line of Newton’s first law” (Collingwood 1940: 50–1). Another
obvious comparison to Collingwood’s conception of absolute presupposi-
tions is Thomas Kuhn’s conception of paradigms as frameworks within
which scientific inquiry takes place and which are adjusted to accommodate
refractory data, until they can no longer be easily adjusted and are replaced.
Unlike the Neo-Kantians, Collingwood was happy to retain the term
“metaphysics,” but what he meant by it was a “historical science,” the
description and analysis of the absolute presuppositions underlying the
more specific questions asked and answered in the inquiries of particular
times and places (Collingwood 1940: 49). He also calls this “metaphysics
without ontology” (p. 17). So although he accepted the term that Neo-
Kantians like Cassirer rejected, like Cassirer he saw philosophy as essentially
connected to history, and his “systematic” works too always included much
history. A good example of this is his posthumous Idea of Nature
(Collingwood 1945). Along with rejecting ontology, Collingwood rejected
being labeled as either a realist or an idealist. By his rejection of realism, he
meant to reject not only naive realism, the view that we perceive things
exactly as they really are, without any mediation let alone distortion by our
own perceptual and intellectual faculties, but also the kind of Oxford realism
in which he had been educated, most closely associated with John Cook
Wilson (1849–1915), which asserted the reality of propositions independ-
ently of our thought of them—in this regard not so different from the early
views of Moore and Russell, and as plausibly considered a form of Platonic
idealism as of realism, that is, a realism about ideas. Collingwood rejected
the reality of propositions as abstract objects, and instead held that human
thought must be understood in terms of questions and answers: in real
contexts of inquiry, real people ask real questions, including about their
presuppositions, although not about their absolute presuppositions, and
arrive at real answers to them (Collingwood 1939: 44–52). In his
Autobiography, Collingwood tells a charming story of how he arrived at
this view. On his walk in London to and from the Admiralty Intelligence
176
Division, where he worked during World War I, he would pass the Albert
Memorial. He thought it “loathsome,” but he could not believe that its
designer had set out to create something ugly. So he finally asked himself,
what had the designer (Sir George Gilbert Scott) thought that he was doing:
what problem had he set himself, what question had he asked, to which he
could have thought this was the answer? (Collingwood 1939: 29–43;
Collingwood was only 49 when he wrote this, but he had already suffered
a major stroke and knew he could not count on a long life.) Collingwood’s
approach is not metaphysical idealism, but it does show a strong faith in
human rationality: the presumption is always that human beings have what
they think is a good reason for doing what they do, and the task of an
interlocutor, whether a historian, a philosopher, or another person in
everyday life is to figure out what that reason is. Something like this is
what has come to be called the principle of charity.
In Collingwood’s philosophy of history, he calls this process “re-
enactment” (Collingwood 1946). This might be thought to mean that the
historian is to literally re-create the original event in her mind, but it does
not really mean anything metaphysical like that: it just means that the task of
the historian is to put herself into the shoes of her subject, try to see the
situation as the protagonist did and to figure out why the protagonist
thought that what she did—starting this campaign, instituting this law,
etc.—was the right thing to do—and only then, if at all, to judge how wise
the protagonist was. So Collingwood’s doctrine of historical re-enactment is
not a metaphysical or ontological form of idealism. The closest that
Collingwood seems to come to metaphysical idealism is in the first part of
his Principles of Art (Collingwood 1938) where, in distinguishing (fine) art
from mere craft, he dismisses the creation of a physical medium for a work
of art from the creation of the work itself, a mere engineering puzzle, and
thinks of the latter as complete in the mind or imagination of the artist. But
this is best seen as an extreme way of stating that the artist’s conception of
what she is trying to do—what question she is posing and what she thinks
the answer is—is a necessary condition of making a work of art (an antic-
ipation of Arthur Danto’s later view that a work of art exists only within a
theory of art); in any case, as the book proceeds, Collingwood makes it clear
that the artist’s task is to find a way to express an emotion in a medium
accessible to others (Part Two), and that the artist’s work typically pro-
gresses in interaction with a public and in many cases (e.g., painting,
sculpture) physical medium. As the artist works, she steps back and looks
at what she has done, modifies it in response, and so on until she is satisfied
177
with the result, at least for the time: it is a physical as well as a mental process,
that takes place in a physical as well as a mental world. Even Collingwood’s
aesthetics is not a metaphysical form of idealism. (On Collingwood gener-
ally, see Mink 1969; Duessen 1981; D’Oro 2002; Dharamsi, D’Oro, and
Leach eds. 2018. On Collingwood’s philosophy of art, see Guyer 2014: 3:
189–233.)
There has been increasing interest in the work of Collingwood in recent
years, going hand in hand with publication of much additional material. But
in his lifetime and mostly since Collingwood has not been regarded as part
of the mainstream of anglophone, analytic philosophy. In that mainstream,
the label of “idealist” has generally been rejected, with horror, although it is
our view that at least the epistemological motivation toward idealism has
continued to be active, even powerful. To trace its subterranean presence of
at least epistemological idealism throughout the remainder of twentieth-
century philosophy would exceed the scope of this book. But we will now
offer some examples of leading twentieth-century philosophers who were
influenced by idealist epistemology, at least at the beginning through trans-
mission from Neo-Kantianism, as well as a few outliers who were actually
willing to identify themselves as metaphysical idealists.
Neo-Kantianism influenced the broader stream of analytic philosophy
most strongly through the work of Rudolf Carnap (1891–1970), whose
Logical Construction of the World (1928) analyzes knowledge in terms of
relations constructed on perceived similarities in qualities of objects, thus
taking a subjectivist starting point and then adding constructive activities of
the mind to it—a form of epistemological idealism (see Carus 2007: espe-
cially ch. 4; as well as Friedman 1999 and 2000). Nelson Goodman’s
(1906–98) Structure of Appearance (1951) undertook a similar project.
Subsequent to the Logical Construction, in influential work in the 1930s
(e.g., Carnap 1937), Carnap distinguished between questions “internal” to a
conceptual framework or system and “external” questions about which
conceptual framework to adopt, which can be decided only on pragmatic
or even aesthetic grounds, and this too might be considered a form of
epistemological idealism, although it also demonstrates the interrelation of
epistemologically motivated idealism with pragmatism that we observed
going back to Peirce and Royce. Thomas Kuhn’s (1922–96) famous concep-
tion of “paradigms” of science which are not automatically rejected
because of refractory evidence but are given up only when an alternative
paradigm comes to seem preferable can be seen as being in the
Carnapian tradition (Kuhn 1962), as can Hilary Putnam’s (1926–2016)
178
“internal realism” of the 1980s (Putnam 1981), and both these positions thus
reflect the continuing influence of the epistemological motivation for ideal-
ism. Even W. V. O. Quine (1908–2000), who was a committed physicalist in
the sense of believing that other sciences are in principle reducible to
physics, nevertheless shared an aspect of idealist epistemology in his con-
ception of the “web of belief,” that is, the idea that knowledge consists in a
body of beliefs, from particular observation statements up to logical princi-
ples, which faces experience only as a whole and which can be modified at
any point within it in order to accommodate refractory experience, as
seems best (see Quine and Ullian 1970). As we have seen, similar ideas
were already to be found in Cassirer’s Substance and Function and
Collingwood’s Essay on Metaphysics. Wilfrid Sellars’s conception of the
“space of reasons,” taken up in Robert Brandom’s inferentialism, also
reflects this impulse, although Sellars always considered himself, like his
father, a scientific realist, and his most explicitly Kantian work, Science and
Metaphysics (1968), gives what might be regarded as a pragmatist rather
than idealist spin to Kant’s phenomena/noumena distinction, interpreting
the noumenal as what would be known if science were complete, an idea
clearly inspired by Charles Sanders Peirce—although also found in
Hermann Cohen and not completely different in spirit from Royce’s idea
that the error of our particular beliefs can be understood only by comparison
to a body of complete and completely true beliefs, not to some independent,
non-belief reality. These are just a few examples of how some of the
most prominent paradigms, to borrow Kuhn’s term, of analytic philosophy
still reflect the impulse to epistemological idealism even though the name
“idealism” was anathematized by Moore, Russell, and the New Realists.
A few anglophone philosophers have been willing to identify themselves
as idealists. Before we continue on to consider some of those who have not
been but have nevertheless been influenced by idealist epistemology, let us
look at a few of those. One mid-twentieth-century philosopher who had no
qualms about identifying himself as an idealist was Brand Blanshard
(1892–1987). The difference between Blanshard and many of the mid-
twentieth-century analytic philosophers is precisely that Blanshard accepted
the assumption that there must be a necessary isomorphism between
knowledge and its object, and so was not content to posit something real
outside of the web of belief or space of reasons, but brought reality into the
realm of thought.
