Vandenabeele, B. - 'Schopenhauer, Nietzsche, and The Aesthetically Sublime'
Vandenabeele, B. - 'Schopenhauer, Nietzsche, and The Aesthetically Sublime'
Vandenabeele, B. - 'Schopenhauer, Nietzsche, and The Aesthetically Sublime'
REFERENCES
Linked references are available on JSTOR for this article:
http://www.jstor.org/stable/3527424?seq=1&cid=pdf-reference#references_tab_contents
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/
info/about/policies/terms.jsp
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content
in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship.
For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
University of Illinois Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Journal of Aesthetic
Education.
http://www.jstor.org
This content downloaded from 130.240.43.43 on Fri, 19 Feb 2016 01:19:52 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Schopenhauer,Nietzsche, and the Aesthetically
Sublime
BART VANDENABEELE
This content downloaded from 130.240.43.43 on Fri, 19 Feb 2016 01:19:52 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Schopenhauer,Nietzsche, and the Sublime 91
The objects can be hostile to the human will in general, the body, in
two different ways: by their immensity or by their threatening power.
Schopenhauer thus retains Kant's distinction between the mathematically
and the dynamically sublime.
At first sight, the distinction between the beautiful and the sublime
seems to be reduced to a passive, will-less and serene contemplation and a
troublesome, violent, and conscious elevation beyond that which threatens
the will, respectively. The will-lessness and disinterestedness, two typical
characteristics of the Schopenhauerian aesthetic spectator, seem to be ab-
sent from his account on the feeling of the sublime: Schopenhauer stresses
the activity of the aesthetic subject in the sublime, that tears itself violently
away from the relations of the object to the own will "by a free exaltation,"
which "must not only be won by consciousness, but also be maintained."4
The question is, "How can such a conscious elevation take place, if it is
This content downloaded from 130.240.43.43 on Fri, 19 Feb 2016 01:19:52 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
92 Bart Vandenabeele
This content downloaded from 130.240.43.43 on Fri, 19 Feb 2016 01:19:52 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Nietzsche,andtheSublime
Schopenhauer, 93
This content downloaded from 130.240.43.43 on Fri, 19 Feb 2016 01:19:52 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
94 Bart Vandenabeele
A very lonely and silent region, under a perfectly cloudless sky, without
animals or human beings is "as it were a summons to seriousness, to con-
templation, with complete emancipation from all willing and its cravings;
but it is just this that gives to such a scene of mere solitude and profound
peace a touch of the sublime [einen Anstrich des Erhabenen]"(WWR,I, 203).
But "let us imagine such a region denuded of plants and showing only
bare rocks; the will is at once filled with alarm through the total absence of
that which is organic and necessary for our subsistence. The desert takes on
a fearful character; our mood becomes tragic" (WWR,I, 204). As it demands
more effort to raise oneself above the interests of the own will, the feeling of
the sublime appears more intensely. Schopenhauer is often closer to Edmund
Burke's theory of the sublime, than to Kant's. In A PhilosophicalEnquiry into
the Origin of Our Ideas of the Sublime and Beautiful, Burke connects the sub-
lime feeling with "anguish," "terror,"and "privation."11In the above-quoted
example, a feeling of silence and emptiness is evoked, which fills the will-
ing individual with terror.Terror is, as Lyotard rightly remarks, closely re-
lated to privation.12 The feeling of the sublime originates in deep terror or
This content downloaded from 130.240.43.43 on Fri, 19 Feb 2016 01:19:52 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Nietzsche,andtheSublime
Schopenhauer, 95
This content downloaded from 130.240.43.43 on Fri, 19 Feb 2016 01:19:52 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
96 Bart Vandenabeele
The Sublime and Music: Between the Apollonian and the Dionysian?
