Global Environmental Ethics
Global Environmental Ethics
ABSTRACT
The problem of environmental degradation is not limited to any particular country or region
but it is global. In fact, the concern for environmental problems has never been as high as it is
now. It is a high time to engage earth’s citizen in a dynamic process about the environmental
realities of today’s world. Attitudes and Ethics towards the use of environmental resources
must change our practices in the environment, we must re-educate ourselves to treat the
environment with greater caution and control. It is this realization that gives
‘environmental attitude’, ‘environmental ethics’, environmental practices’ a place of prime
importance in Environmental Degradation. As culture carries a whole set of attitudes, ethics,
practices and perspectives of one’s relationship with others including environment, there have
been calls from many environmental scholars for the need for a global environmental ethics.
This article brightens the non-prudential dimensions of global environmental affairs and
explains how a focus on the way humans mistreat each other can serve as a central ethical
focus for understanding and addressing environmental injustice. Overall, it aims to show the
importance of The Earth Charter’s vision of universal responsibility towards environmental
protection. The Charter acknowledges that although comprising local communities, the Earth
is also one whole community
INTRODUCTION
international environmental issues and problems. Although differing in remit and focus, all
these bodies claim international relevance and reach. Whether successfully or not, they claim
to represent the interests of the „global community’. Equally, the World Commission on
Environment and Development (WCED), born of the necessity to address environmental issues
at a global level, in 1987, produced Our Common Future, a report written by a transnational
committee chaired by the Norwegian Prime Minister Go Harlem Brundtland. The aim of this
research is to bring about international cooperation in the environmental field. Following what
became known as the Brundtland report came the United Nations Conference on Environment
and Development (UNCED) held in Rio de Janeiro in June 1992. 180 countries participated in
what was known as the “Earth Summit” which rendered it the largest international conference
ever held (Osborn & Bigg 2013). Following the Earth Summit, UNCED called for the
creation of a new charter that would set forth fundamental principles for sustainable
development. The resulting Earth Charter was officially launched at the Peace Palace in The
Hague on June 29th 2000. The ongoing mission of the Charter initiative is to establish a sound
ethical foundation for the emerging global society and to help build a sustainable world based
on respect for nature, universal human rights, economic justice, and a culture of peace. The
Earth Charter is the only attempt to codify a global environmental ethic and is a clear
indication that environmental ethical discourse has gone global.
Environmental philosophers such as Holmes Rolston (1991), J Baird Callicott, and
Peter Singer, have recently been arguing for the need for environmental ethics and that
environmental philosophy consider ethics at a global level. A critical examination of the
philosophical arguments for why global ethics are desirable is one of the key focus of this
research.
Man’s attitude towards his biophysical environment is connected with his ethics,
outlook and knowledge in which actions and attitudes towards environment are determined by
ethics and reflects both in his standard of living and in his biophysical surroundings. Various
countries have different cultural traditions – and many subcultures – that affect the formation
of environmental awareness, knowledge, attitudes, ethics, and practices (Mendie & Eyo 2016).
Environmental Education also enriches Environmental Ethics in some people. Environmental
Ethics concerns itself with judgements of approval and disapproval, judgements as to
the rightness or wrongness, goodness or badness, virtue or vice, desirability or wisdom of
actions, disposition, ends, objects, or states of affairs (Bassey and Eyo 2020). It deal more
specifically with humans interaction and practices with the natural environment with respect to
various environmental existences of the social beings situated in a particular physical
environment. The reason being that local environmental forces, conditions and circumstances
determines the existence, growth and development of locally available biotic and the abiotic
components, their interrelationship, interdependences and co-existence to the corset root.