Blanshard was an undergraduate at the University of Michigan, then won
a Rhodes scholarship to Merton College, Oxford, where his tutor was
179
It is hard to see . . . how anyone could consistently take coherence as the test
of truth unless he also took it as a character of reality. (1939: 2: 267)
(i) that all things are causally related, directly or indirectly; (ii) that being
causally related involves being logically related. (1939: 2: 492)
The aim of thought from its very beginning . . . was at understanding. The
ideal of complete understanding would be achieved only when this system
that rendered it necessary was not a system that itself was fragmentary and
contingent, but one that was all-inclusive and so organized internally that
every part was linked to every other by intelligible necessity . . . . If our
account of the end is accepted, it will be found to throw light backward
along the whole course of the inquiry. For it presents the goal which
thought, from its first stirrings in perception, has more or less unknowingly
been seeking, the end potential in every idea, the whole implicitly at work
181
and what Sprigge called “panpsychism.” In both cases their defenses were
based on the epistemological premise that the object of perception is fully
present in the act of perception; Sprigge added the argument that we must
presuppose some noumenal ground for our phenomenal objects; but unlike
Kant, who after he stripped things in themselves of their spatiality and/or
temporality, insisted that we remain otherwise agnostic about their nature,
Sprigge argued for
the noumenal backing or “in itself” of the physical by saying that it consists
in innumerable mutually interacting centres of experience, or, what comes
to the same, of pulses and flows of experience. (Sprigge 1983: 85)
appropriately sized natural bodies like trees or stars or atoms on the other,
standing in various physical (e.g., spatial, temporal, causal) and mental (e.g.,
conceptual, judgmental, inferential) relations. By not questioning this
framework, the discussion of the ultimate constitution of reality and of
our knowledge of it was thus restricted to an exchange of opinions and
arguments as to what kind of substance, physical or mental, is better suited
to do justice to our most cherished epistemological and metaphysical beliefs
regarding the circumference and the limits of what we know and what we
cannot know about the world. As we have been suggesting, this discussion
led to an impasse because it turned out that traces of epistemological
idealism could be found even in the supposedly realistic, materialistic,
and/or naturalistic positions, just as well as aspects of realism and natural-
ism remained in philosophies that explicitly endorse metaphysical idealism
(again, think of Schelling, Green, and Royce).
However, the twentieth century was not a period only of regression in
metaphysics and epistemology to pre-Kantian idealism. One can also
observe that especially in the non-English-speaking, “continental” world a
renewed interest in what could be called a reshaping of idealistic conceptions
under different brand names like Vitalism, Phenomenology, Existentialism
took place. But these tendencies emerged not only on the “Continent.” They
also appeared in Anglo-American contexts around the second half of the last
century. Although it is difficult to tell what exactly initiated this change in
attitude, two motives are obvious: the acknowledgment of the constitutive
function of a social dimension not only in all our practical dealings with
reality but also in our theoretical approach to the world, and the move away
from talk about the mental to a language that favors terms like “the
conceptual” or “conceptuality” instead. A reason for this shift might have
been that talk about the conceptual is less prone to give rise to psychological
connotations that are invariably connected with a mentalistic vocabulary
(and were already rejected by nineteenth-century philosophers like Frege,
Husserl, and Cohen) and because of a closer affinity to linguistic practices
that are supposed to govern our conceptual activities. Looking at Anglo-
American philosophy of the last seventy years or so against the background
of a new orientation fueled by motivations like the two mentioned, it is not
that surprising that elements of Hegel’s idealism, especially his conceptual
realism connected with his social conception of what he calls “Spirit,”
became of interest again. At any rate, with the exception of Wittgenstein
all of the better-known representatives of positions that integrate concep-
tuality and sociality into their epistemological and metaphysical teachings
185
true and false can be made. This, at least, indicates the direction in which
Wittgenstein’s reflections tend to move (cf. §§94, 162).
These foundational tendencies in Wittgenstein’s considerations already
provide a lot of material that from an idealistic point of view could be seen as
highly reminiscent of idealist epistemology if not ontology, as our compar-
isons with Collingwood already suggest. After all, already the mental con-
notations to which the very concept of a Weltbild is prone to give rise and
the grounding function that is attributed to it can easily remind not only the
idealist of traditional tendencies in idealistic theories to favor mind-
dependence of the world in one form or another in the attempt to account
for the possibility of knowledge. Idealistic tendencies could also be detected
in what is called here Wittgenstein’s contextualism, that is, his view that a
Weltbild is not a stable, unchanging arrangement of a number of different
beliefs, convictions, attitudes, and dispositions but forms a coherent system
that varies in accordance with circumstances. Rather than being conceived
of as the expression of a collection of eternal truths, it has to be characterized
as only the provider of an ever-changing context within which a knowledge-
claim can be evaluated as true, false, or meaningless. Wittgenstein does not
clearly explain how such Weltbilder understood in this contextual sense
come about and what makes them change. The leading idea seems to be that
a Weltbild can be assessed from at least two very different perspectives, from
a personal, subjective stance and a non-personal, objective one. In both cases
it proves to be a flexible, almost amorphous structure that is shaped by and
in accordance with many factors ranging from experiences via learning
processes to social and cultural circumstances. Looked at from a personal
point of view a Weltbild is the by and large obscure and rarely directly
available background against which a person forms her judgments about
what is the case or not. What is contained in this background, the beliefs,
convictions, and attitudes to which the subject is ultimately committed, is
something of which that subject is not immediately aware but what it has to
find out by paying attention to what in the end it is unable and unwilling to
put into question (cf. §512). In what exactly these background assumptions
consist seems to be impossible to tell in advance because they are revealed in
processes the significance of which depends largely on the context in which a
knowledge-claim is made. It is easy to imagine situations in which a person
is surprised about what turns out to be an item she cannot but hold on to
unshakably. This is so because our life is embedded in our Weltbild, “it is
there—like our life” (§559). In the case of a non-personal, objective per-
spective a Weltbild understood as the totality of beliefs and attitudes that
190
cannot be given up though they are not based on grounds (cf. §§410f.) is
subject to random and incidental changes because of its dependence-
relation to historical, cultural, and other social contexts. Which set of
items the participants of a specific culture in a particular historical situation
are prepared to defend by all means, that is, which Weltbild will be dominant
at a certain time, will be influenced by many factors. Some have to do with
the varying degrees in which the members of a life-form take science,
religion and other ideological institutions to provide justifying reasons for
knowledge-claims. However, most of these factors will determine what sort
of experience can count as evidence in what context. Consequently, a
Weltbild understood as a system of evidence is dependent again on processes
and practices that are steadily in flux and hence cannot be established as a
stable context for once and for all (cf. §§105, 136, 140, 350). The picture that
emerges is that epistemically accessible reality, that is, reality understood as
the context in which knowledge-claims can be substantiated, turns out to be
what a knower cannot but help to take for granted (cf. §87). Traces of
idealism can easily be found in this line of reasoning. In particular, the
assumption that knowledge-claims are not grounded in hard facts but find
their legitimation in a somewhat opaque web of beliefs (cf. §225) and
attitudes that ultimately reflects subjective evidences can be seen as pointing
in this direction. The expression “web of belief” of course reminds us of
Quine; at the same time, it might be worth mentioning that if one is willing
to share the perspective that this Wittgensteinian line of thought opens up
then Michel Foucault’s research program for an Archaeology of Knowledge
(1969) also emerges at the horizon: in order to find out what a Weltbild
consists in, how it changes and eventually gives rise to a new one, one has to
look at statements (énoncées) and the changing conditions of their mean-
ingful use in a manner that is informed by how an archaeologist tackles her
pre-historic findings. The line between “analytic” and “continental” philos-
ophy is not always as sharp as is sometimes thought.