The serenity and harmony of the feeling of the beautiful, which holds the
promise of a unified, will-less subject, has totally disappeared in the feeling
of the sublime. It is, of course, still a question of exaltation above the will
[Erhebungiiber den Willen] and a feeling of purity (WWR, I, 201, 209). That is
what renders it a purely aesthetic feeling. It does not form the particularity
of the feeling of the sublime, though. When we acknowledge the impor-
tance of violence and ambivalence in the sublime feeling, it cannot be main-
tained that the feeling of the sublime helps to fulfill the preparatory role of
the beautiful in the perspective of the denial of the will (WWR, I, 200-7).19
The sublime reveals the fundamental twofold nature [Duplizitdt] of human
consciousness in an ambivalent and painful way:
This content downloaded from 130.240.43.43 on Fri, 19 Feb 2016 01:19:52 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Schopenhauer,Nietzsche, and the Sublime 97
Then in the unmoved beholder of this scene the twofold nature of his
consciousness reaches the highest distinctness. Simultaneously, he
feels himself as individual, as the feeble phenomenon of will, which
the slightest touch of these forces can annihilate, helpless against
powerful nature, dependent, abandoned to chance, a vanishing noth-
ing in face of stupendous forces; and he also feels himself as the eter-
nal, serene subject of knowing, who as the condition of every object is
the supporter of this whole world (WWR,I, 204-5).
This content downloaded from 130.240.43.43 on Fri, 19 Feb 2016 01:19:52 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
98 Bart Vandenabeele
above the will is demanded. The differences are essential, however. The
beautiful is an Apollonian feeling of harmony, discipline, and measure: the
objects invite us to feel disinterested pleasure. The sublime, on the contrary,
originates in a boundless and immoderate scene that threatens the indi-
vidual will. The importance of this fundamental difference cannot be over-
estimated, whatever J.E. Atwell may say.22
What is at stake is the life of the individual. The throbbing heart of sub-
jectivity itself, the will, is threatened to death. The moment at which con-
sciousness tears itself loose is not just a detail but is exceptionally funda-
mental. In the sublime, the subject is attracted and rejected at the same time:
as a willing subject it is ravished and withdraws, as a presenting subject it
persists in its own activity. The gap in subjectivity is sublime. In the sub-
lime, the extremely paradoxical possibility is maintained to enjoy aestheti-
cally of the deep gap that characterizes consciousness. This is not to be con-
fused with Nietzsche's concept of Selbstentzweiung; in Schopenhauer, no
Dionysian loss of the self or violent auto-destruction is taken into consider-
ation. According to Schopenhauer, there is a conscious subject divided be-
tween a passively experienced affection of the will and the active will-less
contemplation: either one takes refuge or one wants to remain contempla-
tive. The feeling of the sublime is no sensation or a series of sensations that
can be reported to an Ich denke.Still, it is felt! Not as a lucid insight, a feeling
that can be enjoyed serenely as is the case in the beautiful. It is the felt
"presence," as Lyotard would say, of the incommensurability of subjectiv-
ity itself. It can only be felt as the paradoxicaland strenuous mixture of pleasure
and pain which is the sublime.
This (aesthetic) feeling can only occur if the exaltation is "accompanied
by a constant recollection of the will [von einer steten Erinnerung an den
Willen begleitet]"which contaminates the so-called will-lessness, typical of
the beautiful (WWR, I, 202). So no Erhabenheit,as in Schiller for instance: the
elevation above the will never succeeds completely. There is no room for
happiness and harmony in the sublime. In this way, and this is crucial for a
thorough understanding of Schopenhauer's philosophy, it is rather the
beautiful than the sublime that prepares a successful ethical escape from the
torments of willing.23 The transition to the so-called quieter (of the will) is,
in a way, easier from the beautiful - which is closer to the spiritual serenity
of the saint - than from the restless and painful feeling of the sublime. The
sublime is not a purely spiritual feeling, as it is essentially "accompanied by
a constant recollection of the will...of human willing in general, insofar as it
is expressed universally through its objectivity, the human body" (WWR, I,
202). In this way, an interpretation that considers the aesthetic and the
artistic as a route to a kind of Buddhist liberation from all willing and suf-
fering, is highly problematic.24 The sublime functions as an aesthetic border
crossing-point that hampers a smooth passage to the realm of ethics.