Today, the environmental degradation is a matter of great concern before
mankind. Over the last few decades the delicate ecosystem of our planet is facing the danger
of destruction due to the intervention of human beings. In the development race man has
ruthlessly consuming natural resources and polluting environment. Rapid damage to
environment and depletion of nature’s stock of resources at a faster rate started from the time
of industrial revolution. Demand for more and more resources has been ever – increasing and
spreading to a large number of countries. Such a continuous process of resource exploitation
and consequent environmental degradation has now brought about a situation where nature
itself is in danger. Environmental degradation simply means lowering of environmental
qualities because of adverse changes brought in by human activities in the basic structure of
the components of the environment to such an extent that these adverse changes adversely
affect all biological communities in general and human in particular. Thus, in view of the
above, the cultural bindings of the population under study are inevitable for conceptualization
of the problem identified.
environmental issues are by their very nature connected to the local geophysical environment
(that is, an environment that is 'place-bound'), two facts speak against an environmentally
relativistic refutation of the idea of a shared, common global environmentalism (Eyo & Ojong
2008). Firstly, individual reflection, direct perception and experience - combined with
communication technologies and information systems- allow us to consider the similarities
between our local environmental problems and those suffered by others (Eba 2020). This
naturally assumes that a person on the other side of the globe is worthy of concern; that she is a
moral object, i.e. that a 'global sense of humanity' exists. Secondly, the realization of
the interconnectedness of the global environment- or, indeed, the identification of the globe
with the wider environment- leads to the conc1usion that local environmental problems often
have wider regional, or global causes (be they socio-economic or direct bio-physical). And,
conversely, that local action has wider consequences - analogy to the ubiquitous 'butterfly
effect, from physics and chaos theory will be appropriate for this. Thus, again, the nations of a
global humanity and a global environment are paramount in refuting the idea that a locally
determined geo-physical relativism would cancel out any sense of globalized environmentalist
thought.
The message of protecting the environment will be understood in different ways in
different societies. However, neither cu1tura1relativism, nor the belief that globalization
automatically incurs homogenization of culture are valid arguments on their Own. Instead, the
process should be seen as an interaction between the strong forces of globa1izationand the
(probably) equally strong forces of loca1ism. Environmentalist ideas are adapted and modified
according to the society and environment into which they are imported. However, it is
possib1e to reason that certain care 'messages' of environmentalism- such as global humanity
and global environment - will (with globalizing cultural, social, political and economic
influences) 'percolate' into other (territorial) cultures and influence environmental concern
globally. The development of environmentalist views is just that - a development where
constant change takes place as views influence each other Another issue that warrants
discussion is whether 'global environmenta1ism' will mean that on1y 'cosmopolitans' by
profession, i.e. those professionally invo1ved in these issues such as activists of international
NGOs, politicians and academics, are those influenced by global environmentalist sentiment?
Cosmopolitans can be seen as 'bridgeheads' of global cultural perspectives into territorial
cultures (Hannerz 1990; Ogar 2008; Ogar et al., 2018), meaning that they aid in propagating
environmental concern and shaping attitudes. However, the influence of modern media
should also be taken into account. It could, as Hannerz (1990), indicates, be possible to
become a cosmopolitan without ever leaving one's own borne, when images of environmental
events and problems are conveyed to one's borne via electronic, as well as non-electronic
media. Through the influence of media, the nation of a compressing globe - and therefore also
the realization of a (single) global environment and of a global humanity- became very
tangible (albeit 'two-dimensional') notions. This indicates that genuine (global) concern for the
environment is not limited to certain (professional or occupational) categories of people who
travel and interact face to-face with people in societies globally, hut that it can be, and
increasingly is, held by 'ordinary people' as well.
International Monetary Fund (IMF), and the World Bank function at a global level. They
operate as part of the United Nations (UN) system, either as specialised agencies or
autonomous organisations (with the exception of the WTO which is an independent body with
“special UN cooperation arrangements”). The United Nations is the umbrella beneath which
international cooperation takes place and internationally-binding agreements and regulations
are made. Some of these international agreements include the Kyoto Protocol, Agenda 21, the
Convention on the Rights of the Child, and the Nuclear Non-Proliferation Treaty.