What could be called idealistic tendencies that emphasize the mind-
dependence of what we take to be reality also play a major role in what is
called here, perhaps somewhat uncomfortably, Wittgenstein’s social empir-
icism. What is meant by this term is the view that he discusses repeatedly in
On Certainty that the respective Weltbilder are constituted by what is
revealed through or becomes manifest in what is accepted in a given social
context as empirical evidence on which a knowledge-claim is based. Such a
position is a version of empiricism because it gives precedence to experience
as a source of evidence. It is a social empiricism in that it takes what counts
191
I would have to put my entire system of beliefs into question. This piece of
evidence is for me beyond doubt and I hold fast to it under all circum-
stances” (cf. e.g., §§69–75, 245–8, 279). It is at this point in the process of
defending a knowledge-claim against skeptical doubts that the knower
singles out an item of empirical evidence that cannot be doubted because
she is not willing or prepared to do so. Hence there are empirical proposi-
tions that are taken to be certain although there is no justifying reason
available to the person who relies on them (cf. §§111f., 401). The sum
total of these indisputable propositions make up the Weltbild of a person,
the background against which everything else is affirmed or denied
(cf. §§105, 514).
The outcome of Wittgenstein’s analysis of this process is not just the
obvious contention that each holder of a knowledge-claim, each individual
knower, is equipped with a collection of empirical propositions that for her
individually are indubitable pieces of empirical evidence, or that each person
has their own private Weltbild. His main objective seems to have been more
ambitious and leads again to the question of the constitution of Weltbilder.
From what has been outlined so far, it is safe to say that each individual lives
within a personal Weltbild that functions as the foundation of her
knowledge-claims. Wittgenstein complements this finding with suggestions
about the motives a person might have for sticking to certain propositions
unconditionally. His remarks on this point hint at an attempt to integrate
social aspects into his views on Weltbild-constitution. He very likely holds
that only those propositions are convincing candidates for incontestable
beliefs of a person and hence indicative of their Weltbild that she considers
to be shared by and with others (cf. §§144, 280ff.).
This stance fits well into Wittgenstein’s general outlook regarding the
interplay between a Weltbild and a knowledge-claim. He seems to reckon
that for an ordinary knowledge-claim to become controversial there always
has to be some community or other in which the claim is put forward
(cf. §298). Otherwise it could not be challenged. Thus the task of defending
a claim by relying on empirical evidence expressed in empirical propositions
already appeals to social constellations. Furthermore, for a person even to
assume of an empirical proposition that it cannot but be true presupposes
that there is a publicly accessible source for this conviction. A person who
sticks unconditionally to some conviction or other must be prepared to
answer questions about the origin and the source of this conviction not just
to others but also to herself. She might point to a teacher, to something she
has read in a scientific book, or even to God as a source that for her
193
traditional dualisms in metaphysics. But that is what many others who were
willing to call themselves idealists in some sense, for example, “critical
idealists,” had been doing since the time of Neo-Kantianism, if not since
the period of so-called German Idealism itself.
A way of tackling problems in epistemology and metaphysics that can
also be seen as having idealistic undertones has been pursued especially in
the American philosophical scene in the second half of the twentieth
century. Prominent representatives of these new approaches include
Wilfrid Sellars and John McDowell. They come to mind most readily
because they explicitly connect their theories with elements of what they
take to be philosophical messages and insights of major positions in classical
German philosophy, especially of Kant’s epistemology (Sellars) and Hegel’s
metaphysics (McDowell). This does not mean that they deal with these
classical views in a literal sense, although they have both done detailed
interpretative work on Kant and/or Hegel. Rather, within their own philo-
sophical projects they refer to these historical predecessors to a certain
extent in order to pay homage to the influence of Kant’s and Hegel’s ideas
on their own themes and topics.
At first sight it may seem far-fetched to detect idealist motives in the
philosophical work of Sellars. In his “Autobiographical Reflections” he states
as his goal in philosophy “to formulate a scientifically oriented, naturalistic
realism which would ‘save the appearances’ ” (289), a statement that led his
one-time student Willem deVries to “call his philosophy of science a ‘prag-
matic realism’ because he insists on our commitment to the reality of the
objects to be posited by Peircean ideal science, while explicating most of the
structural features of science in terms of the pragmatic force of their
linguistic expression” (deVries 2021). Talk about realism, whether natural-
istic or pragmatic, seems antithetical to idealistic tendencies. However, when
we take into account the results and implications of Sellars’s famous criti-
cism of what he calls the “Myth of the Given” and his equally renowned
distinction between what he calls the manifest and the scientific image of
man-in-the-world a different picture emerges, a picture that can indeed raise
idealistic sentiments, especially if one keeps in mind what was emphasized
in the foregoing chapters that since the days of Kant and Hegel the priority
of the conceptual has become a distinguishing mark of positions that can be
considered idealist at least epistemologically if not metaphysically.
The topic of the priority of the conceptual over and against the non-
conceptual in contexts in which knowledge-claims are at stake plays a
central role in Sellars’s discussion of the shortcomings of sense-datum
195
Sellars rejects this framework by insisting that epistemic facts like empirical
knowledge-claims cannot be “analyzed without remainder” (§5) into non-
epistemic facts consisting of inner episodes of sensations and impressions
that can have a founding function. This is by no means meant to imply that
he rejects the idea of a foundation of knowledge tout court. On the contrary,
empirical knowledge claims are in one way or another causally related to
what is “out there” (cf. Sellars 1997: §29), thus having their roots in a
subject-independent reality. What has to be given up is, according to
Sellars, the misguided belief that “the fundamental associative tie between
language and the world must be between words and ‘immediate experi-
ences’ ” (ibid.) in the form of inner episodes. Sellars sketches out how this
belief comes about by providing a mythological story of a prehistoric
philosophical ancestor named Jones who somehow manages to develop
the idea of inner episodes out of an original interpretation of “intelligent
196
science of our time tells us. However, Sellars, contrary to Hegel but like other
figures we have considered beginning with the Neo-Kantians, does not
believe in a static and unchangeable set of reality-constituting concepts
and categories. For him science is embedded in an ever-changing historical
process in the course of which new categories and concepts turn up.
Hence at any specific point in history reality is revealed in new conceptual
clothes. But—and this is indeed reminiscent of Hegel—the so to speak
metaphysical fact remains that what there is is ultimately constituted by
variable and time-dependent concepts and categories. In the case of Hegel
they have their roots in purely conceptual requirements, in the case of Sellars
they are the result of scientific research where science is understood as an
ensemble of social practices.
Another much discussed attempt that could be read as integrating ideal-
istic motives into an account of the possibility of empirical knowledge, an
attempt that also hopes to overcome the opposition between idealism and
several forms of realism, is outlined by John McDowell in his influential
book Mind and World, which first appeared in 1994. McDowell sets up his
approach to the problem of empirical knowledge within a framework that
goes back to Kant in both terminology and substance: Empirical knowledge-
claims based on experience have to be seen as the joint product of the
faculties of sensibility and the understanding. Sensibility is a passive faculty
that is responsible for receptivity, that is, for the ability of the knower to
receive data passively from a subject-independent “outside” reality. The
understanding is an active faculty that is rooted in the spontaneity of the
knower and provides conceptual structures on the basis of which these data
from the outside are transformed into empirical judgments. McDowell
stresses that he follows Kant (1) in calling these abilities receptivity and
spontaneity respectively, (2) in attributing them to the faculties of sensibility
and the understanding, and (3) in taking them to be conditions of experi-
ence and empirical knowledge. With these Kantian tools in place he can
formulate his leading question: how to establish a theory of empirical
knowledge that accepts this Kantian analysis and that at the same time
can avoid the deficiencies that are connected with what he takes to be two
palpable although misleading attempts to respond to Kant’s claim about the
nature of empirical knowledge? The first is the attempt to conceive of the
data received from “outside” reality via receptivity as something that is non-
conceptually given. According to McDowell, this maneuver gives rise to the
problems that were outlined by Sellars in his criticism of the Myth of the
Given. The second tactic is to deny that in the case of knowledge there is
198
McDowell is perfectly well aware that his suggestion might easily invoke
the charge of idealism, “in the sense in which to call a position ‘idealism’ is to
protest that it does not genuinely acknowledge how reality is independent of
our thinking” (1994: 26)—not a metaphysical insistence that reality is
ultimately mental, but the epistemological position that we can never
know reality except as it appears to us. The reasoning behind this worry
might be outlined thus: if conceptual activities are rooted in the spontaneity
of the understanding then they must be considered as subjective contribu-
tions of the cognizing subject, contributions that are independent of the
world. This leaves both “outside” and “inside” reality, like Kant’s “outer” and
“inner” senses, a conceptual construct of some mind or other, and this is
exactly the way the idealist wants us to think of the world. However, in
McDowell’s eyes this charge is misguided in his case because he has a story
to tell as to why conceptual content is already present in the deliverances of
passive experiences, that is, in the impressions from an outside and subject-
independent world, a story that does allow conceptual content to be part of
how the world impinges on us.