This content downloaded from 130.240.43.43 on Fri, 19 Feb 2016 01:19:52 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Schopenhauer,Nietzsche, and the Sublime 99
This does not alter the fact that Schopenhauer's remark about the per-
manent recollection of the will in the sublime remains fairly enigmatic. It
cannot mean that the individual will is affected, since if this happened we
would end up in the contrary of the sublime: the charmingor attractive (das
Reizende):"Since opposites throw light on each other, it may here be in place
to remark that the real opposite of the sublime is something that is not at
first sight recognized as such, namely the charming or attractive" (WWR, I,
207). In the charming, one is merely passive and no really cognitive activity
or purely aesthetic affection of the mind [Gemiit] takes place. The charming
is sensual pleasure and not liking [Wohlgefallen]or joy [Freude].Every confu-
sion or mixture on this level would destroy the particularity of the aesthetic.
In the charming, the individual will is affected, because immediate satisfac-
tion is being promised. This immediately disturbs the purity of the aesthetic
feeling (WWR,I, 207). That every beautiful thing of a cheering nature is usu-
ally called charming or attractive is "due to a concept too widely compre-
hended through want of correct discrimination," and Schopenhauer objects
to it (WWR, I, 207). The charming or attractive "draws the beholder down
from pure contemplation," which is crucial to a purely aesthetic feeling,
and thus he "becomes the needy and dependent subject of willing" (WWR,
I, 207). No such Genuss is present in the feeling of the sublime, but there is
still the constant recollection of the will, or, rather, of human willing in gen-
eral [sondernan das menschlicheWillen iiberhaupt](WWR, I, 202):
This content downloaded from 130.240.43.43 on Fri, 19 Feb 2016 01:19:52 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
100 Bart Vandenabeele
flattering light that accompanies the images and the distant scene flits
acrossour minds "like a lost paradise"(WWR,I, 198).
In the feeling of the sublime anotherkind of recollectiontakes place:it is
a constantrecollection- it lasts as long as the aestheticperceptioncontinues.
One notices here a remarkablesort of temporality:the aestheticconscious-
ness is, accordingto Schopenhauer,timeless after all. Aesthetic contempla-
tion does not seem to take time and yet a constantrecollectiontakes place,
which is clearly temporal. The will is present in the (will-less) conscious-
ness, but it is not experiencedas "beingpresentat the moment";it is "only"
a recollectionand, hence, a product of our imagination.A constantoscilla-
tion takes place, which has far-reachingconsequencesfor the interpretation
of the sublime.This intricateissue can only be dealt with summarily.
Firstof all, if the fact that it is (only) a recollection
is secondary,then the
distinctionbetween the sublime and the charming(the attractive)is blurred.
If its status as recollectionis subordinate,then there is no purely aesthetic
feeling;every actualpresenceof the will disturbsthe purity of the aesthetic
feeling. Thatis the danger of Atwell's interpretationof the sublime feeling.
He contends that the will does not disappear as such, but that only "con-
sciousness of the will disappears."26How else, however, can a constant
recollectionof the will be interpretedthan as a mode of consciousness?
But second, if it is unimportantthat thewill is present as recollection
so if thepresenceof the will in consciousness is accidental- the distinction
between the sublime and the beautifulis blurred.In the feeling of the beau-
tiful, the will is completelyabsentfrom consciousness,not even presentas a
faint memory!Somethingis beautiful,if it invitesus to become the objectof
a disinterestedcontemplationand it is very beautiful, if it forcesus to con-
template it aesthetically.In the sublime, however, "a constantrecollection
of human willing as such" occurs,which is difficultto grasp. A moment of
displeasure cannot be absent and that pain remains there, so long as the
aesthetic feeling remains. This aesthetic feeling should not take any time.