Important for my purposes is the Universal Declaration of Human Rights which was
adopted in 1948. This is the central document of over fifty declarations and conventions of
international and regional application to human rights. Although it is based upon Western
political ideas, it is the first statement of its kind to confirm human dignity, and to outline
basic rights and freedoms. Under this declaration, the rights of the individual take precedence
over the interests of the nation. In this way, every individual’s rights are of importance
regardless of their geographical or political status. It is not legally binding; therefore the
principles take the form of recommendations rather than requirements. Because not all UN
member states have unified views on human rights issues, not all have ratified the declaration.
Although it is not in itself legally binding, the international community has encouraged
voluntary compliance and the UN Commission on Human Rights monitors and reports on
human rights situations in various countries and investigates whether those countries are living
up to international standards. If it finds that they are not, even the drawing of attention to
violations can bring great political pressure to bear. It can work, and national policies can
change as a result, for example; the apartheid regime in South Africa. The fight against
apartheid was, according to UN Secretary General Kofi Annan, “one that rallied people and
Governments behind a common objective: the objective of reaffirming the basic human rights
and fundamental freedoms of all peoples” (Moore 2003, p. 43). Crucially it acts as a tool for
recourse. If it is deemed that a nation state is in gross violation of agreed international
standards of human rights, then action can be taken. It may be action in the form of political
pressure, economic and/or political sanctions, or even intervention by UN agencies.
It can of course be argued that, like most UN mechanisms, The Universal Declaration
of Human Rights (UDHR) has not been entirely successful; after all it does seem that member
states tend to take the bits they like, and reject those that do not further their interests. The
United States of America, for example, has refused to sign the Kyoto Protocol – the only
international agreement on climate change. At the Earth Summit – UNCED – in Rio George W
Bush stated that the lifestyle of the US would not be up for discussion. The American
administration also assert that US citizens would not be subject to trial in an International
Criminal Court. This element of voluntariness would seem to defeat the object, if the object is
to promote and encourage universal adherence to democratically and mutually agreed
principles. There are flaws with the UN system as it stands, particularly with regard to
enforcement. Much has been written, discussed and proposed on the subject of UN reform, and
I will touch upon some of the key issues in respect of global governance in Part IV.
There is also a debate over whether universal principles should be adopted without
question. It has been argued that the UNDHR is based on particularly Western political
ideas and Western concepts of individual rights. This is a valid point if it is compared to the
prevailing ideologies of countries such as China where the functioning of the collective is
valued above that of the individual. When the former US Secretary of State, Warren
Christopher, defended human rights as the universal moral language at the World Conference
on Human Rights in 1993, he was heavily criticised. He defended his claim with the argument
that “cultural relativism” had become “the last refuge of repression”, and that cultural
84 Predestinasi
Volume 12, No. 2, Desember 2019, Hal. 79 - 90
traditions could not be regarded as ethical systems. One of his critics, American
communitarian philosopher Deane Curtin, sees views such as Christopher’s as a form of
systemic violence (Epp& Watkinson 1997). Christopher was expressing the view that appeal to
cultural tradition can be used to excuse all manner of repressive, oppressive, and even violent,
practices (Eyo & Essien 2017). For Curtin, on the other hand, to deny these cultural practices is
a form of violence.
Problems with enforcement and philosophical debates notwithstanding, I want to argue
that the very existence of the UNHDR serves to establish that global ethics is possible. The
UNDHR sets a precedent in that it demonstrates the way in which international agreement
can be reached on fundamental issues. This in turn shows that, although being part of distinct
and disparate cultures, human beings globally can share common broad-based values. That is
not to say there will not always be cultural difference and variation overlaying these values,
but fundamentally there can be basic concurrence. If there can be this concurrence on human
rights then perhaps the same could apply within the context of environmental principles
applied universally.