McDowell’s account turns around our understanding of the concept of
nature. According to him there are two ways of thinking about nature that
are both deeply rooted in the history of Western philosophy. The first is the
distinctively modern view that tries to make nature intelligible as an object
governed by natural laws. This modern stance is realized by relying on the
tools and methods provided by natural science. From this perspective, one is
committed to the assumption that receptivity is a natural capacity whose
deliverances are determined by natural laws. This means that it becomes
impossible to integrate conceptual spontaneity into nature. After all, con-
ceptual spontaneity as a capacity sui generis is supposed to be non-natural,
that is, to be independent from natural receptivity. The second way
of thinking about nature goes back to “a common medieval outlook”
(1994: 71) according to which the intelligibility of nature depends on the
degree to which human beings can make sense of and see meaning in nature
by relying on what we experience. The attitude here is to look at nature “as if
all of nature were a book of lessons for us” (ibid.). Nature thus conceived
presents itself to us as something that is not alien to knowledge but is
structured in a meaningful way that is expressed in conceptual relations,
relations whose actual presence is documented in what human beings
experience, namely that “that things are thus and so.” In order to highlight
the contrast that he wants to emphasize McDowell alludes to Max Weber’s
metaphorical distinction between enchanted and disenchanted nature
200
This is a short book, and we have not been completely sparing of judgment
along the way. So there should not be any need for an extensive summary of
what we have said nor for an extended evaluation of the views we have
discussed. But some concluding words might not be amiss.
The legacy of idealism in modern philosophy is ambivalent. On the one
hand, the metaphysical thesis of idealism proper as we have defined it,
namely that reality is ultimately mental in character, in the end does not
seem very promising: We do not have a clear enough idea about what the
mental ultimately is, nor about how it could subsist entirely on its own, to
make such a reduction either adequately informative or adequately plausi-
ble. The everlasting obscurity of the idea of the mental is well documented in
the foregoing pages. The shift from God in Berkeley to the Concept in Hegel
to the Absolute in Schelling, Bradley, and Royce as paradigms or instantia-
tions of the mental bears witness to this. Yet the same could also be said
about physicalism: We do not have a clear enough idea about what the
physical ultimately is, nor about how it could ground, cause, or explain the
undeniable fact of our own consciousness, to speak of nothing else, to make
a physicalist reductionism of the mental any more informative or plausible
than a mentalistic reduction of the physical. This can easily be illustrated
from the case of the recent discovery of the Higgs boson particle. Physicists,
or at least science journalists, celebrated this as solving the mystery of
matter, namely what binds particles together: namely, another particle.
Philosophers, taught by Kant to use the “skeptical method” even if they
need not end up as skeptics (see “The Discipline of Pure Reason,” CPuR
A 738–57/B 766–85), are paid to doubt assertions like this, and there are
obvious problems with the claim: First, what does it really mean to call
something a “particle” that is supposed to exist only for a tiny fraction of a
second—why not just call it a moment in a process? Second, how can a
particle be the ultimate answer to what holds particles together? In antiquity,
Plato’s theory of forms met with what is called the “Third Man” objection—
actually, Plato raised it himself. Namely, if an ordinary particular object is
what it is because it resembles a form—a particular human being is one
Idealism in Modern Philosophy. Paul Guyer and Rolf-Peter Horstmann, Oxford University Press.
© Paul Guyer and Rolf-Peter Horstmann 2023. DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780192848574.003.0011
204
because it resembles the Form of the Human, a bed because it resembles the
Form of the Bed—don’t we need yet another form, the Form of
Resemblance, to see that the particular resembles the first form? And then
yet another Form of Resemblance to see that this second case of resemblance
is in fact a case of resemblance? And so on. Be that as it may, and however
compelling you might think the theory of the Higgs boson particle is,
philosophers should properly be wary of claims to have discovered the
ultimate nature of reality. The problem is not so much with either the
mental or the physical as it is with the claim to know how things ultimately
are. This is another lesson we should have learned from Kant. The result of
his Antinomy of Pure Reason is that while it is the nature of human reason
to seek the “unconditioned,” that which needs no further explanation or
ground, and that idea—Idea of Pure Reason, as he calls it—may have an
indispensable use in practical philosophy, where we must regard the moral
law as unconditionally valid, binding us even when we would vehemently
prefer otherwise, it has no use within the theoretical sphere: whatever might
seem the most fundamental level of explanation in our currently best
scientific theories might itself be further explained, at some point and in
some way that we cannot even currently even imagine. Science, and by this
we mean all well-founded, or not yet refuted, claims to knowledge, is never
more than our currently best explanation, and it is sheer intellectual effron-
tery to claim more than that.
On the other hand, there seems to be something profoundly right, even
inescapable, about at least the epistemological argument for idealism: Of
course we experience the world from the human point of view, and must
perceive and conceive it through our own faculties of perception and
conception. In a way, this is just a tautology: Our experience is after all
our experience, or, as Kant once again put it, the conditions of the possibility
of our experience are the conditions of the possibility of the objects of our
experience. Objects in the most general sense are what we experience, so of
course they are as we experience them. How else could we experience them?
Indeed, even when we scientifically and experimentally investigate the
perceptual and cognitive systems of organisms other than homo sapiens,
when we discover that dogs can hear acoustic frequencies that we cannot,
that insects with their multi-lensed eyes or arachnids with their more than
two eyes must perceive the world differently than we do, we still have to
interpret their experience in terms of our own—we cannot simply have their
experience, though we try to imagine it from our point of view. To be sure,
Kant’s philosophy was not confined to this triviality: he took the crucial step
205
Bradley, Francis Herbert, 1914, Essays on Truth and Reality, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Bradley, Francis Herbert, 1935, Collected Essays, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Brandom, Robert, 1994, Making It Explicit: Reasoning, Representing, and Discursive
Commitment, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Caird, Edward, 1879, “Mr. Balfour on Transcendentalism,” Mind, old series, 4(13):
111–14. doi:10.1093/mind/os-4.13.111.
Caird, Edward, 1883, Hegel, Edinburgh: William Blackwood.
Caird, Edward, 1889, The Critical Philosophy of Immanuel Kant, 2 vols., Glasgow:
James Maclehose.
Caird, Edward, 1892, Essays on Literature and Philosophy, 2 vols., Glasgow: James
Maclehose.
Caird, Edward, 1893, The Evolution of Religion, Glasgow: James Maclehose.
Caird, Edward, 1904, The Evolution of Theology in the Greek Philosophers, Glasgow:
James Maclehose.
Carnap, Rudolf, 1928, Der logische Aufbau der Welt, Leipzig: Felix Meiner Verlag;
translated as The Logical Structure of the World, Rolf A. George (trans.). Second
edition, LaSalle, IL: Open Court, 2003.
Carnap, Rudolf, 1937, The Logical Syntax of Language, London: Routledge & Kegan
Paul.
Cassirer, Ernst, [ECW], 1998–2009, Gesammalte Werke, Birgit Recki (ed.), 26 vols.,
Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag.
Cassirer, Ernst, 1906–57, Das Erkenntnisproblem in der Philosophie und Wissenschaft
der neueren Zeit. ECW vols. 2–5.
Cassirer, Ernst, 1910–21, Substance and Function and Einstein’s Theory of Relativity,
William Curtis Swabey and Marie Collins Swabey (trans.), Chicago: Open Court,
1923.
Cassirer, Ernst, 1923–9, The Philosophy of Symbolic Forms, Ralph Manheim (trans.),
3 vols., New Haven and London: Yale University Press, 1953–9.
Cassirer, Ernst, 1927, The Individual and the Cosmos in Renaissance Philosophy,
Mario Domani (trans.), New York: Harper, 1963.
Cassirer, Ernst, 1932, The Philosophy of the Enlightenment, Fritz C. A. Koelln and
James A. Pettegrove (trans.), Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Cassirer, Ernst, 1936, Determinism and Indeterminism in Modern Physics: Historical
and Systematic Studies of the Problem of Causation, O. Theodore Benfey (trans.),
New Haven: Yale University Press, 1956.
Cassirer, Ernst, 1942, The Logic of the Cultural Sciences, S. G. Lofts (trans.), New
Haven: Yale University Press, 2000.
Cassirer, Ernst, 1944, An Essay on Man, New Haven: Yale University Press.
Cassirer, Ernst, 1946a, The Myth of the State, New Haven: Yale University Press,
2009.
Cassirer, Ernst, 1946b, Language and Myth, Susanne K. Langer (trans.), New York:
Harper & Brothers.