All this is very enigmatic as it is. Schopenhauer wanted to avoid the
Dyonisian "trap"of "becominga work of art"that Nietzsche seems to glo-
rify: the complete self-forgetfulnessand total self-destructionby becoming
one with the whole of reality:"Manis no longer an artist,he has become a
work of art:the artisticpower of the whole of nature reveals itself to the
supreme gratification of the primal Oneness amidst the paroxysms of
intoxication"(BT,I, 18).
In Schopenhauer'saestheticsthere can be no such thing, not even in the
experienceof music, since a kind of self-awareness- be it pleasurableor
not - is the strictcondition to speak about an aestheticfeeling. One should
not, however, as Atwell seems to do, try and avoid the complexities of
Schopenhauer'saccount by reducing the aesthetic and the ethical to the
dichotomy:
This content downloaded from 130.240.43.43 on Fri, 19 Feb 2016 01:19:52 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Nietzsche,andtheSublime
Schopenhauer, 101
liberationfrom the individual will/liberation from the noumenalwill
altogether....Isuggest then that contemplationis liberationfrom the
individual will but not from will altogether (else contemplation
would not be knowledge in which the will knows itself),while saintly
resignation is liberation from the will altogether (thus from every
traceof knowledge).27
The feeling of the beautifulis the promise of pure inner blessed serenity
and harmony.The sublime feeling is pleasure and displeasureat the same
time. The feeling of the sublime is to be situated in the contrast,the fissure,
the resistance[Widerstand] and the differend;it is joy and sorrow, pleasure
and pain, exaltationand terrorat the same time. It is paradoxicaland thor-
oughly ambivalent.It cannotbe identified with the feeling of immortality,
as JulianYoung thinks:"Theexperienceof the sublime is, we may say, an
intimationof immortality,an experiencewhich, as Kant puts it, makes us
'alive to the feeling of the supersensibleside of our being.'"28It cannot be
consideredas the harmoniousfeeling of the beautiful,in which one enjoys
its own undisturbed serenity. The beautiful is cheerful and serene. In the
sublime this happy quietness and cheerfulnessis permanentlythreatened
by the constantrecollectionof the will, which causes deep pain and violent
emotion.
However different Schopenhauer'saccount of the sublime is from the
one of the feeling of the beautiful, it is perhaps even more differentfrom
Nietzsche's analysis of the Dionysian.In Schopenhauer'sdescriptionof the
sublime feeling, the subjectseems to be divided between willing and pure
perception, or between unconscious drive and conscious contemplation,
whereas in Nietzsche the (Dionysian)subjecthas become intoxicatedand is
"joyfullypenetratingthe whole of nature"(BT,I, 17). As in the Kantianac-
count of the sublimefeeling, the sublime sets one shuddering,casts one into
the movement of Erschiitterung, overwhelmingand exceeding one in such a
way that one is drawn beyond narrowindividualityto a universaldestina-
tion. Yet, for Nietzsche that destinationwould be, not moral,but aesthetic:
"for it is only as an aestheticphenomenon that existence and the world are
V,
eternallyjustified"(BT, 32). It has nothing to do with Kant'sdiscovery of
our ethical destinationnor with Schopenhauer'spremonitionof the denial
of the will. Nietzsche writes of the tragic spectatorwhich "shuddersat the
sufferings that will befall the hero and yet anticipatesin them a higher,
much more overpoweringjoy. He sees more extensively and profoundly
than ever and yet wishes he were blind"(BT,XXII,105).As with dissonance
in music, there is desire to hear and at the same time longing to get beyond
all hearing.29True, Nietzsche almost literally repeats Schopenhauerwhen
he argues that "subjectivitybecomes a complete forgettingof the self" and
"each man feels himself not only united, reconciled, and at one with his
neighbor,but one with him, as if the veil of Maya had been rent and now
merelyflutteringin tattersbeforethe mysteriousprimalOneness"(BT,I, 17).