After the Second World War, in the 1940s and 1950s, human rights issues were on the
top of the international political agenda. The ensuing discussions resulted in an international
declaration and broad agreement. In the same way, in the 1980s, 1990s and 2000s,
environmental issues are at the forefront of international discussion. Although potentially
controversial - as was the UNDHR - it could be that a similar broad agreement could be born
of current environmental discourse. Environmental philosopher J Baird Callicott argues that
some form of common environmental values already exists within differing cultures and
religious traditions. In Earth’s Insights, Callicott provides an account of environmental values
as seen from a variety of global religions and cultures. Of his work he says,
“[My] principle purpose is to audit the fund of ecological ideas on which the world’s
various peoples may draw as we face a common and unprecedented global
environmental crisis” (Callenbach et al., 1993, p. 45).
It is not necessary here to reproduce Callicott’s work or to detail how each tradition regards the
natural world. Suffice it to say that he finds evidence - perhaps in varying degrees and for
differing reasons – of consideration and respect for nature in each of the traditions he studied.
These traditions include the major religions as well as spiritual practices/systems less known in
the West such as West Polynesian Paganism, South American Eco-Eroticism and Australian
Aboriginal Dreamtime. Through looking at this variety of traditions, Callicott believes that we
can derive hope from the possibility that there is “an ancient tie to nature in our human
consciousness that simply needs to be rediscovered, reawakened and restored” (Callicott,
1994, p. XXI). He speaks of “..an intellectually diverse global network of indigenous
environmental ethics, each adapted to its cultural and ecological bioregion” (Callicott, 1994,
XVI). He then invites others to join the effort to create this network and acknowledges the
plurality of environmental attitudes and values. Although acknowledging this plurality, his aim
is to show that differing values can be mutually reinforcing, not necessarily contradictory and
divisive. Callicott is appealing to the spiritual nature of humankind and is hopeful that
through some form of spiritual reawakening or recognition we will reconnect with nature and
Maxwell Borjor Achuk Eba; Exploring Global Environmental Ethics |85
thus increase our environmental awareness. The point is that Callicott shows that certain
values can underpin all of human life. Although I am starting from a different point - being
concerned with more basic, physical human needs as the foundation of an environmental ethic
- this is what I also aim to show.
The debate here is not over the possibility of a global environmental ethic, but its
desirability. The question is not can we have a global environmental ethic - I have shown that
in many ways we already do - but should we have one? This question evokes numerous
questions and debates that are interesting to consider from an environmental philosophical
perspective.
Whereas human rights were the central global concern and a matter of UN policy
discussion in the postcolonising world of the 1940s and 1950s, it may be argued that today’s
urgent concern requiring international cooperation is the global ecological crisis. Although
there have been many examples of cooperation within the UN and within global civil society,
there is as of yet no UN Declaration of environmental principles. As mentioned in the
Introduction, The Earth Charter (which failed to achieve the endorsement of the UN General
Assembly at the 2002 Earth Summit in Johannesburg) is the only attempt to codify a global
environmental ethic. I argue that it is evidence that defining principles can result from cross-
cultural conversation and negotiation. It is for this reason that it is interesting to examine it in
light of the foregoing discussion. In particular, the following questions should be asked of the
EC: how far does it succeed as a workable environmental ethic, and what does it offer?