Cassirer, Ernst, 1957, The Problem of Knowledge: Philosophy, Science, and History
since Hegel, William H. Woglom and Charles W. Hendel (trans.), New Haven:
Yale University Press.
209
Cassirer, Ernst, 1996, The Philosophy of Symbolic Forms, vol. 4, John Michael Krois
and Donald Philip Verene (eds.), New Haven: Yale University Press.
Cohen, Hermann, 1871, Kants Theorie der Erfahrung, Berlin: F. Dümmler.
Cohen, Hermann, 1877, Kants Begründung der Ethik, Berlin: F. Dümmler.
Cohen, Hermann, 1883, Das Princip der Infinitesmal-Method und seine Geschichte,
Berlin: F. Dümmler.
Cohen, Hermann, 1889, Kants Begründung der Ästhetik, Berlin: F. Dümmler.
Cohen, Hermann, 1902, Logik des reinen Erkenntnis, Berlin: Bruno Cassirer.
Cohen, Hermann, 1904, Ethik des reinen Willens, Berlin: Bruno Cassirer.
Cohen, Hermann, 1912, Ästhetik des reinen Gefühls, Berlin: Bruno Cassirer.
Cohen, Hermann, 1919, Religion der Vernunft aus den Quellen des Judentums, Berlin:
Bruno Cassirer.
Collier, Arthur, 1713 [1909], Clavis Universalis: Or, A New Inquiry after Truth, Being
a Demonstration of the Non-Existence, or Impossibility, of an External World,
London: Gosling. Reprinted Ethel Bowman (ed.), LaSalle, IL: Open Court.
Collingwood, Robin George, 1924, Speculum Mentis, or The Map of Knowledge,
Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Collingwood, Robin George, 1933, An Essay on Philosophical Method, Oxford:
Clarendon Press.
Collingwood, Robin George, 1938, The Principles of Art, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Collingwood, Robin George, 1939, An Autobiography, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Revised edition, David Boucher and Teresa Smith (eds.), 2013.
Collingwood, Robin George, 1940, An Essay on Metaphysics, Oxford: Clarendon
Press. Revised edition, Rex Martin (ed.), 1998.
Collingwood, Robin George, 1942, The New Leviathan. Revised edition, David
Boucher (ed.), Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992.
Collingwood, Robin George, 1945, The Idea of Nature, T. M. Knox (ed.), Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Collingwood, Robin George, 1946, The Idea of History, T. M. Knox (ed.), Oxford:
Oxford University Press. Revised edition, W. J. van der Dussen (ed.), Oxford:
Clarendon Press, 1992.
Croce, Benedetto, 1902, Aesthetic as the Science of Expression and General Linguistic,
Douglas W. Ainslie (trans.), London: Macmillan, 1909.
Croce, Benedetto, 1905, Logic as the Science of the Pure Concept, Douglas W. Ainslie
(trans.), London: Macmillan, 1917.
Croce, Benedetto, 1907, What Is Living and What Is Dead in the Philosophy of Hegel,
Douglas W. Ainslie (trans.), London: Macmillan, 1915.
Croce, Benedetto, 1909, Philosophy of Practice, Economics, and Ethics, Douglas
W. Ainslie (trans.), London: Macmillan, 1913.
Croce, Benedetto, 1911, The Philosophy of Giambattista Vico, R. G. Collingwood
(trans.), London: Latimer, 1913.
Croce, Benedetto, 1917, Theory and History of Historiography, Douglas W. Ainslie
(trans.), London: Harrop, 1921.
Croce, Benedetto, 1918, Autobiography, R. G. Collingwood (trans.), Oxford:
Clarendon Press, 1927.
210
Davidson, Donald, 1984, “On the Very Idea of a Conceptual Scheme,” in his Inquiries
into Truth and Interpretation, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 183–98.
Davidson, Donald, 2001, Essays on Actions and Events. Second edition, Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Descartes, René, c.1628, Regulae ad directionem ingenii (Rules for the Direction of the
Mind), unpublished in his lifetime. Translated and printed in his Philosophical
Writings 1: 7–78.
Descartes, René, 1637, Discours de la méthode pour bien conduire sa raison, et
chercher la vérité dans les sciences (Discourse on the Method of Rightly
Conducting One’s Reason and of Seeking Truth in the Sciences), Leiden.
Translated and printed in his Philosophical Writings 1: 109–76.
Descartes, René, 1641, Meditationes de prima philosophia, in qua Dei existentia et
animæ immortalitas demonstratur (Meditations on First Philosophy), Paris.
Translated and printed in his Philosophical Writings 2: 1–61.
Descartes, René, 1644, Principia philosophiae (Principles of Philosophy), Amsterdam:
Elzevir. Translated and printed in his Philosophical Writings 1: 177–292.
Descartes, René, 1985–91, The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, John Cottingham,
Robert Stoothoff, Dugald Murdoch, and Anthony Kenny (eds.), 3 vols.,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Falckenberg, Richard, 1886, Geschichte der neueren Philosophie von Nikolaus von
Kues bis zur Gegenwart, Leipzig: Veit. Second edition, 1892.
Feder, Johann and Christian Garve, 1782, “Critik der reinen Vernunft Von Immanuel
Kant,” Zugabe zu den Göttingischen Anzeigen von gelehrten Sachen, 3. Stück,
19 January 1782, pp. 40–8. Translated in Sassen 2000: 53–8.
Feyerabend, Paul, 1975, Against Method: Outline of an Anarchistic Theory of
Knowledge, New York: Humanities Press.
Fichte, Johann Gottlieb, 1794/5, Grundlage der gesamten Wissenschaftslehre, GA 1, 2.
Leipzig. Translated as Doctrine of Science or Foundations of the Science of
Knowledge.
Fichte, Johann Gottlieb, 1797a, Erste Einleitung in die Wissenschaftslehre, in
Philosophisches Journal 5: 1–47. Augsburg.
Fichte, Johann Gottlieb, 1797b, Zweite Einleitung in die Wissenschaftslehre, in
Philosophisches Journal 5: 319–78; 6: 1–40. Augsburg. Translated as First and
Second Introduction into the Doctrine of Science.
Fichte, Johann Gottlieb, [Werke] 1845–6, Johann Gottlieb Fichtes sämmtliche Werke,
Immanuel Hermann Fichte (ed.), Berlin: Veit. [Citation by volume and page
number.]
Fichte, Johann Gottlieb, [GA] 1962–2012, Gesamtausgabe der Bayerischen Akademie
der Wissenschaften, 42 vols., Reinhard Lauth, Erich Fuchs, and Hans Gliwitzky
(eds.), Stuttgart: Frommann-Holzboog. [Cited as GA followed by series, volume,
and page number.]
Foster, John, 1982, The Case for Idealism, London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Garve, Christian, 1783, “Kritik der reinen Venunft, von Immanuel Kant,” Allgemeine
deutsche Bibliothek, Anhang zu dem 37ten bis 52ten Bande, Zweite Abtheilung,
pp. 838–62. Translation in Sassen 2000: 59–77.
211
Hobbes, Thomas, 1655, De Corpore, in his Body, Man, and Citizen, Richard S. Peters
(ed.), New York: Collier Books, 1962.
Hume, David, 1739–40, A Treatise of Human Nature, David Fate and Mary J. Norton
(eds.), 2 vols., Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2007. [Cited by book, part, section, and,
sometimes, paragraph.]
Hume, David, 1748, An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, Tom
L. Beauchamp (ed.), Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2000.
Hume, David, 1874, The Philosophical Works of David Hume, T. H. Green and
T. H. Grose (eds.), 4 vols. Reprinted Aalen: Scientia Verlag, 1964.
Jacobi, Friedrich Heinrich, 1787, David Hume über den Glauben, oder Idealismus
und Realismus: ein Gespräch, Breslau: Gottlieb Löwe. Translated as David Hume
on Faith or Idealism and Realism: A Dialogue, in The Main Philosophical Writings
and the Novel “Allwill,” George di Giovanni (ed.), Montréal: McGill-Queen’s
University Press, 1994, pp. 253–338.
Kant, Immanuel, 1770, De Mundi Sensibilis atque Intelligibilis Forma et Principiis
(On the Forms and Principles of the Sensible and Intelligible Worlds), University of
Königsberg.
Kant, Immanuel, [CPuR] 1781/7, Kritik der reinen Vernunft, Riga. Translated as
Critique of Pure Reason, Paul Guyer and Allen W. Wood (trans.), Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1998.