This content downloaded from 130.240.43.43 on Fri, 19 Feb 2016 01:19:52 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
102 Bart Vandenabeele
But it remains very anti-Schopenhauer to claim that one feels "like a god...
enraptured and elated" in aesthetic experience and "man is no longer an
artist, he has become a work of art" (BT, I, 18). Nietzsche goes still further
than Schopenhauer does, when he maintains - in one of the very few pas-
sages where he literally mentions the sublime [das Erhabene]- that the sub-
lime is "the mantle of the ugly."30 In Schopenhauer - contrary to what is
often assumed - the sublime is not a kind of protection against or a mask-
ing of the pain and horrors of the world. It is an ambivalent confrontation
with the horrid or threatening aspects of the world.
Nietzsche, or the young Nietzsche, seems still very much influenced by
Aristotle's idea of catharsis,when he writes that the sublime is "the taming
of horror through art [die kiinstlerischeBdndigungdes Entsetzlichen]"(BT, VII,
40). According to Nietzsche in Ecce Homo, in the sublime one experiences
courage in the face of "horror and terror of existence," and one is able to
"say Yes to life even in its strangest and sternest problems."31 This is so be-
cause, in the experience of art, one shares in the artist's "Dionysian," "orgi-
astic" transcendence of individual subjectivity. One identifies with the "will
to life rejoicing over its own inexhaustibility."32 Julian Young's claim that
Nietzsche's account of the sublime effect is truly Schopenhauerian, is incor-
rect.33According to Schopenhauer, in the sublime feeling no "Yes to life" is
possible. The sublime is, as I have argued, an ambivalent mixture of joy and
pain and the subject retains its contemplative stance, instead of completely
disappearing and fusing with what Nietzsche calls "primal Oneness" (BI, I,
17, 18; IV, 25). Although both philosophers seem to believe that life and suf-
fering are inseparable - though for different reasons - Nietzsche stresses
that art is to be of service to life, whereas Schopenhauer stresses that art en-
hances, among other things, pure "objective" perception of the Ideas (or, in
the case of music, of the will as such). Instead of a complete destruction of
the subject, as seems to be the case in Nietzsche's Dionysian sublime, the
Schopenhauerian aesthetic subject attains an exceptional state of purity that
allows it to discover the (transcendental) conditions of life.34 It perceives at
a glance what makes life possible: will. Therefore, Schopenhauer feels the
need to stick to Kant's "disinterestedness" in aesthetic appreciation. In de-
- something Nietzsche can-
scribing aesthetic perception as disinterested
-
not agree with Schopenhauer means that in the aesthetic state normal
categories and concepts of perception are suspended, thereby enabling us
to become alive to usually unnoticed aspects, to the "significant form" of
the object.
This is completely different from what Nietzsche means when he states
that the subject is completely transformed or transfigured in the aesthetic
stance. Nietzsche's Dionysian rapture [Verziickung], transgression, over-
flowing energy, Rausch, and ecstasy should not be confused with the
Schopenhauerian aesthetic transcendence of our ordinary mode of perceiving
This content downloaded from 130.240.43.43 on Fri, 19 Feb 2016 01:19:52 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Schopenhauer,Nietzsche, and the Sublime 103
This content downloaded from 130.240.43.43 on Fri, 19 Feb 2016 01:19:52 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
104 Bart Vandenabeele
next to the world can give us an idea of what we might understand by 'the
justification of the world as an aesthetic phenomenon"' (BT, XXIV, 115). It is
the magic of music as "the very voice of the abyss" that transforms the spec-
tacle of annihilation into superior pleasure.40 Music and tragedy "play with
the sting of displeasure," and both "use this play to justify the existence
even of the 'worst world"' (BT, XXV, 116-17). Schopenhauer would never
have drawn such a close analogy between music and tragedy: tragedy is the
highest poetic art and music is completely different, as it is simply beyond
his hierarchy of the arts. At least one of the important reasons for that, if not
the most important, is his completely different idea of what sublimity is.