What exactly is the Earth Charter and what are its origins? To answer this question I
shall draw on the brief history outlined on the Earth Charter website as well as on
Ramachandra Guha’s account (Bosselmann 2004). In 1987 the United Nations issued a report
on sustainable development called, “Our Common Future”, written by a transnational
committee chaired by the Norwegian Prime Minister Go Harlem Brundtland. The aim of the
report was to bring about international cooperation in the environmental field. The United
Nations Conference on Environment and Development (UNCED) followed, held in Rio de
Janeiro in June 1992. 180 countries participated in what became known as the “Earth Summit”
which rendered it the largest international conference ever held. Following the Earth Summit
the UNCED called for the creation of a new charter that would set forth fundamental
principles for sustainable development. The Earth Charter was officially launched at the Peace
86 Predestinasi
Volume 12, No. 2, Desember 2019, Hal. 79 - 90
Palace in The Hague on June 29th 2000. The aims and vision of the Earth Charter and the Earth
Charter Initiative are to establish a sound ethical foundation for the emerging global society
and to help build a sustainable world based on respect for nature, universal human rights,
economic justice, and a culture of peace (Edor 2005; Eyo & Ojong 2008). The vision is one of
universal responsibility, of identifying ourselves with the whole Earth community as well as
our local communities. The Charter states that we must realise that when basic needs have
been met, human development is primarily about being more, not having more (my emphasis).
The preamble to the Earth Charterreads:
“We stand at a critical moment in Earth’s history, a time when humanity must choose
its future. As the world becomes increasingly interdependent and fragile, the future at
once holds great peril and great promise. To move forward we must recognize that in
the midst of a magnificent diversity of cultures and life forms we are one human
family and one Earth community with a common destiny. We must join together to
bring forth a sustainable global society founded on respect for nature, universal human
rights, economic justice, and a culture of peace. Towards this end, it is imperative
that we, the peoples of Earth, declare our responsibility to one another, to the
greater community oflife, and to future generations” (Coleman & Ryan 2005, p. 91).
The Earth Charter’s vision of universal responsibility is highly compatible with my view on
the way forward as it is with the views of Attfield and Singer. The Charter acknowledges that
although comprising local communities, the Earth is also one whole community. This is what I
have been suggesting throughout: that we recognise local communities but need an over-
arching global ethic because we are all part of the global community. It talks of citizens of
different nations and of one world and of everyone sharing responsibility. This echoes the
cosmopolitan position, defended by Attfield and which I endorse.
“We urgently need a shared vision of basic values to provide an ethical foundation for
the emerging world community…a common standard by which the conduct of all
individuals, organisations, businesses, governments, and transnational institutions is to
be guided and assessed” (Attfield & Belsey 1994,p. 64).
The Earth Charter clearly calls for a global environmental ethic in much the same way
that I do. From the quotation above, it is evident that the vision is one of an international
declaration or code similar to the UNDHR, which is as I suggest it could be envisaged. When
it also states that we must realise that when basic needs have been met, human development is
primarily about being more, not having more, the Charter seems to be supporting what Sen and
Nussbaum propound. That is that human freedoms, needs and capabilities are met first and
foremost – the focus being upon functioning and flourishing rather than owning and
consuming. The Earth Charter certainly serves as a model, and, given that is was the product of
delegates from180 countries, provides evidence that people can reach agreement across
cultures. This is a positive move in the right direction. Although the Charter as it stands is not
legally binding, and so lacks teeth, it does offer a sound basis for continuing discourse and
debate.
Maxwell Borjor Achuk Eba; Exploring Global Environmental Ethics |87
A feature of the Earth Charter worth noting is its affirmation of the positive, as
opposed to concentration on denial and restraints. It would be a good move for the
environmental movement to promote positive enticements to change behaviour rather than to
issue warnings or threaten retroactive punishments in order to constrain action. For example,
the assertion of the right to clean air would be a more positive approach than the command to
“cut emissions”. This is a welcome shift in emphasis and one which may prove to generate a
more positive and productive response from the global community. This is not the place to
examine the psychology and relative merits of discipline and punishment versus reward and
positive outcomes, but the latter would seem to be the more optimistic and effective approach.