Kant, Immanuel, 1783, Prolegomena zu einer jeden künftigen Metaphysik, die als
Wissenschaft wird auftreten können, Riga. Translated as Prolegomena to Any
Future Metaphysics, Gary Hatfield (trans. and ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1997. Also in Kant 2002.
Kant, Immanuel, [MANW], 1786. Metaphysische Anfangsgründe der Naturwissenschaft,
Riga. Translated as Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science, Michael Friedman
(trans. and ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004. Also in Kant 2002.
Kant, Immanuel, [CPJ] 1790, Kritik der Urteilskraft. Translated as Critique of the
Power of Judgment, Paul Guyer and Eric Matthews (trans.), Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2000.
Kant, Immanuel, [MM] 1797, Metaphysik der Sitten, Königsberg, translated as
Metaphysics of Morals, Mary J. Gregor (trans. and ed.). In Kant, 1996.
Kant, Immanuel, 1900–, Kants gesammelte Schriften, Royal Prussian (later German,
then Berlin-Brandenburg) Academy of Sciences (ed.), 29 vols., Berlin: Georg
Reimer, later Walter de Gruyter.
Kant, Immanuel, 1996, Practical Philosophy, Mary J. Gregor (trans. and ed.),
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Kant, Immanuel, 2002, Theoretical Philosophy after 1781, Henry E. Allison and Peter
Heath (ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002.
Kant, Immanuel, 2005, Notes and Fragments, Paul Guyer (ed.), Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Kim, Jaegwon, 1993, Supervenience and Mind, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Kuhn, Thomas S., 1962, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, Chicago: University
of Chicago Press.
Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm, c.1680–4, “Primae veritates” (First Truths), unpublished
in his lifetime. Translated in PPL: 267–71.
213
Royce, Josiah, 1885, The Religious Aspect of Philosophy: A Critique of the Bases of
Conduct and Faith, Boston: Houghton, Mifflin & Co. [Royce 1885 available online.]
Royce, Josiah, 1892, The Spirit of Modern Philosophy: An Essay in the Form of
Lectures, Boston: Houghton Mifflin Company. [Royce 1892 available online.]
Royce, Josiah, 1899–1901, The World and the Individual, First and Second Series,
2 vols., New York: MacMillan.
Royce, Josiah, 1918, The Problem of Christianity, New York: MacMillan.
Royce, Josiah, 1919, Lectures on Modern Idealism, New Haven: Yale University Press.
Russell, Bertrand, 1912 [1974], The Problems of Philosophy, Oxford: Oxford
University Press. Reprinted 1974.
Schelling, Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph, [IP] 1797 [1988], Ideen zu einer Philosophie der
Natur als Einleitung in das Studium dieser Wissenschaft, Jena and Leipzig:
Breitkopf und Härtel, in SW 1: 653ff. Translated as Ideas for a Philosophy of
Nature: As Introduction to the Study of this Science, Errol E. Harris and Peter
Heath (trans.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988. [Page numbers in
citations from the translation.]
Schelling, Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph, 1798, Von der Weltseele, eine Hypothese der
höheren Physik zur Erklärung des allgemeinen Organismus (On the World Soul: An
Hypothesis of Higher Physics for Explaining Universal Organism), Hamburg:
Perthes. In SW 1: 413ff.
Schelling, Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph, 1800, System des transcendentalen Idealismus,
Tübingen. Translated as System of Transcendental Idealism, Peter Heath (trans.),
Charlottesville, VA: University of Virginia Press, 1978.
Schelling, Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph, [SW] 1856–61, Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph
Schelling’s Sämmtliche Werke, Karl F. A. Schelling (ed.), I Abtheilung (vols.
1–10), II Abtheilung (vols. 1–4), Stuttgart: Cotta. [Citation by volume and page
number.]
Schopenhauer, Arthur, 1813, Ueber die vierfache Wurzel des Satzes vom zureichenden
Grunde (On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason), doctoral
dissertation, Jena.
Schopenhauer, Arthur, [WWR] 1819 [2010], Die Welt als Wille und Vorstellung,
Leipzig. Translated as The World as Will and Representation, Judith Norman,
Alistair Welchman, and Christopher Janaway (trans.), Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2010. [Page numbers in citations from the translation.]
Sellars, Wilfrid, 1963, Science, Perception, and Reality, London: Routledge & Kegan
Paul.
Sellars, Wilfrid, 1968, Science and Metaphysics: Variations on Kantian Themes,
London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Sellars, Wilfrid, “Autobiographical Reflections” (February 1973), in Action,
Knowledge, and Reality: Studies in Honor of Wilfrid Sellars, H.-N. Castañeda
(ed.), Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1975, pp. 277–93.
Sellars, Wilfrid, 1997, Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind, Robert B. Brandom
(ed.), Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Smart, J. J. C., 1963, Philosophy and Scientific Realism, London: Routledge & Kegan
Paul.
216
Spinoza, Baruch, 1677, Ethics, in The Collected Works of Spinoza (vol. 1), Edwin
Curley (ed. and trans.), Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1985; see also
Spinoza: Complete Works, Samuel Shirley (trans.), Michael L. Morgan (ed.),
Indianapolis and Cambridge: Hackett Publishing Company.
Sprigge, T. L. S., 1983, The Vindication of Absolute Idealism, Edinburgh: Edinburgh
University Press.
Tarski, Alfred, 1936, “Der Wahrheitsbegriff in den formalisierten Sprachen,” Studia
Philosophica 1: 261–405, J. H. Wodger (trans.), “The Concept of Truth in
Formalized Languages,” in Tarski, Logic, Semantics, and Metamathematics:
Papers from 1923 to 1948, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Tarski, Alfred, 1944, “The Semantic Conception of Truth,” Philosophy and
Phenomenological Research 4: 431–76.
Whitehead, Alfred North, 1929, Process and Reality, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Williams, Donald Cary, 1936, “Empirical Realism,” in Williams, Principles of
Empirical Realism, Springfield, IL: Charles C. Thomas, 1986.
Windelband, Wilhelm, 1883, “On Critical and Genetic Method,” in Luft 2015.
Windelband, Wilhelm, 1894, “History and Natural Science,” in Luft 2015.
Windelband, Wilhelm, 1914, Präludien. Sixth edition, Jŏrn Born and Sebastian Luft
(eds.), Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag, 2021.
Wittgenstein, Ludwig, 1969, On Certainty, G. E. M. Anscombe and G. H. von Wright
(eds.), G. E. M. Anscombe and D. Paul (trans.), Oxford: Blackwell.
Wolff, Christian, 1720 (1751), Vernünftige Gedancken von Gott, der Welt, und der
Seele des Menschen, auch allen Dingen überhaupt, Neue Auflage hin und wieder
vermehret, Halle: Renger.
Ameriks, Karl, 1982, Kant’s Theory of Mind, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Second edition, 2000.
Ameriks, Karl, 2000a, Kant and the Fate of Autonomy: Problems in the Appropriation
of the Critical Philosophy, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/
CBO9781139173346.
Ameriks, Karl (ed.), 2000b, The Cambridge Companion to German Idealism,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CCOL0521651786.
Ameriks, Karl, 2012, Kant’s Elliptical Path, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199693689.001.0001.
Anscombe, G. E. M., 1976, “The Question of Linguistic Idealism,” Acta Fennica
Philosophica, 28: 188–215. Reprinted in her Collected Papers, Volume I: From
Parmenides to Wittgenstein, Oxford: Blackwell, 1981, pp. 112–33.
Atwell, John E., 1995, Schopenhauer on the Character of the World, Berkeley and Los
Angeles: University of California Press.
Barrett, Clifford, 1932, Contemporary Idealism in America, New York: Macmillan.
Baugh, Bruce, 2003, The French Hegel: From Surrealism to Postmodernism, London:
Routledge.
Beaney, Michael (ed.), 2013, The Oxford Handbook of the History of Analytic
Philosophy, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Beck, Lewis White, 1960, A Commentary on Kant’s Critique of Practical Reason,
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Beck, Lewis White, 1969, Early German Philosophy: Kant and His Predecessors,
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Beebee, Helen, 2006, Hume on Causation, London: Routledge.
Beiser, Frederick C., 1987, The Fate of Reason: German Philosophy from Kant to
Fichte, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Beiser, Frederick C., 2002, German Idealism: The Struggle against Subjectivism,
1791–1801, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Beiser, Frederick C., 2005, Hegel, London: Routledge.
Beiser, Frederick C., 2011, The German Historicist Tradition, Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Beiser, Frederick C., 2014a, The Genesis of Neo-Kantianism, Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Beiser, Frederick C., 2014b, Late German Idealism: Trendelenburg and Lotze, Oxford:
Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199682959.001.0001.
Beiser, Frederick C., 2018, Hermann Cohen: An Intellectual Biography, Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Berlin, Isaiah, 2013a, Three Critics of the Enlightenment: Vico, Hamann, Herder.
Second edition, Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Berlin, Isaiah, 2013b, The Roots of Romanticism. Second edition, Princeton:
Princeton University Press.
Bird, Graham, 1962, Kant’s Theory of Knowledge, London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Boucher, David and Andrew Vincent, 2012, British Idealism: A Guide for the
Perplexed, London: Continuum.
Bowie, Andrew, 1993, Schelling and Modern European Philosophy: An Introduction,
London: Routledge.
218
Boyle, Nicholas and Liz Dizley (eds.), 2013, The Impact of Idealism: The Legacy of
Post-Kantian German Thought, 4 vols., Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
See especially vol. 1.
Vol. 1: Philosophy and Natural Sciences, Karl Ameriks (vol. ed.).
Vol. 2: Historical, Social and Political Thought, John Walker (vol. ed.).
Vol. 3: Aesthetics and Literature, Christoph Jamme and Ian Cooper (vol. eds.).
Vol. 4: Religion, Nicholas Adams (vol. ed.).
Brandom, Robert B., 2000, Articulating Reasons: An Introduction to Inferentialism,
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Brandom, Robert B., 2002, Tales of the Mighty Dead: Historical Essays in the
Metaphysics of Intentionality, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Brandom, Robert B., 2009, Reason in Philosophy: Animating Ideas, Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press.
Brandom, Robert B., 2019, A Spirit of Trust: A Reading of Hegel’s Phenomenology,
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Brandt, Reinhard, 1991, Die Urteilstafel. Kant-Forschungen, vol. 4, Hamburg: Felix
Meiner Verlag.
Breazeale, Daniel, 2013, Thinking Through the “Wissenschaftslehre”: Themes from
Fichte’s Early Philosophy, Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:
oso/9780199233632.001.0001.
Bristow, William F., 2007, Hegel and the Transformation of Philosophical Critique,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Broad, C. D., 1933–8, An Examination of McTaggart’s Philosophy, 2 vols.,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Bubner, Rüdiger, 2003, The Innovations of Idealism, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511498046.
Butler, Judith, 1987, Subjects of Desire: Hegelian Reflections in Twentieth-Century
France, New York: Columbia University Press.
Campbell, Charles Arthur, 1931, Scepticism and Construction: Bradley’s Sceptical
Principle as the Basis of Constructive Philosophy, London: George Allen and
Unwin.
Campbell, Charles Arthur, 1938, “In Defence of Free-Will,” Glasgow inaugural
lecture. Reprinted in his In Defence of Free-Will, with Other Essays, London:
George Allen and Unwin, 1967.
Campbell, Charles Arthur, 1956, “Self-Activity and Its Modes,” in Contemporary
British Philosophy: Personal Statements, third series, H. D. Lewis (ed.), London:
Macmillan, pp. 85–115.
Carl, Wolfgang, 1987, Der schweigende Kant: Die Entwürfe zu einer Deduktion der
Kategorien vor 1781, Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht.
Cartwright, David E., 2010, Schopenhauer: A Biography, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Carus, A. W., 2007, Carnap and Twentieth-Century Thought: Explication as
Enlightenment, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Chalmers, David, 1996, The Conscious Mind: In Search of a Fundamental Theory,
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
219
Findlay, John N., 1970, Ascent to the Absolute, London: George Allen and Unwin.
Flew, Antony, 1961, Hume’s Philosophy of Belief, London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Flower, Elizabeth and Murray G. Murphey, 1977, A History of Philosophy in America,
2 vols., New York: G. P. Putnam and Sons.
Fogelin, Robert J., 1985, Hume’s Skepticism in the “Treatise of Hume Nature,”
London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Förster, Eckart, 2000, Kant’s Final Synthesis: An Essay on the Opus postumum,
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Förster, Eckart, 2011 [2013], 25 Jahre der Philosophie: eine systematische
Rekonstruktion, Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann. Translated as The
Twenty-Five Years of Philosophy: A Systematic Reconstruction, Brady Bowman
(trans.), Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2013.
Forster, Michael, 2008, Kant and Skepticism, Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Forster, Michael and Kristin Gjesdal (eds.), 2015, The Oxford Handbook of German
Philosophy in the Nineteenth Century, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Foster, John, 1982, The Case for Idealism, London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Franks, Paul, 2005, All or Nothing: Systematicity, Transcendental Arguments, and
Skepticism in German Idealism, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Friedman, Michael, 1999, Reconsidering Logical Positivism, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Friedman, Michael, 2000, A Parting of the Ways: Carnap, Cassirer, Heidegger,
Chicago and LaSalle, IL: Open Court.
Fulda, Hans Friedrich, 1965, Das Problem einer Einleitung in Hegels Wissenschaft der
Logik, Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann.
Fulda, Hans Friedrich, 2003, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, Munich: C. H. Beck.
Garber, Daniel, 2009, Leibniz: Body, Substance, Monad, Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Garber, Daniel and Beatrice Longuenesse (eds.), 2008, Kant and the Early Moderns,
Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Gardiner, Patrick, 1953, Schopenhauer, Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Gardner, Sebastian and Paul Franks, 2002, “From Kant to Post-Kantian German
Idealism,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume, 76:
211–46. doi:10.1111/1467-8349.00096 and doi:10.1111/1467-8349.00097.
Garrett, Don, 1997, Cognition and Commitment in Hume’s Philosophy, New York:
Oxford University Press.
Geach, Peter, 1979, Truth, Love, and Immortality: An Introduction to McTaggart’s
Philosophy, Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press.
Gentry, Gerard and Konstantin Pollok (eds.), 2019, The Imagination in German
Idealism and Romanticism, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Gjesdal, Kristin (ed.), 2016, Debates in Nineteenth-Century European Philosophy,
New York: Routledge.
Goldschmidt, Tyron and Kenneth L. Pearce (eds.), 2017, Idealism: New Essays in
Metaphysics, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Gordon, Peter E., 2010, Continental Divide: Heidegger-Cassirer-Davos, Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press.
221
Hill, R. Kevin, 2003, Nietzsche’s Critiques of the Kantian Tradition, Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Hofweber, Thomas, 2017, “Conceptual Idealism without Ontological Idealism,” in
Idealism: New Essays in Metaphysics, Tyron Goldschmidt and Kenneth L. Pearce
(eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 124–41.
Hönigswald, Richard, 1913, Grundfragen der Erkenntnislehre, Bad Godesberg: Junker
und Dünnhaupt (1966).
Hösle, Vittorio and Fernando Suárez Müller (eds.), 2015, Idealismus heute: aktuelle
Perspektiven und neue Impulse, Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft.
Horstmann, Rolf-Peter, 1984, Ontologie und Relationen: Hegel, Bradley, Russell und
die Kontroverse über interne und externe Beziehungen, Königstein: Athenäum.
Horstmann, Rolf-Peter, 2004, Die Grenzen der Vernunft: eine Untersuchung zu Zielen
und Motiven des Deutschen Idealismus. Third edition, Frankfurt: Klostermann Verlag.
Horstmann, Rolf-Peter, 2008a, “Fichtes anti-skeptisches Programm: zu den
Strategien der Wissenschaftslehren bis 1801/02,” in Internationales Jahrbuch des
deutschen Idealismus 5: 47–89.
Horstmann, Rolf-Peter, 2008b, “Hermann Cohen on Kant’s Transcendental
Aesthetic”, in The Philosophical Forum XXXIX, 2, 127–38.
Horstmann, Rolf-Peter, 2017a, “The Early Philosophy of Fichte and Schelling,” in
The Cambridge Companion to German Idealism. Second edition, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, pp. 154–80.
Horstmann, Rolf-Peter, 2017b, “Hegel on Objects as Subjects”, in Zuckert, Kreines
(Eds): Hegel on Philosophy in History, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
pp. 12–38.
Horstmann, Rolf-Peter, forthcoming, “Hegel on Subjects as Objects”.
Hyder, David J., 2009, The Determinate World: Kant and Helmholtz on the Physical
Means of Geometry, Berlin: Walter de Gruyter & Co.
Hylton, Peter, 1990, Russell, Idealism, and the Emergence of Analytic Philosophy,
Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/019824018X.001.0001.
Hylton, Peter, 2013, “Idealism and the Origins of Analytic Philosophy,” in Boyle and
Disley 2013: 1: 323–46. doi:10.1017/CBO9781139626675.014.
Jacquette, Dale, 2005, The Philosophy of Schopenhauer, Montreal and Kingston:
McGill Queen’s University Press.
Jaeschke, Walter and Andreas Arndt, 2012, Die Klassische Deutsche Philosophie nach
Kant: System der reinen Vernunft und ihre Kritik 1785–1845, Munich: C. H. Beck.
Janaway, Christopher, 1989, Self and World in Schopenhauer’s Philosophy, Oxford:
Clarendon Press.
Kemp Smith, Norman, 1924, Prolegomena to an Idealist Theory of Knowledge,
London: Macmillan.
Kemp Smith, Norman, 1941, The Philosophy of David Hume: A Critical Study of Its
Origins and Central Doctrines, London: Macmillan.
Köhnke, Klaus Christian, 1986 [1991], Entstehung und Aufstieg des
Neukantianismus: die deutsche Universitätsphilosophie zwischen Idealismus und
Positivismus, Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp. Translated as The Rise of Neo-
Kantianism: German Academic Philosophy between Idealism and Positivism,
R. J. Hollingdale (trans.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991.
223
Kreines, James, 2015, Reason in the World: Hegel’s Metaphysics and Its Philosophical
Appeal, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Krois, John Michael, 1987. Cassirer, Symbolic Forms and History. New Haven: Yale
University Press.
Kuklick, Bruce, 1977, The Rise of American Philosophy: Cambridge, Massachusetts,
1860–1930, New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Kuklick, Bruce, 1985a, Josiah Royce: An Intellectual Biography, Indianapolis: Hackett
Publishing Co.
Kuklick, Bruce, 1985b, Churchmen and Philosophers: From Jonathan Edwards to
John Dewey, New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Kutschera, Franz v., 2006, Die Wege des Idealismus, Paderborn: Mentis.
Loeb, Louis E., 2002, Stability and Justification in Hume’s Treatise, New York: Oxford
University Press.
Lofts, Steven G., 2000, Ernst Cassirer: A “Repetition” of Modernity, Albany, NY:
SUNY Press.
Longuenesse, Béatrice, 1981 [2007], Hegel et la critique de la métaphysique: étude sur
la doctrine de l’essence, Paris: Librairie philosophique J. Vrin. Translated as Hegel’s
Critique of Metaphysics, Nicole J. Simek (trans.), Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2007. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511487262.
Luft, Sebastian, 2015, The Space of Culture: Towards a Neo-Kantian Philosophy of
Culture (Cohen, Natorp, and Cassirer), Oxford: Oxford University Press.
McDowell, John, 2009, Having the World in View: Essays on Kant, Hegel and Sellars,
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
McLaughlin, Peter, 1990, Kant’s Critique of Teleology in Biological Explanation.
Lewiston: Edwin Mellen Press.
Magee, Bryan, 1983, The Philosophy of Schopenhauer, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Makkreel, Rudolf and Sebastian Luft, “Dilthey and the Neo-Kantians: The Dispute
over the Status of the Human and Natural Sciences,” in Moyar 2010: 554–97.
Makkreel, Rudolf and Sebastian Luft (eds.), 2010. Neo-Kantianism in Contemporary
Philosophy. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
Mander, W. J., 1994, An Introduction to Bradley’s Metaphysics, Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Mander, W. J., 1997, “McTaggart’s Argument for Idealism,” Journal of Speculative
Philosophy, 11(1): 53–72.
Mander, W. J. (ed.), 2000, Anglo-American Idealism, 1865–1927, Westport, CT:
Greenwood Press.
Mander, W. J., 2011, British Idealism: A History, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199559299.001.0001.
Mander, W. J., 2016, Idealist Ethics, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Mander, W.J., 2020. The Unknowable: A Study in Nineteenth-Century British
Metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Mander, W. J. and Stamatoula Panagakou (eds.), 2016, British Idealism and the
Concept of the Self, London: Palgrave Macmillan. doi:10.1057/978-1-137-46671-6.
Manser, Anthony, 1983, Bradleys Logic, Totowa, NJ: Barnes & Noble Books.
Martin, Wayne, 1997, Idealism and Objectivity: Understanding Fichte’s Jena Project,
Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
224
Watkins, Eric, 2005, Kant and the Metaphysics of Causality, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Willmann, Otto, 1894–7, Geschichte des Idealismus, 3 vols., Braunschweig: F. Vieweg.
Winkler, Kenneth P., 1989, Berkeley: An Interpretation, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Wolff, Michael, 1995, Kants Urteilstafel, Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann.
Wollheim, Richard, 1959, Bradley, Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Wood, Allen W., 1990, Hegel’s Ethical Thought, Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9781139172257.
Young, Julian, 1987, Willing and Unwilling: A Study in the Philosophy of Arthur
Schopenhauer, The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
Young, Julian, 2005, Schopenhauer, London: Routledge.
Young, Juliam, 2010, Friedrich Nietzsche: An Intellectual Biography. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Zöller, Günter, 1998, Fichte’s Transcendental Philosophy: The Original Duplicity of
Intelligence and Will, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Zuckert, Rachel, 2007, Kant on Biology and the Beautiful, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Index
For the benefit of digital users, indexed terms that span two pages (e.g., 52–53) may, on
occasion, appear on only one of those pages.
Absolute, the 85–6, 89–90, 101–2, 131–3, Belief/faith (Glaube) 6–7, 17–18, 26–7, 43,
137–8, 203–4 47–8, 62–8, 75–6, 87–9, 108
Absolute presuppositions 174–6, 187–9, 191–2 web of 6–7, 177–8
Acquaintance 30–1, 155–8 Berkeley, George 2–3, 5, 25–8, 33–9, 41–2,
Activity 9–12, 71–2, 75–6, 78–85, 91–2, 102–10 54–5, 58, 76–7, 105–6, 142–3, 150–3,
Adams, Robert M. 15–16, 21 157–8, 183–4, 203–4
Aestheticism 119–21 Berlin, Isaiah 70–1
Aesthetics 59–60, 119–21, 164–5 Bildung 200–1
Albert Memorial 175–6 Bird, Graham 54
Alexander, Samuel 33–4, 164–5 Blanshard, Brand 125–7, 178–81, 183–4
Allais, Lucy 54 Body 9–10, 20–1, 65–6, 112–13. See also Matter
Allison, Henry 54, 56–7, 63–4, 66–7 Bosanquet, Bernard 5–6, 121–3
Ameriks, Karl 72–3 Bowman, Ethel 39–40
Analytic philosophy vii, 121–4, 150, 159, Bradley, Francis Herbert 5–6, 121–3, 125–7,
177–8, 182–5, 189–90, 205–6 129–34, 137–9, 142–3, 149–51, 157–9,
Antinomies 40, 87–9, 203–4 181–4, 203–4
Anti-psychologism 166, 184–5 Brandom, Robert 177–8, 184–5
Appearance 12–13, 47–52, 56–7, 60–2, 70–1, Bristow, William F. 87–9
97–8, 112–13 Broackes, Justin viii
Apperception 55, 62–3, 75–6 Broad, Charlie Dunbar 132–3
Aristotle 101–2, 200–1
Armstrong, David 10–11 Caird, Edward 125–7
Arndt, Andreas 72–3 Carl, Wolfgang 51
Art 66–7, 85, 176–7 Carnap, Rudolf 4–5, 121–3, 159, 177–8,
Atomism, logical 125–7, 152–5 183–4
Atwell, John 110 Carritt, E. F. 178–9
Austin, John Langshaw 205–6 Cartwright, David 110
Ayer, Alfred Jules 205–6 Carus, A. W. 177–8
Cassirer, Ernst 121–4, 159, 161–2, 167–78
Bauer, Bruno 160–1 Categorical imperative 63–6, 71–2
Baumgarten, Alexander Gottlieb 9, 14, 21, Causality 36–7, 41–2, 44, 58, 60–2
23–4, 68 Chalmers, David 10–11, 182
Beauty 7–8, 66–7 Character, empirical and intelligible 61–2,
Beaney, Michael 121–3 64–5, 67–8
Beattie, James 44 Clark, Maudemarie 114
Beebee, Helen 42–3 Clendenning, John 138–9
Beck, Lewis White 64–5 Cognition/knowledge 17–18, 26–8, 36–7,
Being, conceptions of 140–1 41–2, 55, 68–9, 78–9, 83–6, 94–5,
Beiser, Frederic C. 70–1, 73–6, 87–9, 160–1, 98–9
164–5, 167–8 a priori 2–3, 48–9, 59–60
230