According to Schopenhauer, the feeling of the sublime is the inseparable
intertwining of joy and sorrow, which enables the subject to encounter
the will without being destroyed. The "worst world" cannot be justified,
Schopenhauer maintains, only contemplated. Yet according to Nietzsche, a
split subject dwelling in two no matter how different worlds does not experi-
ence Dionysian sublimity. It is the unbridled and self-destructive jouissance
- as Jacques Lacan would say - of excessive intoxication, a creative state
that finds itself jubilant and anguished to the point of death.38 Perhaps the
pupil is least faithful to his master when he believes to be following him
closest.
NOTES
This content downloaded from 130.240.43.43 on Fri, 19 Feb 2016 01:19:52 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Schopenhauer,Nietzsche, and the Sublime 105
hand and the placementof the orientation[Absicht]to the will on the other,the
acceptance of an aesthetic purposiveness [Absichtlichkeit]seems to imply a
contradictionin adiecto].
7. See Arthur Schopenhauer,Parergaund Paralipomena (Darmstadt:L6hneysen
edition, 1989)V, 494,491.
8. See Neymeyr, AsthetischeAutonomieals Abnormitit,377: "Dem Erfordernis
spezifischerund damit qualitativerDifferenzzwischen den 'beiden Arten der
asthetischenAuffassung'wird auf diese Weisewohl schwerlichgeniig geleistet."
[Theneed for a specificand hence qualitativedifferencebetween "bothkinds of
aestheticperception"has hardlysucceededin this way].
9. See JulianYoung,WillingandUnwilling:A Studyin thePhilosophy ofArthurScho-
penhauer(Dordrecht:MartinusNijhoff,1987),90.
10. See Hans Blumenberg,Schiffbruch mitZuschauer. Paradigma einerDaseinsmetapher
(Frankfurta.M.:Suhrkamp,1979)58-69.
11. EdmundBurke,A Philosophical EnquiryintotheOriginof OurIdeasof theSublime
andBeautiful(1757;reprinted,Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress,1992),36, 42, 65,
79, 121,124.
12. See Jean-Franqois Lyotard,"Lesublime et l'avant-garde,"in Idem, L'inhumain.
Causeriessur le temps(Paris:Galilee,1988),110:"Orles terreurssont liees a des
privations:privation de la lumiere, terreur des tenebres;privation d'autrui,
terreurde la solitude;privationdu langage,terreurdu silence;privationdes ob-
jects,terreurdu vide; privationde la vie, terreurde la mort."[Terrorsare linked
to privation:privationof light, terrorin darkness;privationof others,terrorof
solitude;privationof language, terrorof silence;privationof objects,terrorof
emptiness;privationof life, terrorof death].
13. Burke,Philosophical EnquiryintotheOriginof OurIdeas,33.
14. Ibid.,34.
15. Ibid.,124.
16. See Lyotard,"Lesublimeet l'avant-garde,"105.
17. See also Der HandschriftlicheNachlass(Frankfortam Main:WaldemarKramer,
1966),I, 45;DerHandschriftlicheNachlassIV,249.
18. Typical examples of this overestimationare Chris Janaway,"Knowledgeand
Tranquility:Schopenhaueron the Value of Art,"in Jacquette,Schopenhauer, Phi-
losophy,and theArts,39-61;ClementRosset,L'esthetique de Schopenhauer (Paris:
PUF, 1969);and Neymeyr, Asthetische Autonomieals Abnormitdt. One had better
keep in mind BertrandRussell's remarkin Historyof WesternPhilosophy(Lon-
don: Routledge,1996),722:"He acknowledgesthree sourcesof his philosophy,
Kant,Plato,and the Upanishads,but I do not thinkhe owes as much to Platoas
he thinkshe does."
19. See the frequent use of terms such as Gewalt,Widerstand, Bedrdngnis, Kampf,
Kontrast,Losreissung,and Vernichtung.