So, these principles have been stated and (by some) applauded, but are we prepared to give up
freedom(s)? A reading of the Earth Charter will quickly show that some (mainly in the West)
will have to sacrifice a certain amount in order to adhere to the principles. I have been
predicting - and defending - this necessity throughout this paper. It is indeed the only
logical way forward, and it is a view supported by Ophuls and Singer among others. Some of
our freedoms may be curtailed under such a Charter, declaration, or ethic, but equally
restricted will be discrimination, imperialism, colonisation, oppression. So we may be less free
to destroy rainforest, or pollute the atmosphere, but we will also be less free to abuse others
and impose our will.
not be tried there), Kyoto Protocol (again, the US refusing to sign). However a precedent
has already been set by the UN Declaration on Human Rights and it is an example of how
such a declaration/treaty can work on a global scale. The United Nations has gradually
expanded human rights law to encompass particular standards for vulnerable groups who
now possess rights protecting them from discriminatory practices. General Assembly
decisions have gradually established the universality of human rights, demonstrating their
interrelatedness with development and democracy. The United Nations mechanisms
monitoring compliance with human rights covenants have gained cohesiveness and weight
among Member States. I argue that if this can work then there is hope for a global
environmental ethic.
CONCLUSION
Often, the focus of those around the global negotiating table is on their own national
interests and as long as this is the case it is hard to see how any international agreement can be
reached in any significant way. Again in the case of the US – Kyoto Protocol – America won’t
sign because, as a huge consumer of oil and thus a huge producer of CO2, it is patently not in
its interest to limit its use. This is short-sighted in the extreme, but until this narrow, nation-
centred outlook is addressed and overcome, there can be no global environmental ethic.
Unfortunately it is not within the scope of this paper to answer just how this can be achieved
practically, only to consider a possible, ethical way forward. I propose a global ethic which
would be universal and apply to all. It would enable and ensure sustainability, focussing on
human freedoms, capabilities and flourishing. Damaging activities and negative freedoms
would be restricted. At the same time, individual cultures and traditions would be recognised:
the over-arching concern being respect for human life, and for non-human life as that which
sustains us. There does need to be some form of global governance regarding environmental
ethic and enforcement thereof. This is not just limited to environmentalism: economics,
politics, technology, culture, are all tied up together and need to be considered all as part of
the whole.
This ethic could run along similar lines to the UN Declaration of Human Rights in
that it can be appealed to, not necessarily universally enforced law in itself, but a tool to be
used where individuals or nations feel the need to appeal against environmental (or indeed any
other) injustice. This could be said to be too weak. The question then arises of how to ensure
that member states (ideally all states) adhere to principles: it would have to be enforceable in
some way. Therefore the freedom of states, nations and individuals will necessarily be
curtailed. The “right” freedoms will be upheld and maintained while the damaging will not. Is
this eco- fascism? Well, no. Not if we look at the underlying principles of the UN as they
stand, and consider that, generally, the aims of the UNDHR are not deemed fascist or
totalitarian. And if we consider just the basic duties and responsibilities that we, as citizens of
the world are (or should be) bound by, then it would seem that “imposing” or living by such
broad principles should be acceptable by all. It will, after all, be ultimately essential for all.
REFERENCES
Ajor, J. O. Colonialism and Rural Labour Migration Among Bekwarra 1940-1960. Journal of
Religion, Culture and Society, 1/1, 84, 88.
Maxwell Borjor Achuk Eba; Exploring Global Environmental Ethics |89
Ajor, J. O., & Erim, P. O. (2010). The Canoe Craft of the Ogoja People in a Survival Battle in
Colonial Nigeria. ABIBISEM: Journal of African Culture and Civilization, 3(1).
Ajor, J. O., & Odey, J. S. (2018). History: The epicentre of national integration. Lwati: A
Journal of Contemporary Research, 1
Ajor, J. O., Erim, P. O., & Majuk, S. E. (2011). Colonial Challenge to the Ogoja Salt Industry,
Eastern Nigeria. Lwati: A Journal of Contemporary Research, 8(2).
Akpan, C. O., Ogar, J. N., & Bassey, S. A. (2020). Examining the Ethics of Research in Animal
Experimentation. Bulletin of Pure & Applied Sciences-Zoology, (1).
Attfield, R., & Belsey, A. (Eds.). (1994). Philosophy and the natural environment (Vol.
36).Cambridge University Press.
Bassey, S. A., & Eyo, U. E. (2020). Covid-19 Outbreak: Wet Markets And The Ethics Of
Anthropoholism. Euromentor, 11(3).
Bosselmann, K. (2004). In search of global law: the significance of the Earth
Charter. Worldviews: Global Religions, Culture, and Ecology, 8(1), 62-75.
Callenbach, E., Capra, F., LUTZ, L., Goldman, L., Lutz, R., & Marburg, S.
(1993). EcoManagement: The Elmwood guide to ecological auditing and sustainable
business. Berrett-Koehler Publishers.
Callicott, J. B. (1994). Earth's insights: a multicultural survey of ecological ethics from the
Mediterranean Basin to the Australian Outback. Univ of California Press.
Coleman, J. A., & Ryan, W. F. (2005). Globalization and Catholic Social Thought: present
crisis, future hope. Orbis Books.
Eba, M. B. (2014). Tourism in Nigeria: Past, Present and Future. The Leajon, an academic
journal of intern-disciplinary studies, 6(1), 128-137.
Eba, M. B. A. (2020). A Critique of Aldo Leopold Land Ethic for Environmental
Management. Jurnal Office, 6(2), 131-142.
Eba, M. B. A. (2020). Human Right and Sustainable Development. GNOSI:
AnInterdisciplinary Journal of Human Theory and Praxis, 3(3), 67-82.
Edor, J. E. (2005). The inductive predicament as an indispensable sable evil for practical
life. Sophia: An African Journal of Philosophy, 8(1), 110-115.
Epp, J. R., & Watkinson, A. M. (Eds.). (1997). Systemic violence in education: Promise
broken. SUNY Press.
Eyo, E. B., & Essien, A. E. (2017). Frantz Fanon’s Philosophy of Violence and the
Participation of Intellectuals in the Advancement of Social Liberation in Africa.
Journal of Pan African Studies, 10(3), 62-75.
Eyo, E. B., & Ojong, F. O. (2008). Peace and conflict resolution as a foundation for national
development. Sophia: An African Journal of Philosophy, 11(1).
Falk, R. (2013). (Re) imagining humane global governance (Vol. 11). Routledge.
Hannerz, U. (1990). Cosmopolitans and locals in world culture. Theory, culture & society, 7(2-
3), 237-251.
Ho, J. (2008). Is global governance bad for East Asian queers?. GLQ: A Journal of Lesbian
and Gay Studies, 14(4), 457-479.
Mendie, P. J., & Eyo, E. (2016). Environmental Challenges And Axiology: Towards A
Complementary Studies In Eco-Philosophy. Journal of Integrative Humanism, 7(1),
144-150.
Monbiot, G. (2016). Neoliberalism–the ideology at the root of all our problems. The
Guardian, 15(04).
90 Predestinasi
Volume 12, No. 2, Desember 2019, Hal. 79 - 90
Moore, M. K. (2003). A world without walls: freedom, development, free trade and global
governance. Cambridge University Press.
Ogar, J. N. (2008). A revisitation of the question of truth. Sophia: An African Journal of
Philosophy, 10(2).
Ogar, J. N., & Ogar, T. E. (2019). An Appraisal Of Globalization And Its
History. Cogito, 11(3), 182-195.
Ogar, J. N., Ogar, T. E., & Bassey, S. A. (2018). Ambivalence Human Nature and Social
Justice. Journal of Social Sciences and Humanities Research, 6(01).
Okoi, I. O., & Tabi, F. O. Communal Boundary Conflicts in Nigeria: An Assessment of the
2006 Ebom-Ebijakara Boundary Conflict in Cross River State.
Osborn, D., & Bigg, T. (2013). Earth summit II: outcomes and analysis. Routledge.
Ranganathan, S. (2016). Global commons. European journal of international law,
27(3), 693-717.