20. See FriedrichNietzsche, TheBirthof Tragedyout of the Spiritof Music(London:
Penguin, 1993),26. This book will be cited in the text as BT for all subsequent
references.
21. See Bart Vandenabeele,"On the Notion of Disinterestedness:Kant, Lyotard,
Schopenhauer,"Journalof theHistoryofIdeas,62 (2001):99-112.
22. J.E.Atwell defendsthe view thatthe sublimeis the extremelybeautiful,and that
both aesthetic feelings preparefor a complete liberationfrom willing (that is
completedin asceticrenunciation).See J.E.Atwell, "Artas Liberation:A Central
Theme of Schopenhauer'sPhilosophy,"in Jacquette,Schopenhauer, Philosophy,
andtheArts,81-106.
23. See Bart Vandenabeele,"Wij wenen maar zijn niet gewond. Het sublieme
gevoel in Schopenhauersesthetica,"Tijdschrift voorFilosofie61 (1999):663-95.
24. I am thinkingof, for example,D.W. Hamlyn,Schopenhauer (London:Routledge
and Kegan Paul, 1980),111 and passim;TerryEagleton,TheIdeologyof theAes-
thetic(Oxford:Blackwell,1990):162-63;A.L. Cothey,TheNatureof Art (London:
Routledge,1992):70-71;Atwell, "Artas Liberation,"81-106.
This content downloaded from 130.240.43.43 on Fri, 19 Feb 2016 01:19:52 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
106 Bart Vandenabeele
25. On the importanceof imaginationin artand aestheticcontemplation,see Cheryl
Foster, "Ideas and Imagination,Schopenhaueron the Proper Foundationof
Art,"in TheCambridge Companion to Schopenhauer,
ed. ChrisJanaway(Cambridge:
CambridgeUniversityPress,1999),213-51.
26. See Atwell, "Artas Liberation,"100.
27. Ibid,91.
28. Young, Willingand Unwilling,100. This equalizationof the intimationof im-
mortalitywith the awarenessof the super-sensibleside of our being is highly
disputableas such.
29. JohnSallis,Crossings: NietzscheandtheSpaceof Tragedy(Chicago,The University
of ChicagoPress,1991),100.
30. FriedrichNietzsche, ThusSpokeZarathustra (London:Penguin,1969),74.
31. FriedrichNietzsche,EcceHomo,trans.R.J.Hollingdale(London:Penguin,1992),
50-51;"Affirmationof life in its strangestand sternestproblems;the will to life
rejoicingin its own inexhaustibilitythroughthe sacrificeof its highest types -
that is what I called dionysian, that is what I recognized as the bridge to the
psychology of the tragicpoet."
32. Ibid.
33. This-is not minimizing Schopenhauer'ssignificant influence on Nietzsche's
Birthof Tragedy,as JulianYoung seems to believe. See JulianYoung,Nietzsche's
Philosophy ofArt (Cambridge:CambridgeUniversityPress),1992,26.
34. See also MichelHaar,"TheJoyousStruggleof the Sublimeand the MusicalEs-
sence of Joy,"Researchin Phenomenology 25 (1995):68-89,for typical Apollonian
types of the sublimein Nietzsche.
35. See Haar,"JoyousStruggleof the Sublime,"75.
36. Ibid.,76.
37. Ibid.
38. Ibid.,77.
39. Contraryto Schopenhauer'scontention,temporalityplays a crucialpart in the
sublime.See also E.P.Miller,"SublimeTime:Nietzsche'sTragicRe-Thinkingof
Kant'sAestheticTemporality,"Eidos14 (1997):49-68.
40. The importanceof Nietzsche's connectionbetween creativity,erosand art can-
not be stressedenough. See B.E.Babich,"Nietzscheand Erosbetween the Devil
and God's Deep Blue Sea: The Problem of the Artist as Actor-Jew-Woman,"
Continental PhilosophyReview33 (2000):159-88.
This content downloaded from 130.240.43.43 on Fri, 19 Feb 2016 01:19:52 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions